This paper was converted on www.awesomepapers.org from LaTeX by an anonymous user.
Want to know more? Visit the Converter page.

Weak diamond and pcf theory

Shimon Garti Einstein Institute of Mathematics, The Hebrew University of Jerusalem, Jerusalem 91904, Israel [email protected]
Abstract.

We obtain bounds on the cardinality of pcf(𝔞)pcf(\mathfrak{a}) from instances of weak diamond. Consequently, under mild assumptions there are many singular cardinals of the form δ\aleph_{\delta} for which 2δ<|δ|+32^{\aleph_{\delta}}<\aleph_{|\delta|^{+3}}. For example, if every limit cardinal is a strong limit cardinal then this bound holds at a class of singular cardinals.

Key words and phrases:
Weak diamond, pcf theory, singular cardinals problem, club guessing, Galvin’s property
2010 Mathematics Subject Classification:
03E04

0. Introduction

The singular cardinals problem is the question of possible values of 2λ2^{\lambda}, where λ\lambda is a strong limit singular cardinal. The problem focuses on singular cardinals since the behaviour of 2κ2^{\kappa} when κ\kappa is regular is very well understood. In fact, the global demeanor of the power set operation at every regular cardinal is fully described by Easton’s theorem from [Eas70].

The assumption of strong limitude comes from the fact that one can increase 2λ2^{\lambda} (when λ\lambda is singular) simply by choosing a regular cardinal θλ\theta\in\lambda and increasing 2θ2^{\theta}. In order to avoid this artificial influence on 2λ2^{\lambda} one has to assume that no cardinal below λ\lambda forces a value for 2λ2^{\lambda}, that is, 2θλ2^{\theta}\in\lambda whenever θλ\theta\in\lambda. In other words, λ\lambda is a strong limit cardinal.

One of the highlights of set theory in the twentieth century is the following theorem of Shelah from [She94]. If δ\aleph_{\delta} is a strong limit cardinal and δ<δ\delta<\aleph_{\delta} then 2δ<|δ|+42^{\aleph_{\delta}}<\aleph_{|\delta|^{+4}}. In order to prove this theorem, Shelah developed pcf theory and obtained many results in cardinal arithmetic, including this bound on the power set of strong limit singular cardinals.

To place these results in context we should mention here the other side of the coin. Suppose, for simplicity, that λ>cf(λ)=κ\lambda>{\rm cf}(\lambda)=\kappa and 2β=β+2^{\beta}=\beta^{+} for every βλ\beta\in\lambda. If κ>0\kappa>\aleph_{0} then 2λ=λ+2^{\lambda}=\lambda^{+}, as proved by Silver in [Sil75].111A combinatorial proof of Silver’s theorem appeared in [BP76]. The analysis of 2λ2^{\lambda} in that paper resembles basic features of pcf theory. But Silver’s argument is not applicable if κ=0\kappa=\aleph_{0}. In fact, not only the argument but also the statement. Magidor proved in [Mag77a], [Mag77b] that consistently 20=n+12^{\aleph_{0}}=\aleph_{n+1} for every nωn\in\omega but 2ω>ω+12^{\aleph_{\omega}}>\aleph_{\omega+1}. It should be emphasized that the value of 2ω2^{\aleph_{\omega}} above ω+1\aleph_{\omega+1} obtained by Magidor was relatively small. In fact, 2ω<ω12^{\aleph_{\omega}}<\aleph_{\omega_{1}} in all known models of the failure of SCH at ω\aleph_{\omega},222SCH is an acronym for the singular cardinals hypothesis. A common formulation is 2λ=λ+2^{\lambda}=\lambda^{+} whenever λ\lambda is a strong limit singular cardinal. and the same is true at every strong limit singular cardinal that is not a fixed point of the aleph function. Shelah’s theorem in the specific case of ω\aleph_{\omega} amounts to 2ω<ω42^{\aleph_{\omega}}<\aleph_{\omega_{4}}, so we have an interesting gap between the upper bound and the ability to increase 2ω2^{\aleph_{\omega}} under the above assumption.

Despite a lot of effort in the last few decades, no significant progress was made in either direction. Our goal in this paper is to consider an improvement of Shelah’s bound. That is, we try to reduce |δ|+4|\delta|^{+4} to |δ|+3|\delta|^{+3}. The idea is that if the class of all strong limit singular cardinals is deemed then many of them satisfy the inequality 2δ<|δ|+32^{\aleph_{\delta}}<\aleph_{|\delta|^{+3}}, where many of them means class-many.

Our results hinge upon some cardinal arithmetic assumptions, but these assumptions are relatively weak, and we actually believe that the main result is provable in ZFC. Here is a typical statement which we can prove. Suppose that every limit cardinal is a strong limit cardinal. Then there is a class of singular strong limit cardinals of the form δ\aleph_{\delta}, such that 2δ<|δ|+32^{\aleph_{\delta}}<\aleph_{|\delta|^{+3}}. We emphasize that this conclusion follows from much a weaker assumption, as will be explicated later.

The paper contains three additional sections. In the first one we give some background, focusing on weak diamond and on pcf theory. In the second we describe Galvin’s property and then we state and prove a club guessing theorem which follows from Galvin’s property. In the last one we derive the main results in cardinal arithmetic.

Our notation is (hopefully) standard. If κ=cf(κ)<λ\kappa={\rm cf}(\kappa)<\lambda then Sκλ={δλcf(δ)=κ}S^{\lambda}_{\kappa}=\{\delta\in\lambda\mid{\rm cf}(\delta)=\kappa\}. This set is a stationary subset of λ\lambda, provided that cf(λ)>ω{\rm cf}(\lambda)>\omega. If EE is a subset of κ\kappa then acc(E)={δκ(Eδ)=δ}acc(E)=\{\delta\in\kappa\mid\bigcup(E\cap\delta)=\delta\}. This set is called the set of accumulation points of EE, and in the main application EE is a club of κ\kappa, in which case acc(E)acc(E) is also a club of κ\kappa. Other notation will be introduced as the need arises.

1. Preliminaries

In this section we touch upon two topics. The first is a prediction principle belonging to the diamond family, and the second is pcf theory. Let us commence with the Devlin-Shelah weak diamond from [DS78].

Recall that a diamond sequence (at 1\aleph_{1}) is a sequence of sets (Aααω1)(A_{\alpha}\mid\alpha\in\omega_{1}) such that for every Aω1A\subseteq\omega_{1} the set SA={αω1Aα=Aα}S_{A}=\{\alpha\in\omega_{1}\mid A\cap\alpha=A_{\alpha}\} is a stationary subset of 1\aleph_{1}. The diamond principle 1\Diamond_{\aleph_{1}}, discovered by Jensen in [Jen72], is the statement that there exists a diamond sequence. It is easy to see that 1\Diamond_{\aleph_{1}} implies 20=12^{\aleph_{0}}=\aleph_{1}. A deep ancient result of Jensen shows that 1\Diamond_{\aleph_{1}} is strictly stronger than 20=12^{\aleph_{0}}=\aleph_{1}, see [DJt74] for a detailed account of a forcing construction of this result, namely the failure of the principle 1\Diamond_{\aleph_{1}} in a model of CH.

Motivated by algebraic problems, Devlin and Shelah phrased a prediction principle that is sufficiently strong to imply some of the consequences of diamond but sufficiently weak to follow from CH. The weak diamond Φ1\Phi_{\aleph_{1}} is the statement that for every c:2<ω12c:{}^{<\omega_{1}}2\rightarrow{2} one can find g2ω1g\in{}^{\omega_{1}}2 so that for every f2ω1f\in{}^{\omega_{1}}2 the set {αω1c(fα)=g(α)}\{\alpha\in\omega_{1}\mid c(f\upharpoonright\alpha)=g(\alpha)\} is stationary in ω1\omega_{1}. It follows that Φ1\Phi_{\aleph_{1}} implies 20<212^{\aleph_{0}}<2^{\aleph_{1}} and vice versa. So, unlike the diamond, here the prediction principle at 1\aleph_{1} is equivalent to the cardinal arithmetic statement.333The statement 20<212^{\aleph_{0}}<2^{\aleph_{1}} is called sometimes the weak continuum hypothesis.

This equivalence holds true in general. One can define Φκ\Phi_{\kappa} upon replacing 1\aleph_{1} by κ\kappa in the definition of the weak diamond, and then 2κ<2κ+2^{\kappa}<2^{\kappa^{+}} is equivalent to Φκ+\Phi_{\kappa^{+}} at every infinite cardinal κ\kappa.444The substantial direction can be deduced from [DS78] by replacing any occurrence of 0\aleph_{0} with κ\kappa and any occurrence of 1\aleph_{1} with κ+\kappa^{+}. The proof of the easy direction is spelled-out in [Gar17]. Modern research shows that for κ>0\kappa>\aleph_{0}, the local instance of GCH expressed by 2κ=κ+2^{\kappa}=\kappa^{+} is equivalent to κ+\Diamond_{\kappa^{+}}, so diamond and weak diamond become similar from this point of view.

There is, however, a crucial difference between these principles if one adopts a global point of view. It is consistent that GCH fails everywhere, and then of course κ+\Diamond_{\kappa^{+}} fails for every infinite cardinal κ\kappa.555Let us indicate that κ\Diamond_{\kappa} holds if κ\kappa is a sufficiently large cardinal, e.g. if κ\kappa is measurable. But if one concentrates on successor cardinals then κ+\Diamond_{\kappa^{+}} fails everywhere in models of global failure of GCH, e.g. [FW91]. But weak diamond most hold, in ZFC, at a class of infinite cardinals. The following theorem appears as [BGP23, Proposition 2.14] with a short sketch of the proof. Let us state the theorem and give full details.

Theorem 1.1.

Let κ0\kappa_{0} be an infinite cardinal. Then the weak diamond Φκ\Phi_{\kappa} holds at some κ>κ0\kappa>\kappa_{0}.

Proof.
Let μ=2κ0\mu=2^{\kappa_{0}}. We consider three possible cases. In the first case, μ\mu is a successor cardinal, say μ=θ+\mu=\theta^{+}. Now if 2θ=θ+=μ2^{\theta}=\theta^{+}=\mu then 2θ<2θ+2^{\theta}<2^{\theta^{+}} since 2θ+=2μ>μ2^{\theta^{+}}=2^{\mu}>\mu, and then Φθ+\Phi_{\theta^{+}} holds by [DS78].

If 2θ>μ2^{\theta}>\mu then let κ\kappa be the first cardinal for which 2κ>μ2^{\kappa}>\mu, and notice that κ>κ0\kappa>\kappa_{0}. Now if κ\kappa is a successor cardinal then (letting κ=χ+\kappa=\chi^{+}) one has 2χ<2κ=2χ+2^{\chi}<2^{\kappa}=2^{\chi^{+}} and Φχ+\Phi_{\chi^{+}} holds. If κ\kappa is a limit cardinal then, since κ\kappa is the first cardinal which satisfies 2κ>μ2^{\kappa}>\mu and since 2κ0=μ2^{\kappa_{0}}=\mu, we see that 2τ=μ2^{\tau}=\mu for every τ[κ0,κ)\tau\in[\kappa_{0},\kappa). It follows that κ\kappa cannot be singular,666This is a consequence of the Bukovský-Hechler theorem, see [Buk65]. thus κ\kappa is a regular limit cardinal. However, κ0<κ\kappa_{0}<\kappa and 2κ0=μ>κ2^{\kappa_{0}}=\mu>\kappa, hence κ\kappa is weakly and not strongly inaccessible cardinal. In this case, Φκ\Phi_{\kappa} holds777The statement appears without proof in [DS78]. The detailed argument can be found in [BNGH19, Theorem 1.3].. We conclude, therefore, that in all subcases of the case in which μ=2κ0\mu=2^{\kappa_{0}} is a successor cardinal one has weak diamond at some κ>κ0\kappa>\kappa_{0}, so the first case is covered.

In the second case, μ=2κ0\mu=2^{\kappa_{0}} is a singular cardinal. Let θ=cf(μ)\theta={\rm cf}(\mu). Necessarily, θ>κ0\theta>\kappa_{0} and hence 2θμ2^{\theta}\geq\mu. But cf(2θ)>θ{\rm cf}(2^{\theta})>\theta, so 2θ>μ2^{\theta}>\mu. Let θ0\theta_{0} be the first cardinal so that 2θ0>μ2^{\theta_{0}}>\mu. Either θ0\theta_{0} is a successor cardinal or weakly inaccessible. In both cases Φθ0\Phi_{\theta_{0}} holds, as explained in the previous case. Since θ0>κ0\theta_{0}>\kappa_{0} (recall that 2κ0=μ<2θ02^{\kappa_{0}}=\mu<2^{\theta_{0}}), the second case is covered as well.

The last possible case is when μ=2κ0\mu=2^{\kappa_{0}} is weakly (but not strongly) inaccessible. If 2θ=μ2^{\theta}=\mu for every θ[κ0,μ)\theta\in[\kappa_{0},\mu) then Φμ\Phi_{\mu} holds by [DS78]. If not, let κ\kappa be the first cardinal for which 2κ>μ2^{\kappa}>\mu. Notice that κ>κ0\kappa>\kappa_{0}. As in the previous cases, either κ\kappa is a successor cardinal or weakly inaccessible. In both alternatives, Φκ\Phi_{\kappa} holds as mentioned before, so we are done.

1.1\qed_{\ref{thmclassofwd}}

In the rest of this section we survey some basic facts and definitions from pcf theory. Motivated by the singular cardinals problem, Shelah developed pcf theory in order to determine the possible values of 2λ2^{\lambda} when λ\lambda is a strong limit singular cardinal. Very quickly, Shelah realized that one should understand the possible cofinalities of products of regular cardinals below λ\lambda, in many cases end-segments of Regλ{\rm Reg}\cap\lambda (where Reg{\rm Reg} stands for the class of regular cardinals).

Let 𝔞\mathfrak{a} be a set of regular cardinals. In most theorems one has to assume that |𝔞|<min(𝔞)|\mathfrak{a}|<\min(\mathfrak{a}). A set of regular cardinals which satisfies this proviso will be called progressive. If λ\lambda is a fixed point of the aleph-function, that is λ=δ=δ\lambda=\aleph_{\delta}=\delta, then every end-segment 𝔞\mathfrak{a} of Regλ{\rm Reg}\cap\lambda is of size λ\lambda. Thus, we usually assume that λ\lambda is not a fixed point of the aleph-function.

Let 𝔞={λiiκ}\mathfrak{a}=\{\lambda_{i}\mid i\in\kappa\} be a progressive set. Let 𝒥\mathcal{J} be an ideal over κ\kappa.888We always make the assumption that 𝒥𝒥κbd\mathcal{J}\supseteq\mathcal{J}^{\rm bd}_{\kappa}, where 𝒥κbd\mathcal{J}^{\rm bd}_{\kappa} denotes the ideal of bounded subsets of κ\kappa. The ideal 𝒥\mathcal{J} gives rise to a partial ordering defined on 𝔞\prod\mathfrak{a} as follows. For f,g𝔞f,g\in\prod\mathfrak{a} one says that f<𝒥gf<_{\mathcal{J}}g iff {iκf(i)g(i)}𝒥\{i\in\kappa\mid f(i)\geq g(i)\}\in\mathcal{J}. A sequence f¯=(fααλ)\bar{f}=(f_{\alpha}\mid\alpha\in\lambda) of elements of 𝔞\prod\mathfrak{a} is a scale in (𝔞,𝒥)(\prod\mathfrak{a},\mathcal{J}) iff f¯\bar{f} is both increasing (to wit, α<β<λfα<𝒥fβ\alpha<\beta<\lambda\Rightarrow f_{\alpha}<_{\mathcal{J}}f_{\beta}) and cofinal (that is, for every h𝔞h\in\prod\mathfrak{a} there is αλ\alpha\in\lambda such that h<𝒥fαh<_{\mathcal{J}}f_{\alpha}).

The product (𝔞,𝒥)(\prod\mathfrak{a},\mathcal{J}) has true cofinality iff there is a scale in (𝔞,𝒥)(\prod\mathfrak{a},\mathcal{J}), in which case the true cofinality of (𝔞,𝒥)(\prod\mathfrak{a},\mathcal{J}) is the minimal length of such a scale. We shall write tcf(𝔞,𝒥)=λtcf(\prod\mathfrak{a},\mathcal{J})=\lambda. Given a progressive set 𝔞\mathfrak{a}, pcf(𝔞)pcf(\mathfrak{a}) is the set of all tcf(𝔞,𝒥)tcf(\prod\mathfrak{a},\mathcal{J}) where 𝒥\mathcal{J} is an ideal over 𝔞\mathfrak{a}. It follows immediately that 𝔞pcf(𝔞)\mathfrak{a}\subseteq pcf(\mathfrak{a}) and hence |pcf(𝔞)||𝔞||pcf(\mathfrak{a})|\geq|\mathfrak{a}|. A central challenge in pcf theory is to find an upper bound on the cardinality of pcf(𝔞)pcf(\mathfrak{a}), especially when 𝔞\mathfrak{a} is an interval of regular cardinals.

By finding such an upper bound, one can derive non-trivial conclusions with regard to the singular cardinals problem. The reason is that pcf(𝔞)pcf(\mathfrak{a}) has always a last element dubbed as maxpcf(𝔞)\max pcf(\mathfrak{a}). A fundamental theorem of Shelah says that if λ\lambda is a strong limit singular cardinal that is not a fixed point of the \aleph-function, and if 𝔞\mathfrak{a} is a progressive end-segment of Regλ{\rm Reg}\cap\lambda, then 2λ=maxpcf(𝔞)2^{\lambda}=\max pcf(\mathfrak{a}). Therefore, an upper bound on pcf(𝔞)pcf(\mathfrak{a}) would give an upper bound on the value of 2λ2^{\lambda}. It should be noted that an upper bound in terms of the \beth-function also exists,999Such bounds on 2λ2^{\lambda} when λ>cf(λ)>ω\lambda>{\rm cf}(\lambda)>\omega were obtained in [GH75], shortly before the discovery of pcf theory by Shelah. However, the methods of [GH75] require uncountable cofinality. namely |pcf(𝔞)|2|𝔞||pcf(\mathfrak{a})|\leq 2^{|\mathfrak{a}|}. But this bound is not absolute, as 2|𝔞|2^{|\mathfrak{a}|} can be easily manipulated by forcing. Thus the real interesting bound is the \aleph-scale bound, which says that |pcf(𝔞)|<|𝔞|+4|pcf(\mathfrak{a})|<|\mathfrak{a}|^{+4}. We indicate, however, that sometimes (e.g., if 2|𝔞|=|𝔞|+2^{|\mathfrak{a}|}=|\mathfrak{a}|^{+}) the \beth-scale bound is better than the \aleph-scale bound.

The proof of the \aleph-scale bound is a combination of basic properties of pcf(𝔞)pcf(\mathfrak{a}) and a prediction principle called club guessing. The latter will be discussed extensively in the next section, so here we conclude with one important feature of pcf(𝔞)pcf(\mathfrak{a}), called localization. Needless to say that this property of pcf(𝔞)pcf(\mathfrak{a}) was proved by Shelah.

Theorem 1.2.

Let 𝔞\mathfrak{a} be progressive and assume that 𝔟pcf(𝔞)\mathfrak{b}\subseteq pcf(\mathfrak{a}) is also progressive. Let λpcf(𝔟)\lambda\in pcf(\mathfrak{b}). Then one can find 𝔟0𝔟\mathfrak{b}_{0}\subseteq\mathfrak{b} such that |𝔟0||𝔞||\mathfrak{b}_{0}|\leq|\mathfrak{a}| and λpcf(𝔟0)\lambda\in pcf(\mathfrak{b}_{0}).

Intuitively, this property puts a restriction on the size of pcf(𝔞)pcf(\mathfrak{a}). It is closely related to the Achilles and the Tortoise property, which says that within pcf(𝔞)pcf(\mathfrak{a}) one cannot construct long subsets of the from 𝔟\mathfrak{b} for which maxpcf(𝔟λ)>λ\max pcf(\mathfrak{b}\cap\lambda)>\lambda. The bound of |pcf(𝔞)|<|𝔞|+4|pcf(\mathfrak{a})|<|\mathfrak{a}|^{+4} can be derived from the localization property in the context of an appropriate instance of club guessing, as will be shown later. For more background in pcf theory we suggest [AM10] and [BM90], as well as Shelah’s monograph [She94].

2. Club guessing and Galvin’s property

Let κ,λ\kappa,\lambda be regular cardinals101010In the general setting, λ\lambda can be singular provided that cf(λ)κ++{\rm cf}(\lambda)\geq\kappa^{++}. But for the applications to cardinal arithmetic we may restrict our attention to λ=cf(λ)\lambda={\rm cf}(\lambda). where κ<λ\kappa<\lambda. The set SκλS^{\lambda}_{\kappa} is a stationary subset of λ\lambda. Fix SSκλS\subseteq S^{\lambda}_{\kappa} that is stationary in λ\lambda, and let 𝒞=(CδδS)\mathcal{C}=(C_{\delta}\mid\delta\in{S}) be a sequence of sets such that CδδC_{\delta}\subseteq\delta is a club of δ\delta of order-type κ\kappa for every δS\delta\in{S}. One says that 𝒞\mathcal{C} is a club guessing sequence for λ\lambda iff for every club EE of λ\lambda one can find δS\delta\in{S} for which CδEC_{\delta}\subseteq{E}. The following theorem appears in [She94], and it plays a key role in proofs which bound the cardinality of pcf(𝔞)pcf(\mathfrak{a}).

Theorem 2.1.

Suppose that λcf(λ)κ++\lambda\geq{\rm cf}(\lambda)\geq\kappa^{++}, where κ\kappa is a regular cardinal. Let SSκλS\subseteq S^{\lambda}_{\kappa} be a stationary subset of λ\lambda. Then there exists a club guessing sequence (CααS)(C_{\alpha}\mid\alpha\in{S}).

It is important to notice that there is a gap here between the small parameter κ\kappa (that is, the size of each CαC_{\alpha}) and the cofinality of λ\lambda (that is, κ++\kappa^{++}). In the typical case of λ=κ++\lambda=\kappa^{++} this gap reduces to two cardinalities, and in general this optimal gap cannot be avoided. Indeed, one can force the failure of club guessing at Sκκ+S^{\kappa^{+}}_{\kappa}. As we shall see later, this gap is instrumental when trying to compute the size of pcf(𝔞)pcf(\mathfrak{a}). Our goal in this section is to obtain club guessing at Sκκ+S^{\kappa^{+}}_{\kappa} from an instance of Galvin’s property.

Galvin showed111111The proof was published in [BHM75]. that if κ=κ<κ>0\kappa=\kappa^{<\kappa}>\aleph_{0} and \mathscr{F} is a normal filter over κ\kappa then every family 𝒞={Cγγκ+}\mathcal{C}=\{C_{\gamma}\mid\gamma\in\kappa^{+}\}\subseteq\mathscr{F} admits a subfamily {Cγiiκ}\{C_{\gamma_{i}}\mid i\in\kappa\} such that {Cγiiκ}\bigcap\{C_{\gamma_{i}}\mid i\in\kappa\}\in\mathscr{F}. A central example is the club filter over κ\kappa, denoted by 𝒟κ\mathscr{D}_{\kappa}. We use the notation Gal(,κ,κ+){\rm Gal}(\mathscr{F},\kappa,\kappa^{+}) to denote the above statement. The assumption κ=κ<κ\kappa=\kappa^{<\kappa} boils down to a local instance of GCH if one wishes to apply Galvin’s theorem at successor cardinals. Thus if 2λ=λ+2^{\lambda}=\lambda^{+} then Gal(𝒟λ+,λ+,λ++){\rm Gal}(\mathscr{D}_{\lambda^{+}},\lambda^{+},\lambda^{++}) holds true.

A natural question is whether Galvin’s assumption 2λ=λ+2^{\lambda}=\lambda^{+} is droppable. The answer turns out to be interesting. Abraham and Shelah proved in [AS86] that Galvin’s property consistently fails. More specifically, they proved that if κ\kappa is regular and λcf(λ)>κ+\lambda\geq{\rm cf}(\lambda)>\kappa^{+} then one can force 2κ+=λ2^{\kappa^{+}}=\lambda with ¬Gal(𝒟κ+,κ+,λ)\neg{\rm Gal}(\mathscr{D}_{\kappa^{+}},\kappa^{+},\lambda). This statement is called the ultimate failure of Galvin’s property at 𝒟κ+\mathscr{D}_{\kappa^{+}}, since the size of the family witnessing the failure of Galvin’s property is the largest possible (namely, 2κ+2^{\kappa^{+}}). We conclude, therefore, that Galvin’s theorem is not a ZFC statement.

However, one can prove instances of Galvin’s property under weaker assumptions than the one used by Galvin. It was shown in [Gar17] that if 2κ<2κ+=λ2^{\kappa}<2^{\kappa^{+}}=\lambda then Gal(𝒟κ+,κ+,λ){\rm Gal}(\mathscr{D}_{\kappa^{+}},\kappa^{+},\lambda) holds.121212Recall that the statement 2κ<2κ+2^{\kappa}<2^{\kappa^{+}} is equivalent to the prediction principle Φκ+\Phi_{\kappa^{+}}. Thus 2κ<2κ+2^{\kappa}<2^{\kappa^{+}} yields instances of Galvin’s property even if 2κ>κ+2^{\kappa}>\kappa^{+}, and the original assumption of Galvin can be relaxed. The crucial point here becomes meaningful if one adopts a global point of view. Galvin’s assumption 2κ=κ+2^{\kappa}=\kappa^{+} may fail everywhere, while Φκ\Phi_{\kappa} must hold at many places, as shown in the previous section. This point will be relevant in the sequel, due to the main result of this section which derives club guessing (with a gap of one cardinal) from an instance of Galvin’s property.

Theorem 2.2.

Let κ\kappa be a regular and uncountable cardinal, and let SSκκ+S\subseteq S^{\kappa^{+}}_{\kappa} be stationary. If Gal(𝒟κ+,κ+,2κ+){\rm Gal}(\mathscr{D}_{\kappa^{+}},\kappa^{+},2^{\kappa^{+}}) holds then there exists a club guessing sequence (CααS)(C_{\alpha}\mid\alpha\in{S}).

Proof.
Let 𝒞=(CδδS)\mathcal{C}=(C_{\delta}\mid\delta\in{S}) be a sequence of sets, where CδδC_{\delta}\subseteq\delta is a club of δ\delta for each δS\delta\in{S}. Let Eκ+E\subseteq\kappa^{+} be a club of κ+\kappa^{+}. Denote by 𝒞E\mathcal{C}\upharpoonright{E} the sequence (CδEδacc(E)S)(C_{\delta}\cap{E}\mid\delta\in acc(E)\cap{S}). We move from EE to acc(E)acc(E) in order to make sure that CδEC_{\delta}\cap{E} is a club of δ\delta.

We claim that for some Eκ+E\subseteq\kappa^{+}, the sequence 𝒞E\mathcal{C}\upharpoonright{E} is a club guessing sequence.131313The index set of 𝒞E\mathcal{C}\upharpoonright{E} is acc(E)SSacc(E)\cap{S}\subseteq{S}, but trivially if there is a club guessing sequence for a stationary subset of SS then there is such a sequence for SS. Assume towards contradiction that this claim fails. Therefore, for every club EE of κ+\kappa^{+} there exists a club DEκ+D_{E}\subseteq\kappa^{+} such that if δacc(E)S\delta\in acc(E)\cap{S} then CδEDEC_{\delta}\cap{E}\nsubseteq D_{E}. Of course, if DDED\subseteq{D_{E}} then CδEDC_{\delta}\cap{E}\nsubseteq{D}, so we may shrink each DED_{E} by letting AE=EDEA_{E}=E\cap{D_{E}}, and now for every δacc(E)S\delta\in acc(E)\cap{S} one has CδEAEC_{\delta}\cap{E}\nsubseteq A_{E}.

Let 𝒜={AEEis a club ofκ+}\mathcal{A}=\{A_{E}\mid E\ \text{is a club of}\ \kappa^{+}\}. We may assume, without loss of generality,141414Our goal is to apply Gal(𝒟κ+,κ+,2κ+){\rm Gal}(\mathscr{D}_{\kappa^{+}},\kappa^{+},2^{\kappa^{+}}) to 𝒜\mathcal{A}. Now if |𝒜|<2κ+|\mathcal{A}|<2^{\kappa^{+}} then there are 2κ+2^{\kappa^{+}} many EEs with the same AEA_{E}, and they satisfy (trivially) the conclusion of the Galvin property, so we may assume that |𝒜|=2κ+|\mathcal{A}|=2^{\kappa^{+}}. that |𝒜|=2κ+|\mathcal{A}|=2^{\kappa^{+}}. Notice that each element of 𝒜\mathcal{A} is in 𝒟κ+\mathscr{D}_{\kappa^{+}}, hence Gal(𝒟κ+,κ+,2κ+){\rm Gal}(\mathscr{D}_{\kappa^{+}},\kappa^{+},2^{\kappa^{+}}) applies. Fix a family 𝒜={AEiiκ+}𝒜\mathcal{A}^{\prime}=\{A_{E_{i}}\mid i\in\kappa^{+}\}\subseteq\mathcal{A} and a club Eκ+E_{*}\subseteq\kappa^{+} such that EAEiE_{*}\subseteq A_{E_{i}} for every iκ+i\in\kappa^{+}. If δacc(E)S\delta\in acc(E_{*})\cap{S} then CδEC_{\delta}\cap E_{*} is a club of δ\delta. Since CδECδAEiC_{\delta}\cap{E_{*}}\subseteq C_{\delta}\cap{A_{E_{i}}} we conclude that CδAEiC_{\delta}\cap{A_{E_{i}}} is a club of δ\delta as well, for every iκ+i\in\kappa^{+}. In particular, |CδAEi|=κ|C_{\delta}\cap{A_{E_{i}}}|=\kappa. By induction on ακ+\alpha\in\kappa^{+} we define Eακ+E^{\alpha}\subseteq\kappa^{+} as follows. We let E0=AE0E^{0}=A_{E_{0}} and Eα=βαEβE^{\alpha}=\bigcap_{\beta\in\alpha}E^{\beta} whenever α\alpha is a limit ordinal of κ+\kappa^{+}. Finally, Eα+1=EαAEαE^{\alpha+1}=E^{\alpha}\cap A_{E_{\alpha}} for every ακ+\alpha\in\kappa^{+}. Notice that each EαE^{\alpha} is a club of κ+\kappa^{+}.

Fix δacc(E)S\delta\in acc(E_{*})\cap{S}. Since EAEαE_{*}\subseteq A_{E_{\alpha}} for every ακ+\alpha\in\kappa^{+} one concludes that CδECδAEαC_{\delta}\cap{E_{*}}\subseteq C_{\delta}\cap{A_{E_{\alpha}}} for every ακ+\alpha\in\kappa^{+}. The sequence (CδEαακ+)(C_{\delta}\cap{E^{\alpha}}\mid\alpha\in\kappa^{+}) is \subseteq-decreasing, and since |CδEα|=κ|C_{\delta}\cap{E^{\alpha}}|=\kappa for every ακ+\alpha\in\kappa^{+} we see that there is some ακ+\alpha\in\kappa^{+} for which CδEα=CδEC_{\delta}\cap{E^{\alpha}}=C_{\delta}\cap{E_{*}}. It follows that CδEα=CδEα+1C_{\delta}\cap{E^{\alpha}}=C_{\delta}\cap{E^{\alpha+1}} since EαEα+1EE^{\alpha}\supseteq E^{\alpha+1}\supseteq E_{*}, so CδEα=CδEα+1Eα+1C_{\delta}\cap{E^{\alpha}}=C_{\delta}\cap{E^{\alpha+1}}\subseteq E^{\alpha+1}. On the other hand, Eα+1AEαE^{\alpha+1}\subseteq A_{E_{\alpha}} and δacc(Eα)\delta\in acc(E^{\alpha}) so CδEαEα+1C_{\delta}\cap{E^{\alpha}}\nsubseteq E^{\alpha+1}, a contradiction.

2.2\qed_{\ref{thmcggalvin}}

We conclude this section with a comparison between the classical club guessing of Shelah (i.e., Theorem 2.1) and the current version which comes from the Galvin property. In both cases we have two parameters. The smaller parameter κ\kappa is regular and if forms the size of the guessing club CδC_{\delta}. The bigger parameter λ\lambda is the domain of the clubs to be guessed. In both proofs one begins with an arbitrary sequence 𝒞=(CδδS)\mathcal{C}=(C_{\delta}\mid\delta\in{S}), where SSκλS\subseteq S^{\lambda}_{\kappa} is stationary and each CδC_{\delta} is a club of δ\delta. Then one argues that 𝒞E\mathcal{C}\upharpoonright{E} is a club guessing sequence for some EλE\subseteq\lambda.

In order to define EE one creates a decreasing sequence (Eαακ++1)(E^{\alpha}\mid\alpha\in\kappa^{+}+1) of clubs of λ\lambda, where the last element is E=Eκ+E=E^{\kappa^{+}}. The sequence is continuous and hence EE is the intersection of κ+\kappa^{+}-many clubs of λ\lambda. Apart from the last step of EE, the length of the sequence is κ+\kappa^{+}, and this is necessary in order to stabilize the decreasing derived sequences (CδEαακ+)(C_{\delta}\cap{E^{\alpha}}\mid\alpha\in\kappa^{+}), bearing in mind that otp(Cδ)=κotp(C_{\delta})=\kappa. The last step in which E=Eκ+E=E^{\kappa^{+}} is created, compels λ\lambda to be κ++\kappa^{++} (or, more generally, cf(λ)κ++{\rm cf}(\lambda)\geq\kappa^{++}). This is the reason for the gap between κ\kappa and λ\lambda in the classical club guessing theorem.

But in the presence of Galvin’s property one obtains a decreasing sequence of clubs of λ\lambda so that every element in the sequence contains a fixed club EE_{*}, which serves (at the end) as Eκ+E^{\kappa^{+}}. This can be done, under a mild assumption, even for λ=κ+\lambda=\kappa^{+}. Put another way, Galvin’s property helps to reduce the gap between κ\kappa and λ\lambda to one cardinality. Thus one obtains club guessing at Sκκ+S^{\kappa^{+}}_{\kappa}, and this is crucial for computing the size of pcf(𝔞)pcf(\mathfrak{a}) as we shall see in the next section.

3. A legend of three and four

There are three things which are stately in their march, four which are stately in their going.151515See [BDCE, Chapter 30:29]. Our goal in this section is to supply a mathematical interpretation to the above quotation. Familiarity with the proof of Shelah’s bound |pcf(𝔞)|<|𝔞|+4|pcf(\mathfrak{a})|<|\mathfrak{a}|^{+4} where 𝔞\mathfrak{a} is a progressive interval of regular cardinals leads to the conclusion that an improvement in club guessing would give a better bound on the size of pcf(𝔞)pcf(\mathfrak{a}). In particular, if |𝔞|=η|\mathfrak{a}|=\eta then club guessing at Sη+η++S^{\eta^{++}}_{\eta^{+}} yields the corresponding bound of |pcf(𝔞)|<|𝔞|+3|pcf(\mathfrak{a})|<|\mathfrak{a}|^{+3}.

In this section we spell-out the proof of this statement. The only deviation from the classical proof of Shelah is when we replace the ZFC club guessing by the stronger version based on the Galvin property. Hence we will be able to improve the bound on the size of pcf(𝔞)pcf(\mathfrak{a}) once we show that an appropriate instance of Galvin’s property holds at relevant places, and this will be done later. The proof of the following theorem is based on the presentation in [BM90]. We indicate that one can use the ideas of [AM10] as well.

Theorem 3.1.

Let 𝔞\mathfrak{a} be a progressive interval of regular cardinals, and let η=|𝔞|\eta=|\mathfrak{a}|. Suppose that there is a club guessing sequence at Sη+η++S^{\eta^{++}}_{\eta^{+}}. Then |pcf(𝔞)|<|𝔞|+3|pcf(\mathfrak{a})|<|\mathfrak{a}|^{+3}.

Proof.
By omitting one element from 𝔞\mathfrak{a} (if needed) we may assume that min(𝔞)\min(\mathfrak{a}) is a successor cardinal, say δ+1\aleph_{\delta+1}. It is easy to see that (under this slight modification of 𝔞\mathfrak{a}) all the elements of pcf(𝔞)pcf(\mathfrak{a}) are successor cardinals. Denote maxpcf(𝔞)\max pcf(\mathfrak{a}) by δ+ρ+1\aleph_{\delta+\rho+1}.

We shall define a topological structure whose underlying set is ρ+1\rho+1, and then we will show that the properties of this topological space imply that |ρ|η++|\rho|\leq\eta^{++}. In order to generate our topology we define the following closure operation. Given xρ+1x\subseteq\rho+1 we let:

c(x)={γρδ+γ+1pcf({δ+β+1βx})}.c\ell(x)=\{\gamma\leq\rho\mid\aleph_{\delta+\gamma+1}\in pcf(\{\aleph_{\delta+\beta+1}\mid\beta\in{x}\})\}.

One can verify that c()=c\ell(\varnothing)=\varnothing, that xc(x)x\subseteq c\ell(x) for every xx, that xyx\subseteq{y} implies c(x)c(y)c\ell(x)\subseteq c\ell(y), that c(xy)=c(x)c(y)c\ell(x\cup{y})=c\ell(x)\cup c\ell(y) and that c(c(x))=c(x)c\ell(c\ell(x))=c\ell(x). Less routine properties come from the attributes of pcf, in particular:

  1. (a)(a)

    If xρ+1x\subseteq\rho+1 and γc(x)\gamma\in c\ell(x) then there exists yxy\subseteq{x} such that |y|η|y|\leq\eta and γc(y)\gamma\in c\ell(y).

  2. (b)(b)

    For every xρ+1x\subseteq\rho+1 there is a last element in c(x)c\ell(x).

  3. (c)(c)

    If ω<cf(γ)γρ\omega<{\rm cf}(\gamma)\leq\gamma\leq\rho then there is a club cγc\subseteq\gamma such that c(c)γ+1c\ell(c)\subseteq\gamma+1.

Observe that (a)(a) is simply the localization property, and (b)(b) is the fact that pcf(𝔟)pcf(\mathfrak{b}) has a last element.

Assume towards contradiction that |ρ|η+3|\rho|\geq\eta^{+3}, so without loss of generality |ρ|=η+3|\rho|=\eta^{+3}. Let S=Sη+η++S=S^{\eta^{++}}_{\eta^{+}} and let (CααS)(C_{\alpha}\mid\alpha\in{S}) be a club guessing sequence. Fix a sufficiently large regular cardinal χ\chi. Let (Mββη++)(M_{\beta}\mid\beta\leq\eta^{++}) be an increasing continuous sequence of elementary submodels of (χ)\mathcal{H}(\chi) for which the following requirements are met:

  1. ()(\aleph)

    η++Mβ\eta^{++}\subseteq M_{\beta} and |Mβ|=η++|M_{\beta}|=\eta^{++} for each βη++\beta\in\eta^{++}.

  2. ()(\beth)

    (Mγγβ)Mβ+1(M_{\gamma}\mid\gamma\leq\beta)\in M_{\beta+1} for every βη++\beta\in\eta^{++}.

  3. ()(\gimel)

    (CααS)Mβ(C_{\alpha}\mid\alpha\in{S})\in M_{\beta} for every βη++\beta\in\eta^{++}.

  4. ()(\daleth)

    {x,c(x)xη+3+1}Mβ\{\langle x,c\ell(x)\rangle\mid x\subseteq\eta^{+3}+1\}\in M_{\beta} for every βη++\beta\in\eta^{++}.

For each βη+++1\beta\in\eta^{++}+1 let γβ=Mβη+3\gamma_{\beta}=M_{\beta}\cap\eta^{+3}, so γβη+3\gamma_{\beta}\in\eta^{+3}. It follows that D={γββη++}D=\{\gamma_{\beta}\mid\beta\leq\eta^{++}\} is a closed bounded subset of η+3\eta^{+3}. Notice that (γδδβ)Mβ+1(\gamma_{\delta}\mid\delta\in\beta)\in M_{\beta+1} for every βη++\beta\in\eta^{++} since each γδ\gamma_{\delta} belongs to Mβ+1M_{\beta+1} (being definable in Mβ+1M_{\beta+1}) and then the whole sequence (γδδβ)(\gamma_{\delta}\mid\delta\in\beta) is in Mβ+1M_{\beta+1} by virtue of ()(\beth).

For every α,βη++\alpha,\beta\in\eta^{++} let Eαβ={γδδCαβ}E^{\beta}_{\alpha}=\{\gamma_{\delta}\mid\delta\in C_{\alpha}\cap\beta\}. Observe that EαβE^{\beta}_{\alpha} is definable in Mβ+1M_{\beta+1}, and hence EαβMβ+1E^{\beta}_{\alpha}\in M_{\beta+1}. Therefore, if c(Eαβ)c\ell(E^{\beta}_{\alpha}) is bounded in η+3\eta^{+3} then this bound is computable in Mβ+1M_{\beta+1} and hence belongs to Mβ+1M_{\beta+1}. It follows that if c(Eαβ)c\ell(E^{\beta}_{\alpha}) is bounded in η+3\eta^{+3} then c(Eαβ)γβ+1c\ell(E^{\beta}_{\alpha})\subseteq\gamma_{\beta+1}.

From property (c)(c) one infers that there exists a club EE of γη++\gamma_{\eta^{++}} such that c(E)γη+++1c\ell(E)\subseteq\gamma_{\eta^{++}}+1. For every αS\alpha\in{S} let Tα={γββCα}T_{\alpha}=\{\gamma_{\beta}\mid\beta\in{C_{\alpha}}\}, so TαT_{\alpha} is the DD-copy of the element CαC_{\alpha} in the club guessing sequence. Since CαC_{\alpha} is a club of α\alpha, TαT_{\alpha} is a club of γα\gamma_{\alpha}. Fix an ordinal α\alpha so that TαET_{\alpha}\subseteq{E}. Let ζ\zeta be the last element of c(Tα)c\ell(T_{\alpha}), it exists by (b)(b). Observe that ζγβ\zeta\geq\gamma_{\beta} for every γβTα\gamma_{\beta}\in T_{\alpha} and hence ζγα\zeta\geq\gamma_{\alpha}.

On the other hand, there must be some βα\beta\in\alpha for which ζc(Tαγβ)\zeta\in c\ell(T_{\alpha}\cap\gamma_{\beta}). Indeed, |Tα|=η+|T_{\alpha}|=\eta^{+}. Hence, if yTα,|y|=ηy\subseteq T_{\alpha},|y|=\eta and ζc(y)\zeta\in c\ell(y) then yTαy\cap T_{\alpha} is bounded in γα\gamma_{\alpha} (recall that cf(γα)=η+{\rm cf}(\gamma_{\alpha})=\eta^{+}), thus y=yTαy=y\cap T_{\alpha} is a subset of TαγβT_{\alpha}\cap\gamma_{\beta} for some βα\beta\in\alpha. Therefore, one concludes that ζc(Tαγβ)\zeta\in c\ell(T_{\alpha}\cap\gamma_{\beta}) for some βα\beta\in\alpha, as wanted. Using the above notation, Tαγβ=EαβT_{\alpha}\cap\gamma_{\beta}=E^{\beta}_{\alpha} and hence c(Eαβ)c(Tα)c(E)γη+++1c\ell(E^{\beta}_{\alpha})\subseteq c\ell(T_{\alpha})\subseteq c\ell(E)\subseteq\gamma_{\eta^{++}}+1. In particular, c(Eαβ)c\ell(E^{\beta}_{\alpha}) is bounded in η+3\eta^{+3}. As indicated above, the bound belongs to Mβ+1M_{\beta+1}. Therefore, ζγβ+1<γα\zeta\in\gamma_{\beta+1}<\gamma_{\alpha}, a contradiction.

3.1\qed_{\ref{thmpcfbound3}}

Here is an easy conclusion which gives an improved pcf bound:

Corollary 3.2.

Assume that:

  1. (a)(a)

    λ=δ\lambda=\aleph_{\delta} is a strong limit singular cardinal.

  2. (b)(b)

    λ\lambda is not a fixed point of the \aleph-function.

  3. (c)(c)

    𝔞\mathfrak{a} is an end-segment of Regλ,|𝔞|=η{\rm Reg}\cap\lambda,|\mathfrak{a}|=\eta.

  4. (d)(d)

    2η+<2η++2^{\eta^{+}}<2^{\eta^{++}}.

Then |pcf(𝔞)|<|𝔞|+3|pcf(\mathfrak{a})|<|\mathfrak{a}|^{+3}, and hence 2λ<|δ|+32^{\lambda}<\aleph_{|\delta|^{+3}}.

Proof.
By [Gar17], assumption (d)(d) implies Gal(𝒟η++,η++,2η++){\rm Gal}(\mathscr{D}_{\eta^{++}},\eta^{++},2^{\eta^{++}}). Since η+\eta^{+} is regular we conclude from Theorem 2.2 that there exists a club guessing sequence at Sη+η++S^{\eta^{++}}_{\eta^{+}}. Applying Theorem 3.1 we see that |pcf(𝔞)|<|𝔞|+3|pcf(\mathfrak{a})|<|\mathfrak{a}|^{+3}. Since λ\lambda is a strong limit cardinal, 2λ=maxpcf(𝔞)2^{\lambda}=\max pcf(\mathfrak{a}). Therefore, 2λ<|δ|+32^{\lambda}<\aleph_{|\delta|^{+3}} as desired.

3.2\qed_{\ref{corweakdiamond}}

The corollary shows that an instance of weak diamond yields a locally interesting pcf bound. But the real import of the weak diamond hinges upon the fact that it holds at unboundedly many points in ZFC, as shown before. Of course, we need instances of weak diamond at double successors, and the existence of these instances is not a ZFC statement. However, mild assumptions produce the desired setting.

Theorem 3.3.

Assume that every limit cardinal is a strong limit cardinal. Then there is a class \mathfrak{C} of singular cardinals such that:

  1. ()(\aleph)

    If δ\aleph_{\delta}\in\mathfrak{C} and 𝔞Regδ\mathfrak{a}\subseteq{\rm Reg}\cap\aleph_{\delta} is progressive then |pcf(𝔞)|<|𝔞|+3|pcf(\mathfrak{a})|<|\mathfrak{a}|^{+3}.

  2. ()(\beth)

    If δ\aleph_{\delta}\in\mathfrak{C} then 2δ<(|δ|+3)2^{\aleph_{\delta}}<\aleph_{(|\delta|^{+3})}.

Proof.
Fix an infinite cardinal κ0\kappa_{0} and let λ0\lambda_{0} be the first singular cardinal greater than κ0\kappa_{0}. Let κ=κ0+\kappa=\kappa_{0}^{+}. Since λ0\lambda_{0} is strong limit, μ=2κ<λ0\mu=2^{\kappa}<\lambda_{0}. By the arguments of Theorem 1.1 there must be some χκ+\chi\geq\kappa^{+} such that χμ\chi\leq\mu and Φχ\Phi_{\chi} holds. Notice that χ\chi is necessarily a double successor cardinal, so from Corollary 3.2 one can find a singular strong limit cardinal δ\aleph_{\delta} such that δ<δ\delta<\aleph_{\delta} and a progressive interval 𝔞Regδ\mathfrak{a}\subseteq{\rm Reg}\cap\aleph_{\delta} so that |𝔞|=χ|\mathfrak{a}|=\chi, and infer that |pcf(𝔞)|<|𝔞|+3|pcf(\mathfrak{a})|<|\mathfrak{a}|^{+3}. Since δ\aleph_{\delta} is a strong limit cardinal, 2δ=maxpcf(𝔞)2^{\aleph_{\delta}}=\max pcf(\mathfrak{a}) and hence 2δ<(|δ|+3)2^{\aleph_{\delta}}<\aleph_{(|\delta|^{+3})}. This reasoning holds with respect to every starting point κ0\kappa_{0}, so we are done.

3.3\qed_{\ref{thmglobalpcfbound3}}

The assumption that every limit cardinal is a strong limit cardinal is much stronger than the assumption needed for getting the conclusion of the above theorem. Basically, in order to avoid instances of 2η+<2η++2^{\eta^{+}}<2^{\eta^{++}} one has to accept a restricted constellation of cardinal arithmetic. Let us describe a typical cardinal arithmetic setting in which Corollary 3.2 does not apply. In this setting, all the relevant instances of weak diamond concentrate on weakly but not strongly inaccessible cardinals.161616Of course, there might be weak diamonds on large cardinals, but these are irrelevant to our arguments, since by starting from any κ0\kappa_{0} we consider possible instances of weak diamond between κ0\kappa_{0} and 2κ02^{\kappa_{0}}. In particular, there is a class of weakly but not strongly inaccessible cardinals and 2η+2^{\eta^{+}} is weakly inaccessible for every successor cardinal of the form η+\eta^{+}. Moreover, 2η+=2η++2^{\eta^{+}}=2^{\eta^{++}} everywhere, so cardinal arithmetic is very peculiar: there are long intervals of regular cardinals with a constant value of the power set, and all the regular cardinals are arranged in this way.

This is not the only setting in which Corollary 3.2 may fail, but the other possibilities are similar. That is, long intervals with the same power set, with values either at weakly but not strongly inaccessible cardinals, or at their successors, or at successors of singular cardinals. The main thing is that the assumption that 2η+=2η++2^{\eta^{+}}=2^{\eta^{++}} holds everywhere is quite restricting. We state, therefore, the following:

Conjecture 3.4.

In any model of ZFC there is a class of strong limit singular cardinals of the form δ\aleph_{\delta} for which 2δ<(|δ|+3)2^{\aleph_{\delta}}<\aleph_{(|\delta|^{+3})}.

References

  • [AM10] Uri Abraham and Menachem Magidor. Cardinal arithmetic. In Handbook of set theory. Vols. 1, 2, 3, pages 1149–1227. Springer, Dordrecht, 2010.
  • [AS86] U. Abraham and S. Shelah. On the intersection of closed unbounded sets. J. Symbolic Logic, 51(1):180–189, 1986.
  • [BDCE] Solomon Ben David. Proverbs. In Writings. 952 B.C.E.
  • [BGP23] Tom Benhamou, Shimon Garti, and Alejandro Poveda. Negating the Galvin property. J. Lond. Math. Soc. (2), 108(1):190–237, 2023.
  • [BHM75] J. E. Baumgartner, A. Ha̧jņal, and A. Mate. Weak saturation properties of ideals. In Infinite and finite sets (Colloq., Keszthely, 1973; dedicated to P. Erdős on his 60th birthday), Vol. I, pages 137–158. Colloq. Math. Soc. János Bolyai, Vol. 10. North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1975.
  • [BM90] Maxim R. Burke and Menachem Magidor. Shelah’s pcf{\rm pcf} theory and its applications. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 50(3):207–254, 1990.
  • [BNGH19] Omer Ben-Neria, Shimon Garti, and Yair Hayut. Weak prediction principles. Fund. Math., 245(2):109–125, 2019.
  • [BP76] J. E. Baumgartner and K. Prikry. On a theorem of Silver. Discrete Math., 14(1):17–21, 1976.
  • [Buk65] L. Bukovský. The continuum problem and powers of alephs. Comment. Math. Univ. Carolinae, 6:181–197, 1965.
  • [DJt74] Keith J. Devlin and Hå vard Johnsbrå ten. The Souslin problem, volume Vol. 405 of Lecture Notes in Mathematics. Springer-Verlag, Berlin-New York, 1974.
  • [DS78] Keith J. Devlin and Saharon Shelah. A weak version of \diamondsuit which follows from 20<212^{\aleph_{0}}<2^{\aleph_{1}}. Israel J. Math., 29(2-3):239–247, 1978.
  • [Eas70] William B. Easton. Powers of regular cardinals. Ann. Math. Logic, 1:139–178, 1970.
  • [FW91] Matthew Foreman and W. Hugh Woodin. The generalized continuum hypothesis can fail everywhere. Ann. of Math. (2), 133(1):1–35, 1991.
  • [Gar17] Shimon Garti. Weak diamond and Galvin’s property. Period. Math. Hungar., 74(1):128–136, 2017.
  • [GH75] Fred Galvin and András Hajnal. Inequalities for cardinal powers. Ann. of Math. (2), 101:491–498, 1975.
  • [Jen72] R. Björn Jensen. The fine structure of the constructible hierarchy. Ann. Math. Logic, 4:229–308; erratum, ibid. 4 (1972), 443, 1972. With a section by Jack Silver.
  • [Mag77a] Menachem Magidor. On the singular cardinals problem. I. Israel J. Math., 28(1-2):1–31, 1977.
  • [Mag77b] Menachem Magidor. On the singular cardinals problem. II. Ann. of Math. (2), 106(3):517–547, 1977.
  • [She94] Saharon Shelah. Cardinal arithmetic, volume 29 of Oxford Logic Guides. The Clarendon Press Oxford University Press, New York, 1994. , Oxford Science Publications.
  • [Sil75] Jack Silver. On the singular cardinals problem. In Proceedings of the International Congress of Mathematicians (Vancouver, B.C., 1974), Vol. 1, pages 265–268. Canad. Math. Congr., Montreal, QC, 1975.