Vanishing theorems for Fano threefolds in positive characteristic
Abstract.
We prove that Kodaira vanishing holds for an arbitrary smooth Fano threefold in positive characteristic. To this end, we show that it is quasi--split when the Picard number or the Fano index is larger than one. We also establish Akizuki-Nakano vanishing for smooth Fano threefolds when the Picard number or the Fano index is larger than one, and therefore they lift to the ring of Witt vectors.
Key words and phrases:
Fano threefolds, (quasi-)-split, Kodaira vanishing2020 Mathematics Subject Classification:
14J45, 13A35, 14F171. Introduction
In the context of the minimal model program, Fano varieties play a significant role in the classification of algebraic varieties. The classification of Fano varieties in characteristic zero has a long history. In the early nineteenth century, Gino Fano established a partial classification result for smooth Fano threefolds, in order to attack the rationality problem of cubic threefolds. In 1980s, the classification of smooth Fano threefolds was carried out by Mori–Mukai ([MM81], [MM83]), based on earlier works by Iskovskih and Shokurov. Recently, this classification result has been extended to the case of positive characteristic [SB97, Meg98, FanoI, FanoII, FanoIII, FanoIV].
In this paper, our focus lies in vanishing theorems for them. Kodaira vanishing for Fano varieties is particularly crucial since their anti-canonical divisors are ample. For example, Kodaira vanishing implies for every nef divisor on a smooth Fano variety . From now on, we work over an algebraically closed field of characteristic . Let be a smooth Fano threefold over . Then, for an ample Cartier divisor , the vanishing has been proven by Shepherd-Barron and the first author [SB97], [Kaw2, Theorem 1.1] (cf. [FanoI, Theorem 2.4]). If for the Picard number and the index , then Kodaira vanishing is established in [FanoI, Corollary 4.5]. In this case, the vanishing is simple since can be written as . On the other hand, as the Picard number increases, the description of ample divisors become more complicated, making it harder to establish Kodaira vanishing.
To address this issue, we turn to -splitting, as it implies Kodaira vanishing. Consequently, investigating -splitting of smooth Fano threefolds leads us to our goal: Kodaira vanishing for smooth Fano threefolds. However, it is known that smooth del Pezzo surfaces of characteristic are not necessarily -split. Then, taking the product with , we can exhibit non--split smooth Fano threefolds. To overcome this issue, we shall use quasi--splitting, introduced by Yobuko [Yob19], which is a weaker condition than -splitting. Although quasi--splitting is not as restrictive as -splitting, quasi--split varieties satisfy various useful vanishing theorems including Kodaira vanishing.
Since every smooth del Pezzo surface is known to be quasi--split [KTTWYY1, Corollary 4.7], it is tempting to extend this result to smooth Fano threefolds. However, the Fermat quartic hypersurface is not quasi--split in characteristic three [KTY, Example 7.12]. Moreover, we find another non-quasi--split smooth Fano threefold, which is a weighted hypersurface in characteristic five. On the other hand, each of these examples satisfies . Hence it is natural to expect quasi--splitting for many smooth Fano threefolds such that or . In fact, we prove the following theorem.
Theorem A.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold over an algebraically closed field of positive characteristic. Then the following hold.
-
(1)
is quasi--split if or , where is the Picard number and denotes the index.
-
(2)
for every and every ample Cartier divisor .
Surprisingly, Theorem A asserts that Fano threefolds with wild conic bundle structures (i.e., conic bundles which are not generically smooth) are all quasi--split. These varieties are known to be non--split. Therefore, quasi--splitting is a notion which can be applicable to such pathological varieties in positive characteristic, allowing it to establish many useful vanishing theorems. This is a significant advantage of quasi--splitting.
1.1. Akizuki-Nakano vanishing
As another remarkable property of quasi--splitting, it is known that every quasi--split smooth variety lifts to together with an arbitarary effective Cartier divisor [AZ21], [KTTWYY1, Section 7.2]. From this, we can deduce the logarithmic Akizuki-Nakano vanishing if . Moreover, we can also prove the non-logarithmic Akizuki-Nakano vanishing holds for every . To summarise, we obtain the following theorem.
Theorem B.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold over an algebraically closed field of characteristic such that or . Then the following hold.
-
(1)
for every ample Cartier divisor and every pair of integers and satisfying .
-
(2)
Assume . Take a reduced divisor with simple normal crossing support and an ample -divisor such that the support of the fractional part of is contained in . Then
holds for every pair of integers and satisfying .
As an immediate consequence, we obtain the following theorem.
Theorem C.
Every smooth Fano threefold over an algebraically closed field of positive characteristic such that or lifts to the ring of Witt vectors.
1.2. -splitting
It is well known that smooth del Pezzo surfaces are -split if . Then it is natural ask when a smooth Fano threefold is -split. In the process of the proof of Theorem A, we show the following theorem.
Theorem D.
Every smooth Fano threefold over an algebraically closed field of characteristic such that or is -split.
Remark 1.1.
-splitting of some smooth Fano threefolds has been proven by Totaro in a different way [Totaro(Fano), the proof of Lemma 1.5].
Remark 1.2.
-
(1)
As mentioned above, if is a non--split del Pezzo surface, then is a smooth Fano threefold which is not -split. Since this construction can be applicable for , the assumption in Theorem D is optimal.
-
(2)
If , then the Fermat quartic hypersurface is not -split by Fedder’s criterion.
-
(3)
If , then we shall prove that there exists a smooth Fano threefold which is not -split (Example 8.4).
-
(4)
The authors do not know whether there exists a non--split smooth Fano threefold of characteristic .
1.3. Strategy of proofs
We now overview how to show that a smooth Fano threefold with is quasi--split (Theorem A(1)). In order to show that is quasi--split, we shall use one of the following strategies.
-
(A)
Inversion of adjunction for -splitting.
-
(B)
Inversion of adjunction for quasi--splitting.
-
(C)
Cartier operator criterion for quasi--splitting.
(A) For many cases (e.g., except for No. 3-10), we can prove that is -split. For example, let us consider the case when is of No. 2-30, i.e., there is a blowup along a smooth conic on . Take the plane containing . For the the proper transform of on , we have the following implications:
Of course, is -split. The implication (i) follows from the inversion of adjunction for -splitting, e.g., if is -split and is ample, then is -split. The equivalence (ii) is assured by . Finally, (iii) holds by definition.
(B) Even if the strategy (A) does not work, we can apply a quasi--split version of (A) for most of the remaining cases. The authors has proved that an inversion of adjunction for log Calabi-Yau pairs in [Kawakami-Tanaka(dPvar)]. This allows us to prove the following statement: a smooth Fano threefold is quasi--split if there are smooth prime divisors and such that and is a smooth curve which is quasi--split (Corollary 2.18).
As other technical issues, we shall encounter the following obstructions:
-
•
is not necessarily smooth. For some cases, the generic member is enough as a replacement (cf. Section 2.3). To this end, we shall need to treat algebraic varieties defined over an imperfect field.
-
•
If the first prime divisor is a smooth weak del Pezzo surface, then it is often hard to find such that is smooth. For example, if has no smooth member, then can not be smooth. In order to avoid such a pathological phenomenon, we shall establish some properties on weak del Pezzo surfaces, e.g., if is a surface over a -field of characteristic two and its base change is a Langer surface (defined as the base change of the blowup of along all the -rational points), then (Lemma 5.5).
(C) Except when is one of 2-2, 2-6, 2-8, and 3-10, we may apply one of (A) and (B). For these remaining cases, we shall apply a quasi--splitting criterion via Cartier operator, which has been established in [KTTWYY1, Theorem F] (cf. Proposition 2.20). To this end, we need to prove for suitable triples . Even if is explicitly given, it is often hard to compute such cohomologies directly. The main strategy is to embed into a (typically toric) fourfold , and apply Bott vanishing for . For example, if is of No. 2-2, then we can find such an embedding with . Although is not necessaliry toric for the other cases, we shall find a closed embedding to a fourfold which almost satisfies Bott vanishing. For more details on (C), see Section 6.
Acknowledgements. The authors express their gratitude to Burt Totaro for valuable comments. They also thank Teppei Takamatsu and Shou Yoshikawa for useful conversations. Kawakami was supported by JSPS KAKENHI Grant number JP22J00272. Tanaka was supported by JSPS KAKENHI Grant number JP22H01112 and JP23K03028.
2. Preliminaries
2.1. Notation
In this subsection, we summarise notation and basic definitions used in this article.
-
(1)
Throughout the paper, denotes a prime number and we set . Unless otherwise specified, we work over an algebraically closed field of characteristic . We denote by the absolute Frobenius morphism on an -scheme .
-
(2)
We say that is a variety (over a field ) if is an integral scheme that is separated and of finite type over . We say that is a curve (resp. surface, resp. threefold) if is a variety of dimension one (resp. two, resp. three).
-
(3)
For a variety , we define the function field of as the stalk at the generic point of .
-
(4)
We say that an -divisor on a normal variety is simple normal crossing if for every point , the local ring is regular and there exists a regular system of parameters of the maximal ideal of and such that .
-
(5)
Given an integral normal Noetherian scheme , a projective birational morphism is called a log resolution (of singularities) of if is regular and is a simple normal crossing divisor.
-
(6)
We say that an -scheme is -finite if the absolute Frobenius morphism is a finite morphism. We say that an -algebra is -finite if is -finite. In particular, a field is -finite if and only if . If is a variety over an -finite field, then is -finite.
-
(7)
Given a normal variety and an -divisor , we define the subsheaf of the constant sheaf on by the following formula
for every open subset of . In particular, .
-
(8)
Given a field and -schemes and , we say that is -isomorphic to if there exists an isomorphism over .
-
(9)
Given a closed subscheme of , we set for unless otherwise specified. Similarly, if is a closed subscheme of , then we define for .
-
(10)
Given a coherent sheaf and a Cartier divisor on a variety , we set unless otherwise specified. Note that (resp. ) does not mean (resp. ) even if is Cartier (cf. Subsection 2.2).
-
(11)
Given two closed subschemes and on a scheme , we denote by the scheme-theoretic intersection, i.e., .
2.2. Cartier operators
In this section, we recall the fundamental facts on the higher Cartier operators ([Ill79], [KTTWYY1]).
Let be a smooth variety over a perfect field of characteristic and a Cartier divisor on . The Frobenius pushforward of the de Rham complex
is a complex of -modules. Tensoring with , we obtain a complex
We define locally free -modules as follows.
We have an isomorphism
resulting from the Cartier isomorphism. In fact, tensoring with with the usual Cartier isomorphism
we obtain the above isomorphism.
Taking the Frobenius pushforward, we obtain
We denote by and the preimages of and by the above map. Inductively, we define locally -module and for all . Moreover, we set and .
Lemma 2.1.
Then we have the following exact sequences
(2.1.1) |
(2.1.2) |
for all and all .
Proof.
The assertion follows from [KTTWYY1, (5.7.1) and Lemma 5.8]. ∎
Remark 2.2.
Taking , we have the following exact sequence:
(2.2.1) |
(2.2.2) |
for all .
Remark 2.3.
Taking , we have short exact sequences
(2.3.1) |
(2.3.2) |
which coincides with [KTTWYY1, (2.15.1) and Lemma 2.16] respectively. Then we can confirm that
holds for all . In particular,
hold for all .
2.3. Generic members
Let be a regular projective variety over a field and let be a Cartier divisor on satisfying . For a base point free linear system and the corresponding linear subspace , the generic member of is defined by the following diagram:
where
-
(1)
denotes the universal family that parametrises all the members of ,
-
(2)
is the function field of the projective space and is the induced morphism.
Then the following hold.
-
(3)
is a purely transcendental extension of finite transcendence degree.
-
(4)
is a regular projective variety.
-
(5)
is a regular prime divisor [Tan-Bertini, Theorem 4.9(4)(12)].
For more details, we refer to [Tan-Bertini]. By abuse of notation, also is called the generic member when is a purely transcendental extension, because we shall encounter the situation as in the following remark.
Remark 2.4.
We now consider the case when we have two base point free linear systems and on . As above, we obtain two generic members on and on . For and , i.e., each of and is a transcendental basis, we set
For and ,
-
the sum is a simple normal crossing divisor.
The similar statement holds even if we start with finitely many base point free linear systems on , i.e., the sum
of the generic members is simple normal crossing, where and denotes the base change to .
Proof of .
Both and are clearly regular prime divisors. It suffices to show that the scheme-theoretic intersection is regular. For each , let be the Cartier divisor with and let be the -vector subspace corresponding to . Consider the restriction map:
Then the generic member coincides with the base change of the generic member of . Therefore, the intersection coincides with the generic member of by [Tan-Bertini, Proposition 5.10(2)], which is regular [Tan-Bertini, Theorem 4.9(4)]. ∎
2.4. -splitting criteria
Definition 2.5.
Let be a normal variety and let be an effective -divisor on .
-
(1)
We say that is -split if
splits as an -module homomorphism for every .
-
(2)
We say that is sharply -split if
splits as an -module homomorphism for some .
-
(3)
We say that is globally -regular if, given an effective -divisor , there exists such that
splits as an -module homomorphism.
We say that is -split (resp. globally -regular) if so is .
Remark 2.6.
We have the following implications:
where the former implication is clear and the latter one holds by the same argument as in [Sch08g]*Proposition 3.3. Moreover, if the condition () holds, then is sharply F-split if and only if is -split.
-
()
is a -divisor for some
In particular, is -split if and only if splits as an -module homomorphism. For more foundational properties, we refer to [SS10].
In what follows, we summarise some -splitting criteria, which are well known to experts.
Proposition 2.7.
Let be a birational morphism of normal projective varieties. Take an effective -divisor on such that is Cartier for some . Assume that the -divisor defined by is effective. Then is -split if and only if is -split.
Proof.
If is -split, then so is (take the pushforward). As for the opposite implication, the same argument as [HX15]*the first paragraph of the proof of Proposition 2.11 works. ∎
Proposition 2.8.
Let be an -finite field of characteristic . Let be a normal Gorenstein projective variety over . Take a normal prime Cartier divisor and an effective -Cartier -divisor on such that . Assume that
-
(1)
is -split, and
-
(2)
there exists such that is Cartier and
Then is -split.
Proof.
The same argument as in [CTW17, Lemma 2.7] works. ∎
Corollary 2.9.
Let be an -finite field of characteristic . Let be a normal Gorenstein projective variety over . Take a normal prime Cartier divisor such that is -split and is ample. Then is -split.
Proof.
By applying Proposition 2.8 with , it suffices to show that for , which follows from Serre vanishing. ∎
Remark 2.10.
In the setting of Corollary 2.9, even if is quasi--split, is not necessarily quasi--split [KTY, Example 7.7].
Corollary 2.11.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold over . Assume that there exist a field extension and effective divisors on such that
-
(1)
is an -finite field,
-
(2)
,
-
(3)
is a normal prime divisor,
-
(4)
is one-dimensional, smooth, and
-
(5)
is non-empty, zero-dimensional, and smooth over , and
-
(6)
(cf. Lemma 2.12).
Then is -split. In particular, is -split.
Proof.
First of all, we show that
(2.11.1) |
To this end, it suffices to prove and . The former one follows from (6). The latter one holds by
This completes the proof of (2.11.1).
By and (2.11.1), we obtain
Therefore, is a smooth projective curve. By (4) and (5), and are smooth over . In particular, for the algebraic closure of and some distinct points and . Then is -split.
Lemma 2.12.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold over and let be a field extension. Take a divisor on . Assume that one of the following conditions hold.
-
(1)
is nef and .
-
(2)
There exists a morphism such that and .
Then .
Proof.
Taking the base change to the algebraic closure of , we may assume that is algebraically closed. Then the problem is reduced to the case when . If (1) holds, then we may apply [Kaw1, Corollary 3.6]. If (2) holds, then we may assume that is a general fibre of , which is a prime divisor, and hence implies . ∎
Remark 2.13.
Let be an -finite field and let be a Gorenstein projective curve over . If is ample and there exists a Cartier divisor satisfying , then [Kol13, Lemma 10.6], and hence is -split.
Example 2.14.
If is a normal toric variety and is a torus-invariant reduced divisor, then is -split. This follows essentially from [Fuj07, 2.6] (cf. [Tan-toric, Proposition 2.17]).
Proposition 2.15.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold. Suppose that the following condition.
-
(1)
.
-
(2)
.
-
(3)
.
-
(4)
.
Then is -split.
Proof.
Firstly, the global -splitting of (i.e., splitting of ) is equivalent to the surjectivity of the evaluation map
By Grothendieck duality, they are equivalent to the injectivity of
Thus it suffices to show that . By (2.2.1) and (2), this vanishing can be reduced to . By (2.2.2), it is enough to prove
The latter one follows from (4) and Serre duality. It suffices to show the first one. By (2.2.1) and the condition (1), this vanishing is reduced to
By 2.2.2, it suffices to show
The first vanishing holds by and the ampleness of . The latter one follows from (3) and Serre duality. ∎
2.5. Quasi--splitting criteria
We recall that definition of -splitting and quasi--splitting. We refer to [Kawakami-Tanaka(dPvar), Section 3] for details.
Definition 2.16.
Let be a normal variety. We define a -module and a -module homomorphism by the following pushout diagram:
Applying to , we have a -module homomorphism
We say that is quasi--split if
is surjective.
Remark 2.17.
Let be a normal variety. Then is -split if and only if
is surjective for every , where . In particular, if is -split, then is quasi--split for every .
Corollary 2.18.
Let be an algebraically closed field of characteristic and let be a field extension, where is -finite. Let be a smooth Fano threefold over . Assume that there exist a prime divisor and a reduced divisor on such that
-
(a)
,
-
(b)
is regular, is smooth over , ,
-
(c)
, and
-
(d)
.
Then is -quasi--split for all .
Proof.
Set . We show that is weakly -quasi--split (see [Kawakami-Tanaka(dPvar), Definition 5.13] for the definition of weak quasi--splitting).
Since is ample, is connected, and hence . By [Kawakami-Tanaka(dPvar), Corollary 5.17], it is enough to show that is weakly -quasi--split. Again by [Kawakami-Tanaka(dPvar), Corollary 5.17], it suffices to prove that
-
(i)
is a prime divisor,
-
(ii)
, and
-
(iii)
is -quasi--split.
Consider an exact sequence
which induces the following one:
Then (ii) follows from
By the induced exact sequence
is a field. Since is smooth, we obtain (i). Let us show (iii). Since is a smooth projective curve over with , the base change to the algebraic closure of is an elliptic curve, which is 2-quasi--split ([KTTWYY1, Remark 2.11]). Thus so is [KTY, Proposition 2.12], and (iii) holds.
Now, we show that is quasi--split. Since is weakly -quasi--split it follows that is -quasi--split. By [KTY, Proposition 2.12], is -quasi--split. ∎
Remark 2.19.
The assumptions (c) and (d) automatically hold when and is connected. Indeed, we have an exact sequence for any reduced connected divisor on .
Although the following result is contained in [KTTWYY1, Theorem F], we include a proof for the reader’s convenience, as its proof is quite short.
Proposition 2.20.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold. Suppose that the following condition.
-
(1)
for all .
-
(2)
.
-
(3)
for all .
Then is quasi--split.
Proof.
It is enough to show that for some . By (2.1.1) and (2), it suffices to prove for some . By (2.1.2), this vanishing is reduced to
Repeating this procedure, the vanishing is reduced to
for every . Taking , we may assume by Serre vanishing. By (2.1.1) and (1), it suffices to show that for every . By Serre duality, we have
for every . By (2.1.2), the problem is finally reduced to for all . This holds because and is ample. ∎
2.6. Weak del Pezzo surfaces
In this subsection, we recall when canonical weal del Pezzo surfaces are -split.
Definition 2.21.
Let be a normal Gorenstein projective surface.
-
(1)
We say that is weak del Pezzo if is nef and big.
-
(2)
We say that is del Pezzo if is ample.
Theorem 2.22.
Let be a canonical weak del Pezzo surface. Then is -split if or .
Proof.
See [KT, Theorem A]. ∎
3. Fano threefolds with
Proposition 3.1.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold with . Then is quasi--split.
Proof.
In this case, for a smooth del Pezzo surface [FanoIV, Section 7.6]. Since is quasi--split and is -split, is quasi--split [KTY, Proposition 6.7]. ∎
Proposition 3.2.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold with . Then is -split.
Proof.
Recall that is of No. 5-1, 5-2, or 5-3 [FanoIV, Section 7.5]. If is 5-3, then for a smooth del Pezzo surface with , and hence -split (e.g. is toric, and hence so is ).
Assume that is 5-1. Then , where is a blowup of along a conic and are mutually distinct one-dimensional fibres of [FanoIV, Section 7.5]. Since the smallest linear subvariety of containing is a plane, we obtain for suitable hyperplanes and on . Set for each . We then get a scheme-theoretic equality . Note that each is a (possibly singular) quadric surface in , which is smooth along . It is easy to see that is effective for the divisor defined by , where denotes the induced birational morphism. It is enough to show that is -split (Proposition 2.7). Take a general hyperplane section . Since and all , and are smooth, is -split (Corollary 2.11), and hence is -split.
Assume that is No. 5-2. Then , where is a blowup of along a disjoint union of lines and , and and are mutually distinct one-dimensional fibres of lying over [FanoIV, Section 7.5]. Take two planes and on such that . Note that each is a smooth point. Pick a plane containing . Then it is easy to see that is effective for the divisor defined by . It is enough to show that is -split (Proposition 2.7). Pick a general hyperplane . Apply Corollary 2.11 by setting , and . Then is -split, and hence is -split. ∎
Proposition 3.3.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold with . Then is -split.
Proof.
We treat the following six cases separately:
-
(1)
4-4, 4-10, 4-12.
-
(2)
4-3, 4-6, 4-8, 4-13.
-
(3)
4-5, 4-7, 4-9, 4-11.
-
(4)
4-11.
-
(5)
4-2.
-
(6)
4-1.
(1) If is 4-4, then there is a smooth curve on such that the blowup of along is Fano [FanoIV, Proposition 5.31]. Since is -split (Proposition 3.2), so is . If is 4-10, then we can write for a smooth del Pezzo surface with [FanoIV, Section 7.4]. In this case, is clearly -split. Assume that is 4-12. Then we have , where is the blowup of along a line , and and are mutually disjoint one-dimensional fibres of the induced blowup . In this case, we can apply a similar argument to that of 5-2 in the proof of Proposition 3.2.
(2) Assume that is one of 4-3, 4-6, 4-8, 4-13. In this case, there is a blowup along a curve of tridegree for some [FanoIV, Section 7.4]. Let be the image of , which is a curve of bidegree . Then the induced morphism to the first direct product factor is an isomorphism. Hence . Set to be the inverse image of , which satisfies and . Then it is easy to see that is effective for the divisor defined by . It is enough to show that is -split (Proposition 2.7), which follows from the fact that is -split and is ample (Corollary 2.9).
(3) Assume that is one of 4-5, 4-7, 4-9. Let be the blowdown of the -curve and set . Then there is a blowup along a smooth curve lying over , where is disjoint from the -curve and is the inverse image of a line [FanoIV, Section 7.4]. Then the induced composite morphism
is the blowup along , where denotes the image of . In particular, we get for a line passing through . Then it is easy to see that is effective for the divisor defined by . It is enough to show that is -split (Proposition 2.7). This holds, because we may assume that is a torus-invariant reduced divisor on a toric variety .
(4) Assume that is 4-11. Then there is a blowup along , where for the -curve on and a closed point of [FanoIV, Section 7.4]. For the blowup , consider the composite birational morphism:
For the blowup centre of , pick two lines and on passing through . Then we have
where and denote the proper transforms of and , respectively. Since is contained in , we see that the divisor defined by is effective. Then is -split, because is -split (Proposition 2.7).
(5) Assume that is 4-2. Then is a blowup of along an elliptic curve on a section of the -bundle disjoint from the negative section of [FanoIV, Proposition 5.28]. Note that . We have that . Indeed, since is -numerically trivial, we can write for some Cartier divisor on . By restricting to , we obtain .
Then, the -divisor
is ample for . After perturbing , the problem is reduced to the case when is Cartier for some . Replacing by some , we may assume that . Since is sharply -split, is sharply -split (Proposition 2.8). Hence is -split.
(6) Assume that is 4-1. Then is a prime divisor on of multi-degree [FanoIV, Section 7.4]. For each , we set and , where and denote the the induced morphisms:
It holds that . Note that
Take the generic members of , where each is an effective Cartier divisor on for suitable purely transcendental field extension (Remark 2.4). Set . Then is smooth, because (Remark 2.13). By Corollary 2.11, is -split. ∎
4. Fano threefolds with (except for 3-10)
The purpose of this subsection is to prove that an arbitrary smooth Fano threefold with is -split except for 3-10 (Proposition 4.4). We start with some complicated cases: 3-1, 3-3 and 3-4.
Lemma 4.1.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold of No. 3-1. Then the following hold.
-
(1)
Let be a finite double cover such that . Then is separable, i.e., the induced field extension is separable.
-
(2)
is -split.
Proof.
Let us show (1). Set and . By [CD89, Proposition 0.1.2] and [Ful98, Lemma 3.2], it suffices to show that
Set for every , i.e.,
We have . Then the following holds (cf. [Har77, Appendix A, Section 3]):
Therefore, we get
as required. Thus (1) holds.
Let us show (2). There is a finite separable double cover as in (1) [FanoIII, Theorem 6.7]. Moreover, for each , the composition is the contraction of an extremal ray [FanoIII, Remark 6.8]. Since is separable, if are general members, then the scheme-theoretic intersection is reduced two points. Let be their generic members. Then the regular curve is automatically smooth (Remark 2.13). Then is -split (Corollary 2.11, Lemma 2.12). ∎
Lemma 4.2.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold of No. 2-18. Let and be the contractions of the extremal rays. Take a general point and a general line on . Then for the scheme-theoretic intersection .
Proof.
Set and . By [FS20, Theorem 15.2] and [BT22, Theorem 3.3], is a canonical del Pezzo surface. In particular, is a rational surface. Since [FanoIII, Proposition 5.9 and Section 9.2], the divisor is ample for the generic fibre of , where . Hence is ample, as is chosen to be a general fibre of . Therefore, by [CT19, Proposition 3.3] (or [Muk13, Theorem 3]), and hence . ∎
Lemma 4.3.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold of No. 3-3 or 3-4. Then is -split.
Proof.
For each case, has exactly three extremal rays and there is a conic bundle structure [FanoIV, Section 7.3]. In what follows, we shall use their properties obtained in [FanoIV, Propositions 4.33 and 4.35]. For each , let
be the induced composite contraction. Note that each corresponds to a two-dimensional extremal face of . Let be the contraction of the remaining two-dimensional extremal face of . For each , let be the pullback of the ample generator on . We recall ([FanoIV, Propositions 4.33 and 4.35]). In particular,
For each , denotes the generic member of , which is a regular prime divisor on for a suitable purely transcendental extension (Remark 2.4). Note that is a smooth curve, because is not wild [MS03, Corollary 8 and Remark 9].
We now finish the proof by assuming that
-
(i)
, and
-
(ii)
.
By Corollary 2.11 and Lemma 2.12, it suffices to find such that is smooth and zero-dimensional. Since is an infinite field and is isomorphic to a smooth conic on , the Bertini theorem enables us to find a smooth zero-dimensional effective Cartier divisor on such that . Therefore, it is enough to show that the restriction maps
are surjective. The restriction map is surjective, because
The problem is reduced to the surjectivity of . To this end, it suffices to prove . We have an exact sequence
By
(i) and (ii) imply . Therefore, it is enough to prove (i) and (ii).
Claim.
The following hold.
-
(1)
is a regular weak del Pezzo surface for every .
-
(2)
for every .
-
(3)
for every .
-
(4)
for .
-
(5)
and for every .
-
(6)
and .
-
(7)
Proof of Claim.
Since is the generic member of a base point free linear system , is a regular prime divisor on . If , then is ample, because is the generic fibre of . We see that is nef and big by and . Thus (1) holds. If , then (2) holds by the fact that is (a base change of) the generic fibre of a contraction . We have , because general members of the complete linear system are geometrically integral [FanoI, Proposition 2.10]. Thus, (2) holds.
Let us show (3). Consider an exact sequence
By (2) and Serre duality, we obtain and . Therefore, . Thus (3) holds.
Let us show (4). If , then by an exact sequence
where follows from Serre duality and . Similarly, by . Thus (4) holds.
Let us show (5). By an exact sequence
it suffices to prove , which follows from (4) by using . Thus (5) holds.
Let us show (6). Since has exactly three extremal rays, there is the extremal ray such that is the intersection of the extremal faces corresponding to and . Let be the contraction of . If is 3-3, then and and is isomorphic to the corresponding intersection on , because is disjoint from . Therefore, is geometrically integral. If is 3-4, then or is a smooth Fano threefold of No. 2-18. If , then is a smooth fibre of . The other case follows from Lemma 4.2 by using the upper semi-continuity [Har77, Ch. III, Theorem 12.8]. Thus (6) holds.
Let us show (7). We have
because and a fibre of is not contracted by for each . Fix a general member of . By Serre duality, it is enough to show for an effective Cartier divisor on . By (2), the problem is reduced to . Clearly, is nef. It holds that . Hence is nef and big. Then is a field [Eno, Corollary 3.17]. Since contains which is a -rational point by , we obtain field extensions
which implies , as required. This completes the proof of Claim. ∎
It is enough to show (i) and (ii). As (ii) has been settled by Claim(4), let us show (i). By and (Claim(2)(6)), we get by the following exact sequence:
By Serre duality, we get
We have the following exact sequences:
where the last equality follows from Claim (7). Thus . Similarly, we obtain . Thus (i) holds. ∎
Proposition 4.4.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold with .
-
(1)
If is not 3-10, then is -split.
-
(2)
Assume that is 3-10. Then is -split if and only if has no wild conic bunlde structure.
Proof.
We may assume that is none of 3-1, 3-3, and 3-4 (Lemma 4.1, Lemma 4.3). Note that if has a wild conic bundle structure, then is not -split [GLP15, Theorem 2.1 or Corollary 2.5]. In what follows, we assume that any conic bundle structure from is generically smooth. Under this additional assumption, it suffices to show that is -split. We divide the proof into the following four cases.
-
(1)
3-27, 3-28, 3-31.
-
(2)
3-5, 3-8, 3-12, 3-13, 3-15, 3-16, 3-17, 3-19, 3-20, 3-21, 3-22, 3-23, 3-24, 3-26, 3-29.
-
(3)
3-6, 3-10, 3-18, 3-25.
-
(4)
3-2, 3-7, 3-9, 3-11, 3-14, 3-30.
(1) In this case, is toric [FanoIV, Subsection 7.3], and hence -split.
(2) In this case, there exist a smooth Fano threefold with , a -bundle , and a subsection of such that , , and is one of 2-32, 2-34, 2-35 [FanoIV, Subsection 7.3, cf. Theorem 4.23]. Set , which is a -bundle over , and hence -split. Let be the pullback of the ample generator by the contraction of the other extremal ray . By [FanoIII, Proposition 5.9(3)], we can write , where is the length of . Then we can check that in each case [FanoIV, Subsection 7.2]. Thus is ample by Kleiman’s criterion. Therefore, is -split (Proposition 2.8), and hence is -split (Proposition 2.7).
(3) In this case, we can write or for a disjoint union of smooth curves and on or [FanoIV, Subsection 7.3]. We only treat the case when is 3-6, as the other cases are similar. In this case, , is a line, and we can write for some quadric surfaces and . Take a general plane containing the line and a general quadric surface containing . Let and be the proper transforms of and , respectively. Although and are not necessarily isomorphisms, these birational morphisms are isomorphic over . Therefore, we obtain . This is nothing but a general fibre of the contraction [FanoIV, Proposition 4.37]. Since this is not a wild conic bundle, we get . Then is -split by applying Proposition 2.8 twice. Hence is -split (Proposition 2.7).
(4) In what follows, we treat the remaining cases separately.
3-2: We use the same notation as in [FanoIV, Proposition 4.32]. We have and a conic bundle , where , and each is the pullback of by . Moreover is a finite double cover which can be written as for some double cover . For the generic member of , the intersection is a regular curve of genus zero with , because . By , we get . Hence is -split (Corollary 2.11).
3-7: In this case, is a blowup along an elliptic curve with [FanoIV, Subsection 7.3]. Let be a general member of containing . Since is an ample effective Cartier divisor on , it follows that is smooth along and is normal. Note that the proper transform of on is a fibre of a contraction . Therefore, the geometric generic fibre of is normal, where and denotes the algebraic closure of . Since is a regular del Pezzo surface, has at worst canonical singularities [BT22, Theorem 3.3]. Therefore, a general fibre of is a canonical del Pezzo surface. By , Theorem 2.22 shows that is -split. Since is ample, we have is -split (Proposition 2.8), and hence is -split (Proposition 2.7).
3-9: By [FanoIV, Proposition 4.42], there is a blowup along a smooth curve such that
-
•
is contained in a section of the -bundle structure , and
-
•
is disjoint from another section of .
Since is -bundle, we have . Since is ample for some and is -split, is -split (Proposition 2.8). Hence is -split (Proposition 2.7).
3-11: By [FanoIV, Subsection 7.3], there exists a blowup along an elliptic curve with . By the same argument as in that of 3-7, a general member of is a canonical del Pezzo surface with . Then is -split (Theorem 2.22). Since is ample, is -split (Proposition 2.8), and hence is -split (Proposition 2.7).
3-14: By [FanoIV, Subsection 7.3], we have , where is a smooth cubic curve contained in a plane and is a point satisfying . Take two distinct planes and containing . Then is -split, and hence so is (Proposition 2.7).
3-30: By [FanoIV, Subsection 7.3], there exist blowups
where is a blowup at a point and the blowup centre of is the proper transform of a line passing through . Take two planes containing . Then is F-split, and hence is F-split (Proposition 2.7). ∎
5. Fano threefolds with (except for 2-2, 2-6, 2-8)
5.1. Quasi--splitting (imprimitive case)
5.1.1. (imprimitive)
Proposition 5.1.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold with . If the types of the extremal rays are , then is quasi--split.
Proof.
In this case, is imprimitive [FanoIV, Subsection 7.2], i.e., the types of the extremal rays are . Let (resp. ) be the contraction of type (resp. type ). Let be the smooth curve on that is the blowup centre of , i.e., . By [FanoIV, Subsection 7.2], we may assume that one of the following holds.
-
(1)
(2-4, 2-25, 2-33).
-
(2)
, where is a smooth quadric hypersurface on (2-7, 2-29).
-
(3)
with , where is a smooth Fano threefold of index two satisfying (2-1, 2-3, 2-5, 2-10, 2-14).
Claim.
A general fibre of is a canonical del Pezzo surface.
Proof of Claim.
By [FS20, Theorem 15.2], the generic fibre of is geometrically normal, where denotes the function field of . Then its base change to the algebraic closure has at worst canonical singularities [BT22, Theorem 3.3]. Hence a general fibre of is normal and has at worst canonical singularities. This completes the proof of Claim. ∎
(1) Assume that . In this case, for some surfaces of degree , i.e., is 2-4 (), 2-25 (), or 2-33 (). Although might be singular, is a normal prime divisor on , because is smooth along an effective ample Cartier divisor . After replacing by a general member of the pencil generated by and , we may assume that is a canonical del Pezzo surface (Claim). If , then is -split (Theorem 2.22). Then is -split (Corollary 2.9), which implies that is -split (Proposition 2.7). We may assume that is a cubic surface, i.e., is 2-4. Recall that , where denotes the proper transform of and . Replacing and by general members of and , we obtain . Since is a general hyperplane section of a normal cubic surface , we have is an elliptic curve. Hence is quasi--split (Corollary 2.18, Remark 2.19).
(2) Assume that . In this case, for some surfaces with , i.e., is 2-29 (), or 2-7 . By Claim, is a canonical del Pezzo surface. We have
If , then , and thus is -split (Theorem 2.22). Then is -split (Corollary 2.9), which implies that is -split (Proposition 2.7). We may assume that , i.e., is 2-7. Set . Replacing and by general members of and , we obtain . Since is a general hyperplane section of a canonical del Pezzo surface of degree with , it follows that is an elliptic curve. Hence is quasi--split (Corollary 2.18, Remark 2.19).
(3) Assume that . In this case, is an elliptic curve which is a complete intersection of two prime divisors and , i.e., is 2-1, 2-3, 2-5, 2-10, or 2-14. We then get , where and and are the proper transforms of and , respectively. Fix general members and of containing . Let be the generic member of the pencil generated by and . Let be the function field of this pencil. For every -scheme , we set . Then and is the blowup along . Note that the proper transform is regular [Tan-Bertini, Theorem 4.9]. Since is smooth over , we conclude that is quasi--split (Corollary 2.18, Remark 2.19). ∎
5.1.2. (imprimitive)
Proposition 5.2.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold with . Assume that the types of the extremal rays are and . Then the following hold.
-
(1)
is quasi--split.
-
(2)
If is not 2-12, then is -split.
Proof.
Let be a contraction of type and let be the contraction of the other extremal ray, which is of type . Let (resp. ) be the ample Cartier divisor that generates (resp. ). Set and . The list of such smooth Fano threefolds is as follows [FanoIV, Subseciton 7.2]:
In particular, is , , or with . Then is very ample, and hence we may assume that is a smooth prime divisor on . Note that we have except when is 2-30 [FanoIII, Remark 3.4 and Proposition 5.9].
Step 1.
If is 2-15, 2-28, or 2-30, then is -split.
Proof of Step 1.
In this case, there is a blowup along a smooth curve such that is contained in a prime divisor on of degree ([FanoIII, Proposition 9.3], [FanoIV, Subsection 7.2]). Since is -split and is ample, it follows that is -split (Corollary 2.9), which implies that is -split (Proposition 2.7). This completes the proof of Step 1. ∎
Step 2.
If is 2-17 2-19, 2-21, 2-22, 2-23, or 2-26, then is -split.
Proof of Step 2.
Replace by a general member of . We now prove that is a smooth prime divisor that is -split. We first treat the case when is 2-17, 2-19, or 2-22. In this case, there is a blowup along a smooth curve of degree . For a general plane , its pullback is nothing but the blowup of along . Since is smooth and is nef and big, it follows that is a smooth weak del Pezzo surface. By , we have is -split [KT, Proposition 3.6]. For the the remaining case (i.e., is 2-21, 2-23, or 2-26), we can apply the same argument, because there is a blowup along a smooth curve of degree , and hence we may apply [KT, Proposition 3.6]. Therefore, is a smooth prime divisor which is -split.
In order to prove that is -split, it is enough to show that
for some by and Proposition 2.8. Set . By the Fujita vanishing theorem [Fuj17, Theorem 3.8.1], we can find and such that
for every integer . Indeed, we can find such that is ample. Then, by Fujita vanishing, there exists such that
for any nef Cartier divisor on . Then we take and satisfying .
Recall that is ample for some and satisfies the Kodaira vanishing theorem (for Cartier divisors), because is a smooth projective surface with negative Kodaira dimension or a singular quadric surface [FanoIII, Definition 3.3]. Hence, for each , we can find such that
for every . Set
It suffices to prove
for every . By descending induction on , this follows from
This completes the proof of Step 2. ∎
Step 3.
If is 2-12, then is quasi--split.
Proof of Step 3.
In this case, the contraction of each extrmeal ray is a blowup of along a smooth curve of degree [FanoIV, Subsection 7.2]. As in the argument in Step 2, replacing and by general members of and respectively, we may assume that and are smooth weak del Pezzo surfaces with .
We now finish the proof by assuming that the restriction map
is surjective. Since a general member of is an elliptic curve [KN, Theorem 1.4] and is a general member in , it follows that is an elliptic curve. Therefore, is quasi--split by Corollary 2.18.
It suffices to show that is surjective. By an exact sequence
it is enough to prove that . Note that
Since is a smooth rational surface and is nef and big, we have for by [Muk13, Theorem 3]. Thus, we have a surjection
for every integer . Since we have , using the above surjectivity for , we obtain . This completes the proof of Step 3. ∎
5.1.3. Langer surface
Definition 5.3.
-
(1)
For all the -points , we set
For a field of characteristic two, we set , which is called the Langer surface over .
-
(2)
For a field of characteristic two and a zero-dimensional closed subscheme of , we say that is a Langer configuration if is -isomorphic to the Langer surface over .
Lemma 5.4.
Let be an algebraically closed field of characteristic two. Take a Langer configuration . Then there exists a -automorphism such that , where
Proof.
Fix a -isomorphism . We have two birational contractions
where (resp. ) is the blowup along (resp. ). Recall that the Langer surface has exactly -curves ([CT18, Theorem 5.4] or [KN, Lemma 4.5(4)]). Then both and contracts all the -curves on and . Therefore, we obtain a -automorphism which completes the following commutative diagram:
This diagram shows that . ∎
Lemma 5.5.
Let be a -field of characteristic two and take its algebraic closure . Let be a smooth projective surface over whose base change is -isomorphic to the Langer surface over . Then the following hold.
-
(1)
If is perfect, then is -isomorphic to the Langer surface over .
-
(2)
.
Proof.
We now show the implication (1) (2). Set to be the purely inseparable closure of in , i.e.,
Note that is a -field, because being is stable under algebraic extensions [GS17, Definition 6.2.1 and Lemma 6.2.4]. Therefore, (1) is applicable to the perfect -field and the base change . Therefore, is the Langer surface over , and hence . Since the field extension is purely inseparable, it holds that [Tan18b, Proposition 2.4]. This completes the proof of the implication (1) (2).
It suffices to show (1). Assume that is perfect. Recall that contains the exactly -curves . Set and . We now show that
-
(i)
there is an invertible sheaf on such that , where is the natural morphism and
-
(ii)
there exists an effective Cartier divisor on such that and the equality of Weil divisors holds.
Let us show (i). By and [GS17, Proposition 6.2.3], we obtain [FanoII, Proposition 2.3] (essentially due to [CTS21, Proposition 5.4.2]). Then it holds that
for every , and hence for some . Thus (i) holds. Let us show (ii). By the flat base change theorem, we obtain
which implies . In particular, there exists an effective Cartier divisor on such that and . Thus (ii) holds.
Since is smooth, so is (note that might be irreducible, although is not). Let be the contraction of , where is a smooth projective surface over . Then its base change to is the birational contraction of , i.e., . By , we get a -isomorphism [CTS21, Proposition 7.1.6]. Via this isomorphism, we identify and (resp. and ):
Recall that is the blowup along some closed subscheme on [Har77, Ch. II, Theorem 7.17]. Since blowups commutes with flat base changes [Liu02, Section 8, Proposition 1.12(c)], is the blowup along the base change . Since is a zero-dimensional reduced scheme consisting of points, is a smooth zero-dimensional closed subscheme of satisfying .
Set , which is the Hilbert scheme of that parametrises the zero-dimensional closed subschemes satisfying . Let be its universal family (cf. [FGI05, Section 5]): . Let be the subset consisting of the Langer configurations over (Definition 5.3(2)). Set , which is an algebraic group over . By Lemma 5.4, is equal to the -orbit of , where
Recall that the -orbit is a locally closed subset of [Mil16, Proposition 1.65(b)]. Since is irreducible, so is . There exists an integral locally closed subscheme of whose set of the -valued points coincides with . Set . We have the Langer configuration as the fibre of over :
Since equivariantly acts on , we have the orbits
of the above points . Since each is a locally closed subset, this is a subvariety (integral scheme). Since any fibre of is geometrically reduced, it follows that is reduced. Therefore, we get a scheme-theoretic equality
because we have the corresponding set-theoretic equality.
Note that corresponds to a -rational point such that the corresponding -rational point is contained in . Then the image
is contained in the Langer locus (over ). Therefore, is obtained by a base change of
and hence must be split up into distinct points. ∎
5.1.4. (imprimitive)
Proposition 5.6.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold such that and the types of the extremal rays are . Then the following hold.
-
(1)
is quasi--split.
-
(2)
If is not 2-9, then is -split.
Proof.
Let (resp. ) be the contraction of the extremal ray of type (resp. ). Let be a general member of and let be a general member of , where denotes the ample generator of . Since , or with [FanoIV, Subsection 7.2], the complete linear system is very ample. Note that is the blowup of a smooth surface along the zero-dimensional smooth closed subscheme , and hence is a smooth prime divisor. We have that
for the length of the extremal ray of type [FanoIII, Proposition 5.9], i.e., if is of type with , then . Note that is nef and [FanoIII, Lemma 5.3 and Proposition 5.9(2)].
Step 1.
If is of type , then is -split.
Proof of Step 1.
Assume that is of type . In this case, is 2-27 or 2-31 [FanoIV, Subsection 7.2]. If is 2-27 (resp. 2-31), then for (resp. ), where is a smooth curve of degree (resp. ). Recall that . We then get in both cases. Since we have
it follows that is a smooth del Pezzo surface with (resp. ). Since is ample, so is . Thus is -split (Theorem 2.22). Therefore, is -split (Corollary 2.9). This completes the proof of Step 1. ∎
Step 2.
Assume that is of type . Then the following hold.
-
(i)
and is a smooth weak del Pezzo surface.
-
(ii)
The induced composite morphism
coincides with the morphism induced by the complete linear system . Moreover, is a generically finite morphism of degree two.
-
(iii)
If there exists a smooth prime divisor on satisfying , then is quasi--split.
Proof of Step 2.
It holds that
Thus (i) holds.
Let us show (ii). We have that . The Riemann–Roch theorem, together with (i), implies . By , the composition coincides with the morphism induced by the complete linear system . In particular, is a generically finite morphism of degree two. Thus (ii) holds.
Let us show (iii). By (ii), we have the induced isomorphism:
via , i.e., is bijective. By our assumption, there exists a line such that is a smooth prime divisor. This property holds even after replacing by a general member of , and hence we may assume that . We then obtain , which is a smooth elliptic curve. By , is quasi--split (Corollary 2.18). Thus (iii) holds. This completes the proof of Step 2. ∎
Step 3.
Assume that is of type . Then there exists a smooth prime divisor on satisfying .
Proof of Step 3.
Recall that is a general member of . Suppose that any member of is singular. By Step 2(iii), it is enough to derive a contradiction. Note that, for every line on and every smooth member , its intersection is not smooth (Step 2(ii)).
We now show that every smooth member of is isomorphic to the Langer surface over (Definition 5.3). The Stein factorisation of the composition is the anti-canonical model of (Step 2(ii)). Note that each fibre of is contained in a fibre of , which is a conic. In particular, any singularity on is either or . By (Step 2(i)) and [KN, Theorem 1.4], it holds that and is isomorphic to the Langer surface.
Fix two general members and of . In particular, is a smooth curve and each of and is isomorphic to the Langer surface. Let be the blowup along , and hence we get the morphism induced by the pencil generated by and , where , which coincides with the proper transform of on . By construction, every general fibre of is isomorphic to the Langer surface (as otherwise we could find a smooth member of which is not the Langer surface). Set to be the generic fibre of , where .
For the algebraic closure of , it is enough to show, by Lemma 5.5, that the base change is isomorphic to the Langer surface over . In fact, this implies , which is a contradiction. Fix a general fibre of . Let be all the -curves on ( is called a -curve if and ). Since can be defined around the generic point of the base and is general, we obtain the corresponding -curves on . By the invariance of intersection numbers for flat families, we see that for every . Since is the Langer surface over , there are exactly -curves and they are mutually disjoint [CT18, Theorem 5.4]. Then we see that and (i.e., ) for every . As has no smooth member, neither does . By [KN, Theorem 1.4], we get , i.e., is isomorphic to the Langer surface over . This completes the proof of Step 3. ∎
5.2. Quasi--splitting (primitive case)
In Section 5.1, the quasi--splitting for smooth Fano threefolds with has been settled for the imprimitive case. Hence the remaining cases are as follows [FanoIV, Subsection 7.2]:
In what follows, we shall settle the cases except for 2-2, 2-6, and 2-8. These cases will be treated in Section 6.
Lemma 5.7.
If is a smooth Fano threefold of No. 2-32, 2-34, 2-35, or 2-36, then is -split.
Proof.
It is well known that is toric except when it is 2-32. Assume that is 2-32, i.e., is a smooth hypersurface on of bidegree . Note that is a -bundle [FanoIV, Subsection 7.2]. Take a general member , which is a -bundle over . Hence is -split. As in the proof of Proposition 4.4(2), we can see is ample by [FanoIII, Proposition 5.9(3)] and [FanoIV, Section 7.2]. Therefore, is -split (Corollary 2.9). ∎
Lemma 5.8.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold of No. 2-18. Then the following hold.
-
(1)
is -split.
-
(2)
Let be a smooth fibre of the contraction of type . Then the blowup of along is a smooth Fano threefold of No. 3-4.
The following argument is almost identical to that of [FanoIV, Proposition 4.35].
Proof.
By Proposition 4.4, (2) implies (1). Let us show (2). It is enough to show that is ample [FanoIV, Subsection 7.2]. By construction, we have the following commutative diagram except for . Since is not a finite morphism, its Stein factorisation of is not an isomorphism. We get , because we have , and is not an isomorphism. Then is a contraction of a (possibly non -negative) extremal ray. Since this extramal ray is contained in the two-dimensional extremal faces corresponding to and , is generated by three extremal rays, which are corresponding to .
By the same argument as in [FanoIV, Proposition 4.35], we obtain
where each is the pullback of the ample generator by . Since is a finite morphism, is ample, as required. ∎
Lemma 5.9.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold of No. 2-24. Assume that the contraction of type is generically smooth. Then the following hold.
-
(1)
is -split.
-
(2)
Let be a smooth fibre of . Then the blowup of along is a Fano threefold of No. 3-4.
The following argument is almost identical to that of [FanoIV, Proposition 4.40].
Proof.
Since (2) implies (1), it is enough to show (2). Let us show (2). It is enough to show that is ample [FanoIV, Subsection 7.2]. By construction, we get the following commutative diagram except for . By the same argument as in [FanoIV, Proposition 4.40], we see that
-
•
is not a finite morphism, and
-
•
,
where each is the pullback of the ample generator by . Then has exactly three extremal rays and is ample.
∎
Lemma 5.10.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold of No. 2-24. Assume that the contraction of type is not generically smooth. Then the following hold.
-
(1)
is isomorphic to , where and .
-
(2)
is quasi--split.
Proof.
Since (1) implies (2) [KTY, Example 7.13], it is enough to show (1). Recall that can be written as follows:
Since every fibre of is a non-reduced conic, we can write
where each is a homogeneous polynomial of degree . We see that
-
none of is zero.
Indeed, if , then the affine open subset of defined by contains a singular point. After applying a suitable coordinate change, we may assume that . Therefore, we can write
We can write . By applying , we may assume that . Note that implies . Replacing by , we may assume that , i.e.,
Similarly, by applying a coordinate change for some , the problem is reduced to the case when for some . By , we may assume that . Thus (1) holds. ∎
Remark 5.11.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold of No. 2-24. Combining Lemma 5.9, Lemma 5.10, and [KTY, Example 7.13], is -quasi--split. Moreover, the following hold.
-
(1)
The following are equivalent.
-
(a)
The quasi--split height is , i.e., is -split.
-
(b)
The contraction of type is generically smooth.
-
(a)
-
(2)
The following are equivalent.
-
(a)
The quasi--split height is .
-
(b)
The contraction of type is not generically smooth (called wild).
-
(c)
.
-
(a)
Proposition 5.12.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold with . Then is quasi--split if is none of 2-2, 2-6, and 2-8.
5.3. -splitting
Theorem 5.13.
Assume . Let be a smooth Fano threefold with . If is neither 2-2 nor 2-6, then is -split.
Proof.
By Proposition 3.1, Proposition 3.2, Proposition 3.3, and Proposition 4.4, we may assume that . The types of the extremal rays and are as follows, because the case does not occur [FanoIV, Subsection 7.2]:
-
(I)
or .
-
(II)
.
-
(III)
.
-
(IV)
.
For each , let be the contraction of , denotes the length of , and set to be the pullback of the ample generator of . Recall that we can write [FanoIII, Proposition 5.9]. In what follows, we treat the above four cases separately.
(I) Since is or , we have or . Pick a general member of .
Claim.
is a canonical weak del Pezzo surface.
Proof of Claim.
We first treat the case when . Let be the geometric generic fibre of . Then is normal and is ample [FS20, Theorem 15.2], which implies that is canonical [BT22, Theorem 3.3]. Hence is a canonical del Pezzo surface for the case when .
It is enough to settle the case when . In this case, is the inverse image of a general line on . Since the discriminant scheme of is a reduced divisor [Tan-conic, Proposition 7.2], the scheme theoretic intersection is a zero-dimensional smooth scheme. For the resulting conic bundle , we have [Tan-conic, Remark 3.4]. Since and are smooth, also is smooth [Tan-conic, Theorem 4.4]. We have that for . In particular, and are nef and big. By the adjunction formula: , we have is a smooth weak del Pezzo surface. This completes the proof of Claim. ∎
By Claim, is -split (Theorem 2.22). We have for . By and Proposition 2.8, it is enough to find such that
by. Fix such that is ample for . By the Serre vanishing theorem, there is such that . Set . It suffices to prove
for every by descending induction on . The base case has been checked already. Fix an integer satisfying . By the induction hypothesis, we have the following exact sequence
It suffices to show . Note that is ample, because so are and ). Then we get by the fact that is toric or a smooth ruled surface [Muk13, Theorem 3].
(II) Assume that is . The list of such Fano threefolds is as follows [FanoIV, Subsection 7.2]: 2-12, 2-15 2-17, 2-19, 2-21, 2-22, 2-23, 2-26, 2-28, 2-30. We treat the following two cases separately:
-
(1)
2-12, 2-15, 2-17, 2-19, 2-22, 2-28, 2-30.
-
(2)
2-21, 2-23, 2-26.
If (1) (resp. (2)) holds, then there is a blowup (resp. ) along a smooth curve on . Note that is the inverse image of the corresponding member on . After replacing by a general member of , we may assume that is the blowup along a smooth zero-dimensional scheme of a smooth surface , and hence is a smooth projective surface. We have that for some with nef. Then it holds that is nef and big. Hence is a smooth weak del Pezzo surface. The same argument as in (I) deduces that is -split.
(III) Assume that the types of the extremal rays are . Since we are assuming that is not 2-2, is 2-18 or 2-34 [FanoIV, Subsection 7.2]. If is 2-34, i.e., ), then is clearly -split. The case when is 2-18 has been settled in Lemma 5.8.
6. -splitting and Quasi--splitting via Cartier operators
6.1. Quasi--splitting for 2-2, 2-6, 2-8, and 3-10
6.1.1. Preparation
Lemma 6.1.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold. Assume that is SRC. Then for every and every pseudo-effective Cartier divisor on .
For the definition of SRC (separable rational connectedness), we refer to [Kol96].
Proof.
The assertion follows from the essentially same proof as in [Kaw1, Proposition 3.4] by using the fact that the restriction of a pseudo-effective Cartier divisor to a general curve is pseudo-effective. ∎
We repeatedly use the following basic lemma.
Lemma 6.2.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold. Assume that there exists a conic bundle , i.e., is a flat morphism to a smooth projective surface such that every fibre is isomorphic to a conic (cf. [Tan-conic, Definition 2.3]). Then the following hold.
-
(1)
is SRC.
-
(2)
for every and every pseudo-effective Cartier divisor on .
In particular, if is one of No. 2-2, 2-6, 2-8, and 3-10, then satisfies the condition (1) in Proposition 2.20.
Proof.
Since (1) implies (2) (Lemma 6.1), it is enough to show (1). If is generically smooth, then is a smooth rational surface [FanoIV, Proposition 3.13], and hence is SRC by [GLP15, Theorem 0.5]. We may assume that is wild, i.e., not generically smooth. Then is 2-24 or 3-10 by [MS03, Corollary 8]. Assume that is 2-24. Then the contraction of the other extremal ray is of type and its contraction gives a generically smooth conic bundle structure. We are done by the generically smooth case. Assume that is 3-10. Then is obtained as a blowup of (cf. [MS03, Corollary 8] or [FanoIV, Section 7]). Since is rational (and hence SRC), so is . Thus (1) holds. ∎
6.3Double covers.
Given smooth projective varieties and , we say that is a double cover if is a finite surjective morphism such that the induced field extension is of degree . Recall that we have an exact sequence
for some Cartier divisor on [Kaw2, Lemma A.1]. In particular, . Moreover, [CD89, Proposition 0.1.3]. We say a double cover is split if the induced homomorphism splits as an -module homomorphism (i.e., the above exact sequence splits). In this case, we obtain .
Lemma 6.4.
Let be a split double cover of smooth projective varieties. Let be a Cartier divisor on satisfying (cf. (6.3)). Then there exists a closed immersion which satisfies the following properties.
-
(1)
, where denotes the induced -bundle.
-
(2)
For the section of corresponding to the second projection , it holds that , , , and ,
-
(3)
For the section of corresponding to the first projection , it holds that , , , , and .
-
(4)
.
Proof.
In what follows, we only treat the case when , as otherwise the problem is easier. By [CD89, the proof of Proposition 0.1.3] (note that splits if and only if corresponds to a splittable admissible triple), there is a closed immersion to the -bundle
Since is an open subscheme of , we obtain a closed immersion over . By definition, we get , , and , where denotes for by abuse of notation. We can write for some Cartier divisors and on . By and , we obtain , which implies . Similarly, we obtain by . Hence we get
which implies
Claim.
The following hold.
-
(a)
.
-
(b)
.
-
(c)
.
Proof of Claim.
Let us show (c)’ below, which is weaker than (c):
-
(c)’
, where denotes the numerical equivalence.
Since is a double cover, we can find a Cartier divisor on such that . Then
which implies [Kle66, Corollary 1(ii) in page 304]. Thus (c)’ holds.
The assertion (a) holds by the following (cf. [FanoIII, Proposition 7.1(2)]):
Let us show (b). By (a) and (c)’, we obtain . This, together with , implies . By , we obtain , as otherwise we could find a curve on which properly intersects . Thus (b) holds. Then it holds that
which implies , i.e., (c) holds. This completes the proof of Claim. ∎
We can write for some Cartier divisor on . By , we obtain . Then . This completes the proofs of (2) and (3).
Let us show (4). We have an exact sequence
where the injectivity of can be checked by taking the corresponding sequence of the stalks at the generic point. Taking the wedge products, we get . By and , we obtain
Thus (4) holds. ∎
Lemma 6.5.
We use the same notation as Lemma 6.4. Fix and take a Cartier divisor on . Assume that
-
(1)
, and
-
(2)
.
Then .
Proof.
We have an exact sequence
By (2), it is enough to show , i.e., . Using an exact sequence twice, it suffices to prove that and with . By , these equalities follow from (2) and (1), respectively. ∎
Proposition 6.6.
We use the same notation of Lemma 6.4. Assume that , and both and are ample. Moreover, suppose that the following hold.
-
(0)
-
(0a)
for every and every ample Cartier divisor on .
-
(0b)
for every .
-
(0c)
for every .
-
(0a)
-
(1)
-
(1a)
for every .
-
(1b)
.
-
(1c)
for every and every .
-
(1a)
-
(2)
for every .
Then the following hold.
-
(I)
.
-
(II)
for every .
-
(III)
is quasi--split.
Proof.
By (2) and Proposition 2.20, (I) and (II) imply (III). In what follows, we shall prove (I) and (II). Note that we can write for , and hence is ample.
Step 1: Proof of (I). By the conormal exact sequence, we have an exact sequence
where . It follows from , , and that
Thus it suffices to show .
By , , and , we have the following exact sequence:
Thus, in order to prove (I), it is enough to show
-
(i)
and
-
(ii)
.
Step 1-1: Proof of (i). We have the following exact sequence:
It holds that
Then it suffices to show . Using an exact sequence twice, the vanishing can be reduced, by , to those of
-
•
for and
-
•
.
Both of them follow from (1a). Thus (i) holds.
Step 1-2: Proof of (ii). In order to show (ii), it is enough to verify the assumptions of Lemma 6.5 for the case when and . The conditions Lemma 6.5(1) and Lemma 6.5(2) hold by (0a) and (1b), respectively. This completes the proofs of (ii) and (I).
Step 2: Proof of (II). Fix . By the conormal exact sequence, we have the following exact sequence:
It follows from , , and that
Thus it suffices to show .
We get
because Lemma 6.5, for the case when and , is applicable by (0b) and (1c). Since and , we have the following exact sequence:
Thus it suffices to show that
By and an exact sequence , the problem is reduced to
-
•
for and
-
•
.
The second vanishing has been settled already. Thus it suffices to show the first one. Fix . By the conormal exact sequence, we have the following exact sequence
It follows from that
Then we are done by . ∎
6.1.2. 2-2
Lemma 6.7.
A smooth Fano threefold of No. 2-2 satisfies the following properties:
-
(1)
There is a split double cover .
-
(2)
for a Cartier divisor satisfying .
-
(3)
is (isomorphic to) a divisor on .
-
(4)
and , where and denotes the projection.
-
(5)
There exists a section of such that , , , , and .
-
(6)
There exists a section of such that , , , , and .
Proof.
The assertions (1) and (2) follow from [FanoIII, Subsection 9.2]. Then the remaining ones hold by Lemma 6.4. ∎
Lemma 6.8.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold of No. 2-2. Then the following hold.
-
(1)
.
-
(2)
for every .
-
(3)
is quasi--split.
Proof.
We use the same notation as Lemma 6.7. It is enough to verify the conditions of Proposition 6.6 for , and . Note that is ample when . By Lemma 6.2, Proposition 6.6(2) holds. Since satisfies Kodaira vanishing, it is easy to see that Proposition 6.6(0) holds. As satisfies Bott vanishing, it is obvious that Proposition 6.6(1) holds. ∎
6.1.3. 2-6-a
Definition 6.9.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold of No. 2-6. By [FanoIV, Section 7.2], one of the following holds up to isomorphisms.
-
(2-6-a)
is a hypersurface of of bidegree . In this case, , where . In this case, we say that is (a Fano threefold) of No. 2-6-a.
-
(2-6-b)
There is a split double cover satisfying , where is a Cartier divisor on with . In this case, we say that is (a Fano threefold) of No. 2-6-b.
Lemma 6.10.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold of No. 2-6-a. Then the following hold.
-
(1)
for and .
-
(2)
for .
Proof.
Use an exact sequence . ∎
Lemma 6.11.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold of No. 2-6-a. Then the following hold.
-
(1)
.
-
(2)
for every .
-
(3)
is quasi--split.
Proof.
We use the notation of Definition 6.9. By Proposition 2.20 and Lemma 6.2, it suffices to show (1) and (2).
Step 1: Proof of (1). By the conormal exact sequence, we have the following exact sequence:
Since we have
by Lemma 6.10, it suffices to show .
We have the following exact sequence:
By Bott vanishing, we have
-
•
and
-
•
.
Therefore, (1) holds.
Step 2: Proof of (2). Fix . By the conormal exact sequence, we have the following exact sequence
We have
by Lemma 6.10. Thus, it suffices to show .
We have the following exact sequence:
Then
-
•
by Bott vanishing and
-
•
by [Totaro(Fano), Proposition 1.3].
Therefore, the assertion holds. ∎
6.1.4. 2-6-b
Lemma 6.12.
A smooth Fano threefold of No. 2-6-b satisfies the following properties:
-
(1)
There is a split double cover , where is a smooth hypersurface of of bidegree .
-
(2)
for a Cartier divisor .
-
(3)
is a divisor of .
-
(4)
, .
-
(5)
There exists a section of such that , , , , and .
Proof.
The assertions (1) and (2) follow from [FanoIII, Subsection 9.2]. Then the remaining ones hold by Lemma 6.4. ∎
Lemma 6.13.
Let (resp. , resp. ), where is a smooth quadric hypersurface of and is a smooth hypersurface of of bidegree . Let (resp. , resp. ). Then the following hold.
-
(1)
for .
-
(2)
for .
-
(3)
for .
-
(4)
for .
-
(5)
for .
-
(6)
for .
-
(7)
for .
Proof.
Since is -split (Lemma 5.7), (1)-(3) hold. The assertions (4) and (7) follow from the fact that is SRC (Lemma 6.2). Let us prove (5) and (6). If , then these follow from the Bott vanishing theorem and [Totaro(Fano), Proposition 1.3]. In what follows, we assume . If (resp. ), then
-
•
we have an embedding for (resp. ),
-
•
we set (resp. ), and
-
•
we get for (resp. ). It holds that .
We have the following exact sequence:
By Bott vanishing and [Totaro(Fano), Proposition 1.3], we have
-
•
for ,
-
•
for , and
-
•
for .
We then get
-
•
for and
-
•
for .
By and the conormal exact sequence, we have the following exact sequence:
Recall that
-
•
for and
-
•
for .
Hence we get
-
(5)’
for and
-
(6-a)
for .
In particular, (5) holds. Comparing (6) with (6-a), it suffices to show (6-b) below by Serre duality.
-
(6-b)
for .
Taking the wedge product to the conormal exact sequence, we get the following exact sequence:
Since we have for (6-a), it is enough to prove for . This holds by an exact sequence
because Bott vanishing implies for and . ∎
Lemma 6.14.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold of No. 2-6-b. Then the following hold.
-
(1)
.
-
(2)
for every .
-
(3)
is quasi--split.
Proof.
The above argument can be applied for some hyperelliptic Fano threefolds. Let us start by recalling the definition.
Definition 6.15.
We say that a smooth Fano threefold is hyperelliptic if is of index one, is base point free, and the induced morphism is a double cover.
It is known that if , then is isomorphic to or in the above notation [FanoI, Theorem 6.5]. The assumption in Proposition 6.16(i) is sharp as we shall see later (Example 8.7).
Proposition 6.16.
Let be a hyperelliptic smooth Fano threefold such that . Let be the double cover induced by . Assume the following.
-
(i)
If , then .
-
(ii)
If , then .
Then the following hold.
-
(1)
.
-
(2)
for every .
-
(3)
is quasi--split.
Proof.
We have for a Cartier divisor , where denotes the index of (i.e., if (resp. ), then (resp. )). It is enough to verify the conditions in Proposition 6.6. Note that we have and . Then Lemma 6.2 and Lemma 6.13 imply all the conditions in Proposition 6.6 except for Proposition 6.6(0c). By our assumptions (i) and (ii), Proposition 6.6(0c) directly follows from Serre duality, e.g.,
for every . ∎
6.1.5. 2-8
Lemma 6.17.
A smooth Fano threefold of No. 2-8 satisfies the following properties:
-
(1)
is (isomorphic to) a divisor on .
-
(2)
, , and .
-
(3)
is base point free and is big.
-
(4)
Let be the birational morphism to a normal projective variety such that and for some ample invertible sheaf on . Then is a small birational morphism which is an isomorphism around .
We say that a birational morphism is small if .
Proof.
Note that a Fano threefold of No. 2-8 is characterised by the following properties (i) and (ii) [FanoIII, Theorem 5.34]:
-
(i)
is a Fano threefold with .
-
(ii)
One of the extremal rays is of type , and the the other extremal ray is of type or .
Then we may apply [FanoIII, Proposition 5.29 and Lemma 5.30]. By [FanoIII, Proposition 5.29(3), Lemma 5.30], is a divisor on satisfying . Thus (1) holds. Moreover, [FanoIII, the proof of Lemma 5.30] implies that . Then the adunction formula implies . Thus (2) holds.
Let us show (3) and (4). We have three sections of the induced -bundle , where . corresponding to the projections of to the factors , respectively. Similarly, we have the following three prime divisors which are -bundles over :
-
•
, corresponding to .
-
•
, corresponding to .
-
•
, corresponding to .
By construction, we have for every . Fix a line on and set , which is a prime divisor on . For each , we can write for some . It holds that
i.e., . Then we have that
By , is base point free. Since is relatively ample over and is the pullback of an ample divisor, the divisor is big. Thus (3) holds. Let be as in the statement of (4).
We now show that . By , is a point. In particular, . Pick a curve such that is a point. It suffices to show . We have . Note that is not a point, because is -ample. In particular, . Therefore,
By , we obtain and . Hence , as required.
It is enough to prove . Suppose . By , we obtain . Then the Stein factorisation of the composite morphism is a birational morphism which contracts to a point. This is absurd, because has no extremal ray of or . Thus (4) holds. ∎
Lemma 6.18.
A smooth Fano threefold of No. 2-8 is quasi-F-split.
Proof.
We use the notation of Lemma 6.17. By Proposition 2.20 and Lemma 6.2, it suffices to show that
-
(1)
.
-
(2)
for every .
Step 1: Proof of (1). By the conormal exact sequence, we have the following exact sequence
Since and , we have an exact sequence
Since is toric and is nef, it follows from and [Totaro(Fano), Proposition 1.3] that
-
•
and
-
•
.
Thus , and it suffices to show .
Since we have a closed embedding around which is smooth (Proposition 6.17(4)), we have the following exact sequence:
By Bott vanishing [Fuj07, Theorem 1.1 or Corollary 1.3], we have
-
•
and
-
•
.
This completes the proof of (1).
Step 2: Proof of (2). By the conormal exact sequence, we have the following exact sequence
We have
Thus it suffices to show that .
We have the following exact sequence:
Since is nef and is a smooth toric variety, we have
-
(1)
and
-
(2)
.
by [Totaro(Fano), Proposition 1.3]. Thus (2) holds. ∎
6.1.6. 3-10
Lemma 6.19.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold of No. 3-10 such that there is a wild conic bundle structure . Then the following properties hold:
-
(1)
is (isomorphic to) a divisor on satisfying .
-
(2)
Each of and is nef and big.
-
(3)
and are ample.
-
(4)
, where .
-
(5)
is nef for every .
Proof.
The assertion (1) follows from [MS03, Corollary 8]. Let us show (2). By , it suffices to show that is base point free and is big. Set , and
We have three sections of :
-
•
Set , which is corresponding to the projection . We get .
-
•
Set , which is corresponding to the projection . We get .
-
•
Set , which is corresponding to the projection . We get .
Similarly, we have three prime divisors on which are -bundles over :
-
•
Set , which is corresponding to the projection .
-
•
Set , which is corresponding to the projection .
-
•
Set , which is corresponding to the projection .
By construction, we get for every .
We now show that
Fix . Note that we have for some . By restricting this to , we obtain
Hence we get , as required.
It follows from that is base point free. We have
Since is ample and is an effective -ample divisor, is big. Thus (2) holds.
Let us show (3). The following holds (cf. [FanoIII, Proposition 7.1(2)]):
Since is nef and -ample, is ample. Similarly, is ample by
Thus (3) holds. This linear equivalence implies (4). Finally, (5) follows from
∎
Lemma 6.20.
A smooth Fano threefold of No. 3-10 is quasi-F-split.
Proof.
By Proposition 4.4, we may assume that and has a wild conic bundle structure. In what follows, we use the notation of Lemma 6.19. By Proposition 2.20 and Lemma 6.2, it suffices to show that
-
(1)
.
-
(2)
for every .
Step 1: Proof of (1). By the conormal exact sequence, we have the following exact sequence:
Considering the restriction , we have an exact sequence
Since is nef, we have and by [Totaro(Fano), Proposition 1.3]. Thus, we have . Then it suffices to show .
We have the following exact sequence:
Since and are ample, we get
by Bott vanishing. Thus (1) holds.
Step 2: Proof of (2). By the conormal exact sequence, we have an exact sequence
Since and , we have
Thus it suffices to show .
We have the following exact sequence:
Since and is nef, we have
by [Totaro(Fano), Proposition 1.3]. Thus (2) holds. ∎
6.2. -splitting for 2-2 and 2-6
Proposition 6.21.
We use the same notation of Lemma 6.4. Assume that . Moreover, suppose that the following hold.
-
(0)
-
(0a)
for .
-
(0b)
for .
-
(0c)
for .
-
(0a)
-
(1)
-
(1a)
for .
-
(1b)
for .
-
(1c)
.
-
(1a)
-
(2)
-
(2a)
for .
-
(2b)
.
-
(2a)
Then the following hold.
-
(A)
.
-
(B)
.
-
(C)
.
Proof.
By taking the wedge product of the conormal exact sequence, we have an exact sequence
Therefore, we get the following implication:
In what follows, we shall prove (A) and (B).
Step 1: Proof of (A). By the conormal exact sequence, we have an exact sequence
We recall that , , , and . We then get
Thus it suffices to show .
Since , , and , we have the following exact sequence:
By applying Lemma 6.5 for and , (0a) and (1b) imply . Then the problem is reduced to
We have the following exact sequence:
Thus it is enough to prove that
-
(I)
and
-
(II)
.
Step 1-1: Proof of (I). By using an exact sequence twice, the problem is reduced to
-
(Ia)
for and
-
(Ib)
.
By
(Ia) follows from (1b). We have
and hence (1c) implies (Ib). This completes thep proof of (I).
Step 1-2: Proof of (II). By , We have . By using an exact sequence four times, it is enough to prove (IIa) and (IIb) below.
-
(IIa)
for .
-
(IIb)
.
By
(IIa) follows from (0b). We have
and hence (0c) implies (IIb). Thus (II) holds.
Step 2: Proof of (B). Since , , and , we have the following exact sequence:
Thus it suffices to show that
-
(III)
and
-
(IV)
.
Step 2-1: Proof of (III). Taking the wedge product of the relative exact sequence , we get
Thus we have
It holds that
Then it suffices to show . By and an exact sequence , the problem is reduced to the vanishings of the following:
-
•
for .
-
•
.
Both of them follow from (2a). Thus (III) holds.
Step 2-2: Proof of (IV). By the relative exact sequence , we get the following exact sequence:
We have . By and an exact sequence , the vanishing of can be reduced to those of
-
•
for and
-
•
.
These follow from (1a) and (1b). Thus (IV) holds. ∎
6.2.1. 2-2
Lemma 6.22.
A smooth Fano threefold of No. 2-2 is -split if .
Proof.
We follow the notation of Lemma 6.7. It is enough to verify the conditions (1)-(4) in Proposition 2.15. Proposition 2.15(1) holds by Lemma 6.2. Lemma 6.8 implies Proposition 2.15(2) and Proposition 2.15(3).
It suffices to show Proposition 2.15(4). It is enough to verify the conditions of Proposition 6.21. Recall that , , and . Since is toric, satisfies Bott vanishing. Then it is enough to check the following (concerning Proposition 6.21(0), use the fact that is ample):
-
(0)
.
-
(1)
.
The assertion (0) follows from
Let us show (1). We have
Then it holds that
and
where we have by and the Euler exact sequence [Har77, Ch. II, Example 8.20.1], where . Indeed, if , then this immediately follows from Bott vanishing. When , use the Euler exact sequence , which is still exact even after applying by Bott vanishing, and hence . ∎
6.2.2. 2-6-a
Lemma 6.23.
A smooth Fano threefold of No. 2-6-a is -split if .
Proof.
We follow the notation of Definition 6.9. It is enough to verify the conditions (1)-(4) in Proposition 2.15. Proposition 2.15(1) holds by Lemma 6.2. Lemma 6.14 implies Proposition 2.15(2) and Proposition 2.15(3).
It suffices to show Proposition 2.15(4). By the first paragraph of the proof of Proposition 6.21, it is enough to prove that
-
(1)
.
-
(2)
.
Step 1: Proof of (1). By the conormal exact sequence, we have an exact sequence
We have
by and Lemma 6.10. Thus it suffices to show .
We have the following exact sequence:
Then the required vanishing follows from
and
where each vanishing follows from Bott vanishing. Thus (1) holds.
Step 2: Proof of (2). We have the following exact sequence:
By Bott vanishing, we get
and
Therefore, (2) holds. ∎
6.2.3. 2-6-b
Lemma 6.24.
A smooth Fano threefold of No. 2-6-b is -split if .
Proof.
By a similar argument, we obtain an analogous result for the hyperelliptic case. We shall later prove that the assumption on in (1) is optimal (Example 8.4).
Proposition 6.25.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold such that and is not very ample, where denotes the index of . Let be the double cover induced by , where (cf. [FanoI, Theorem 6.5]). Then the following hold.
-
(1)
If and , then is -split.
-
(2)
If and , then is -split.
7. Proofs of the main theorems
Lemma 7.1.
Let be a smooth projective variety. Take an ample Cartier divisor on . Suppose that is quasi--split. Then there exists such that for every and every .
Proof.
Fix such that is -quasi--split. Pick integers and satisfying . By definition, is -quasi--split. By [KTTWYY1, Lemma 3.8 and Lemma 5.9], we get an isomorphism
and an exact sequence
Since satisfies Kodaira vanishing [KTTWYY1, Theorem 3.15], the following hold:
By the Serre vanishing theorem, we can find such that the following holds for :
Hence we are done by setting . ∎
Lemma 7.2.
Let be a smooth projective threefold. Take an ample Cartier divisor . Suppose that
-
(1)
for every integer , and
-
(2)
for every sufficiently large integer .
Then
Proof.
Proposition 7.3.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold with . Then the following hold.
-
(1)
is SRC if is none of 2-1, 2-3, 2-5, 2-10, and 2-14.
-
(2)
for every pseudo-effective Cartier divisor on .
Proof.
Let us show (1). Note that is SRC if is rational or has a conic bundle structure (Lemma 6.2). We first treat the case when . In this case, has a conic bundle structure except when is 3-18 [FanoIV, Theorem 4.10, Theorem 5.2]. If is 3-18, then is rational by [FanoIV, Section 7.3]. Hence we may assume that . Since and are rational, is rational or has an extremal ray of type except when is one of 2-1, 2-3, 2-5, 2-10, and 2-14 [FanoIV, Section 7.2]. Thus (1) holds.
Let us show (2). By (1) and Lemma 6.1, we may assume that is one of 2-1, 2-3, 2-5, 2-10, and 2-14. It follows from [FanoIV, Section 7.2] that
-
•
there is a blowup to a smooth Fano threefold of index with for some and
-
•
we have a del Pezzo fibration .
Take a general fibre of . Then is a canonical del Pezzo surface by [FS20, Theorem 15.2] and [BT22, Theorem 3.3]. By construction, we see that has a smooth anti-canonical member. In fact, is a blowup along an elliptic curve which is a complete intersection of two members of , and this blowup centre is isomorphic to some member of .
Since is torsion-free, we get
where . Thus we have
Then it is enough to prove . By , the divisor is nef. Set . Since is general and the base locus of is either empty or zero-dimensional, it suffices to show , because it implies (indeed, if there is , then we could find a member , which implies ). Since is smooth along the blowup centre, we get , and hence is a canonical del Pezzo surface. Let be the smooth locus of . By taking the exterior power of the conormal exact sequence and applying the tensor product with , we get an exact sequence
Applying the pushforward by the inclusion (which is left exact), we obtain an exact sequence
By , it is enough to prove .
Pick a general member of , which is an elliptic curve. Since is smooth along , we have . Then it suffices to show
By the conormal exact sequence, we have an exact sequence
Then the required vanishing follows from
-
•
, and
-
•
.
∎
Proof of Theorem A.
Let us show (1). Assume . If , then or is isomorphic to a smooth quadric threefold, and hence is -split. If , then is quasi--split by [Kawakami-Tanaka(dPvar), Theorem A and Remark 2.8]. Therefore, we may assume that . In this case, the assertion holds by former parts as follows:
We now show (2), i.e., Kodaira vanishing for . When or , this follows from (1) and Kodaira vanishing for quasi--split varieties [KTTWYY1, Theorem 3.15]. When , then Kodaira vanishing holds by [FanoI, Corollary 4.5]. ∎
Proof of Theorem B.
Proof of Theorem C.
By Theorem B(1), we have . Combining with , we conclude from [FAG, Theorem 8.5.19] that lifts to . ∎
Corollary 7.4.
Let be a blowup along a smooth curve, where and are smooth Fano threefolds. Then admits a -lifting , and the blowup along is a -lifting of .
Proof.
By , Theorem B(1) implies
and thus formally lifts to [FAG, Theorem 8.5.9(b)]. Moreover, we have by Kodaira vanishing [Muk13, Theorem 3]. Thus formally lifts to as a closed subscheme of by [Har2, Theorem 6.2]. Since and , it follows that formally lifts to and formally lifts to as a closed subscheme by [AZ-nonlift, Proposition 2.3(1)]. Since , they are algebraisable by [FAG, Corollary 8.5.6 and Corollary 8.4.5]. By [MR2791606, Theorem 2.5.8], for every closed point , there exists an affine open neighbourhood of and an étale morphism such that . Set and . Then , and we conclude that is a -lifting of . ∎
Corollary 7.5.
Let be a smooth Fano threefold and let be a morphism to a normal projective variety such that and is not isomorphism. Then lifts to .
Proof.
Since is not isomorphism, we have . Then the Fano threefold admits a -lifting . Let be an ample invertible sheaf on and set . By , there exists a -lifting of . We take such that , where is the contraction associated to the complete linear system . By Kodaira vanishing (Theorem A), we have . This, together with upper-semicontinuity theorem, implies . It follows from the Grauert theorem that
Let be the base locus of . We show that . Since is projective over , the image of in is closed. Since is free, the image does not contain the closed point of . Thus . Then we can see that the contraction gives a lift of . ∎
8. Examples
In this section, we gather examples of non--split or non-quasi--split smooth Fano threefolds.
Example 8.1 ().
Let be a smooth del Pezzo surface which is not -split. Then is a Fano threefold which is not -split. Therefore, if the characteristic of the base field and satisfies one of (1)-(3) below, then there exists a non--split smooth Fano threefold over satisfying .
-
(1)
and
-
(2)
and .
-
(3)
and .
Example 8.2 (Wild conic bundles).
Wild conic bundles are not -split. Indeed, if is -split and is a conic bundle, then is generically reduced [GLP15, Lemma 2.4] and hence not wild. Therefore, if and is a smooth Fano threefold which is 2-24 or 3-10, then is not necessarily -split.
Example 8.3 (, non--split).
Assume . Then
is not -split. Indeed, we have
and hence Fedder’s criterion [Fed83, Proposition 2.1] implies that is not -split (cf. [KTY, Proposition A.8]).
Example 8.4 (, non--split).
Assume . Take
i.e., with and for every , and
Let us prove that
-
(1)
is not -split, and
-
(2)
is a smooth Fano threefold.
The assertion (1) follows from Fedder’s criterion [Fed83, Proposition 2.1] (cf. [KTY, Proposition A.8]).
Let us show (2). It is enough to prove that is smooth, as the other assertions in (2) follow from the adjunction formula and the fact that is an ample -Cartier effective Weil divisor on (which implies the connectedness of ). Suppose that is a singular point of , where . Recall that we have for every . For , we have
and
which is smooth. Then it holds that . By symmetry, we get , which implies . However, does not pass through , which is absurd. Thus (2) holds.
Example 8.5 (No. 2-3, , non--split).
Assume . We construct a Fano threefold which is 2-3 and not -split. Let be a Fano threefold of index such that and is not -split (e.g., in for and , cf. the proof of Example 8.4). Take a Cartier divisor on such that . Then is base point free and it induces a finite double cover. By a Bertini theorem [Spr98, Corollary 4.3], we may assume that is a smooth prime divisor on , which is a smooth del Pezzo surface with . Pick a general member of , which is a smooth elliptic curve [KN, Theorem 1.4]. By an exact sequence
there exists a member such that . Let be the blowup along . Since coincides with the resolution of the indeterminacies of the pencil generated by and , there is a contraction of type such that the proper transforms of and are fibres of . By Kleimann’s criterion, is a smooth Fano threefold, which is of No. 2-3.
Example 8.6 (No. 2-1, , non--split).
Assume . We construct a Fano threefold which is 2-1 and is not -split. Let be a Fano threefold of index such that and is not -split. We can find such an example by setting
where (cf. [Oka21, Section 3.1]). Take a Cartier divisor on such that . Then we have a scheme-theoretic equality for some closed point on . We take generic members and of twice. Then is a regular curve of genus one. By , is a smooth elliptic curve [PW22, Corollary 1.8]. Therefore, the intersection of two general members and of is a smooth elliptic curve. Take the blowup along . Then we can apply the same argument as in Example 8.6.
Example 8.7 (, non-quasi--split).
Assume . Take
i.e., with and for every , and
Then is a smooth Fano threefold by the same proof as in Example 8.4. Moreover, is not quasi--split by [KTY, Corollary 4.19(i), Proposition A.8].