Unavoidable induced subgraphs in graphs with complete bipartite induced minors
Abstract
We prove that if a graph contains the complete bipartite graph as an induced minor, then it contains a cycle of length at most 12 or a theta as an induced subgraph. With a longer and more technical proof, we prove that if a graph contains as an induced minor, then it contains a triangle or a theta as an induced subgraph. Here, a theta is a graph made of three internally vertex-disjoint chordless paths , , , each of length at least two, such that no edges exist between the paths except the three edges incident to and the three edges incident to .
A consequence is that excluding a grid and a complete bipartite graph as induced minors is not enough to guarantee a bounded tree-independence number, or even that the treewidth is bounded by a function of the size of the maximum clique, because the existence of graphs with large treewidth that contain no triangles or thetas as induced subgraphs is already known (the so-called layered wheels).
1 Introduction
Graphs in this paper are finite and simple. A graph is an induced subgraph of a graph if can be obtained from be repeatedly deleting vertices. It is an induced minor of if can be obtained from be repeatedly deleting vertices and contracting edges. It is a minor of if can be obtained from be repeatedly deleting vertices, deleting edges and contracting edges. We denote by the complete graph on vertices and by the complete bipartite graph with sides of size and . The -grid is the graph whose vertices are the pairs of integers such that and where is adjacent to if and only if .
The tree-independence number was introduced in [3]. It is defined via tree-decompositions similarly to treewidth, except that the number associated to each bag of a tree-decomposition is the maximum size of an independent set of the graph induced by the bag, instead of its number of vertices (we omit the full definition for the sake of brevity). It attracted some attention lately, in particular because for each class of graphs with bounded tree-independence number, there exists polynomial time algorithms for maximum independent set and other related problems [3, 5, 6, 11].
The celebrated grid minor theorem of Robertson and Seymour [7] states that there exists a function so that any graph with treewidth at least contains a -grid as a minor. The motivation for our work is the quest for a similar theorem with “tree-independence number” instead of “treewidth”.
Here, the natural containment relation should be “induced minor” instead of “minor”, since the tree-independence number is monotone under taking induced minors but not under taking minors. The list of unavoidable graphs arising from a large tree-independence number should contain at least large grids and large complete bipartite graphs, which are known to have unbounded independence-tree number. Our main result is that this list is not complete. Indeed, we prove that a construction called layered wheel, first defined in [8], contains no -grid and no as an induced minor, while having arbitrarily large tree-independence number.
Outline of the proof
We do not need to define layered wheels, which is good since the definition is a bit long. We just need some of their properties and some preliminary definitions to state them. A theta is a graph made of three internally vertex-disjoint chordless paths , , , each of length at least two, such that no edges exist between the paths except the three edges incident to and the three edges incident to . A graph is theta-free if it does contain a theta as an induced subgraph, and more generally, a graph is -free whenever it does not contain (when is a graph) or any graph in (when is a class of graphs, such as thetas) as an induced subgraph. The only property of layered wheels that we need is the following theorem that states their existence.
Theorem 1.1 (see [8]).
For all integers and , there exists a theta-free graph of girth that contains as a minor.
Since containing as a minor implies having treewidth at least , layered wheels provide theta-free graphs of arbitrarily large girth and treewidth. Their tree-independence number is also arbitrarily large, since the treewidth of a triangle-free graph with tree-independence number at most is at most where denotes the classical Ramsey number, see [3]. To fulfill our goal, it therefore remains to prove that layered wheels do not contain large grids or complete bipartite graphs as induced minors. As far as we can see, this is non-trivial because even if layered wheels are precisely defined, checking directly that they do not contain some -grid or as an induced minor seems to be tedious, at least according to our several attempts. An indication of this is that some layered wheels do contain as an induced minor, which is not obvious, see Fig. 1 (this figure is meaningful only with the precise definition of a layered wheel).

Our approach is therefore less direct: we study what induced subgraphs are forced by the presence of a large grid or complete bipartite graph as an induced minor as we explain now.
Complete bipartite graphs
The list of induced subgraphs forced by the presence of as an induced minor is already known and not very difficult to obtain, see [4]. But this is not enough for our purpose since containing as an induced minor does not imply anything we can use. By a short argument, we first prove the following.
Theorem 1.2.
If a graph contains as an induced minor, then contains a cycle of length at most 12 or a theta as an induced subgraph.
The advantage of Theorem 1.2 is its short proof. But its statement is far from being optimal, as shown by the following, that we obtain by a more careful structural study.
Theorem 1.3.
If a graph contains as an induced minor, then contains a triangle or a theta as an induced subgraph.
Once Theorem 1.2 (or 1.3) is proved, checking that layered wheels contain no (or no ) as an induced minor becomes trivial since by Theorem 1.1, they do not contain short cycles and thetas as induced subgraphs. Our results therefore avoid some tedious checking, but we also believe that they are of independent interest.
Note that Theorem 1.3 is best possible in several ways. First, thetas need to be excluded because the subdivisions of provide triangle-free graphs that obviously contain as an induced minor. Triangles must be excluded because of line graphs of subdivisions of . A less obvious construction is represented in Fig. 2, showing that cannot be replaced by in Theorem 1.3.

In fact, we prove a more general result than Theorem 1.3. Before stating it, we need some definitions.
A prism is a graph made of three vertex-disjoint chordless paths , , , such that and are triangles and no edges exist between the paths except those of the two triangles and either:
-
•
, and all have length at least 1, or
-
•
one of , has length 0 and each of the other two has length at least 2.
Note that allowing a path of length zero in prisms (for instance if ) is not standard, but natural in our context. A prism with a path of length zero is sometimes referred to as a line wheel, but we do not use this terminology here.

A pyramid is a graph made of three chordless paths , , , each of length at least one, and two of them with length at least two, vertex-disjoint except at , and such that is a triangle and no edges exist between the paths except those of the triangle and the three edges incident to .
A hole in a graph is a chordless cycle of length at least 4. A graph that is either a theta, a prism or a pyramid is called a 3-paths configuration, or 3PC for short. Observe that a graph is a 3PC if and only if there exist three pairwise internally vertex disjoint paths , , such that and for every , induces a hole.
Theorem 1.4.
If a graph contains as an induced minor, then contains a 3-path configuration as an induced subgraph.
Theorem 1.4 clearly implies Theorem 1.3 because a 3PC that is not a theta contains a triangle. Proving Theorem 1.4 is just slightly longer than Theorem 1.3, but is also interesting in its own right for the following reason. A hole is even if it has an even number of vertices. Computing the maximum independent set of an even-hole-free graph in polynomial time is a well known open question. Hence, understanding the tree-independence number of even-hole-free graphs would be interesting. Moreover, Theorem 1.4 implies directly the existence of even-hole-free graphs of large tree-independence number that contain no large grids and no as induced minors. Indeed, [8] not only provides the layered wheels that we already mentioned, but a variant, called even-hole-free layered wheels, whose existence is stated in the next theorem.
Theorem 1.5 (see [8]).
For all integers , there exists a (, even hole, 3PC)-free graph that contains as a minor.
So, the simple counter-part of the Robertson and Seymour grid theorem, that would state that graphs with large tree-independence number should contain a large grid or a large complete bipartite graph as an induced minor is false, even when we restrict ourselves to even-hole-free graphs. Even-hole-free layered wheels provide a counter-example (note that being -free ensures that the high treewidth implies a high tree-independence number, see [3]).
Theorem 1.4 is best possible in some sense since we cannot get rid of thetas in the statement, which are needed because of subdivisions of that are easily seen to contain thetas. Also prisms are needed because the line graph of a theta is a prism, so line graphs of subdivisions of contain prisms. Observe that we have to allow a path of length zero in a prism because of the graph depicted in Fig. 4 that contains as an induced minor while the only 3PC in it is a prism with a path of length zero. Maybe pyramids are are not needed in the statement, but we need them in the proof for reasons that we now explain.

The proof of Theorem 1.4 relies on a precise description of how can be contained as an induced minor in a 3PC-free graph, see Lemma 5.2. The description is too long to be stated in the introduction, but Fig. 5 provides representations of the different possible situations.

Observe that excluding pyramids is necessary in Lemma 5.2, because of the graph presented in Fig. 6, that contains as induced minor, while the only 3PC in it is a pyramid.

Grids
Grids are easier to handle than complete bipartite graphs as shown by the next lemma whose proof is less involved than the proofs of Theorems 1.2, 1.3 or 1.4. We do not know if a -grid as an induced minor is enough to guarantee the presence of a 3PC as an induced subgraph.
Lemma 1.6.
If a graph contains a -grid as an induced minor, then contains a 3-path configuration as an induced subgraph.
Checking that layered wheels (and their even-hole-free variant) contain no -grid as an induced minor is then easy by Theorem 1.1 and Theorem 1.5.
Outline of the paper
In Section 2, we prove some technical lemmas about how a connected induced subgraph of some graph sees the rest of . These lemmas are more or less known already. We reprove them for the sake of completeness and because we could not find them with the precise statement that we need. Note that they are needed for all the other results. In Section 3, we prove Lemma 1.6. In Section 4, we prove Theorem 1.2. In Section 5, we prove Theorem 1.4. We conclude the paper by Section 6 that presents several open questions.
Notation
Let be a graph and and be disjoint sets of vertices of . We say that is complete to if every vertex of is adjacent to every vertex of , is anticomplete to if every no vertex of is adjacent to a vertex of . We say that sees if there exist and such that . Note that the empty set is complete (and anticomplete) to every set of vertices of .
By path we mean a sequence of vertices such that for all , if and only if . Therefore, what we call path for the sake of brevity is sometimes referred to as chordless path or induced path in a more standard notation. We use the notation to denote the subpath of from to (possibly since a path may consist of a single vertex).
When we deal with a theta with two vertices of degree 3 and , we say that the theta is from to . We use similar terminology for prisms and pyramids that are, respectively, from a triangle to a triangle and from a vertex to a triangle.
To avoid too heavy notation, we allow some abuse. Typically, we do not distinguish between a set of vertices in graph and the subgraph of that it induces. For instance, when is a path and is a vertex in a graph , we denote by either or . Also, we may say that a set of vertices of is connected when the correct statement should be that is connected. We hope that this improves the readability without causing any confusion.
2 Types

Let , , and be four disjoint sets of vertices in a graph . We distinguish three different types the set can have, see Fig. 7 for an illustration.
We say that is of type path centered at with respect to , and if there exists a path in such that sees , sees , sees , is anticomplete to and is anticomplete to .
Similarly we define being of type path centered at and being of type path centered at . We say that is of type path with respect to , and if it is of type path centered at either , or . Additionally, if is of type path centered at a set , we call a center for .
Observe that when is of type path centered at and a unique vertex of sees , and moreover this vertex is , then is also centered at . In particular, if , then is centered at , and .
We say that is of type claw with respect to , and if there exists in a vertex and three paths , and such that , , and are pairwise anticomplete, sees , sees , sees , is anticomplete to , is anticomplete to and is anticomplete to .
Observe that possibly , or (in fact, possibly two or three of these equalities hold). Observe that if , then is not only of type claw, but also of type path centered at , this case is additionally depicted in Fig. 7.
We say that is of type triangle with respect to , and if there exists in three vertex-disjoint paths , and such that the only edges between , and are , and , sees , sees , sees , is anticomplete to , is anticomplete to and is anticomplete to .
Observe that each of , and is possibly of length 0.
Lemma 2.1.
Let be a graph and , , and be disjoint sets of vertices of . If is connected and sees , and , then is of type path, of type claw, or of type triangle with respect to , and .
Proof.
Suppose that is not of type path. Let be a path in such that sees , sees , is anticomplete to and is anticomplete to . Note that such a path exists (consider for instance a shortest path from the vertices that see to the vertices that see ). Since is not of type path centered at , is anticomplete to . Let be path in disjoint from and such that sees , sees , is anticomplete to and is anticomplete to . Note again that such a path exists (consider for instance a shortest path from the vertices that see to the vertices that see ). We suppose that and are chosen subject to the minimality of .
Let be the neighbor of in closest to along and be the neighbor of in closest to along (possibly or ).
If sees both and , then consider vertex in such that sees both and , and choose closest to along . The path shows that is of type path (centered at or , possibly both, possibly also centered at if ), a contradiction. Hence, we may assume up to symmetry that is anticomplete to . If sees , then the path shows that is of type path centered at , a contradiction. Hence, is anticomplete to and .
If and , then consider the path . If , then because of , is of type path centered at , a contradiction. So, and the paths and contradict the minimality of .
Hence or . If , then the three paths , and show that is of type claw with respect to , and . If , then the three paths , and show that is of type triangle with respect to , and . ∎
The next lemma is implicitly about the presence of as an induced minor in a graph. In [4], it is proved along similar lines that a graph contains as an induced minor if and only if it contains some configuration from a restricted list as an induced subgraph (the so-called thetas, pyramids, long prisms and broken wheels, not worth defining here).
Lemma 2.2.
Let be a 3PC-free graph and , , , and be disjoint connected subsets of . If , and are pairwise anticomplete, and are anticomplete to each other, and each of and sees each of , and , then and are of type path with respect to , and .
Proof.
Suppose for a contradiction that (the argument for is the same by symmetry) is not of type path with respect to , and . Hence, by Lemma 2.1, we may consider the two cases below.
Case 1: is of type claw (and not of type path). So, there exists a vertex and three paths , and like in the definition of type claw. Moreover, , and for otherwise, would be of type path.
If is of type claw, then there exist a vertex and three paths , and like in the definition of type claw. Consider a shortest path from to with interior in , and let and be defined similarly through and . The nine paths , , , , , , , and form a theta from to , a contradiction.
If is of type triangle, a similar contradiction is found because of the existence of a pyramid in .
So is not of type claw or triangle. By Lemma 2.1, is of type path, and up to symmetry we suppose that it is centered at . Let be a path like in the definition of type path. Consider a shortest path from to with interior in , and let be defined similarly through . Let be a shortest path in such that and sees . Let be the neighbor of in closest to along . Let be the neighbor of in closest to along . If , then is of type claw, a contradiction. If , then the seven paths , , , , , and form a pyramid from to , a contradiction. Hence and . So the paths , , , , , , and form a theta from to , a contradiction.
Case 2: is of type triangle.
The proof is almost the same as in Case 1, so we just sketch it. If is of type claw, then contains a pyramid. If is of type triangle, then contains a prism. And if is of type path, then contains a prism or a pyramid. ∎
Let and be two graphs. An induced minor model of in is a collection of pairwise disjoint sets called the branch sets of the model, such that
-
•
for all
-
•
induces a connected subgraph of for every and
-
•
sees (in ) if and only if .
It is well known and easy to check that contains a graph isomorphic to as an induced minor if and only if there exists an induced minor model of in . We identify an induced minor model of in with the graph . Please note that the definition of the branch sets is not uniquely determined by
An induced minor model of is minimal if does not contain an induced minor isomorphic to for all
We denote by the graph obtained from by subdividing every edge once, i.e., is the graph with two degree-3 vertices and three paths of length four between them.
Lemma 2.3.
If a graph contains as an induced minor, then it contains a 3PC.
Proof.
Suppose for a contradiction that a 3PC-free graph contains as an induced minor. Denote by and the degree-3 vertices and let , and be the three paths of . Consider a minimal induced minor model of in . For all , has two neighbors and in and by minimality, is a path such that see , sees , is anticomplete to and is anticomplete to . It follows that if we set , , , and , cannot be of type path with respect to , and . Indeed, since , and all induce paths of length at least 1 in , cannot contain a path with vertices seeing , and . Hence, , , , and contradict Lemma 2.2. ∎
3 Proof of Lemma 1.6
We here prove Lemma 1.6 that we restate.
See 1.6
Proof.
If a graph contains a -grid as an induced minor, then it contains as an induced minor, because the -grid contains as an induced subgraph. The result therefore follows from Lemma 2.3. ∎
4 Proof of Theorem 1.2
Lemma 4.1.
Let and be graphs and a minimal induced minor model of in . For every , the graph does not contain cycles longer than the degree of .
Proof.
First, for every neighbor of in , let us mark a single vertex in that is adjacent to a vertex in . If there exists a connected induced proper subgraph of that contains all of the marked vertices, we contradict the minimality of the induced minor model.
Suppose that contains a cycle of length longer than the degree of , and let be the vertices of this cycle. We say that a vertex is necessary if either is marked or there exists a connected component of that contains a marked vertex and whose only neighbor in is the vertex . Because is larger than the number of marked vertices, there exists a vertex in that is not necessary, let be such a vertex. We remove from the vertex and every component of whose only neighbor in is . All of the remaining vertices in are still connected to and contain all of the marked vertices, so we get a connected induced proper subgraph of that contains all of the marked vertices, which is a contradiction. ∎
Lemma 4.1 is useful for asserting that is a tree, which in turn is useful for obtaining degree-1 vertices in . We make use of degree-1 vertices with the following lemma.
Lemma 4.2.
Let be a minimal induced minor model of a graph in a graph , and let . For every vertex whose degree is one in , there exists so that is the only neighbor of in .
Proof.
Otherwise, we could remove from and contradict the minimality of . ∎
We say that such a branch set is private to the vertex . We may now prove Theorem 1.2 which we restate below.
See 1.2
Proof.
Let and . Let be a graph with girth at least , and let be a minimal induced minor model of in . We denote the branch sets corresponding to vertices of on the side with vertices by and on the other side by . Note that is triangle-free.
First suppose that there are two branch sets , of size . In this case, there must be a vertex that is adjacent to at least different branch sets on the other side, and a vertex that is adjacent to at least different branch sets on the other side that is also adjacent to. Fix three different branch sets , , that both and are adjacent to. Now, by selecting in each branch set , , a shortest path from a neighbor of to a neighbor of , we obtain a theta from to .
We may therefore assume that at least of the branch sets contain at least three vertices. By Lemma 4.1 and because has girth at least , for all branch sets the induced subgraph is a tree, and for all such sets with , the tree must have two non-adjacent leaves and . By Lemma 4.2, both and have a private branch set on the other side, so we can label each branch set with with an unordered pair so that is private to and is private to .
Now, because , there must exist three branch sets , , and that are labeled with the same pair . By contracting both and into a single vertex and taking the paths in , , and between the corresponding leaves, we obtain as an induced minor. By Lemma 2.3, must contain a theta since the theta is the only triangle-free 3PC. ∎
5 Proof of Theorem 1.4
We start with an improvement of Lemma 2.2.
Lemma 5.1.
Let be a 3PC-free graph and be an integer. Suppose that , , and , …, are disjoint connected subsets of , , and are pairwise anticomplete, , …, are pairwise anticomplete, and for every , sees , and .
Then the ’s are all of type path with respect to , and and furthermore, one of , and is a center for all of them.
Proof.
By Lemma 2.2 applied to , for some and , and , we see that all ’s are of type path with respect to , and . It remains to prove that they all share a common center.
We denote by the sets of all elements such that is centered at . Note that for all , is nonempty. It is enough to prove that for all , either or . Indeed, this implies that the sets are linearly ordered by the inclusion, so that is non-empty and contains the common center that we are looking for.
So suppose for a contradiction that and are such that and are inclusion-wise incomparable. So, up to symmetry, is centered at and not at while is centered at and not at .
Since is centered at , there exists in such that sees , sees , sees , is anticomplete to and is anticomplete to . Since is centered at , there exists in such that sees , sees , sees , is anticomplete to and is anticomplete to .
Let be a shortest path in such that and . Let be a shortest path in such that sees and . Let be a shortest path in such that sees and . Observe that each of , , , and can be of length 0.
Let be the neighbor of in closest to along . Let be the neighbor of in closest to along . Let be the neighbor of in closest to along . Let be the neighbor of in closest to along . See Figure 8.

Suppose first that . Observe that for otherwise would be centered at , contrary to our assumption. Hence, . If , then , , , and form a theta from to , so . If , then , , , and form a pyramid from to . If , then , , , , and form a theta from to (because as already noted). Hence , and symmetrically we can prove that .
Suppose now . If , then , , , and form a prism from to . If , then , , , , and form a pyramid from to . Hence , and symmetrically we can prove that .
We are left with the case where , , and . Then , , , , , and form a theta from to . ∎
The following lemma describes what happens when is an induced minor of some 3PC-free graph. It is worth noting that it has a true converse that we do not need to state formally. More precisely, if in any graph six paths , , , , and satisfy all the properties described in Lemma 5.2, then they form a model for a induced minor, and moreover the graph that they induce can be checked to be 3PC-free, see Fig. 5.
Note that the statement of Lemma 5.2 is not completely symmetric. Namely, , and are assumed to be minimal while , and are not. This yields a slightly stronger statement which is needed for the application in the proof of Theorem 1.4.
Lemma 5.2.
Let be a 3PC-free graph and , , , , and be connected disjoint subsets of such that , and are pairwise anticomplete, , and are pairwise anticomplete and each of , and sees each of , and . Suppose that no connected proper subset of (resp. and ) sees each of , and . Then, there exist six vertex-disjoint paths , , , , and in such that:
-
•
Each of , and is equal to exactly one of , or .
-
•
Each of , and contains exactly one of , or .
-
•
is a hole.
-
•
(resp. , , ) is anticomplete to (resp. , , ).
-
•
and both have length at most 1 (so they each contain at most two vertices).
-
•
(resp. , , ) has at least three neighbors in (resp. , , ). In particular, each of , , and contains at least three vertices.
-
•
is complete to , or has four vertices and five edges.
Proof.
By Lemma 5.1, , and are of type path with respect to , and , centered at some . By Lemma 5.1, , and are of type path with respect to , and , centered at some . We let , , and be such that and .
So, contains some path that sees , and as in the definition of type path centered at , but by the assumption about the minimality of , or , we see that this path is in fact itself. So is equal to exactly one of , or . The arguments works also with and , so that , , , each of , and sees , each of , and sees , each of , and sees , each of , and is anticomplete to and each of , is and is anticomplete to .
Also contains a path such that sees , sees , is anticomplete to , is anticomplete to and sees . Note that we cannot claim that , since we made no assumption about the minimality of . But since is anticomplete to and is anticomplete to , the only possible edge between and is . Similarly, is the only edge between and . Moreover, sees , and since is anticomplete to , we know that sees (and not only ).
Similarly, contains a path with , , is anticomplete to , is anticomplete to and such that sees . Observe that , , and form a hole .
Also is of type path with respect to , and and centered at . So, contains a path such that sees , sees , is anticomplete to , is anticomplete to and sees .
Let be the neighbor of in closest to along . Let be the neighbor of in closest to along . Let be the neighbor of in closest to along . Let be the neighbor of in closest to along . Let be the neighbor of in closest to along . Let be the neighbor of in closest to along . Let be the neighbor of in closest to along . Let be the neighbor of in closest to along . See Fig. 9.

Suppose that has length at least 2. Then and contains a theta, a prism or a pyramid, namely from (if ) or (if ) or (otherwise), to (if ) or (if ) or (otherwise). Hence has length at most 1, meaning that either or . Similarly, has length at most 1 and or .
Suppose that . Then for otherwise and contain a theta (if ), or a pyramid from to (if ), or a theta from to (otherwise). Since sees , has a neighbor in . If has a unique neighbor in , say up to symmetry (so either , or and ), then the three paths , and form a theta from to . So, has two neighbors in . Hence, the three paths , and form a pyramid from to . We proved that .
Suppose that . Then for otherwise and contains a pyramid from to (if ), a prism from to (if ) or a pyramid from to (otherwise). Since sees , has a neighbor in . If has a unique neighbor in , say up to symmetry (so either , or and ), then the three paths , and form a pyramid from to . So, has two neighbors in . Hence, the three paths , and form a prism from to . We proved that . This implies that has at least three neighbors in for otherwise and would form a theta from to .
We proved has at least three neighbors in . By a symmetric argument, we can prove that (resp. , ) has at least three neighbors in (resp. , ). It remains to prove that is complete to , or induces a graph with four vertices and five edges. So suppose that is not complete to .
Since sees and is not complete to , there is at least one edge and at least one non-edge with ends in and . So, there must be a vertex, either in or , that is incident to such an edge and such a non-edge. Up to symmetry, we assume that this vertex is and (so and ). If , or if and has only three edges (namely , and ), then , and form a theta from to . We proved that and has at least four edges. So, has four vertices and it remains to prove that it has exactly five edges. So suppose for a contradiction that has exactly four edges.
If (and therefore ), then , and form a theta from to . If (and therefore ), then , and form a pyramid from to . ∎
Lemma 5.3.
Let be a 3PC-free graph and , , , , and be connected disjoint subsets of such that , and are pairwise anticomplete, , and are pairwise anticomplete, and each of , and sees each of , and . Suppose that no connected proper subset of (resp. and ) sees each of , and . Then exactly one of , and contains at most 2 vertices.
Proof.
Follows directly from Lemma 5.2. ∎
We may now prove Theorem 1.4 that we restate.
See 1.4
Proof.
Suppose for a contradiction that a 3PC-free graph contains has an induced minor. So, contains seven disjoint connected sets , , , , , and such that , and are pairwise anticomplete, , , and are pairwise anticomplete, and each of , and sees each of , , and . We suppose that these sets are chosen subject to the minimality of . It follows that no proper connected subset of (resp. , , ) sees , and (note that it is important here that no assumption is made about the minimality of , and ).
6 Open questions
We need pyramids in Theorem 1.4 only for the sake of the precise description of Lemma 5.2, see Fig. 6. We therefore wonder whether pyramids in Theorem 1.4 are really needed. More precisely, we do not know whether a (theta, prism)-free graph that contains as an induced minor exists.
A wheel is a graph made of a hole called the rim together with a vertex called the center that has at least three neighbors on the rim. It is even if the center has an even number of neighbors in the rim. It is well known (and easy to check) that even-hole-free graphs contain no prisms, no thetas and no even wheels as induced subgraphs, since each of these configurations implies the presence of an even hole. Conversely, many theorems about even-hole-free graphs suggest that (theta, prism, even wheel)-free graphs, that are called odd signable graphs, capture the essentials structural properties of even-hole-free graphs, see [9, 10]. We believe that the following is true.
Conjecture 6.1.
If is an odd signable graph (in particular if is an even-hole-free graph), then does not contain as an induced minor.
Observe that we do not know whether the even-hole-free layered wheels contain as an induced minor. 6.1 would prove that they do not. We also propose the following.
Conjecture 6.2.
If contains as a minor, then contains a triangle (as a subgraph) or contains as an induced minor.
In [1], it is proved that triangle-free odd-signable graphs (in particular (triangle, even-hole)-free graphs) have treewidth at most 5 and therefore do not contain as a minor. So, provided that 6.1 is true, 6.2 is just a more precise statement.
Here are some remarks about 6.2. It is false with a assumption instead of a assumption, see Fig. 10 where an (even hole, triangle)-free graph with a minor, first discovered in [2], is represented. It is false with a “ as an induced minor or triangle” conclusion because of the layered wheels. Provided that 6.1 is true, it is false with a “ as an induced minor or 3PC as an induced subgraph” conclusion, or with a “ as an induced minor or as subgraph” conclusion, because of the even-hole-free layered wheels that are pyramid-free and -free by Theorem 1.5. 6.2 would therefore provide a statement that is best possible in many ways.

It might be interesting to study the implications of a induced minor in an even-hole free graph, where is the graph obtained from by removing one edge. In Fig. 11, an even-hole-free graph that contains as an induced minor is represented, and we observe that this graph plays an important role in the structural study of even-hole-free graphs, see [9]. In Fig. 12, another example of a graph that contains as an induced minor is represented, and we observe that this graph contains an even wheel.


More generally, we believe that studying implications between different containment relations for different kinds of graphs might have more applications. For instance, this approach is used in [4] to design a polynomial time algorithm that decides whether an input graph contains as an induced minor. We wonder what is the complexity of detecting as an induced minor.
7 Acknowledgement
We are grateful to Marthe Bonamy, Sepehr Hajebi, Martin Milanič, Sophie Spirkl and Kristina Vušković for helpful discussions.
Maria Chudnovsky is supported by NSF-EPSRC Grant DMS-2120644 and by AFOSR grant FA9550-22-1-0083.
Tuukka Korhonen is supported by the Research Council of Norway via the project BWCA (grant no. 314528).
Nicolas Trotignon is partially supported by the French National Research Agency under research grant ANR DIGRAPHS ANR-19-CE48-0013-01 and the LABEX MILYON (ANR-10-LABX-0070) of Université de Lyon, within the program Investissements d’Avenir (ANR-11-IDEX-0007) operated by the French National Research Agency (ANR).
Sebastian Wiederrecht is supported by the Institute for Basic Science (IBS-R029-C1).
Part of this research was conducted during two Graph Theory Workshops at the McGill University Bellairs Research Institute, and we express our gratitude to the institute and to the organizers of the workshop.
Part of this work was done when Nicolas Trotignon visited Maria Chudnovsky at Princeton University with generous support of the H2020-MSCA-RISE project CoSP- GA No. 823748.
References
- [1] Kathie Cameron, Murilo V. G. da Silva, Shenwei Huang, and Kristina Vušković. Structure and algorithms for (cap, even hole)-free graphs. Discrete Mathematics, 341(2):463–473, 2018.
- [2] Michele Conforti, Gérard Cornuéjols, Ajai Kapoor, and Kristina Vušković. Triangle-free graphs that are signable without even holes. Journal of Graph Theory, 34(3):204–220, 2000.
- [3] Clément Dallard, Martin Milanič, and Kenny Storgel. Treewidth versus clique number. II. Tree-independence number. Journal of Combinatorial Theory, Series B, 164:404–442, 2024.
- [4] Clément Dallard, Maël Dumas, Claire Hilaire, Martin Milanič, Anthony Perez, and Nicolas Trotignon. Detecting as an induced minor. arXiv:2402.08332, 2024.
- [5] Clément Dallard, Fedor V. Fomin, Petr A. Golovach, Tuukka Korhonen, and Martin Milanic. Computing tree decompositions with small independence number. arXiv:2207.09993, 2022.
- [6] Paloma T. Lima, Martin Milanič, Peter Muršič, Karolina Okrasa, and Kenny Storgel Pawel Rzazewski. Tree decompositions meet induced matchings: beyond max weight independent set. arXiv:2402.15834, 2024.
- [7] Neil Robertson and Paul Seymour. Graph minors. V. Excluding a planar graph. Journal of Combinatorial Theory, Series B, 41(1):92–114, 1986.
- [8] Ni Luh Dewi Sintiari and Nicolas Trotignon. (Theta, triangle)-free and (even hole, K)-free graphs - Part 1: Layered wheels. Journal of Graph Theory, 97(4):475–509, 2021.
- [9] Kristina Vušković. Even-hole-free graphs: a survey. Applicable Analysis and Discrete Mathematics, 10(2):219–240, 2010.
- [10] Kristina Vušković. The world of hereditary graph classes viewed through Truemper configurations. In S. Gerke S.R. Blackburn and M. Wildon, editors, Surveys in Combinatorics, London Mathematical Society Lecture Note Series, volume 409, pages 265–325. Cambridge University Press, 2013.
- [11] Nikola Yolov. Minor-matching hypertree width. In Proceedings of the 29th Annual ACM-SIAM Symposium on Discrete Algorithms, SODA 2018, pages 219–233. SIAM, 2018.