TRIVIAL CUP PRODUCTS IN BOUNDED COHOMOLOGY OF THE FREE GROUP VIA ALIGNED CHAINS
Abstract.
We prove that the cup product of -decomposable quasimorphisms, Brooks quasimorphisms or Rolli quasimorphisms with any bounded cohomology class of arbitrary positive degree is trivial.
1. Introduction
Despite its wide range of uses in mathematics, bounded cohomology turns out to be hard to compute in general. Even for the case of a non-abelian free group , while something can be said about the bounded cohomology group with trivial real coefficients up to degree , for degrees and higher it is still not known whether vanishes or not. Expecting the former to hold, we consider the following weaker question:
Open Problem.
For all is the cup product
trivial?
In recent years a whole variety of examples of trivial cup products have been exhibited in the case , namely it holds that:
Theorem 1.
For all quasimorphisms and satisfying either of the following conditions
-
(a)
(Bucher, Monod, [BM18]) and are Brooks quasimorphisms,
-
(b)
(Heuer, [Heu20]) is a -decomposable quasimorphism and a -continuous quasimorphism,
-
(c)
(Heuer, [Heu20]) Each of and is either a Brooks quasimorphism on non-selfoverlapping words or a Rolli quasimorphism,
- (d)
the cup product
vanishes.
Although the publication dates of Theorem 1 (a) and (b)-(c) differ, these two results, which have a significant overlap, were announced at the same conference in 2017.
In the present paper we provide an intermediate result towards answering the Open Problem for all :
Theorem A.
Let and be arbitrary. Let be a quasimorphism. Then the cup product
vanishes whenever
-
(a)
is a -decomposable quasimorphism,
-
(b)
is a Brooks quasimorphism,
-
(c)
is a Rolli quasimorphism.
Even in the case of , our Theorem A is a priori stronger than Theorem 1, since it is not known whether every quasimorphism is -decomposable, -continuous or a Calegari quasimorphism. Moreover for , since both and are known to be infinite dimensional (see [Bro81], [Gri95] as well as [Som97]), our Theorem gives infinitely many examples of the triviality of the cup product of non trivial classes.
Important examples of -decomposable quasimorphisms are the classical Brooks quasimorphisms on non-selfoverlapping words and Rolli quasimorphisms. Thus, Theorem A (c) is a particular case of Theorem A (a). For Brooks quasimorphisms on selfoverlapping words we are however not aware of a construction as -decomposable quasimorphisms. As a consequence, we will deal with case (b) separately in Section 4.
Similar to the generalisation of Heuer’s vanishing result in Theorem 1(b) by Fournier-Facio in Theorem 1(d), we expect the generalization of Theorem A to Fournier-Facio’s setting to be straightforward following [Fac20].
Our strategy to prove Theorem A (a) is to apply the geometric proof from [Heu20] to the setting of aligned cochains from [BM19]. On the one hand, Nicolaus Heuer introduced in [Heu20] the notion of -decomposition which abstracts the geometric properties of both Brooks quasimorphisms on non-selfoverlapping words and Rolli quasimorphisms needed to prove Theorem 1(b). On the other hand, the aligned chain complex is a geometric construction introduced by Monod and the second author in [BM19] to prove the vanishing of the continuous bounded cohomology of automorphism groups of trees and also the vanishing of the cup product of Brooks quasimorphisms (Theorem 1(a)) in [BM18]. In our setting, the aligned cochain complex allows for consequent simplifications in the proof by Heuer to the point where we can relax the hypothesis on the second factor of the cup product in Theorem 1(b) significantly; that is, from being a -continuous quasimorphism, and hence an a priori strict subset of , to an arbitrary cohomology class in any degree .
The proof of Theorem A (b) is essentially a translation of the combinatorial aspects of the proof of Theorem A (a) to Brooks quasimorphisms and does not rely on -decompositions. For a unified approach to these two proofs, see the last remark of Section 6.
The paper is structured as follows: In Section 2 we recall a selection of basic notions on bounded cohomology theory. Section 3 introduces the inhomogeneous aligned cochain complex, where we follow [BM19]. The proof of Theorem A (b) for Brooks quasimorphisms is given in Section 4. Then to define -decompositions, the induced -decomposable quasimorphisms and their special cases of Brooks quasimorphisms and Rolli quasimorphisms, we follow [Heu20] in Section 5. Finally, Theorem A (a) is proven in Section 6.
Acknowledgements
This paper is part of a master thesis project by the first author under the supervision of the second author within the framework of the Master Class program organized by NCCR SwissMAP. We are especially grateful to Nicolas Monod for his interesting feedback while refereeing the thesis and to Pierre de la Harpe, Francesco Fournier-Facio, Clara Löh and Marco Moraschini for several useful comments. We also wish to thank an anonymous referee for his or her pertinent corrections.
2. Bounded cohomology
We shortly define bounded cohomology, originally introduced in [Gro82]. For more details, the reader is referred to [Fri17].
2.1. Inhomogeneous cochains and bounded cohomology
We give the definition of (bounded) cohomology of a group with trivial real coefficients by using the inhomogeneous resolution. For all we denote by
where
the set of cochains and bounded cochains respectively. The coboundary map is defined by
and it restricts to the bounded coboundary map . Since holds for all , we have that is a (bounded) cochain complex. Moreover, the (bounded) -cochain is called a (bounded) -cocycle if , and a (bounded) -coboundary if there exists a (bounded) -cochain such that . The (bounded) cohomology of is then defined as the cohomology of the (bounded) cochain complex. More precisely:
Definition 2.
The -th (bounded) cohomology of with trivial coefficients is defined as
We shall denote by both the bounded and the unbounded coboundary maps.
2.2. Cup product
We introduce the operation that allows to obtain elements of (bounded) cohomology groups of higher degrees from elements of (bounded) cohomology groups of lower degrees.
Definition 3.
The cup product is the map given by
where is represented by the cocycle that is defined as follows
This map induces a well defined map on bounded cohomology that we also call the cup product
2.3. Quasimorphisms on a free group
We recall that for any group a quasimorphism is a map for which there exists a constant such that
There is a straightforward connection to bounded cohomology: for any such the norm of is bounded by and therefore is a cocycle and represents a cohomology class in .
For the case of a non-abelian free group , the study of boils down to studying the set of quasimorphisms on which we denote by , since the following holds
where and denote the set of homomorphisms and real-valued bounded maps on respectively (see for example [Gri95, Proposition 3.2]). For instance, with help of various explicit constructions of certain families of quasimorphisms it was proved that is non-vanishing and moreover infinite-dimensional, e.g. Brooks quasimorphisms, due to Brooks in [Bro81] (see also [Gri95]), and Rolli quasimorphisms, due to Rolli in [Rol09].
Example 4.
Brooks quasimorphisms. Let be the symmetrization of a free generating set of and be any reduced word in . Then a Brooks quasimorphism on the word is a function loosely defined as
(For a precise definition, we refer to Section 4.) A reduced word in the non-abelian free group is called a non-selfoverlapping word if there do not exist words and with non-trivial such that as a reduced word. In this case counts disjoint occurences of . Otherwise we say that is a selfoverlapping word and then counts occurences of which may overlap.
Example 5.
Rolli quasimorphisms. Let be the symmetrization of a free generating set of . A Rolli quasimorphism is a map defined as
where
-
•
are the unique non-zero integers such that it holds that
where no consecutive are the same.
-
•
are bounded alternating222 is alternating, if it holds that for all . functions.
We encounter another viewpoint for these examples of quasimorphisms in Section 5.
3. The inhomogeneous aligned cochain complex
In this section we briefly present the inhomogeneous version of aligned cochain complexes of non-abelian free groups first introduced in [BM19] in the homogeneous context to prove the vanishing of continuous bounded cohomology for certain automorphisms groups of a tree.
Let again be a free group of rank and be the symmetrization of a generating set of .
For any we define
Geometrically, this means that in the Cayley graph of with respect to the corresponding homogenous -tuple of distinct vertices is ordered on the geodesic segment between and (see Figure 1).
Definition 6.
The (inhomogeneous) aligned cochain complex is defined as the set of functions
The bounded (inhomogeneous) aligned chain complex consists of bounded aligned cochains:
Definition 7.
The (bounded) (inhomogeneous) aligned alternating cochain complex is defined as the set of functions such that
for every .
These four complexes are endowed with their inhomogenous coboundary
There is a chain map
defined as
for every and .
Since is a subset of , we have by restriction natural maps
which commute with the coboundary maps. It is proven in [BM18, Proposition 8] that the composition of the chain maps
induces an isomorphism between the (bounded) cohomology of the free group and the cohomology of the cocomplex .
Let now be represented by inhomogenous cocoycles and . To show that the cup product vanishes it is hence sufficient to show that
is a coboundary in . This immediately follows if is a coboundary in . Indeed, if
for some then
This is the strategy we will use to prove Theorem A.
4. Proof of Theorem A (b)
Let be the symmetrization of a free generating set of and be any nontrivial element of , i.e. a nonempty reduced word in . Define a function as
Let denote the length of . The Brooks quasimorphism on is the function defined by
if is a reduced expression of length , where the sum is considered to be equal to if the index set is empty, i.e. if .
Proof of Theorem A (b).
Due to the above discussion we can prove Theorem A (b) by showing that the cup product of the restriction to aligned cochains of cocycles representing the cohomology classes in consideration is a coboundary. Thus, it is enough to consider the restriction of Brooks quasimorphisms to aligned chains, which we still denote by , and to show that for any and , there exists such that
Let be defined by
(1) |
where is a reduced expression of length , and .
Define by
By construction, , so that we only need to show that is bounded. Let in be arbitrary. Since this chain is aligned, the concatenation of a reduced expression for and respectively, is a reduced expression (obviously for ). Let and be reduced expressions.
Then by definition, we have that
(2) | ||||
By expanding as in its definition (1) we obtain
(3) | ||||
Using the definition of and the cocycle relation
(4) | ||||
the expression in (3) reduces to
Now the -th terms in the first and second sum cancel for while the -th terms in the second and third sum cancel for , so that we are left with
which is bounded by . ∎
5. -decompositions and induced quasimorphisms of the free group
We recall the notion of -decomposable quasimorphisms introduced by Heuer as a way of uniformizing the geometric properties of both Brooks quasimorphisms on non-selfoverlapping words and Rolli quasimorphims. For more details, the reader is referred to [Heu20, Section 3]
5.1. -decompositions
Let be a free group and the symmetrization of a free generating set of . For any symmetric set satisfying we call its elements pieces. Furthermore, let be the set of finite sequences of pieces, more precisely:
For any in , we shall write for the length of the tuple , not to be confused with the length of with respect to .
Definition 8.
A -decomposition of into the pieces is a map
that satisfies the following properties
-
[A]
for single words: For every with we have the following:
-
•
as a reduced word,
-
•
,
-
•
for all .
-
•
-
[B]
for products of two words: There exists a constant such that for all , the sequences , and written in the following form
where so that is of maximal length, satisfy
for .
In order to refer to the system of equations in property [B] of a given -decomposition, we say for short that and form a -triangle. This reflects the geometric picture of property [B], as illustrated in Figure 2.
Moreover, we refer to the part of the -triangle consisting of and as the -part and the part consisting of and as the (bounded) -part.
5.2. -decomposable quasimorphisms
Assigning a real value to each element of the pieces in an appropriate way, ensures that any -decomposition of induces quasimorphisms on . This is done in the following way:
Definition 9.
Let be a decomposition with pieces and let , i.e. an alternating bounded map on . Then the map defined by
where , is called a -decomposable quasimorphism.
This is indeed a legitimate name for this map which can be justified by using property [B] of the -decomposition:
Proposition 10 (Heuer, [Heu20]).
Let be a decomposition with pieces and let .Then the map in Definition 9 is a quasimorphism.
By taking and arbitrary, one can recover all homomorphisms on the free group. We now give examples of -decomposable quasimorphisms: Brooks quasimorphisms on non-selfoverlapping words and Rolli quasimorphisms.
Example 11.
-decomposition and Brooks quasimorphisms on non-selfoverlapping words . Let be a non-empty non-selfoverlapping word, meaning by definition that it cannot be written as , with non-empty. Note that in any reduced word , occurrences of and as subwords cannot overlap. As is assumed to be non-selfoverlapping, any such can be represented uniquely as
where each possibly empty is in reduced form, does not contain or as subwords, and . In this setting, define the pieces to be
Then the -decomposition on the word is the map
for as above. The map given by
induces the -decomposable quasimorphism , namely precisely the Brooks quasimorphism on .
Example 12.
-decomposition and Rolli quasimorphisms. If is a free group of rank and then any non-trivial can be uniquely represented in the following form
where all are non-zero and no consecutive are identical. If we define the pieces to be then we define the -decomposition as the map
for as above. Let , namely bounded functions satisfying . Then the map
induces the quasimorphism , namely precisely the Rolli quasimorphism.
6. Proof of Theorem A (a)
Due to the discussion in Section 3 we can prove Theorem A (a) by showing that the cup product of the restriction to aligned cochains of cocycles representing the cohomology classes in consideration is a coboundary. Thus Theorem A (a) is a direct consequence of
Theorem A’.
Let be a -decomposable quasimorphism and for any let . Then there exists such that
Proof.
Let and be as in Theorem A’ and fix a -decomposition on pieces for which is -decomposable. Further let be defined by
(5) |
where and for , and by
By construction, , so that we only need to show that is bounded. Let in be arbitrary. Then by definition, we have that
(6) | ||||
Let and be the -decompositions of , and . By expanding as in its definition (5) and by recalling that is as a -decomposable quasimorphism defined as (see Definition 9)
we obtain
(7) | ||||
Using the cocycle relation
(8) | ||||
the expression in (7) reduces to
(9) | ||||
We now decompose the -triangle into its - and -parts as in Definition 8. Observe that since we are working with aligned chains, we have so that
We set and and note that since the lengths of the -parts are bounded by we have
Furthermore, by comparing the -parts, we see that and agree at the head, while and agree at the tail of their corresponding -decompositions (see Figure 3). More precisely, we have
Finally, if , then , and if then . This allows us to further reduce the expression for in (9) to
which is bounded since each of the three sums has at most summands, each of which is bounded since is bounded and is uniformly bounded on pieces of the -decomposition.
∎
Remark.
Clearly the two proofs of Theorem A for (a) -decomposable quasimorphisms and (b) Brooks quasimorphisms have a similar flavour and could in fact be put in the following unified context: Given a -decomposition, and a bounded alternating function
by which we mean that , the function defined by
is a quasimorphism for which Theorem A holds. The case of -decomposable quasimorphisms corresponds to taking , while Brooks quasimorphisms correspond to taking the trivial -decomposition with and
for any word of length .
References
- [Bro81] Robert Brooks, Some remarks on bounded cohomology, Ann. of Math. Stud., 97 (1981), 53–63
- [BM18] Michelle Bucher and Nicolas Monod, The cup product of Brooks quasimorphisms, Forum Mathematicum, 30 (5) (2018), 1157–1162
- [BM19] Michelle Bucher and Nicolas Monod, The bounded cohomology of over local fields and S-integers, International Mathematics Research Notices, 6 (2019), 1601–1611
- [Cal09] Danny Calegari, scl, 20. Mathematical Society of Japan, MSJ Memoirs, Tokyo, 2009, xii–209
- [Fac20] Francesco Fournier-Facio, Infinite sums of Brooks quasimorphisms and cup products in bounded cohomology, (2020), available at arXiv:1710.03193
- [Fri17] Roberto Frigerio, Bounded cohomology of discrete groups, Mathemaical Surveys and Monographs, 227 (2017), 1–220
- [Gro82] Michael Gromov, Volume and bounded cohomology, Inst. Hautes Études Sci. Publ. Math. 56 (1982), 5–99.
- [Gri95] Rostislav Grigorchuk, Some results on bounded cohomology, Combinatorial and geometric group theory (Edinburgh, 1993), 111–163, London Math. Soc. Lecture Note Ser., 204, Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge, 1995.
- [Heu20] Nicolas Heuer, Cup product of bounded cohomology of the free group, Ann. Scuola Norm. di Pisa, 1–26, 2020.
- [Rol09] Pascal Rolli, Quasi-morphisms on free groups, (2009), available at arXiv:0911.4234
- [Som97] Teruhiko Soma, Bounded cohomology and topologically tame Kleinian groups, Duke Math. J., 88(2) (1997), 357–370