This paper was converted on www.awesomepapers.org from LaTeX by an anonymous user.
Want to know more? Visit the Converter page.

The Local Account of Bell Nonlocality

Charles Alexandre Bédard Università della Svizzera italiana
[email protected]
(June 2024)
Abstract

In the century-long history of quantum theory, Bell’s theorem [1] stands out among the most thought-provoking results of its foundations. It reveals a conflict between quantum theory’s predictions and those allowed by a general framework aligning with locality and realism. Experimental vindications [2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9, 10] of the quantum predictions were of Nobel-Prize merit [11] and contributed to an established conclusion that nature is non-local. In stark contrast with this orthodoxy, I show that within the Heisenberg picture of unitary quantum theory [12, 13, 14], Bell inequalities are violated with local elements of reality interacting locally. Here is how: Upon measuring her particle of the entangled pair, Alice smoothly and locally evolves into two non-interacting versions of herself, each of which witnesses and records a different outcome — she foliates [15]. Everything that suitably interacts with the Alices foliates in turn, creating worlds which, for all practical purposes, are independent and autonomous. At spacelike separation, an analogous process occurs to Bob when he measures his particle, locally differentiating him and his surroundings into two non-interacting instances. To confirm the violation of Bell inequalities, Alice and Bob must further interact to produce a record of the joint outcomes. The record arises from the two local worlds of Alice, and those of Bob, and foliates into four instances that respectively indicate ‘0000’, ‘0101’, ‘1010’ and ‘1111’. If at least one input of the CHSH [16] test is ‘0’, the total measure of records displaying the same outcome is cos2(π/8)\cos^{2}(\pi/8); if not, this measure pertains to the records of different outcomes. This article formalizes and explains this local account of Bell ‘nonlocality’.

1 Local Realism Beyond Local Hidden Variables

How can remote measurements on a pair of entangled particles be both genuinely random yet perfectly correlated? That was the puzzle of Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen (EPR), who argued [17] that if locality is to be preserved and quantum theory is empirically adequate, then it ought to be completed. A natural completion is given by hidden variables thought to underpin the source of randomness in measurements. In spite of being unknown, or even perhaps unknowable, these underlying parameters would be determinative of the outcomes. A local hidden variable theory is one in which all influences, including those by and on hidden variables, are constrained by the structure of spacetime, and hence limited by the speed of light. For instance, if two laboratories are spacelike separated, Alice’s freely chosen experimental setting neither affects Bob’s laboratory nor the hidden variables in its vicinity. Building upon the EPR argument, Bell [1] showed that quantum theory’s predictions are incompatible with an underlying determination by local hidden variables. The incompatibility materializes [16] in the experimental measurement of a quantity which ought to be bounded if nature operates by local hidden variables. This is a Bell inequality. According to quantum theory, however, Bell inequalities can be violated. And they are: Ever more convincing experiments systematically corroborate the quantum predictions, thereby refuting the local hidden variable account that Bell formalized.

The most vocal conclusions are that ‘the physical world itself is non-local’ [18] or that ‘we should renounce local realism’ [19] (emphases mine). Some instead posit retrocausality, which ‘includes the existence of backwards-in-time influences’ [20], while others invoke superdeterminism, the assumption that ‘the prepared state of an experiment is never independent of the detector settings’ [21]. But all of the above explanations are cast in a worldview shaped by hidden variables as if they were the only path to reconcile quantum theory with realism, namely the conjectured existence of a real physical world. Hidden variables were indeed a realist defence against the void enforced by Bohr and the Copenhagen school, which effectively forbade the inquiry of actual states of affairs between measurements. But by no means are they the sole realist program. For instance, Raymond-Robichaud [22] showed how Bell inequalities can in principle be violated in a local-realistic way, thereby contradicting the widespread yet misconceived equivalence between local hidden variables and local realism. He did so by inventing a fantasy world where Alice and Bob locally split in bubbles that interact in a way that yields Popescu-Rohrlich correlations [23]. As I shall show, this fantasy shares a lot with reality. The story outlined in the abstract, manifestly local-realistic, is not to be invoked merely as a proof of principle in a toy model: It is how Bell inequalities are actually violated, insofar as we rely on quantum theory, which I shall treat fully unitarily and in the Heisenberg picture.

2 Locality from Unitarity in the Heisenberg Picture

Textbook quantum theory instructs a blatant inconsistency between two types of dynamical laws. On the one hand, all dynamical processes except ‘measurements’ abide by unitary evolution, which is continuous, local, deterministic, and in principle reversible. On the other hand, the so-called ‘measurements’ follow a collapse rule that is discontinuous, non-local, stochastic and irreversible. Everett [13] solved this inconsistency by dismissing the need for the ambiguous yet supposedly consequential notion of ‘measurement’. Measurements are, Everett argues, mere interactions. And observers, other quantum systems. He thus investigated measurement interactions within the unitary quantum theory and showed that in spite of being in superposition and highly entangled with other systems, observers do not directly witness those facts. Instead, they evolve alongside and in relation with other systems in independent and autonomous terms of the wave function, each describing a single classical world. Everett’s proposal not only saved the compatibility of quantum theory with scientific realism, but it made important progress on the question of locality, as it dismissed the instantaneous collapse of the wave function. As a remarkable side-effect of his solution, the totality of what we see around us, the universe, is but a tiny sliver of a much richer multiverse. Full unitarity has provided key insights on the analyses of the EPR [24] and Bell [25, 26] scenarios, like the explanatory possibilities of observers in superposition and the crucial interaction in which observers compare their results, which must also be treated quantum-mechanically. But only so much of locality can be saved in the Schrödinger picture. As Wallace [27, Chapter 8] puts it, ‘in Everettian quantum mechanics interactions are local but states are nonlocal’.

Einstein, whose steadfast defence of locality led to no less than the general theory of relativity, insisted that ‘the real factual situation of system S2S_{2} is independent of what is done with the system S1S_{1}, which is spatially separated from the former’ [28]. This criterion of locality cannot be met by the modes of description offered in the Schrödonger picture. Indeed, if the wave function is intended to capture the real factual situation, then entanglement undermines the required independence: An action on system S1S_{1} alters the same wave function that also describes system S2S_{2}. On the other hand, while reduced density matrices do maintain this independence, they fail to fully represent the real factual situation as they provide an overly superficial account that omits how entangled systems can further interact.

Remarkably, Deutsch and Hayden [14] defied conventional wisdom by demonstrating that the Heisenberg picture admits a mode of description that fulfils Einsteinian locality. Each system possesses a descriptor that remains unchanged by actions on other systems; furthermore, any collection of these descriptors provides an empirically complete description of the composite system, capturing the distribution of any measurement performed on it. This underlying separable [29] ontology is the most satisfactory notion of locality, and it holds notwithstanding entanglement. Descriptors have been used to solve important conundrums: superdense coding [30] and quantum teleportation [31] were offered completely local explanations [32, 14, 33]; the Aharanov–Bohm [34] phase was shown to be locally acquired [35]; and a local-realistic treatment of indistinguishable particles led to the discovery of creation operators for non-abelian anyons [36, 37]. Regarding Bell experiments, the pioneers of descriptors demonstrated [14] that the information about the rotation angles is fully localised and by analyzing the dynamics of specific observables, Rubin [38] showcased how observers evolve into local copies. For descriptors, this amounts to their foliation into relative descriptors, a formalization by Kuypers and Deutsch [15] that is central to my analysis.

3 Descriptors

For a complete and pedagogical exposition of how descriptors work, see Ref. [32]. Here, I provide a less detailed, though sufficient, overview. In the Heisenberg picture, the state is stationary and conveniently set to |0n\rvert 0\rangle^{\otimes n} in quantum computational networks. The uncountably many time-evolving observables can all be obtained from a generating set, namely a set of operators that multiplicatively generate an operator basis. These operators can be chosen in a way that each acts non-trivially on one single system. For each given system, the generators acting on it are encompassed into the descriptor of that system.

Let 𝔘\mathfrak{U} be the whole system considered, and let 𝔔i\mathfrak{Q}_{i} denote the iith qubit. At time 0 the descriptor of 𝔔i\mathfrak{Q}_{i} can be expressed as the pair of operators acting on 𝔘𝔔i𝔔i¯\mathcal{H}^{\mathfrak{U}}\simeq\mathcal{H}^{{\mathfrak{Q}_{i}}}\otimes\mathcal{H}^{\overline{\mathfrak{Q}_{i}}},

𝒒i(0)=(qix(0),qiz(0))=(σx𝟙𝔔i¯,σz𝟙𝔔i¯),\boldsymbol{q}_{i}(0)=\left(q_{ix}(0),\,q_{iz}(0)\right)=\left(\sigma_{x}\otimes\mathds{1}^{\overline{\mathfrak{Q}_{i}}}\,,\,\sigma_{z}\otimes\mathds{1}^{\overline{\mathfrak{Q}_{i}}}\right)\,, (1)

where σx\sigma_{x} and σz\sigma_{z} are the Pauli matrices, and 𝟙𝔔i¯\mathds{1}^{\overline{\mathfrak{Q}_{i}}} is the identity operator on all but 𝔔i\mathfrak{Q}_{i}. As they evolve, descriptors preserve their algebraic relations, so in particular, at any given time, the descriptor components of different qubits commute.

If between time tt and t+1t+1, a gate GG is applied to a set of systems labelled by 𝒥\mathcal{J}, the descriptor of qubit ii evolves according to

𝒒i(t+1)=𝖴G({𝒒j(t)}j𝒥)𝒒i(t)𝖴G({𝒒j(t)}j𝒥),\boldsymbol{q}_{i}(t+1)=\mathsf{U}^{\dagger}_{G}\left(\left\{\boldsymbol{q}_{j}(t)\right\}_{j\in\mathcal{J}}\right)\,\boldsymbol{q}_{i}(t)\,\mathsf{U}_{G}\left(\left\{\boldsymbol{q}_{j}(t)\right\}_{j\in\mathcal{J}}\right)\,, (2)

where 𝖴G()\mathsf{U}_{G}(\cdot) is a fixed operator-valued function characteristic of the gate GG. Note that if i𝒥i\notin\mathcal{J}, the commutation of the components of 𝒒i\boldsymbol{q}_{i} with those of 𝒒j\boldsymbol{q}_{j} ensures that the descriptor of 𝔔i\mathfrak{Q}_{i} ‘is independent of what is done with the system’ labelled by 𝒥\mathcal{J}, as mandated by Ensteinian locality.

Gates have an action on the systems they affect. The Hadamard acts as

H:(qx,qz)(qz,qx),H\,\colon\,\left(q_{x},q_{z}\right)\to\left(q_{z},q_{x}\right)\,, (3)

namely, it switches the components of the descriptor of the affected system, regardless of their expressions when acted upon. A Bloch-sphere rotation around the y^\hat{y}-axis transforms the descriptor as

Rθ:(qx,qz)(cosθqx+sinθqz,sinθqx+cosθqz).R_{\theta}:\quad(q_{x},q_{z})\to\left(\cos\theta q_{x}+\sin\theta q_{z}\,,\,-\sin\theta q_{x}+\cos\theta q_{z}\right)\,. (4)

And the action of the Cnot is

Cnot:{(qcx,qcz)(qtx,qtz)}{(qcxqtx,qcz)(qtx,qczqtz)},{\text{Cnot}}\,\colon\,\left\{\begin{array}[]{lcl}(q_{cx}&,&q_{cz})\vspace{2pt}\\ (q_{tx}&,&q_{tz})\vspace{2pt}\\ \end{array}\right\}\to\left\{\begin{array}[]{lcl}(q_{cx}q_{tx}&,&q_{cz}\hphantom{q_{tz}})\vspace{2pt}\\ (q_{tx}&,&q_{cz}q_{tz})\vspace{2pt}\\ \end{array}\right\}\,, (5)

where the label cc refers to the ccontrol qubit and the label tt to the ttarget qubit.

Any observable 𝒪(t)\mathcal{O}(t) pertaining to a set of systems labelled by 𝒥\mathcal{J} can be expressed as a polynomial in {𝒒j(t)}j𝒥\left\{\boldsymbol{q}_{j}(t)\right\}_{j\in\mathcal{J}}. Its expectation value 𝒪(t)\langle\mathcal{O}(t)\rangle is calculated by bracketing the Heisenberg state. Multiversal measures, or probabilities, are special cases of such calculations. An observable 𝒪(t)\mathcal{O}(t) is sharp [15], if, with respect to the Heisenberg state, it has a definite value, i.e. null variance, 𝒪(t)2=𝒪(t)2\langle\mathcal{O}(t)^{2}\rangle=\langle\mathcal{O}(t)\rangle^{2}.

Let 𝔖\mathfrak{S} be a system with descriptor 𝒔\boldsymbol{s}, which at time tt has a sharp observable. Let UU be a unitary on 𝔖\mathfrak{S} that transforms it into another value of the same sharp observable, and let 𝔔1\mathfrak{Q}_{1} be a control with an unsharp q1z(t)q_{1z}(t). The functional form of the controlled unitary is

𝖴Ctrl-U(𝒒1,𝒔)=P+1(q1z) 1+P1(q1z)𝖴U(𝒔),\mathsf{U}_{\text{Ctrl-$U$}}(\boldsymbol{q}_{1},\boldsymbol{s})=P_{+1}(q_{1z})\,\mathds{1}+P_{-1}(q_{1z})\,\mathsf{U}_{U}(\boldsymbol{s})\,, (6)

where P±1(q1z)=def𝟙±q1z2P_{\pm 1}(q_{1z})\stackrel{{\scriptstyle\text{\tiny{def}}}}{{=}}\frac{\mathds{1}\pm q_{1z}}{2} is a projector. From equations (2) and (6),

𝒔(t+1)=P+1(q1z(t))𝒔(t)𝒔+1(t+1)+P1(q1z(t))𝖴U(𝒔(t))𝒔(t)𝖴U(𝒔(t))𝒔1(t+1).\boldsymbol{s}(t+1)=\underbrace{P_{+1}(q_{1z}(t))\,\boldsymbol{s}(t)}_{\boldsymbol{s}_{+1}(t+1)}\,+\,\underbrace{P_{-1}(q_{1z}(t))\,\mathsf{U}_{U}^{\dagger}(\boldsymbol{s}(t))\,\boldsymbol{s}(t)\,\mathsf{U}_{U}(\boldsymbol{s}(t))}_{\boldsymbol{s}_{-1}(t+1)}\,.

This foliates the system 𝔖\mathfrak{S} in two instances, the relative descriptors 𝒔±1(t+1)=P±1(𝒒1z(t))𝒔(t+1)\boldsymbol{s}_{\pm 1}(t+1)=P_{\pm 1}(\boldsymbol{q}_{1z}(t))\boldsymbol{s}(t+1), each admitting a distinct value of a sharp observable. Under some forthcoming dynamics, they remain distinct and autonomous. For instance, any follow-up unitary VV on 𝔖\mathfrak{S} alone results in

𝒔(t+2)=𝖴V(𝒔+1(t+1))𝒔+1(t+1)𝖴V(𝒔+1(t+1))𝒔+1(t+2)+𝖴V(𝒔1(t+1))𝒔1(t+1)𝖴V(𝒔1(t+1))𝒔1(t+2).\boldsymbol{s}^{{}_{(t+2)}}=\underbrace{\mathsf{U}^{\dagger}_{V}\left(\boldsymbol{s}^{{}_{(t+1)}}_{+1}\right)\,\boldsymbol{s}^{{}_{(t+1)}}_{+1}\,\mathsf{U}_{V}\left(\boldsymbol{s}^{{}_{(t+1)}}_{+1}\right)}_{\boldsymbol{s}^{{}_{(t+2)}}_{+1}}\,+\,\underbrace{\mathsf{U}^{\dagger}_{V}\left(\boldsymbol{s}^{{}_{(t+1)}}_{-1}\right)\boldsymbol{s}^{{}_{(t+1)}}_{-1}\,\mathsf{U}_{V}\left(\boldsymbol{s}^{{}_{(t+1)}}_{-1}\right)}_{\boldsymbol{s}^{{}_{(t+2)}}_{-1}}\,.

4 A Bell Experiment

(q1x,q1z)(q_{1x}\hskip 1.0pt,\,q_{1z})(q2x,q2z)(q_{2x}\hskip 1.0pt,\,q_{2z})HH(q1z,q1x)(q_{1z}\hskip 1.0pt,\,q_{1x})(q1zq2x,q1x)(q_{1z}q_{2x}\hskip 1.0pt,\,q_{1x})(q2x,q2zq1x)(q_{2x}\hskip 1.0pt,\,q_{2z}q_{1x})(qAx,qAz)(q_{Ax}\,,\,q_{Az})(qBx,qBz)(q_{Bx}\,,\,q_{Bz})RθR_{\theta}RϕR_{\phi}(cθq1zq2x+sθq1x,sθq1zq2x+cθq1x)(c_{\theta}q_{1z}q_{2x}+s_{\theta}q_{1x}\hskip 1.0pt,\,-s_{\theta}q_{1z}q_{2x}+c_{\theta}q_{1x})(cϕq2x+sϕq2zq1x,sϕq2x+cϕq2zq1x)(c_{\phi}q_{2x}+s_{\phi}q_{2z}q_{1x}\hskip 1.0pt,\,-s_{\phi}q_{2x}+c_{\phi}q_{2z}q_{1x})𝒔C\boldsymbol{s}_{C}+2{+2}+1{+1}(qAx,qAz(sθq1zq2x+cθq1x))\left(q_{Ax}\hskip 1.0pt,\,q_{Az}(-s_{\theta}q_{1z}q_{2x}+c_{\theta}q_{1x})\right)(qBx,qBz(sϕq2x+cϕq2zq1x))\left(q_{Bx}\hskip 1.0pt,\,q_{Bz}(-s_{\phi}q_{2x}+c_{\phi}q_{2z}q_{1x})\right)𝒔C(5)\boldsymbol{s}_{C}(5)𝒔C(6)\boldsymbol{s}_{C}(6)𝔔1\mathfrak{Q}_{1}𝔔2\mathfrak{Q}_{2}𝔔A\mathfrak{Q}_{A}𝔔B\mathfrak{Q}_{B}𝔖C\mathfrak{S}_{C}t=0t=0t=3t=3t=4t=4t=6t=6
Figure 1: A Bell experiment. Particles 11 and 22 are entangled and shared among Alice and Bob, who perform a rotation in accordance with the input of the Bell test. Upon measuring their particles, they communicate the outcome to Charlie, who records them. All systems are qubits except 𝔖C\mathfrak{S}_{C}, which is a 4-level system represented by a thicker line. It admits a computational observable spectrally decomposed as j=03j|jj|\sum_{j=0}^{3}j|j\rangle\langle j|, which is initially sharp in the 0th eigenvalue. The gate ‘+k+k’ alters |j\rvert j\rangle to |j+k (mod 4)\rvert j+k\text{~{}(mod $4$)}\rangle. Thanks to the locality of descriptors, the calculations are performed directly on the wires, with the help of equations (3), (4) and (5). A descriptor with no time label indicates its initial form, which for qubits is set by equation (1), and for 𝒔C\boldsymbol{s}_{C} is irrelevant for the current purposes. The notations sγs_{\gamma} and cγc_{\gamma} stand for sinγ\sin\gamma and cosγ\cos\gamma.

The computational network of a Bell experiment is displayed in Figure 1. Upon measuring her particle of the entangled pair, Alice smoothly and locally evolves into

𝒒A(4)=𝒒A,+1(4)+𝒒A,1(4).\boldsymbol{q}_{A}(4)=\boldsymbol{q}_{A,+1}(4)+\,\boldsymbol{q}_{A,-1}(4)\,.

Because Alice is entangled, 𝒒A(4)\boldsymbol{q}_{A}(4) admits no sharp observable. Indeed, the expectation values of qAx(4)q_{Ax}(4), qAz(4)q_{Az}(4) and qAy(4)=iqAx(4)qAz(4)q_{Ay}(4)=iq_{Ax}(4)q_{Az}(4) are all zero, which is incompatible with sharpness. Yet as qAzqAz(0)q_{Az}\equiv q_{Az}(0) is sharp with value 11, within each instance 𝒒A,±1(4)=P±1(q1z(3))(qAx,±qAz)\boldsymbol{q}_{A,\,\pm 1}(4)=P_{\pm 1}(q_{1z}(3))\left(q_{Ax}\,,\,\pm q_{Az}\right), a ±1\pm 1 z^\hat{z}-outcome is indicated; each with measure 1/21/2 (see §7.2 in the Supplementary Discussion). At spacelike separation, Bob similarly foliates as 𝒒B(4)=𝒒B,+1(4)+𝒒B,1(4)\boldsymbol{q}_{B}(4)=\boldsymbol{q}_{B,+1}(4)+\,\boldsymbol{q}_{B,-1}(4). Unlike relative states of the Schrödinger picture, relative descriptors are entirely local entities; they only concern individual localized systems. Therefore, Alice’s and Bob’s foliations are independent of each other, as required by Lorentz’s covariance.

Crucially, to confirm the violation of Bell inequalities, Alice and Bob must further interact to produce a record of the joint outcomes. In the single-world orthodoxy, bringing systems together that are each in a definite state merely amounts to convenience for comparison. But in unitary quantum theory, that comparison needs to be analyzed within the theory and, as shall be seen, permits non-trivial arrangements of the outcomes’ measures. Without loss of generality, Charlie first processes Alice’s communication, so between time 44 and 55, he foliates with respect to qAz(4)q_{Az}(4), in a way that mirrors that the foliations previously encountered, 𝒔C(5)=𝒔C,+1(5)+𝒔C,1(5)\boldsymbol{s}_{C}(5)=\boldsymbol{s}_{C,+1}(5)+\,\boldsymbol{s}_{C,-1}(5), with

𝒔C,+1(5)\displaystyle\boldsymbol{s}_{C,+1}(5) =\displaystyle= P+1(qAz(4))𝒔C\displaystyle P_{+1}(q_{Az}(4))\,\boldsymbol{s}_{C}
𝒔C,1(5)\displaystyle\boldsymbol{s}_{C,-1}(5) =\displaystyle= P1(qAz(4))𝖴+2(𝒔C)𝒔C𝖴+2(𝒔C).\displaystyle P_{-1}(q_{Az}(4))\,\mathsf{U}_{+2}^{\dagger}(\boldsymbol{s}_{C})\,\boldsymbol{s}_{C}\,\mathsf{U}_{+2}(\boldsymbol{s}_{C})\,.

When Charlie processes Bob’s communication, both 𝒔C,+1(5)\boldsymbol{s}_{C,+1}(5) and 𝒔C,1(5)\boldsymbol{s}_{C,-1}(5) foliate again:

𝒔C(6)\displaystyle\boldsymbol{s}_{C}(6) =\displaystyle= 𝖴C+1(𝒒B(5),𝒔C,+1(5))𝒔C,+1(5)𝖴C+1(𝒒B(5),𝒔C,+1(5))\displaystyle\mathsf{U}_{\text{C}_{+1}}^{\dagger}\left(\boldsymbol{q}_{B}(5),\boldsymbol{s}_{C,+1}(5)\right)\,\boldsymbol{s}_{C,+1}(5)\,\mathsf{U}_{\text{C}_{+1}}\left(\boldsymbol{q}_{B}(5),\boldsymbol{s}_{C,+1}(5)\right)
+𝖴C+1(𝒒B(5),𝒔C,1(5))𝒔C,1(5)𝖴C+1(𝒒B(5),𝒔C,1(5))\displaystyle\,+\,\mathsf{U}_{\text{C}_{+1}}^{\dagger}\left(\boldsymbol{q}_{B}(5),\boldsymbol{s}_{C,-1}(5)\right)\,\boldsymbol{s}_{C,-1}(5)\,\mathsf{U}_{\text{C}_{+1}}\left(\boldsymbol{q}_{B}(5),\boldsymbol{s}_{C,-1}(5)\right)
=\displaystyle= P+1(qBz(5))P+1(qAz(4))𝒔C\displaystyle P_{+1}(q_{Bz}(5))\,P_{+1}(q_{Az}(4))\,\boldsymbol{s}_{C}
+P1(qBz(5))P+1(qAz(4))𝖴+1(𝒔C)𝒔C𝖴+1(𝒔C)\displaystyle\,+\,P_{-1}(q_{Bz}(5))\,P_{+1}(q_{Az}(4))\,\mathsf{U}_{+1}^{\dagger}(\boldsymbol{s}_{C})\,\boldsymbol{s}_{C}\,\mathsf{U}_{+1}(\boldsymbol{s}_{C})
+P+1(qBz(5))P1(qAz(4))𝖴+2(𝒔C)𝒔C𝖴+2(𝒔C)\displaystyle\,+\,P_{+1}(q_{Bz}(5))\,P_{-1}(q_{Az}(4))\,\mathsf{U}_{+2}^{\dagger}(\boldsymbol{s}_{C})\,\boldsymbol{s}_{C}\,\mathsf{U}_{+2}(\boldsymbol{s}_{C})
+P1(qBz(5))P1(qAz(4))𝖴+3(𝒔C)𝒔C𝖴+3(𝒔C).\displaystyle\,+\,P_{-1}(q_{Bz}(5))\,P_{-1}(q_{Az}(4))\,\mathsf{U}_{+3}^{\dagger}(\boldsymbol{s}_{C})\,\boldsymbol{s}_{C}\,\mathsf{U}_{+3}(\boldsymbol{s}_{C})\,.

The record arises from the two local worlds of Alice, and those of Bob, and foliates into four non-interacting instances that respectively indicate 0000, 0101, 1010 and 1111, in binary. As is calculated in §7.2 of the Supplementary Discussion, the respective measures of those instances are

12(cos2(θϕ2),sin2(θϕ2),sin2(θϕ2),cos2(θϕ2)).\frac{1}{2}\left(\cos^{2}\left(\frac{\theta-\phi}{2}\right),\,\sin^{2}\left(\frac{\theta-\phi}{2}\right),\,\sin^{2}\left(\frac{\theta-\phi}{2}\right),\,\cos^{2}\left(\frac{\theta-\phi}{2}\right)\right)\,. (8)

If the angles are optimally chosen, a cos2(π/8)\cos^{2}(\pi/8) win rate in a CHSH test is obtained (see the Supplementary Discussion §7.1).

5 Relativity

Consider the relativistic twin paradox involving Alice, who has been staying on Earth, and her brother Bob, who has been travelling at high velocity and is currently far away. Should they eventually reunite on Earth, which twin shall be the younger? Invoking the rule of thumb that the traveller is younger to de facto declare Bob younger is generically mistaken, for there is no fact of the matter concerning age relations at spacelike separation. Indeed, different unfoldings of the story lead to different relations. In the most common continuation, Bob returns to Earth and finds himself younger than his stationary sister. Yet, imagine a twist where, during Bob’s journey, Alice embarks on an even faster and more extensive voyage. When she returns to Earth alongside Bob, she is younger than her sibling.

Similarly, there is no fact of the matter about the relationship between spacelike separated worlds because, following the unitarity of quantum theory, local worlds can in principle be altered in a way that affects their future matching. Like with the travelling twins, different continuations lead to different relationships, which are only measured once records about them are generated. For instance, suppose Alice receives input ‘0’ for the CHSH test, and, abiding by the usual protocol (exposed in §7.1), performs no rotation, i.e θ0=0\theta_{0}=0. Consider now the Alice who measured output ‘0’ (or +1+1 of the z^\hat{z} observable). What can she say about the Bob that she will meet? After Bob has followed the protocol and measured, it seems absolute that Alice will meet, within sub-measure cos2π/8\cos^{2}{\pi/8}, a Bob who has also seen output ‘0’. But that is the same mistake that assumes the common continuation. Since no measurement is definitive, Bob — or rather Wigner [39], who has coherent control over Bob — can in principle undo Bob’s measurement, alter the particle’s rotation with RπϕR_{\pi-\phi}, re-measure, and proceed towards Alice to compare results. The Alice who observed ‘0’ then meets with the Bob who observed ‘11’ with measure unity. This practically-hard-yet-theoretically-possible continuation contradicts the absoluteness of the relationship between worlds before systems composing them interact. Bell violations do not occur at spacelike separation.

6 Classicality

The attempted completion of quantum theory by hidden variables is an aspiration to explain the quantum domain with an underlying classical reality. Abiding by the probability calculus that underpins Shannon’s theory [40], hidden variables amount to pieces of genuinely classical information. More precisely, they are the supposed information missing to determine measurement outcomes. Bell’s theorem shows that should they exist, such pieces of classical information cannot be constrained by the causal structure of spacetime, so only conspicuous and problematic mechanisms can save the program. But genuinely classical information does not exist. Indeed, the tables must be turned, and it is the classical realm that demands an underlying quantum explanation. That is the role of decoherence theory [41, 42, 43, 44, 45], which studies how interactions involving also the environment give rise to quasi-classical domains.

(q1x(3),q1z(3))(q_{1x}(3),q_{1z}(3))(q2x(3),q2z(3))(q_{2x}(3),q_{2z}(3))(q¯Ex,q¯Ez)(\bar{q}_{Ex},\bar{q}_{Ez})(q1x(3)q¯Ex,q1z(3))\left(q_{1x}(3)\bar{q}_{Ex}\hskip 1.0pt,\,q_{1z}(3)\right)(qAx,qAz)(q_{Ax}\,,\,q_{Az})(qAx,qAzq1z(3))\left(q_{Ax}\hskip 1.0pt,\,q_{Az}q_{1z}(3)\right)(qAx,qAz)(q_{A^{\prime}x}\,,\,q_{A^{\prime}z})(qAx,qAzqAzq1z(3))\left(q_{A^{\prime}x}\hskip 1.0pt,\,q_{Az}q_{A^{\prime}z}q_{1z}(3)\right)(qA′′x,qA′′z)(q_{A^{\prime\prime}x}\,,\,q_{A^{\prime\prime}z})(qA′′x,qAzqAzqA′′zq1z(3))\left(q_{A^{\prime\prime}x}\hskip 1.0pt,\,q_{Az}q_{A^{\prime}z}q_{A^{\prime\prime}z}q_{1z}(3)\right)𝒔C\boldsymbol{s}_{C}+2{+2}+1{+1}\dots(qB′′x,qBzqBzqB′′zq2z(3))\left(q_{B^{\prime\prime}x}\hskip 1.0pt,\,q_{Bz}q_{B^{\prime}z}q_{B^{\prime\prime}z}q_{2z}(3)\right)𝒔C(6)\boldsymbol{s}^{\prime}_{C}(6)DecoherenceChain reaction\dots𝔔1\mathfrak{Q}_{1}𝔔2\mathfrak{Q}_{2}𝔔E\mathfrak{Q}_{E}𝔔A\mathfrak{Q}_{A}𝔔A\mathfrak{Q}_{A^{\prime}}𝔔A′′\mathfrak{Q}_{A^{\prime\prime}}𝔖C\mathfrak{S}_{C}𝔔B′′\mathfrak{Q}_{B^{\prime\prime}}t=3t=3
Figure 2: The Bell experiment is enhanced with considerations of classicality. First, after 𝔔1\mathfrak{Q}_{1}’s rotation, but before Alice’s measurement, a decoherent interaction involves an environmental system, which contains at least the logical space of a qubit. Its descriptor (q¯Ex,q¯Ez)(\bar{q}_{Ex},\bar{q}_{Ez}) is given by some generic representation of the Pauli algebra, which may differ from that of equation (1). Second, a chain reaction through properly initialized systems 𝔔A\mathfrak{Q}_{A^{\prime}}, 𝔔A′′\mathfrak{Q}_{A^{\prime\prime}} — and generically many more — models classical communication. The non-trivial arrangement of 𝔖C\mathfrak{S}_{C}’s relative descriptors is unhindered by these considerations of classicality.

The processes involving 𝔔A\mathfrak{Q}_{A}, 𝔔B\mathfrak{Q}_{B} and 𝔖C\mathfrak{S}_{C} are classical, according to explanations of what ‘classical’ can mean within quantum theory. As illustrated in Figure 2, after the rotation of Particle 11, a nearby environment can be modelled to interact with 𝔔1\mathfrak{Q}_{1} in a way that stabilizes the z^\hat{z} observable to be measured. The effect is that the unstructured q¯Ex\bar{q}_{Ex} obfuscates q1x(3)q_{1x}(3), but is not copied onto the following systems. Decoherence as such may also affect 𝔔A\mathfrak{Q}_{A}, 𝔔A\mathfrak{Q}_{A^{\prime}}, 𝔔A′′\mathfrak{Q}_{A^{\prime\prime}}, the analogous systems on Bob’s side, or with appropriate generalizations, 𝔖C\mathfrak{S}_{C}. These interactions neither prevent the mergings of Alice’s and Bob’s worlds portrayed in equation (4) nor, therefore, the ability to violate Bell’s inequalities. Such robustness to decoherence is a distinguishing property of classical processes.

Moreover, the realistic physical processes that amount to measuring and eventually communicating an experiment’s result involve more than a single binary system. In fact, in the kind of communication we call ‘classical,’ a precise quantum system is not sent from one location to another; rather, the information is transmitted through a chain reaction in a collection of quantum systems, like 𝔔A\mathfrak{Q}_{A^{\prime}}, 𝔔A′′\mathfrak{Q}_{A^{\prime\prime}}, and generically many more. The resulting descriptor 𝒔C(6)\boldsymbol{s}^{\prime}_{C}(6) admits, like in equation (4), a foliation into four entities, which are only altered insofar as the arguments in P±1()P_{\pm 1}(\cdot) acquire extra factors of qAzqA′′zq_{A^{\prime}z}q_{A^{\prime\prime}z} and qBzqB′′zq_{B^{\prime}z}q_{B^{\prime\prime}z}. As these operators have eigenvalue 11 with respect to the Heisenberg state, the measures in equation (8) are invariant. Systems such as 𝔔A\mathfrak{Q}_{A^{\prime}} and 𝔔A′′\mathfrak{Q}_{A^{\prime\prime}} can also represent parts of a macroscopic Alice. In this light, although the foliation of 𝔔A\mathfrak{Q}_{A} presented in section 4 is one Cnot away from recombining, this fragility is removed when Alice is instantiated with many more degrees of freedom. As the unsharp observable q1z(3)q_{1z}(3) gets copied through the interacting systems, they foliate. Therefore, everything that suitably interacts with the Alices foliates in turn, creating worlds which, for all practical purposes, are independent and autonomous.


I explored how sets of local worlds generated by remote foliations interact in their future lightcone. When entanglement relates the unsharp observables responsible for the foliations, nontrivial arrangements of the worlds’ measures arise as systems further interact. This kind of interference persists even when systems decohere. Therefore, joining lists or comparing statistics, seemingly mundane and classical operations, are not trivial in the multiverse. This unsuspected interaction enables Bell correlations while preserving locality.

7 Supplementary Discussion

The Supplementary Discussion supports and completes the main text with elementary background on Bell’s theorem (§7.1) as well as technical details for calculating multiversal measures (§7.2).

7.1 Bell’s Theorem as a Game

An elementary presentation of Bell’s theorem is presented via the CHSH game [16, 46, 47]. The game is played cooperatively by two players, Alice and Bob, who know the game’s rules and attempt to achieve the highest score. The game occurs when the players are at spacelike separation, ensuring no communication takes place between them. Each player is asked a binary question, 0 or 11, and produces a binary answer, 0 or 11. They win the game if the product of the questions equals the parity of the answers. In other words, if at least one question is 0, Alice and Bob must answer the same bit; otherwise, both questions are 11, and they must answer different bits. Before playing the game, the players are colocated and can agree on a strategy. They can share pieces of classical information or throw coins for common randomness if they deem it helpful.

If Alice opts for a deterministic strategy, her output aa is one of the four functions {0,1}{0,1}\{0,1\}\to\{0,1\} of her input xx, and similarly, a deterministic strategy for Bob consists of b=b(y)b=b(y), for a total of 1616 joint deterministic strategies. To avoid the contradicting bottom line, one (or three) of the following equations must not hold.

a(0)b(0)=0a(0)b(1)=0a(1)b(0)=0a(1)b(1)=10=1.\begin{array}[]{rcl}a(0)\oplus b(0)&=&0\\[2.0pt] a(0)\oplus b(1)&=&0\\[2.0pt] a(1)\oplus b(0)&=&0\\[2.0pt] a(1)\oplus b(1)&=&1\\[2.0pt] \cline{1-3}\cr\\[-10.0pt] 0&=&1\,.\end{array}

This means that deterministic strategies can, at best, win on 33 out of the 44 possible input pairs. Assuming that the questions are independent of any prior knowledge of Alice and Bob, exchanging information or shared randomness cannot improve their cause, so their best-expected win rate is 3/43/4

Sharing Entanglement and the Quantum Strategy

…Unless the players share entangled particles. Let Particles 1 and 2 be in the |Φ+\rvert\Phi^{+}\rangle state. To beat the 3/43/4 win rate at the Bell game, Alice and Bob can perform a Bloch-sphere rotation that depends on their input, as prescribed in Table 1, before measuring their particle.

Input Alice’s Rotation (θ\theta) Bob’s Rotation (ϕ\phi)
0 θ0=0\theta_{0}=0 ϕ0=π4\phi_{0}=\frac{\pi}{4}\hphantom{-}
1 θ1=π2\theta_{1}=\frac{\pi}{2} ϕ1=π4\phi_{1}=-\frac{\pi}{4}
Table 1: The quantum strategy with a shared |Φ+\rvert\Phi^{+}\rangle.

The angles are such that if an input is ‘0’, they differ by π/4\pi/4, and if not, by 3π/43\pi/4. The measurement’s probabilities, given in Table 2, yield an expected win rate of cos2(π/8)\cos^{2}(\pi/8). Larger than 3/43/4.

Input Pair Distribution of Outcomes
0000 0101 1010 1111
(0,0)(0,0) cos2(π/8)/2\cos^{2}(\pi/8)/2 sin2(π/8)/2\sin^{2}(\pi/8)/2 sin2(π/8)/2\sin^{2}(\pi/8)/2 cos2(π/8)/2\cos^{2}(\pi/8)/2
(0,1)(0,1) cos2(π/8)/2\cos^{2}(\pi/8)/2 sin2(π/8)/2\sin^{2}(\pi/8)/2 sin2(π/8)/2\sin^{2}(\pi/8)/2 cos2(π/8)/2\cos^{2}(\pi/8)/2
(1,0)(1,0) cos2(π/8)/2\cos^{2}(\pi/8)/2 sin2(π/8)/2\sin^{2}(\pi/8)/2 sin2(π/8)/2\sin^{2}(\pi/8)/2 cos2(π/8)/2\cos^{2}(\pi/8)/2
(1,1)(1,1) sin2(π/8)/2\sin^{2}(\pi/8)/2 cos2(π/8)/2\cos^{2}(\pi/8)/2 cos2(π/8)/2\cos^{2}(\pi/8)/2 sin2(π/8)/2\sin^{2}(\pi/8)/2
Table 2: Distribution of the quantum strategy for each input pair.

From the Game Back to Physics

How do entangled particles work? The lesson of the Bell game is that it provides a generic way by which they cannot work: The particles’ apparently random outcomes cannot be determined by underlying parameters shared in their common past and constrained by the causal structure of spacetime. Many ‘conclusions’ drawn from Bell’s theorem are attempts to save the hidden variable program by confronting the causal structure. Some turn to non-local actions between particles that can entail a secret coordination of the particle’s response across space. Others advocate superdeterminism, which, viewed in the CHSH game, amounts to positing that the particles knew the questions, so the information λ\lambda initially shared is unusually helpful in order to achieve a winrate better than 3/43/4. Many advocates of Everettian quantum theory simply avoid Bell’s theorem on the basis that the assumption of a single outcome in Bell’s framework is invalid in Everettian quantum theory. While true, this defensive attitude offers no explanation as to how the possibilities given by the coexistence of multiple outcomes operate to violate Bell inequalities. This is what I have demonstrated.

7.2 Calculating Measures

A few more properties of descriptors are provided, and the calculations of measures of 𝒒A(4)\boldsymbol{q}_{A}(4) and 𝒔C(6)\boldsymbol{s}_{C}(6) are explained.

Let GG be the matrix representation of a gate acting nontrivially only on systems labelled by 𝒥\mathcal{J}. Its functional representation 𝖴G\mathsf{U}_{G} satisfies the defining equation

𝖴G({𝒒j(0)}j𝒥)=G,\mathsf{U}_{G}\left(\{\boldsymbol{q}_{j}(0)\}_{j\in\mathcal{J}}\right)=G\,, (9)

which is guaranteed to exist by the generative ability of the components of {𝒒j(0)}j𝒥\{\boldsymbol{q}_{j}(0)\}_{j\in\mathcal{J}}. For instance, if the gate affects qubits 11 and 22, then the matrix GG can be expressed as polynomial in the matrices q1x(0)q_{1x}(0), q1z(0)q_{1z}(0), q2x(0)q_{2x}(0), q2z(0)q_{2z}(0), and 𝖴G\mathsf{U}_{G} is one such polynomial.

Descriptors evolve as operators do, namely,

𝒒i(t)=U𝒒i(0)U,\boldsymbol{q}_{i}(t)=U^{\dagger}\boldsymbol{q}_{i}(0)U\,,

where UU denotes the matrix form of the evolution of the whole network between time 0 and time tt. This more familiar evolution is equivalent to the step-by-step evolution of Eq. (2). Indeed let VV and GG be the matrices of the dynamical operators occurring between time 0 and tt and between time tt and t+1t+1, respectively. Then,

VG𝒒i(0)GV\displaystyle V^{\dagger}G^{\dagger}\boldsymbol{q}_{i}(0)GV =\displaystyle= V𝖴G({𝒒j(0)}j𝒥)VV𝒒i(0)VV𝖴G({𝒒j(0)}j𝒥)V\displaystyle V^{\dagger}\mathsf{U}^{\dagger}_{G}\left(\{\boldsymbol{q}_{j}(0)\}_{j\in\mathcal{J}}\right)V\,V^{\dagger}\boldsymbol{q}_{i}(0)V\,V^{\dagger}\mathsf{U}_{G}\left(\{\boldsymbol{q}_{j}(0)\}_{j\in\mathcal{J}}\right)V
=\displaystyle= 𝖴G({V𝒒j(0)V}j𝒥)V𝒒i(0)V𝖴G({V𝒒j(0)V}j𝒥)\displaystyle\mathsf{U}^{\dagger}_{G}\left(\{V^{\dagger}\boldsymbol{q}_{j}(0)V\}_{j\in\mathcal{J}}\right)\,V^{\dagger}\boldsymbol{q}_{i}(0)V\,\mathsf{U}_{G}\left(\{V^{\dagger}\boldsymbol{q}_{j}(0)V\}_{j\in\mathcal{J}}\right)
=\displaystyle= 𝖴G({𝒒j(t1)}j𝒥)𝒒i(t1)𝖴G({𝒒j(t1)}j𝒥).\displaystyle\mathsf{U}^{\dagger}_{G}\left(\{\boldsymbol{q}_{j}(t-1)\}_{j\in\mathcal{J}}\right)\,\boldsymbol{q}_{i}(t-1)\,\mathsf{U}_{G}\left(\{\boldsymbol{q}_{j}(t-1)\}_{j\in\mathcal{J}}\right)\,.

The second equality holds because in each term of the polynomial 𝖴G({V𝒒j(0)V}j𝒥)\mathsf{U}_{G}\left(\{V^{\dagger}\boldsymbol{q}_{j}(0)V\}_{j\in\mathcal{J}}\right), products will have their inner VV^{\dagger}s and VVs cancelled, leaving only the outer ones, which can be factorised outside of the polynomial to retrieve the first line.

As is usual for qubits, the +1+1 and 1-1 eigenvalues of the z^\hat{z} observable are identified respectively with the computational values 0 and 11. The multiversal measure of Alice witnessing outcome i{0,1}i\in\{0,1\} is given by the expectation of the observable |ii|𝔔A𝟙𝔔A¯|i\rangle\langle i|^{\mathfrak{Q}_{A}}\otimes\mathds{1}^{\overline{\mathfrak{Q}_{A}}}. Letting UU denote the whole unitary operator between time 0 and 44, and recalling that the Heisenberg state is |0n|𝟎\rvert 0\rangle^{\otimes n}\equiv\rvert\boldsymbol{0}\rangle, this expectation is

U(|ii|𝔔A𝟙𝔔A¯)U\displaystyle\left\langle U^{\dagger}\left(|i\rangle\langle i|^{\mathfrak{Q}_{A}}\otimes\mathds{1}^{\overline{\mathfrak{Q}_{A}}}\right)U\right\rangle =\displaystyle= UP(1)i(qAz(0))U\displaystyle\langle U^{\dagger}P_{(-1)^{i}}(q_{Az}(0))U\rangle
=\displaystyle= P(1)i(qAz(4))\displaystyle\langle P_{(-1)^{i}}(q_{Az}(4))\rangle
=\displaystyle= 12+(1)i𝟎|qAz(sinθq1zq2x+cosθq1x)|𝟎2\displaystyle\frac{1}{2}+(-1)^{i}\frac{\langle\boldsymbol{0}\rvert q_{Az}(-\sin{\theta}q_{1z}q_{2x}+\cos{\theta}q_{1x})\rvert\boldsymbol{0}\rangle}{2}
=\displaystyle= 12.\displaystyle\frac{1}{2}\,.

For ii, j{0,1}j\in\{0,1\}, let |ij\rvert ij\rangle denote in binary the eigenstates of the computational observable of 𝔖C\mathfrak{S}_{C}. The measure of Charlie witnessing ijij is given by the expectation of the observables |ijij|𝔖C𝟙𝔖C¯|ij\rangle\langle ij|^{\mathfrak{S}_{C}}\otimes\mathds{1}^{\overline{\mathfrak{S}_{C}}}, which can be expressed as a function fij(𝒔C(0))f_{ij}(\boldsymbol{s}_{C}(0)) of 𝔖C\mathfrak{S}_{C}’s initial descriptor. Without even knowing the form of 𝒔C(0)\boldsymbol{s}_{C}(0), its generative abilities guarantee that one can construct from it any functional form of a gate concerning 𝔖C\mathfrak{S}_{C}, as well as any observables pertaining to 𝔖C\mathfrak{S}_{C}. At time 66, the observables can be expressed with the help of Eq. (4) as

fij(𝒔C(6))\displaystyle f_{ij}(\boldsymbol{s}_{C}(6)) =\displaystyle= P+1(qBz(5))P+1(qAz(4))fij(𝒔C)\displaystyle P_{+1}(q_{Bz}(5))\,P_{+1}(q_{Az}(4))\,f_{ij}(\boldsymbol{s}_{C})
+P1(qBz(5))P+1(qAz(4))𝖴+1(𝒔C)fij(𝒔C)𝖴+1(𝒔C)\displaystyle\,+\,P_{-1}(q_{Bz}(5))\,P_{+1}(q_{Az}(4))\,\mathsf{U}_{+1}^{\dagger}(\boldsymbol{s}_{C})\,f_{ij}(\boldsymbol{s}_{C})\,\mathsf{U}_{+1}(\boldsymbol{s}_{C})
+P+1(qBz(5))P1(qAz(4))𝖴+2(𝒔C)fij(𝒔C)𝖴+2(𝒔C)\displaystyle\,+\,P_{+1}(q_{Bz}(5))\,P_{-1}(q_{Az}(4))\,\mathsf{U}_{+2}^{\dagger}(\boldsymbol{s}_{C})\,f_{ij}(\boldsymbol{s}_{C})\,\mathsf{U}_{+2}(\boldsymbol{s}_{C})
+P1(qBz(5))P1(qAz(4))𝖴+3(𝒔C)fij(𝒔C)𝖴+3(𝒔C),\displaystyle\,+\,P_{-1}(q_{Bz}(5))\,P_{-1}(q_{Az}(4))\,\mathsf{U}_{+3}^{\dagger}(\boldsymbol{s}_{C})\,f_{ij}(\boldsymbol{s}_{C})\,\mathsf{U}_{+3}(\boldsymbol{s}_{C})\,,

where again 𝒔C\boldsymbol{s}_{C} without label refers to its initial form, which in this case is the same at times 0 and 44. Using the defining equation (9), 𝖴+k(𝒔C)\mathsf{U}_{+k}(\boldsymbol{s}_{C}) amounts to the gate ‘+k+k’ in its matrix form. This is useful to compute 𝟎|fij(𝒔C(6))|𝟎\langle\boldsymbol{0}\rvert f_{ij}(\boldsymbol{s}_{C}(6))\rvert\boldsymbol{0}\rangle from the right. In each term, ‘+k+k’ transforms the Heisenberg state to |k𝔖C|𝟎𝔖C¯{\rvert k\rangle}^{\mathfrak{S}_{C}}\otimes{\rvert\boldsymbol{0}\rangle}^{\overline{\mathfrak{S}_{C}}}, which cancels upon finding fij(𝒔C)f_{ij}(\boldsymbol{s}_{C}) except for the term where k=ijk=ij in binary. The operator 𝖴+k(𝒔C)\mathsf{U}_{+k}^{\dagger}(\boldsymbol{s}_{C}) transforms back |k\rvert k\rangle to |0\rvert 0\rangle, leaving P(1)i(𝒒Az(4))P(1)j(𝒒Bz(5))\langle P_{(-1)^{i}}(\boldsymbol{q}_{Az}(4))P_{(-1)^{j}}(\boldsymbol{q}_{Bz}(5))\rangle. This can then be calculated:

P(1)i(qAz(sθq1zq2x+cθq1x))P(1)j(qBz(sϕq2x+cϕq2zq1x))\displaystyle\left\langle P_{(-1)^{i}}(q_{Az}(-s_{\theta}q_{1z}q_{2x}+c_{\theta}q_{1x}))P_{(-1)^{j}}(q_{Bz}(-s_{\phi}q_{2x}+c_{\phi}q_{2z}q_{1x}))\right\rangle
=\displaystyle= 14+(1)i+j(qAz(sθq1zq2x+cθq1x))(qBz(sϕq2x+cϕq2zq1x))\displaystyle\frac{1}{4}+(-1)^{i+j}\langle(q_{Az}(-s_{\theta}q_{1z}q_{2x}+c_{\theta}q_{1x}))(q_{Bz}(-s_{\phi}q_{2x}+c_{\phi}q_{2z}q_{1x}))\rangle
=\displaystyle= 14+(1)i+j(sθsϕ+cθcϕ)4\displaystyle\frac{1}{4}+(-1)^{i+j}\frac{(s_{\theta}s_{\phi}+c_{\theta}c_{\phi})}{4}
=\displaystyle= 14+(1)i+j(cos(θϕ))4\displaystyle\frac{1}{4}+(-1)^{i+j}\frac{(\cos(\theta-\phi))}{4}
=\displaystyle= {12cos2(θϕ2)if i=j12sin2(θϕ2)if ij.\displaystyle\begin{cases}\frac{1}{2}\cos^{2}\left(\frac{\theta-\phi}{2}\right)&\text{if }i=j\\ \frac{1}{2}\sin^{2}\left(\frac{\theta-\phi}{2}\right)&\text{if }i\neq j\,.\end{cases}

Aknowledgements

I am grateful to David Deutsch for discussions, to Xavier Coiteux-Roy for comments on an earlier version of this article, and to Samuel Kuypers for both. This work was supported by the Fonds de recherche du Québec – Nature et technologie, the Swiss National Science Foundation, and the Hasler Foundation.

References

  • [1] John S Bell. On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen paradox. Physics, 1(3):195–200, 1964.
  • [2] Stuart J Freedman and John F Clauser. Experimental test of local hidden-variable theories. Physical Review Letters, 28(14):938, 1972.
  • [3] Alain Aspect, Philippe Grangier, and Gérard Roger. Experimental tests of realistic local theories via Bell’s theorem. Physical Review Letters, 47(7):460, 1981.
  • [4] Alain Aspect, Philippe Grangier, and Gérard Roger. Experimental realization of Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen-Bohm Gedankenexperiment: a new violation of Bell’s inequalities. Physical Review Letters, 49(2):91, 1982.
  • [5] Alain Aspect, Jean Dalibard, and Gérard Roger. Experimental test of Bell’s inequalities using time-varying analyzers. Physical Review Letters, 49(25):1804, 1982.
  • [6] Gregor Weihs, Thomas Jennewein, Christoph Simon, Harald Weinfurter, and Anton Zeilinger. Violation of Bell’s inequality under strict Einstein locality conditions. Physical Review Letters, 81(23):5039, 1998.
  • [7] Jian-Wei Pan, Dik Bouwmeester, Matthew Daniell, Harald Weinfurter, and Anton Zeilinger. Experimental test of quantum nonlocality in three-photon greenberger–horne–zeilinger entanglement. Nature, 403(6769):515–519, 2000.
  • [8] Bas Hensen, Hannes Bernien, Anaïs E Dréau, Andreas Reiserer, Norbert Kalb, Machiel S Blok, Just Ruitenberg, Raymond FL Vermeulen, Raymond N Schouten, Carlos Abellán, et al. Loophole-free Bell inequality violation using electron spins separated by 1.3 kilometres. Nature, 526(7575):682–686, 2015.
  • [9] Marissa Giustina, Marijn AM Versteegh, Sören Wengerowsky, Johannes Handsteiner, Armin Hochrainer, Kevin Phelan, Fabian Steinlechner, Johannes Kofler, Jan-Åke Larsson, Carlos Abellán, et al. Significant-loophole-free test of Bell’s theorem with entangled photons. Physical Review Letters, 115(25):250401, 2015.
  • [10] Lynden K Shalm, Evan Meyer-Scott, Bradley G Christensen, Peter Bierhorst, Michael A Wayne, Martin J Stevens, Thomas Gerrits, Scott Glancy, Deny R Hamel, Michael S Allman, et al. Strong loophole-free test of local realism. Physical Review Letters, 115(25):250402, 2015.
  • [11] The Nobel Committee for Physics. Scientific background on the Nobel Prize in physics 2022. The Royal Swedish Academy of Sciences, October 2022. https://www.nobelprize.org/uploads/2023/10/advanced-physicsprize2022-4.pdf (accessed in June 2024).
  • [12] W Heisenberg. Über quantentheoretische umdeutung kinematischer und mechanischer beziehungen. Zeitschrift für Physik, 33(1):879–893, 1925.
  • [13] Hugh Everett III. The theory of the universal wave function. In Bryce DeWitt and Neill Graham, editors, The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics, pages 3–140. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 1973.
  • [14] David Deutsch and Patrick Hayden. Information flow in entangled quantum systems. Proceedings of the Royal Society A. Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences, 456(1999):1759–1774, 2000.
  • [15] Samuel Kuypers and David Deutsch. Everettian relative states in the Heisenberg picture. Proceedings of the Royal Society A, 477(2246):20200783, 2021.
  • [16] John F. Clauser, Michael A. Horne, Abner Shimony, and Richard A. Holt. Proposed experiment to test local hidden-variable theories. Physical Review Letters, 23(15):880–884, 1969.
  • [17] Albert Einstein, Boris Podolsky, and Nathan Rosen. Can quantum-mechanical description of physical reality be considered complete? Physical Review, 47(10):777, 1935.
  • [18] Tim Maudlin. What Bell did. Journal of Physics A: Mathematical and Theoretical, 47(42):424010, 2014.
  • [19] Alain Aspect. Closing the door on Einstein and Bohr’s quantum debate. Physics, 8:123, 2015.
  • [20] Roderick Ian Sutherland. Causally symmetric Bohm model. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 39(4):782–805, 2008.
  • [21] Sabine Hossenfelder and Tim Palmer. Rethinking superdeterminism. Frontiers in Physics, 8:139, 2020.
  • [22] Gilles Brassard and Paul Raymond-Robichaud. Parallel lives: A local-realistic interpretation of “nonlocal” boxes. Entropy, 21(1):87, 2019.
  • [23] Sandu Popescu and Daniel Rohrlich. Quantum nonlocality as an axiom. Foundations of Physics, 24(3):379–385, 1994.
  • [24] Don N Page. The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen physical reality is completely described by quantum mechanics. Physics Letters A, 91(2):57–60, 1982.
  • [25] Frank J Tipler. Does quantum nonlocality exist? Bell’s theorem and the many-worlds interpretation. arXiv preprint quant-ph/0003146, 2000.
  • [26] Harvey R Brown and Christopher G Timpson. Bell on Bell’s theorem: The changing face of nonlocality. arXiv preprint arXiv:1501.03521, 2014.
  • [27] David Wallace. The Emergent Multiverse: Quantum Theory According to the Everett Interpretation. Oxford University Press, 2012.
  • [28] Paul A Schilpp. Albert Einstein: philosopher-scientist, volume 7. Open Court Publishing Co., 3d revised edition, 1970.
  • [29] Don Howard. Einstein on locality and separability. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 16(3):171–201, 1985.
  • [30] Charles H Bennett and Stephen J Wiesner. Communication via one-and two-particle operators on Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen states. Physical review letters, 69(20):2881, 1992.
  • [31] Charles H Bennett, Gilles Brassard, Claude Crépeau, Richard Jozsa, Asher Peres, and William K Wootters. Teleporting an unknown quantum state via dual classical and Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen channels. Physical Review Letters, 70(13):1895, 1993.
  • [32] Charles Alexandre Bédard. The ABC of Deutsch–Hayden descriptors. Quantum Reports, 3(2):272–285, 2021.
  • [33] Charles Alexandre Bédard. Teleportation revealed. Quantum Reports, 5(2):510–525, 2023.
  • [34] Yakir Aharonov and David Bohm. Significance of electromagnetic potentials in the quantum theory. Physical review, 115(3):485, 1959.
  • [35] Chiara Marletto and Vlatko Vedral. Aharonov-Bohm phase is locally generated like all other quantum phases. Physical Review Letters, 125(4):040401, 2020.
  • [36] N Tibau Vidal. On the locality of indistinguishable quantum systems. PhD thesis, University of Oxford, 2023.
  • [37] Nicetu Tibau Vidal and Lucia Vilchez-Estevez. Creation and annihilation operators for 2d non-abelian anyons. arXiv preprint arXiv:2304.10462, 2023.
  • [38] Mark A Rubin. Locality in the Everett interpretation of Heisenberg-picture quantum mechanics. Foundations of Physics Letters, 14:301–322, 2001.
  • [39] Eugene P Wigner. Remarks on the mind-body question. Indiana University Press, 1961.
  • [40] Claude E Shannon. A mathematical theory of communication. The Bell System Technical Journal, 27:379–423, 1948.
  • [41] H Dieter Zeh. On the interpretation of measurement in quantum theory. Foundations of Physics, 1(1):69–76, 1970.
  • [42] Wojciech H Zurek. Pointer basis of quantum apparatus: Into what mixture does the wave packet collapse? Physical review D, 24(6):1516, 1981.
  • [43] Wojciech H Zurek. Environment-induced superselection rules. Physical review D, 26(8):1862, 1982.
  • [44] Murray Gell-Mann and James B Hartle. Classical equations for quantum systems. Physical Review D, 47(8):3345, 1993.
  • [45] Erich Joos, H. Dieter Zeh, Claus Kiefer, Domenico Giulini, Joachim Kupsch, and Ion-Olimpiu Stamatescu. Decoherence and the Appearance of a Classical World in Quantum Theory. Number XII, 496. Springer Berlin, Heidelberg, 2 edition, 2003.
  • [46] Richard Cleve, Peter Hoyer, Benjamin Toner, and John Watrous. Consequences and limits of nonlocal strategies. In Proceedings. 19th IEEE Annual Conference on Computational Complexity, 2004., pages 236–249. IEEE, 2004.
  • [47] Nicolas Gisin. Quantum chance: Nonlocality, teleportation and other quantum marvels. Springer, 2014.