The Halász–Székely Barycenter
Abstract.
We introduce a notion of barycenter of a probability measure related to the symmetric mean of a collection of nonnegative real numbers. Our definition is inspired by the work of Halász and Székely, who in 1976 proved a law of large numbers for symmetric means. We study analytic properties of this Halász–Székely barycenter. We establish fundamental inequalities that relate the symmetric mean of a list of nonnegative real numbers with the barycenter of the measure uniformly supported on these points. As consequence, we go on to establish an ergodic theorem stating that the symmetric means of a sequence of dynamical observations converges to the Halász–Székely barycenter of the corresponding distribution.
2020 Mathematics Subject Classification:
26E60; 26D15, 15A15, 37A30, 60F151. Introduction
Means have fascinated man for a long time. Ancient Greeks knew the arithmetic, geometric, and harmonic means of two positive numbers (which they may have learned from the Babylonians); they also studied other types of means that can be defined using proportions: see [He, pp. 85–89]. Newton and Maclaurin encountered the symmetric means (more about them later). Huygens introduced the notion of expected value and Jacob Bernoulli proved the first rigorous version of the law of large numbers: see [Mai, pp. 51, 73]. Gauss and Lagrange exploited the connection between the arithmetico-geometric mean and elliptic functions: see [BB]. Kolmogorov and other authors considered means from an axiomatic point of view and determined when a mean is arithmetic under a change of coordinates (i.e. quasiarithmetic): see [HLP, p. 157–163], [AD, Chapter 17]. Means and inequalities between them are the main theme of the classical book [HLP] by Hardy, Littlewood, and Pólya, and the book [Bu] by Bullen is a comprehensive account of the subject. Going beyond the real line, there are notions of averaging that relate to the geometric structure of the ambient space: see e.g. [St, EM, Na, KLL].
In this paper, we are interested in one of the most classical types of means: the elementary symmetric polynomials means, or symmetric means for short. Let us recall their definition. Given integers , the -th symmetric mean of a list of nonnegative numbers is:
(1.1) |
where is the elementary symmetric polynomial of degree in variables. Note that the extremal cases and correspond to arithmetic and the geometric means, respectively. The symmetric means are non-increasing as functions of : this is Maclaurin’s inequality: see [HLP, p. 52] or [Bu, p. 327]. For much more information on symmetric means and their relatives, see [Bu, Chapter V].
Let us now turn to Probability Theory. A law of large numbers in terms of symmetric means was obtained by Halász and Székely [HS], confirming a conjecture of Székely [Sz1]. Let , , …be a sequence of nonnegative independent identically distributed random variables, and from them we form another sequence of random variables:
(1.2) |
The case of corresponds to the setting of the usual law of large numbers. The case of constant is not significantly different from the classical setting. Things become more interesting if is allowed to depend on , and it turns out to be advantageous to assume that converges to some number . In this case, Halász and Székely [HS] have proved that if is strictly positive and satisfies some integrability conditions, then converges almost surely to a non-random constant. Furthermore, they gave a formula for this limit, which we call the Halász–Székely mean with parameter of the random variable . Halász and Székely theorem was extended to the nonnegative situation by van Es [vE] (with appropriate extra hypotheses). The simplest example consists of a random variable that takes two nonnegative values and , each with probability , and ; in this case the Halász–Székely mean is . But this example is misleadingly simple, and Halász–Székely means are in general unrelated to power means.
Fixed the parameter , the Halász–Székely mean of a nonnegative random variable only depends on its distribution, which we regard as a probability measure on the half-line . Now we shift our point of view and consider probability measures as the fundamental objects. Instead of speaking of the mean of a probability measure, we prefer the word barycenter, reserving the word mean for lists of numbers (with or without weights), functions, and random variables. This is more than a lexical change. The space of probability measures has a great deal of structure: it is a convex space and it can be endowed with several topologies. So we arrive at the notion of Halász–Székely barycenter (or HS barycenter) of a probability measure with parameter , which we denote . This is the subject of this paper. It turns out that HS barycenters can be defined directly, without resort to symmetric means or laws of large numbers (see Definition 2.3).
Symmetric means are intrinsically discrete objects and do not make sense as barycenters. In [Bu, Remark, p. 323], Bullen briefly proposes a definition of a weighted symmetric mean, only to conclude that “the properties of this weighted mean are not satisfactory” and therefore not worthy of further consideration. On the other hand, given a finite list of nonnegative numbers, we can compare the symmetric means of with the HS barycenter of the associated probability measure . It turns out that these quantities obey certain precise inequalities (see Theorem 3.4). In particular, we have:
(1.3) |
Furthermore, if denotes the -tuple obtained by concatenation of copies of , then
(1.4) |
and we have precise bounds for the relative error of this approximation, depending only on the parameters and not on the numbers themselves.
Being a natural limit of symmetric means, the HS barycenters deserve to be studied by their own right. One can even argue that they give the “right” notion of weighted symmetric means that Bullen was looking for. HS barycenters have rich theoretical properties. They are also cheap to compute, while computing symmetric means involves summing exponentially many terms.
Using our general inequalities and certain continuity properties of the HS barycenters, we are able to obtain in straightforward manner an ergodic theorem that extends the laws of large numbers of Halász–Székely [HS] and van Es [vE].
A prominent feature of the symmetric mean (1.1) is that it vanishes whenever more than of the numbers vanish. Consequently, the HS barycenter of a probability measure on vanishes when . In other words, once the mass of leftmost point exceeds the critical value , then it imposes itself on the whole distribution, and suddenly forces the mean to agree with it. Fortunately, in the subcritical regime, , the HS barycenter turns out to be much better behaved. As it will be seen in Section 2, in the critical case the HS barycenter can be either positive or zero, so the HS barycenter can actually vary discontinuously. Therefore our regularity results and the ergodic theorem must take this critical phenomenon into account.
This article is organized as follows. In Section 2, we define formally the HS barycenters and prove some of their basic properties. In Section 3, we state and prove the fundamental inequalities relating HS barycenters to symmetric means. In Section 4, we study the problem of continuity of the HS barycenters with respect to appropriate topologies on spaces of probability measures. In Section 5, we apply the results of the previous sections and derive a general ergodic theorem (law of large numbers) for symmetric and HS means. In Section 6, we turn back to fundamentals and discuss concavity properties of the HS barycenters and means. Finally, in Section 7 we introduce a different kind of barycenter which is a natural approximation of the HS barycenter, but has in a sense simpler theoretical properties.
2. Presenting the HS barycenter
Hardy, Littlewood, and Pólya’s axiomatization of (quasiarithmetic) means [HLP, § 6.19] is formulated in terms of distribution functions, using Stieltjes integrals. Since the first publication of their book in 1934, measures became established as fundamental objects in mathematical analysis, probability theory, dynamical systems, etc. Spaces of measures have been investigated in depth (see e.g. the influential books [Pa, Vi]). The measure-theoretic point of view provides the convenient structure for the analytic study of means or, as we prefer to call them in this case, barycenters. The simplest example of barycenter is of course the “arithmetic barycenter” of a probability measure on Euclidean space , defined (under the appropriate integrability condition) as . Another example is the “geometric barycenter” of a probability measure on the half-line , defined as . In this section, we introduce the Hallász–Székely barycenters and study some of their basic properties.
2.1. Definitions and basic properties
Throughout this paper we use the following notations:
(2.1) |
We routinely work with the extended line , endowed with the order topology.
Definition 2.1.
The Halász–Székely kernel (or HS kernel) is the following function of three variables , , and :
(2.2) |
Proposition 2.2.
The HS kernel has the following properties (see also Fig. 1):
-
(a)
The function is continuous, attaining the value only at the points .
-
(b)
is increasing with respect to .
-
(c)
is decreasing with respect to , and strictly decreasing when .
-
(d)
is independent of .
-
(e)
, with equality if and only if or .
-
(f)
For each , the function is affine, and its graph is the tangent line to at .
-
(g)
, for all .
Proof.
Most properties are immediate from Definition 2.1. To check monotonicity with respect to , we compute the partial derivative when :
(2.3) |

Let denote the set of all Borel probability measures on . The following is the central concept of this paper:
Definition 2.3.
Let and . If , then we require that the function is semi-integrable111A function is called semi-integrable if the positive part is integrable or the negative part is integrable. with respect to . The Halász–Székely barycenter (or HS barycenter) with parameter of the probability measure is:
(2.4) |
where is the HS kernel (2.2).
First of all, let us see that the definition is meaningful:
-
•
If , then for all , the function is bounded from below by , and therefore it has a well-defined integral (possibly ); so is a well-defined element of the extended half-line .
-
•
If , then by part (d) of Proposition 2.2, the defining formula (2.4) becomes:
(2.5) The integral is a well-defined element of , so is well-defined in .
Formula (2.5) means that the HS barycenter with parameter is the geometric barycenter; let us see that corresponds to the standard arithmetic barycenter:
Proposition 2.4.
For any , we have .
Proof.
Let . If , then for every , the non-constant affine function has infinite integral, so definition (2.4) gives . On the other hand, if , then is defined as . ∎
Let denote the subset formed by those such that:
(2.6) |
or, equivalently, (we will sometimes write “” instead of “”).
Proposition 2.5.
Let and . Then if and only if .
Proof.
The case being clear, assume that . Note that for all , the expression
(2.7) |
is a bounded function of , so the integrability of and are equivalent. ∎
Next, let us see that the standard properties one might expect for something called a “barycenter” are satisfied. For any , we denote by the probability measure such that .
Proposition 2.6.
For all and , the following properties hold:
-
(a)
Reflexivity: , for every .
-
(b)
Monotonicity with respect to the measure: If , have distribution functions , such that 222I.e., is “more to the right” than . This defines a partial order, called usual stochastic ordering or first order stochastic dominance., then .
-
(c)
Internality: If for an interval , then .
-
(d)
Homogeneity: If , and denotes the pushforward of under the map , then .
-
(e)
Monotonicity with respect to the parameter: If , then .
Proof.
The proofs use the properties of the HS kernel listed in Proposition 2.2. Reflexivity is obvious when when or , and in all other cases follows from property (e). Monotonicity with respect to the measure is a consequence of the fact that the HS kernel is increasing in . The internality property of the HS barycenter follows from reflexivity and monotonicity. Homogeneity follows from property (g) of the HS kernel and the change of variables formula. Finally, monotonicity with respect to the parameter is a consequence of the corresponding property of the HS kernel. ∎
As it will be clear later (see Example 2.13), the internality and the monotonicity properties (w.r.t. and w.r.t. ) are not strict.
2.2. Computation and critical phenomenon
In the remaining of this section, we discuss how to actually compute HS barycenters. In view of Proposition 2.5, we may focus on measures in . The mass of zero plays an important role. Given and , we use the following terminology, where :
(2.8) |
The next result establishes a way to compute in the subcritical case; the remaining cases will be dealt with later in Proposition 2.11.
Proposition 2.7.
If , and (subcritical case), then the equation
(2.9) |
has a unique positive and finite solution , and the in formula (2.4) is attained uniquely at ; in particular,
(2.10) |
Proof.
Fix and as in the statement. We compute the partial derivative:
(2.11) |
Since is bounded, we are allowed to differentiate under the integral sign:
(2.12) |
where . The partial derivative
(2.13) |
is positive, except at . Since , the function is strictly increasing. Furthermore,
(2.14) |
and so
(2.15) |
using the assumption . Therefore there exists a unique that solves the equation , or equivalenlty equation (2.9). By (2.12), the function decreases on and increases on , and so attains its infimum at . Formula (2.10) follows from the definition of . ∎
Remark 2.8.
If belongs to but not to , and still , then equation (2.9) (or its equivalent version (2.16)) still has a unique positive and finite solution , and formula (2.10) still holds. On the other hand, if and , then all conclusions of Proposition 2.7 still hold, with a similar proof.
We introduce the following auxiliary function, plotted in Fig. 2:
(2.17) |

The following alternative formula for the HS barycenter matches the original one from [HS], and in some situations is more convenient:
Proposition 2.9.
If and , then:
(2.18) |
Furthermore, if , then the is attained at the unique positive finite solution of the equation
(2.19) |
Proof.
If is a Borel probability measure on not entirely concentrated at zero (i.e., ) then we denote by the probability measure obtained by conditioning on the event , that is,
(2.20) |
Obviously, if , then as well.
Proposition 2.10.
Let and . If and (critical or subcritical cases), then
(2.21) |
Proof.
Finally, we compute the HS barycenter in the critical and supercritical cases:
Proposition 2.11.
Let and .
-
(a)
Critical case: If , then .
-
(b)
Supercritical case: If , then .
In both cases above, the infimum in formula (2.4) is not attained.
Proof.
In the critical case, we use (2.21) with and conclude.
In the supercritical case, we can assume that . Note that , thus . Moreover, since , we have
(2.26) |
Therefore, using (2.25), we obtain . ∎
Propositions 2.7 and 2.11 allow us to compute HS barycenters in all cases. For emphasis, let us list explicitly the situations where the barycenter vanishes:
Proposition 2.12.
Let and . Then if and only if one of the following mutually exclusive situations occur:
-
(a)
and .
-
(b)
, , and .
-
(c)
and .
Proof.
The case being obvious, assume that , and so . In the critical case, part (a) of Proposition 2.11 tells us that if and only if , which by (2.5) is equivalent to . In the supercritical case, part (b) of the Proposition ensures that . ∎
Example 2.13.
Consider the family of probability measures:
(2.27) |
If , then
(2.28) |
These formulas were first obtained by Székely [Sz1]. It follows that the function
(2.29) |
(whose graph is shown on [vE, p. 680]) is discontinuous at the points with , and only at those points. We will return to the issue of continuity in Section 4.
The practical computation of HS barycenters usually requires numerical methods. In any case, it is useful to notice that the function from Proposition 2.7 satisfies the internality property:
Lemma 2.14.
Let , , and suppose that . If for an interval , then .
The proof is left to the reader.
3. Comparison with the symmetric means
3.1. HS means as repetitive symmetric means
The HS barycenter of a probability measure, introduced in the previous section, may now be specialized to the case of discrete equidistributed probabilities. So the HS mean of a tuple of nonnegative numbers with parameter is defined as:
(3.1) |
Using (2.18), we have more explicitly:
(3.2) |
where is the function (2.17). On the other hand, recall that for , the -th symmetric mean of the -tuple is:
(3.3) |
where denotes the elementary symmetric polynomial of degree in variables.
Since they originate from a barycenter, the HS means are repetition invariant333or intrinsic, in the terminology of [KLL, Def. 3.3] in the sense that, for any ,
(3.4) |
where denotes the -tuple obtained by concatenation of copies of the -tuple . No such property holds for the symmetric means, even allowing for adjustment of the parameter . Nevertheless, if the number of repetitions tends to infinity, then the symmetric means tend to stabilize, and the limit is a HS mean; more precisely:
Theorem 3.1.
If , , and , then:
(3.5) |
Furthermore, the relative error goes to zero uniformly with respect to the ’s.
This Theorem will be proved in the next subsection.
It is worthwhile to note that the Navas barycenter [Na] is obtained as a “repetition limit” similar to (3.5).
Example 3.2.
Using Propositions 2.7 and 2.11, one computes:
(3.6) |
Therefore:
(3.7) |
The last equality was deduced in [CHMW, p. 31] from the asymptotics of Legendre polynomials.
Let us pose a problem:
Question 3.3.
Is the sequence always monotone decreasing?
There exists a partial result: when and , [CHMW, Lemma 4.1] establishes eventual monotonicity.
3.2. Inequalities between symmetric means and HS means
The following is the first main result of this paper.
Theorem 3.4.
If , , and , then
(3.8) |
Let us postpone the proof to the next subsection. The factor at the RHS of (3.8) is asymptotically with respect to ; indeed:
Lemma 3.5.
For all integers , we have
(3.9) |
with equality if and only if .
Proof.
Theorems 3.4 and 3.5 imply that HS means (with rational values of the parameter) can be obtained as repetition limits of symmetric means:
Proof of Theorem 3.1.
Applying Theorem 3.4 to the tuple , using observation (3.4) and Lemma 3.5, we have:
(3.13) |
Remark 3.6.
If is fixed, then
(3.14) |
and therefore the bound from Theorem 3.7 may be less satisfactory. But in this case we may use the alternative bound coming from Maclaurin inequality:
(3.15) |
3.3. Proof of Theorem 3.4
The two inequalities in (3.8) will be proved independently of each other. They are essentially contained in the papers [BIP] and [HS], respectively, though neither was stated explicitly. In the following Theorems 3.8 and 3.7, we also characterize the cases of equality, and in particular show that each inequality is sharp in the sense that the corresponding factors cannot be improved.
Let us begin with the second inequality, which is more elementary. By symmetry, there is no loss of generality in assuming that the numbers are ordered.
Theorem 3.7.
If with , and , then:
(3.16) |
Furthermore, equality holds if and only if or .
Proof.
Our starting point is Vieta’s formula:
(3.17) |
Therefore, by Cauchy’s formula, for any :
(3.18) |
That is,
(3.19) |
Taking absolute values,
(3.20) |
But these inequalities are valid for all , and therefore:
(3.21) |
Now let us investigate the possibility of equality. We consider three mutually exclusive cases, which correspond to the classification (2.8):
(3.22) |
Using Proposition 2.11, in the critical case we have:
(3.23) |
while in the supercritical case the two means vanish together. So, in both cases, inequality (3.16) becomes an equality. Now suppose we are in the subcritical case; then the at the RHS of (3.21) is attained at some : see Proposition 2.9. On the other hand, for this (and actually any) value of , the second inequality in (3.20) must be strict, because the integrand is non-constant. We conclude that, in the subcritical case, inequality (3.21) is strict, and therefore (3.16) is strict. ∎
The first inequality in (3.8) is a particular case of an inequality between two types of matrix means introduced in [BIP], which we now explain. Let be a matrix with nonnegative entries. Recall that the permanent of is the “signless determinant”
(3.24) |
where runs on the permutations of . Then the permanental mean of is defined as:
(3.25) |
On the other hand, the scaling mean of the matrix is defined as:
(3.26) |
where and run on the set of strictly positive column vectors, and denotes the geometric mean of the entries of the vector. Equivalently,
(3.27) |
see [BIP, Rem. 2.6].444Incidentally, formula (3.27) shows that, up to the factor , the scaling mean is a matrix antinorm in the sense defined by [GZ]. By [BIP, Thrm. 2.17],
(3.28) |
with equality if and only if has permanent or rank . This inequality is far from trivial. Indeed, if the matrix is doubly stochastic (i.e. row and column sums are all ), then an easy calculation (see [BIP, Prop. 2.4]) shows that , so (3.28) becomes , or equivalently,
(3.29) |
This lower bound on the permanent of doubly stochastic matrices was conjectured in 1926 by van der Waerden and, after a protracted series of partial results, proved around 1980 independently by Egorichev and Falikman: see [Zh, Chapter 5] for the exact references and a self-contained proof, and [Gu] for more recent developments. Our inequality (3.28), despite being a generalization of Egorichev–Falikman’s (3.29), is actually a relatively simple corollary of it: we refer the reader to [BIP, § 2] for more information.555The proof of [BIP, Thrm. 2.17] uses a theorem on the existence of particular type of matrix factorization called Sinkhorn decomposition. The present article only needs the inequality (3.28) for matrices of a specific form (3.32). So the use of the existence theorem could be avoided, since it is possible to explicitly compute the corresponding Sinkhorn decomposition.
We are now in position to complete the proof of Theorem 3.4, i.e., to prove the second inequality in (3.8). The next result also characterizes the cases of equality.
Theorem 3.8.
If with , and , then:
(3.30) |
Furthermore, equality holds if and only if :
(3.31) |
Proof.
Consider the nonnegative matrix:
(3.32) |
Note that:
(3.33) |
and so
(3.34) | ||||
(3.35) |
Now let’s compute the scaling mean of using formula (3.27). Assume that . Given a column vector with positive entries, we have:
(3.36) |
On the other hand, by the inequality of arithmetic and geometric means,
(3.37) |
with equality if , . So, in order to minimize the quotient , it is sufficient to consider column vectors satisfying these conditions. We can also normalize to , and (3.27) becomes:
(3.38) | ||||
(3.39) |
by (3.2). This formula also holds for , taking the form ; this can be checked either by adapting the proof above, or more simply by using the homogeneity and reflexivity properties of the scaling mean (see [BIP]).
In conclusion, the matrix (3.32) has scaling and permanental means given by formulas (3.39) and (3.35), respectively, and the fundamental inequality (3.28) translates into , that is, (3.8).
Furthermore, equality holds if and only if the matrix defined by (3.32) satisfies , by formulas (3.39) and (3.35). As mentioned before, if and only if has rank or permanent (see [BIP, Thrm. 2.17]). Note that has rank if and only if or . On the other hand, by (3.35), has permanent if and only if , or equivalently . So we have proved that equality is equivalent to condition (3.31). ∎
We close this section with some comments on related results.
Remark 3.9.
In [HS], the asymptotics of the integral (3.18) are determined using the saddle point method (see e.g. [Si, Section 15.4]). However, for this method to work, the saddle must be steep, that is, the second derivative at the saddle must be large in absolute value. Major [Maj, p. 1987] discusses this situation: if the second derivative vanishes, then “a more sophisticated method has to be applied and only weaker results can be obtained in this case. We shall not discuss this question in the present paper”. On the other hand, in the general situation covered by our Theorem 3.4, the saddle can be flat. (It must be noted that the setting considered by Major is different, since he allows random variables to be negative.)
Remark 3.10.
Given an arbitrary non-negative matrix , the permanental and scaling means satisfy the following inequalities (see [BIP, Theorem 2.17]),
(3.40) |
The sequence is increasing and converges to . In general, as tends to infinity the permanental mean does not necessarily converges to the scaling mean. However, there are some special classes of matrices for which this is indeed the case: for example, in the repetitive situation covered by the Generalized Friedland limit [BIP, Theorem 2.19]. Note that and correspond to the th power of the scaling and permanental mean of the matrix , respectively. Therefore, (3.8) can be regarded as an improvement of (3.40) for this particular class of matrices.
Remark 3.11.
A natural extension of symmetric means are Muirhead means, see [HLP, § 2.18], [Bu, § V.6] for definition and properties. Accordingly, it should be possible to define a family of barycenters extending the HS barycenters, taking over from [BIP, § 5.2]. An analogue of inequality (3.30) holds in this extended setting, again as a consequence of the key inequality (3.28) between matrix means. However, we do not know if inequality (3.16) can be extended in a comparable level of generality.
4. Continuity of the HS barycenter
In this section we study the continuity of the HS barycenter as a two-variable function, , defined in the space . The most natural topology on is the weak topology (defined below). The barycenter function is not continuous with respect to this topology, but, on the positive side, it is lower semicontinuous, except in a particular situation. In order to obtain better results, we need to focus on subsets of measures satisfying the natural integrability conditions (usually (2.6), but differently for the extremal parameters and ), and endow these subsets with stronger topologies that are well adapted to the integrability assumptions.
In a preliminary subsection, we collect some general facts on topologies on spaces of measures. In the remaining subsections we prove several results on continuity of the HS barycenter. And all these results will be used in combination to prove our general ergodic theorem in Section 5.
4.1. Convergence of measures
If is a separable complete metric space, let be the set of all continuous bounded real functions on , and let denote the set of all Borel probability measures on . Recall (see e.g. [Pa]) that the weak topology is a metrizable topology on according to with a sequence converges to some if and only if for every test function ; we say that converges weakly to , and denote this by . The space is Polish, and it is compact if and only if is compact. Despite the space being huge (nonseparable w.r.t. its usual topology if is noncompact), by [Pa, Theorem II.6.6] we can nevertheless find a countable subset such that, for all and in ,
(4.1) |
The following result deals with sequences of integrals where not only the measures but also the integrands vary, and bears a resemblance to Fatou’s Lemma:
Proposition 4.1.
Suppose that is a sequence in converging weakly to some measure , and that is a sequence of continuous functions on converging uniformly on compact subsets to some function . Furthermore, assume that the functions are bounded from below by a constant independent of . Then, .
Note that, as in Fatou’s Lemma, the integrals in Proposition 4.1 can be infinite.
Proof.
Without loss of generality, assume that . Let be such that . By the monotone convergence theorem, there exists such that . For a function , let . Note that
(4.2) |
By Prokhorov’s theorem (see e.g. [Pa, Theorem 6.7]), the sequence forms a tight set, that is, for every , there exists a compact set such that for all . Since converges uniformly on compact subsets to , we obtain:
(4.3) |
We also have:
(4.4) |
Since converges weakly to , we have . Therefore, combining (4.2), (4.3) and (4.4), for sufficiently large values of we obtain . The result now follows. ∎
The next direct consequence is useful.
Corollary 4.2.
Suppose that is a sequence in converging weakly to some measure , and that is a sequence of continuous functions on converging uniformly on compact subsets to some function . Furthermore, assume that the functions are bounded by a constant independent of . Then, .
We will also need a slightly stronger notion of convergence. Let denote the set of measures with finite first moment, that is,
(4.5) |
Here and in what follows, is a basepoint which we consider as fixed, the particular choice being entirely irrelevant. We metrize with Kantorovich metric (see e.g. [Vi, p. 207]):
(4.6) |
Of course, the Kantorovich metric depends on the original metric on ; in fact, it “remembers” it, since . The metric space is called -Wasserstein space; it is separable and complete. Unless is compact, the topology on is stronger than the weak topology. In fact, we have the following characterizations of convergence:
Theorem 4.3 ([Vi, Theorem 7.12]).
For all and in , the following statements are equivalent:
-
(a)
.
-
(b)
if is a continuous function such that is bounded, then .
-
(c)
and .
-
(d)
and the following “tightness condition” holds:
(4.7) where denotes the open ball of center and radius .
The next Lemma should be compared to Corollary 4.2:
Lemma 4.4.
Suppose that is a sequence in converging to some measure , and that is a sequence of continuous functions on converging uniformly on bounded subsets to some function . Furthermore, assume that the functions are bounded by a constant independent of . Then, .
Proof.
Fix . By part (d) of Theorem 4.3, there exists such that, for all sufficiently large ,
(4.8) |
Then, we write:
(4.9) |
By part (b) of Theorem 4.3, the term tends to as . By the assumption of uniform convergence on bounded sets, tends to as well. Finally,
(4.10) |
for all sufficiently large . Since is arbitrary, we conclude that , as claimed. ∎
4.2. Lower and upper semicontinuity
The HS barycenter is definitely not continuous with respect to the weak topology, since the complement of is dense in , and the barycenter is there (by Proposition 2.5). Nevertheless, lower semicontinuity holds, except in the critical configuration:
Theorem 4.5.
For every , we have:
(4.12) |
To be explicit, the inequality above means that for every , there exists a neighborhood of with respect to the product topology (weak standard) such that for all .
Proof.
We now consider the converse implication: given such that or , we want to show that . There are some trivial cases:
-
•
If , then the conclusion is obvious.
-
•
If , then by Proposition 2.11, and again the conclusion is clear.
In what follows, we assume that and . Fix a sequence converging to . We need to prove that:
(4.15) |
We may also assume without loss of generality that for each . We divide the proof in two cases:
Case : We can also assume that for every . By Proposition 2.5, the hypothesis means that . By Portmanteau’s Theorem [Pa, Theorem 6.1(c)], . Thus, for sufficiently large values of we have . In this setting, the HS barycenter can be computed by Proposition 2.7. Recall from (2.16) that denotes the unique positive solution of the equation . Note that is well defined even in the case (see Remark 2.8). We claim that:
(4.16) |
Proof of the claim.
Fix numbers , with . Then a monotonicity property shown in the proof of Proposition 2.7 gives:
(4.17) |
Note the uniform bounds:
(4.18) |
So, using Corollary 4.2, we see that . In particular, for all sufficiently large ,
(4.19) |
and thus , proving the claim (4.16). ∎
For simplicity, write . By Proposition 2.2.(b),
(4.20) |
for some finite , since and . This allows us to apply Proposition 4.1 and obtain:
(4.21) |
where . Using formula (2.10), we obtain (4.15). This completes the proof of Theorem 4.5 in the case .
Case : By Proposition 4.1 we obtain, , that is, . So we can assume that for every , like in the previous case.
In order to prove (4.15) in the case , let us fix an arbitrary positive , and let us show that for every sufficiently large . By the monotone convergence theorem, there exists such that . Let (resp. ) be the push-forward of the measure (resp. ) by the map . Then and, by Proposition 2.6.(b), . Furthermore, we have , since for every ,
(4.22) |
So, to simplify the notations, we remove the hats and assume that the measures , are all supported in the interval .
The numbers and are well-defined, as in the previous case, and furthermore they belong to the interval , by Lemma 2.14. On the other hand, by Proposition 4.1,
(4.23) |
It follows that for all sufficiently large . We claim that , as before in (4.16). The proof is the same, except that the upper bound in (4.18) becomes infinite and must be replaced by the following estimate:
(4.24) |
So a repetition of the previous arguments yields (4.16), then (4.20) and (4.21), and finally (4.15). Therefore, Theorem 4.5 has been proved in both cases and . ∎
Next, let us investigate the behaviour of the HS barycenter on the product space , where is endowed with the topology defined in the end of Section 4.1.
Theorem 4.6.
For every , we have:
(4.25) | unless | and | |||||||||
(4.26) | unless | and |
Proof of part (4.25) of Theorem 4.6.
Let us start by proving the following implication:
(4.27) |
Consider measures . Clearly, ; moreover,
(4.28) |
So using characterization (c) of Theorem 4.3, we conclude that in the topology of . On the other hand, . This proves (4.27).
Next, let us prove the converse implication. So, let us fix such that or , and let us show that if is any sequence in converging to , then . This is obviously true if , so let us assume that . Then our assumption becomes , so by removing finitely many terms from the sequence , we may assume that . Fix some finite number . By Definition 2.3, there is some such that . The sequence of continuous functions is uniformly bounded, as a direct calculation shows. Furthermore, uniformly on compact subsets of . So Lemma 4.4 ensures that . Now it follows from Definition 2.3 that for all sufficiently large . Since is arbitrary, we conclude that , as we wanted to show. ∎
Proof of part (4.26) of Theorem 4.6.
First, we prove that, for all ,
(4.29) |
Consider measures . Clearly, in the topology of . By Proposition 2.11.(b), . This proves (4.29). For the converse is a direct consequence of Theorem 4.5, since the topology on is stronger. If and then the result is obvious. If then, as the example above shows, the result does not hold. ∎
4.3. Continuity for extremal values of the parameter
Theorem 4.6 shows that the HS barycenter map on is not continuous at the pairs (except if ), nor at the pairs (except if ). Let us see that continuity can be “recovered” if we impose extra integrablity conditions and work with stronger topologies.
If we use the standard distance on the half-line , then the resulting -Wasserstein space is denoted . On the other hand, using the distance
(4.30) |
the corresponding -Wasserstein space will be denoted . We consider the latter space as a subset of , since any measure on can be extended to by setting . The topologies we have just defined on the spaces and are stronger than the topologies induced by ; in other words, the inclusion maps below are continuous:
(4.31) |
Note that the “arithmetic barycenter” is finite on , while the “geometric barycenter” is finite and non-zero on .
Finally, let us establish continuity of the HS barycenter for the extremal values of the parameter with respect to these new topologies:
Proposition 4.7.
Consider a sequence in .
-
(a)
If in , then .
-
(b)
If in , then .
Proof of part (a) of Proposition 4.7 .
Note that if for every , the result is direct from the definition of the topology in (use characterization (c) of Theorem 4.3). We assume now that , for every . It is a consequence of Theorem 4.5 that:
(4.32) |
The same proof as that of part (4.25) of Theorem 4.6 can be used to prove,
(4.33) |
Indeed, in the topology of the HS kernels satisfy the assumptions of Lemma 4.4. For this, it suffices to notice that, for any fixed value , the sequence of continuous functions is uniformly bounded, and that uniformly on compact subsets of . ∎
Proof of part (b) of Proposition 4.7 .
In the case that for every , the result is direct from the topology in (use characterization (c) of Theorem 4.3). We assume that , for every . It is a consequence of (4.25) of Theorem 4.6 that:
(4.34) |
Recall that the HS barycenter is decreasing in the variable ; see Proposition 2.6.(e). In particular, , for every . Noticing that is a test function for the convergence in the topology of , we obtain:
(4.35) |
The following observation complements part (b) of Proposition 4.7, since it provides a sort of lower semicontinuity property at under a weaker integrability condition:
Lemma 4.8.
Let and let be such that . Then:
(4.36) |
Proof.
By definition, . Note that if , then , while if , then by Proposition 2.2.(e). In any case, , and the Lemma follows. ∎
5. Ergodic theorems for symmetric and HS means
Symmetric means (3.3) are only defined for lists of nonnegative numbers. On the other hand, HS barycenters are defined for probability measures on , and are therefore much more flexible objects. In particular, there is an induced concept of HS mean of a list of nonnegative numbers, which we have already introduced in (3.1). We can also define the HS mean of a function:
Definition 5.1.
If is a probability space, is a measurable nonnegative function, and , then the Halász–Székely mean (or HS mean) with parameter of the function with respect to the probability measure is:
(5.1) |
that is, the HS barycenter with parameter of the push-forward measure on . In the case , we require that is semi-integrable.
For arithmetic means, the classical ergodic theorem of Birkhoff states the equality between limit time averages and spatial averages. From the probabilistic viewpoint, Birkhoff’s theorem is the strong law of large numbers. We prove an ergodic theorem that applies simultaneously to symmetric and HS means, and extends results of [HS, vE]:
Theorem 5.2.
Let be a probability space, let be an ergodic measure-preserving transformation, and let be a nonnegative measurable function. Then there exists a measurable set with with the following properties. For any , for any such that
(5.2) |
and
(5.3) |
and for any sequence in tending to , we have:
(5.4) |
furthermore, for any sequence of integers such that and , we have:
(5.5) |
Remark 5.3.
Since we allow HS means to take infinity value, we do not need integrability conditions as in [HS, vE], except for the unavoidable hypothesis (5.3). In the supercritical case , both limits (5.4) and (5.5) are almost surely attained in finite time. In the critical case , strong convergence does not necessarily hold, and the values may oscillate. However, in the IID setting, van Es proved that the sequence of symmetric means converges in distribution, provided that the sequence converges in : see [vE, Theorem A1 (b)].
As we will soon see, part (5.4) of Theorem 5.2 is obtained using the results about continuity of the HS barycenter with respect to various topologies proved in Section 4, and then part (5.5) follows from the inequalities of Theorem 3.4 and Remark 3.6.
To begin the proof, let us fix , , and as in the statement, and let denote the push-forward measure. Given , we consider the sequence of associated sample measures:
(5.6) |
As the next result shows, these sample measures converge almost surely666[Pa, Theorem II.7.1] contains a similar result, with essentially the same proof.:
Lemma 5.4.
There exists a measurable set with such that for every , the corresponding sample measures converge weakly to :
(5.7) |
furthermore, stronger convergences may hold according to the function :
-
(a)
if , then in the topology of ;
-
(b)
if , then in the topology of ;
-
(c)
if , then in the topology of .
Proof.
Let be a countable set of bounded continuous functions which is sufficient to test weak convergence, i.e., with property (4.1). For each , applying Birkhoff’s ergodic theorem to the function we obtain a measurable set with such that for all ,
(5.8) |
Since is countable, we can choose a single measurable set of full probability that works for all . Then we obtain for all . To obtain stronger convergences, we apply Birkhoff’s theorem to the functions , , and , provided they are integrable, and reduce the set accordingly. If, for example, is integrable, then for all we have:
(5.9) |
Applying part (c) of Theorem 4.3 with and , we conclude that converges to in the topology of . The assertions about convergence in and are proved analogously, using instead the corresponding distances (4.11) and (4.30). ∎
Proof of Theorem 5.2.
Let be the set given by Lemma 5.4. By the semi-integrable version of Birkhoff’s theorem (see e.g. [Kr, p. 15]), we can reduce if necessary and assume that for all ,
(5.10) |
Fix a point and a number satisfying conditions (5.2) and (5.3). Consider any sequence in converging to . Let us prove (5.5), or equivalently,
(5.11) |
There are several cases to be considered, and in all but the last case we will use Lemma 5.4:
-
•
First case: and . Since , (5.11) is a consequence of Theorem 4.5.
-
•
Second case: and . Then . Therefore in the topology of , and Theorem 4.6 implies (5.11).
-
•
Third case: and . Then , and hence in the topology of . So (5.11) follows from Proposition 4.7.(a).
-
•
Fourth case: and . Then . Thus in the topology of , and Theorem 4.6 yields (5.11).
-
•
Fifth case: and . Then . Therefore in the topology of , and (5.11) becomes a consequence of Proposition 4.7.(b).
- •
Part (5.4) of the Theorem is proved, and now let use it to prove part (5.5). Consider a sequence of integers such that and tends to . By Theorem 3.4,
(5.14) |
If , i.e. , then the first inequality forces the symmetric means to tend to as well. So let us assume that is finite. If then, by Lemma 3.5, the fraction on the RHS converges to as , and therefore we obtain the desired limit (5.5). If , then we appeal to Maclaurin inequality in the form
(5.15) |
So:
(5.16) |
Since (5.11) also holds with , we see that all three terms converge together to , thus proving (5.5) also in the case . ∎
Like Birkhoff’s Ergodic Theorem itself, Theorem 5.2 should be possible to generalize in numerous directions. For example, part (5.4) can be easily adapted to flows or semiflows (actions of the group or the semigroup ). One can also consider actions of amenable groups, like [Au, Na]. We shall not pursue these matters. In another direction, let us note that Central Limit Theorems for symmetric means of i.i.d. random variables have been proved by Székely [Sz2] and van Es [vE].
A weaker version of Theorem 5.2, in which the function is assumed to be bounded away from zero and infinity, was obtained in [BIP, Theorem 5.1] as a corollary of a fairly general pointwise ergodic theorem: the Law of Large Permanents [BIP, Theorem 4.1]. We now briefly discuss a generalization of that result obtained by Balogh and Nguyen [BN, Theorem 1.6]. Suppose that is an ergodic measure preserving action of the semigroup on the space . Given an observable and a point , we define an infinite matrix whose -entry is . Consider square truncations of this matrix and then take the limit of the corresponding permanental means as the size of the square tends to infinity. It is proved that the limit exists -almost everywhere. But not only that, it is also possible to identify the limit. It turns out that it is a functional scaling mean. This is a far reaching generalization of the matrix scaling mean (3.26): see [BIP, Section 3.1].
6. Concavity properties of the HS barycenter
In Section 4, we have studied properties of the HS barycenter that rely on topological structures. In this section, we discuss properties that are related to affine (i.e. convex) structures.
6.1. Basic concavity properties
Let us first consider the HS barycenter as a function of the measure.
Proposition 6.1.
For all , the function is log-concave.
Proof.
By definition,
(6.1) |
For each and , the function is affine. Since the infimum of affine functions is concave, we conclude that is concave as a function of . ∎
Next, let us consider the HS barycenter as a function of the parameter.
Proposition 6.2.
For all , the function is log-concave.
This Proposition can be regarded as a version of Newton inequality, which says that for every , the function
(6.2) |
is log-concave (see [HLP, Theorem 51, p. 52] or [Bu, Theorem 1(1), p. 324]).
Proof of Proposition 6.2.
Note the following trait of the HS kernel: for all and , the function
(6.3) |
is concave. Integrating over with respect to the given , and then taking infimum over , we conclude that the function is concave, as we wanted to show. ∎
Recall from Definition 5.1 that the HS mean of a function with respect to a probability measure is simply the HS barycenter of the push-forward . Let us now investigate this mean as a function of . The same argument from the proof of Proposition 6.2 shows that is log-concave. However, we are able to show more:
Proposition 6.3.
Let be a probability space. Let be the set of nonnegative measurable functions such that . For every , the function is concave.
This is a consequence of the fact that is a functional scaling mean (see [BIP]), but for the convenience of the reader we provide a self-contained proof. We start with the following observation: if is the set of positive measurable functions such that , then for all ,
(6.4) |
with the infimum being attained at . Indeed, this is just a reformulation of the inequality between arithmetic and geometric means.
Proof of Proposition 6.3.
Let us first consider the case . For every fixed value of , the function
(6.5) |
belongs to the set defined above. Using identity (6.4),
(6.6) |
Consider this expression as a function of ; since it is an infimum of affine functions, it is concave. Taking the infimum over , we conclude that is concave, as claimed.
The proof of the remaining case is similar, but then we need to extend identity (6.4) to functions in ; we leave the details for the reader. ∎
6.2. Finer results
For the remaining of this section, we assume that the parameter is in the range . Let us consider the HS barycenter as a function of the measure again. We define the subcritical locus as the following (convex) subset of :
(6.7) |
The function restricted to the subcritical locus is well-behaved. It is analytic, in a sense that we will make precise below. By Proposition 6.1, this function is log-concave. Nevertheless, we will show that it is not strictly log-concave.
Let us begin with an abstract definition.
Definition 6.4.
A real-valued function defined on a convex subset of a real vector space is called quasi-affine if, for all , ,
(6.8) |
where , and the right-hand side is the interval with extremes , , independently of their order.
The explanation for the terminology is that quasi-affine functions are exactly those that are simultaneouly quasiconcave and quasiconvex (for the latter concepts see e.g. [ADSZ, Chapter 3]). Note that the level sets of a quasi-affine function are convex.
For in the subcritical locus , the HS barycenter can be computed using Proposition 2.7, and this computation relies on finding the solution of equation (2.16). Since the integrand in (2.16) is monotonic with respect to , the function is quasi-affine. Concerning the barycenter itself, we have:
Proposition 6.5.
Let , . Then the restriction of the function to the segment is log-affine if , and is strictly log-concave otherwise.
See Fig. 3.

Proof.
As observed above, the function on is quasi-affine, and in particular its level sets are convex. As a consequence of (2.10), along each level set of , the function is log-affine, and so not strictly log-concave there. This proves the first part of the Proposition.
To prove the second part, consider , such that , and parametrize the segment by , . Then, Lemma 6.6 below ensures that the second derivative of the function is nonpositive and vanishes at finitely many points (if any). So the function is strictly log-concave. This proves Proposition 6.5, modulo the Lemma. ∎
Lemma 6.6.
Suppose is an interval and is an affine mapping. Write , . Then and are analytic functions of . Furthermore, letting dot denote derivative with respect to , the following formula holds:
(6.9) |
The integral is strictly positive (since , so formula (6.9) tells us that, at any point in , the Hessian of the function is negative semidefinite (not a surprise, given Proposition 6.1), and has the same kernel as the derivative of the function at the same point.
Proof of Lemma 6.6.
Let us omit the parameter in the formulas, so . As in the proof of Proposition 2.7, we consider the following functions:
(6.10) |
(We temporarily denote by .) Then is defined implicitly by , for all . The mapping can be extended uniquely to an affine mapping on whose values are signed measures. Inspecting the proof of Proposition 2.7, we see that is well-defined for all in an open interval .
The partial derivative was computed before (2.13), and satisfies the bounds . So we can differentiate under the integral sign and write . This derivative is positive, since for all and . Therefore, since is an analytic function on the domain , the inverse function theorem ensures that is analytic on . In particular, is analytic as well, as claimed.
Now we want to prove (6.9); in that formula and in the following calculations, we omit the dependence on . First, we differentiate with respect to :
(6.11) |
(where is a signed measure), which by (2.9) simplifies to:
(6.12) |
Differentiating again, and using that (since is affine), we obtain:
(6.13) |
On the other hand, differentiating (2.9),
(6.14) |
so (6.13) can be rewritten as:
(6.15) |
Let us transform this expression. Consider the function , which was introduced before in (2.11). Since , using (2.9) once again, we obtain . So equation (6.15) becomes:
(6.16) |
Substituting the expression of given by (2.13), we obtain (6.9).777Incidentally, note that it is not true that everywhere ( is not a convex function of ), so formula (6.15) by itself is not as useful as the final formulas (6.16) and (6.9). ∎
For or , the barycenter is a quasi-affine function. On the other hand, an inspection of Fig. 3 shows that this is not true for , at least, since the level sets are slightly bent. Using Proposition 6.5, we will formally prove:
Proposition 6.7.
If , then the function is not quasi-affine.
A proof is given in the next section.
7. A deviation barycenter related to the HS barycenter
There is a large class of means called deviation means, which includes the class of quasiarithmetic means. Let us recall the definition (see [Da, DP]). Let be an open interval. A deviation function is a function such that for all , the function is continuous, strictly decreasing, and vanishes at . Given -tuples and with , , and , the deviation mean of with weights (with respect to the deviation function ) is defined as the unique solution of the equation:
(7.1) |
In terms of the probability measure , this equation can be rewritten as:
(7.2) |
So it is reasonable to define the deviation barycenter of an arbitrary probability (with respect to the deviation function ) as the solution of this equation. Of course, existence and uniqueness of such a solution may depend on measurability and integrability conditions, and we will not undertake this investigation here. Nevertheless, let us note that if is a convex set of probability measures where the deviation barycenter is uniquely defined, then it is a quasi-affine function there. Indeed, for each , the corresponding upper level set is:
(7.3) |
and so it is convex; similarly for lower level sets.
Remark 7.1.
Let us mention a related concept (see [EM, AL] and references therein). Let be a manifold endowed with an affine (e.g. Riemannian) connection for which the exponential maps are diffeomorphisms. Given a probability measure , a solution of the equation
(7.4) |
is called an exponential barycenter of . (For criteria of existence and uniqueness, see [AL].) The similarity between equations (7.4) and (7.2) is evident. Furthermore, like deviation barycenters, the level sets of exponential barycenters are convex. (Since has no order structure, it does not make sense to say that the exponential barycenter is quasi-affine.)
We have mentioned that the HS barycenter with parameter is not quasi-affine on the subcritical locus. Therefore HS barycenters are not a deviation barycenters, except for the extremal values of the parameter. Nevertheless, there exists a naturally related parametrized family of deviation barycenters, as we now explain.
Letting be the HS kernel (see Definition 2.1), we let:
(7.5) |
For any value of the parameter , this is a deviation function, provided we restrict it to . The corresponding deviation barycenter will be called the derived from Halász–Székely barycenter (or DHS barycenter) with parameter . More precisely:
Definition 7.2.
Let and . If , then we require that the function is semi-integrable with respect to . The DHS barycenter with parameter of the probability measure , denoted , is defined as follows:
-
(a)
if , or and , then ;
-
(b)
if and , or and , then ;
-
(c)
in all other cases, is defined at the unique positive and finite solution of the equation .
Of course, we need to show that the definition makes sense in case (c), i.e., that there exists a unique such that . This is obvious if or , so assume that . Since , the function is finite, and (by the dominated convergence theorem) continuous and strictly decreasing. Furthermore, converges to as and (since to as . So has a unique zero on , as we wanted to prove.
The DHS barycenters have the same basic properties as the HS barycenters (Proposition 2.6); we leave the verification for the reader.888For example, monotonicity with respect to follows simply from the corresponding property of the deviation functions, so we do not need to use the finer comparison criteria from [Da, DP]. Furthermore, we have the following inequality:
Proposition 7.3.
. The inequality is strict unless either is a delta measure, , , or .
Proof.
Let and . If is either or , then it is clear from Definition 7.2 and basic properties of the HS barycenter that . So assume that is neither nor . Then it satisfies the equation , or equivalently . Considering in the definition (2.4), we obtain , as claimed.
Let us investigate the cases of equality. It is clear that and are the arithmetic and geometric barycenters, respectively, and so coincide with the corresponding HS barycenters. Also, if , then . So consider and such that . The infimum in formula (2.4) is attained at , and thus (see Proposition 2.11) we are in the subcritical regime . Hence equation (2.16) holds with . Note that the equation can be rewritten as:
(7.6) |
On the other hand,
(7.7) |
So we have an equality in Jensen’s inequality, which is only possible if the integrands are almost everywhere constant, that is, is a delta measure. ∎
In some senses, the DHS barycenters are better behaved than HS barycenters. For example, there is no critical phenomena.
Example 7.4.
As in Example 2.13, consider the measures , where . A calculation gives:
(7.8) |
For , the graphs of the two barycenters are shown in Fig. 4.

The definition of DHS barycenters is not so arbitrary as it may seem at first sight; indeed, they approximate HS barycenters:
Proposition 7.5.
The HS and DHS barycenters are tangent at , for any . In other words, if is an affine path with , then:
(7.9) |
Proof.
It is sufficient to consider . Let us use the notations from the proof of Lemma 6.6. We evaluate (6.12) at , using , thus obtaining:
(7.10) |
Next, consider . By definition, . Differentiating this equation,
(7.11) |
Evaluating at and , we obtain:
(7.12) |
But a calculation shows that (this can also be seen as a consequence of part (e) of Proposition 2.2), so we obtain:
(7.13) |
as we wanted to prove. ∎
The approximation between the two barycenters is often surprisingly good, even for measures that are not very close to a delta measure:
Example 7.6.
If is Lebesgue measure on and , then:
(7.14) | ||||
(7.15) |
a difference of %.
To conclude our paper, let us confirm that HS barycenters are not quasi-affine, except for the extremal cases and :
Proof of Proposition 6.7.
Let . Choose some in subcritical locus (6.7) which is not a delta measure. Let and . Then . We claim that . Indeed, if , then, by (2.4), , and so , which by Proposition 7.3 implies that is a delta measure: contradiction. Now Proposition 6.5 guarantees that the function is strictly log-concave on the segment ; in particular, it is not constant. Since the function attains the same value on the extremes of the segment, it cannot be quasi-affine. ∎
Acknowledgement. We thank Juarez Bochi for helping us with computer experiments at a preliminary stage of this project.
References
- [AD] Aczél, János; Dhombres, Jean G. – Functional equations in several variables. Encyclopedia of Mathematics and its Applications, 31. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1989. MR ZB
- [AL] Arnaudon, Marc; Li, Xue-Mei -- Barycenters of measures transported by stochastic flows. Ann. Probab. 33 (2005), no. 4, 1509--1543. MR ZB
- [Au] Austin, Tim -- A CAT(0)-valued pointwise ergodic theorem. J. Topol. Anal. 3 (2011), no. 2, 145--152. MR ZB
- [ADSZ] Avriel, Mordecai; Diewert, Walter E.; Schaible, Siegfried; Zang, Israel -- Generalized concavity. Reprint of the 1988 original ed. Classics in Applied Mathematics, 63. Society for Industrial and Applied Mathematics (SIAM), Philadelphia, PA, 2010. MR ZB
- [BN] Balogh, József; Nguyen, Hoi -- A general law of large permanent. Discrete Contin. Dyn. Syst. 37 (2017), no. 10, 5285--5297. DOI MR ZB
- [BIP] Bochi, Jairo; Iommi, Godofredo; Ponce, Mario -- The scaling mean and a law of large permanents. Adv. Math. 292 (2016), 374--409. DOI MR ZB
- [BB] Borwein, Jonathan M.; Borwein, Peter B. -- Pi and the AGM. A study in analytic number theory and computational complexity. Reprint of the 1987 original. Canadian Mathematical Society Series of Monographs and Advanced Texts, 4. John Wiley & Sons, Inc., New York, 1998. MR ZB
- [Bu] Bullen, Peter S. -- Handbook of means and their inequalities. Mathematics and its Applications, 560. Kluwer Academic Publishers Group, Dordrecht, 2003. MR ZB
- [CHMW] Cellarosi, Francesco; Hensley, Doug; Miller, Steven J.; Wellens, Jake L. -- Continued fraction digit averages and Maclaurin’s inequalities. Exp. Math. 24 (2015), no. 1, 23--44. DOI MR ZB
- [Da] Daróczy, Zoltán -- Über eine Klasse von Mittelwerten. Publ. Math. Debrecen 19 (1972), 211--217. MR ZB
- [DP] Daróczy, Zoltán; Páles, Zsolt -- On comparison of mean values. Publ. Math. Debrecen 29 (1982), 107--115. MR ZB
- [EM] Émery, Michel; Mokobodzki, Gabriel -- Sur le barycentre d’une probabilité dans une variété. Séminaire de Probabilités, XXV, 220--233, Lecture Notes in Math., 1485, Springer, Berlin, 1991. MR ZB
- [Fe] Feller, William -- An introduction to probability theory and its applications. Vol. I. 3rd. ed. John Wiley & Sons, Inc., New York-London-Sydney, 1968. MR ZB
- [GZ] Guglielmi, Nicola; Zennaro, Marino -- An antinorm theory for sets of matrices: bounds and approximations to the lower spectral radius. Linear Algebra Appl. 607 (2020), 89--117. DOI MR
- [Gu] Gurvits, Leonid -- Van der Waerden/Schrijver-Valiant like conjectures and stable (aka hyperbolic) homogeneous polynomials: one theorem for all. With a corrigendum. Electron. J. Combin. 15 (2008), no. 1, Research Paper 66, 26 pp. DOI MR ZB
- [HS] Halász, Gábor; Székely, Gábor J. -- On the elementary symmetric polynomials of independent random variables. Acta Math. Acad. Sci. Hungar. 28 (1976), no. 3-4, 397--400. DOI MR ZB
- [HLP] Hardy, Godfrey H.; Littlewood, John E.; Pólya, George -- Inequalities. Reprint of the 1952 edition. Cambridge Mathematical Library. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1988. MR ZB
- [He] Heath, Thomas -- A history of Greek mathematics. Vol. I. From Thales to Euclid. Corrected reprint of the 1921 original. Dover Publications, Inc., New York, 1981. MR ZB
- [KLL] Kim, Sejong; Lawson, Jimmie; Lim, Yongdo -- Barycentric maps for compactly supported measures. J. Math. Anal. Appl. 458 (2018), no. 2, 1009--1026. DOI MR ZB
- [Kr] Krengel, Ulrich -- Ergodic theorems. With a supplement by Antoine Brunel. De Gruyter Studies in Mathematics, 6. Walter de Gruyter & Co., Berlin, 1985. MR ZB
- [Mai] Maistrov, L.E. -- Probability theory: a historical sketch. Translated and edited by Samuel Kotz. Probability and Mathematical Statistics, Vol. 23. Academic Press, New York-London, 1974. MR ZB
- [Maj] Major, Péter -- The limit behavior of elementary symmetric polynomials of i.i.d. random variables when their order tends to infinity. Ann. Probab. 27 (1999), no. 4, 1980--2010. URL MR ZB
- [Na] Navas, Andrés -- An ergodic theorem with values in a non-positively curved space via a canonical barycenter map. Ergodic Theory Dynam. Systems 33 (2013), no. 2, 609--623. DOI MR ZB
- [Pa] Parthasarathy, Kalyanapuram R. -- Probability measures on metric spaces. Probability and Mathematical Statistics, No. 3. Academic Press, Inc., New York-London, 1967. MR ZB
- [Si] Simon, Barry -- Advanced complex analysis. A Comprehensive Course in Analysis, Part 2B. American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 2015. MR ZB
- [St] Stone, Marshall H. -- Postulates for the barycentric calculus. Ann. Mat. Pura Appl. (4) 29 (1949), 25--30. DOI MR ZB
- [Sz1] Székely, Gábor J. -- On the polynomials of independent random variables. Limit theorems of probability theory (Colloq., Keszthely, 1974), pp. 365--371. Colloq. Math. Soc. János Bolyai, Vol. 11, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1975. MR ZB
- [Sz2] Székely, Gábor J. -- A limit theorem for elementary symmetric polynomials of independent random variables. Z. Wahrsch. Verw. Gebiete 59 (1982), no. 3, 355--359. DOI MR ZB
- [vE] van Es, Bert -- On the weak limits of elementary symmetric polynomials. Ann. Probab. 14 (1986), no. 2, 677--695. URL MR ZB
- [Vi] Villani, Cédric -- Topics in optimal transportation. Graduate Studies in Mathematics, 58. American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 2003. MR ZB
- [Zh] Zhan, Xingzhi -- Matrix inequalities. Lecture Notes in Mathematics, 1790. Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 2002. MR ZB