Rationality of weighted hypersurfaces of special degree
Abstract
Let be a quasismooth well-formed weighted projective hypersurface and let . We characterize when is rational under the assumption that divides . Furthermore, we give a new family of normal rational weighted projective hypersurfaces with ample canonical divisor, valid in all dimensions, adding to the list of examples discovered by Kollr. Finally, we determine precisely which affine Pham-Brieskorn threefolds are rational, answering a question of Rajendra V. Gurjar.
Author information. Michael Chitayat, University of Ottawa, [email protected], ORCID: 0000-0002-0590-539X
Keywords. Commutative algebra, algebraic geometry, weighted complete intersections, rational varieties, Pham-Brieskorn varieties.
Statements and declarations. The author has no competing interests or funding to declare.
Acknowledgements. The author wishes to thank Rajendra V. Gurjar for proposing Question 1.1, Pedro Garcia Sanchez for sharing some useful comments as well as the reference [1], and Daniel Daigle for multiple comments and suggestions, the most important of which significantly shortened the proof of Theorem A.
1 Introduction
Let be a smooth projective hypersurface over of degree . It is well known that
(1) |
We consider the more general situation of weighted hypersurfaces in the weighted projective space . This additional generality makes understanding when is rational more difficult; we give new results in this direction with subsequent applications.
A Pham-Brieskorn ring is a -algebra of the form
where each . These rings, their corresponding affine varieties and their singular points have been studied extensively for decades from many perspectives (see [20], [11], [18], [15], etc.). This work was motivated by the following question of Rajendra V. Gurjar, to which we manage to provide a complete answer.
1.1 Question.
For which 4-tuples is rational?
We begin by defining an -grading on by declaring that is homogeneous of degree , where . Thus, is a hypersurface of the weighted projective space . In view of Castelnuovo’s Theorem, which states that rationality and unirationality are equivalent in dimension 2 over , it is clear that is rational if and only if is rational. As such, we instead answer the following question, which has the same answer as Question 1.1.
1.2 Question.
For which 4-tuples is rational?
To answer Question 1.2, we require a theorem on numerical semigroups. We say that a tuple is well-formed if for all .
Theorem A.
Suppose is well-formed, let be the numerical semigroup generated by and let .
-
(i)
If then .
-
(ii)
If and , then and .
In addition to Theorem A, we prove the rationality of a special family of projective varieties in Proposition 3.6.
Proposition.
Let and consider the graded polynomial ring where is a field, , , and for all . Suppose is irreducible and homogeneous of degree and both and are non-zero. Then is rational over .
Using Theorem A together with Proposition 3.6, we eventually obtain the following (Theorem 3.14) which generalizes (1):
Theorem.
Let where and let . Suppose is a well-formed quasismooth hypersurface of degree for some . Then the following are equivalent:
-
(a)
is rational,
-
(b)
,
-
(c)
one of the following holds
-
(i)
, , and ;
-
(ii)
.
-
(i)
With Theorem 3.14 available to us, we are able to address Gurjar’s Question 1.2. We will see that Question 1.2 reduces to the special case where (see Definition 4.4) and hence is completely answered by the following, which is Theorem 4.7.
Theorem.
Suppose and . Then is rational if and only if one of the following holds:
-
(a)
, and ;
-
(b)
.
Another interesting application of our results is Example 3.18, which gives a new family of rational quasismooth weighted hypersurfaces with ample canonical divisor. We believe these are the first such examples since Kollr introduced in [14] what are now known as Kollr hypersurfaces. Our examples are simple and exist in any dimension. As a very special case, if are such that and then is a quasismooth normal rational projective surface with quotient singularities and ample canonical divisor.
Notation
We use the following terminology and notation throughout the article.
-
•
The set of natural numbers includes and is denoted by . The set of positive integers is denoted by .
-
•
Let denote the set of prime numbers and let . Given , define
and observe that is the prime factorization of . Given , we define .
-
•
If , we define to be the submonoid of generated by .
-
•
A numerical semigroup is a subset of satisfying the following three conditions:
-
(i)
-
(ii)
is finite
-
(iii)
The Frobenius number of is defined as . If , we may write instead of .
-
(i)
-
•
Let be a field. If is a field extension, the notation means that is purely transcendental of transcendence degree .
-
•
A variety is an integral separated scheme of finite type over an algebraically closed field . A surface is a two-dimensional variety.
-
•
Let be a normal variety over . Then is its group of Weil divisors and denotes a canonical divisor of . The group of -divisors is denoted by . A divisor is ample if there exists some such that is a very ample invertible sheaf (over ).
-
•
A del Pezzo surface is a normal projective surface with at most quotient singularities such that is ample. It is well known that a del Pezzo surface over is rational.
2 A Semigroup Theorem
2.1 Definition.
A tuple is well-formed if for all .
Theorem A.
Suppose is well-formed, let and let .
-
(i)
If then .
-
(ii)
If and , then and .
2.2 Remark.
With the assumptions of Theorem A(ii), if we assume in addition that , then and .
2.3 Remark.
Not only is the well-formedness assumption in Theorem A natural given the geometric context of weighted projective varieties discussed in the following section, it is also the case that various general questions about numerical semigroups can be reduced to the special case where is well-formed. (See for instance Section 3 of [13], Proposition 8 in [10], as well as Lemma 2.16 and Proposition 2.17 in [17].)
3 Rationality of Some Weighted Hypersurfaces
3.1.
Let denote the graded polynomial ring where and for each . The weighted projective space is well-formed if is well-formed. Every weighted projective space is a projective variety and is isomorphic to a well-formed weighted projective space. Note also that every weighted projective space is rational.
3.2.
Let be a homogeneous prime ideal of the graded ring and define . If are homogeneous elements of , we abbreviate by . If is generated by a regular sequence of homogeneous elements of of respective degrees where , then is called a weighted complete intersection of multidegree . In particular, if , and , we will say that is a weighted hypersurface of degree . The closed subset is called the affine cone over ; note that passes through the origin of and that is an integral affine scheme. The variety is quasismooth if is nonsingular away from the origin. A weighted complete intersection is well-formed if both
-
(i)
is well-formed,
-
(ii)
.
The amplitude of a well-formed weighted complete intersection is the quantity where . (We will preserve this notation for the amplitude through to the end of Section 3.) It is well known that if is a well-formed quasismooth weighted complete intersection, then is a normal, Cohen-Macaulay, -factorial variety with at most cyclic quotient (hence rational) singularities.
We make use of 3.3 to 3.5 in the proof of Corollary 3.17. Paragraph 3.3 appears in Section 5.4 of [5], Lemma 3.4 (a) is due to Demazure. Lemma 3.4 (b) and Proposition 3.5 are unpublished results of Daigle.
3.3.
If is an -graded domain, the number is called the saturation index of . One says that is saturated in codimension if for every height homogeneous prime ideal of . Let and . Let be the set of height homogeneous prime ideals of . If then is an extension of discrete valuation rings whose ramification index we denote by . For each , let (resp. ) be the closure of in (resp. in ); note that (resp. ) is a prime divisor of (resp. of ), and that each prime divisor on is a for some . For each prime divisor , define , and extend linearly to a -linear map , where .
3.4 Lemma.
Let be an -graded normal domain that is finitely generated over such that and .
-
(a)
There exists an ample -divisor of such that for all .
-
(b)
If is saturated in codimension , then (i.e. has integral coefficients).
Proof.
We use the notation of 3.3. Let be nonzero homogeneous elements of such that and let . By the Theorem below Section 3.5 in [7], there exists a unique such that and this is ample and satisfies for all . This shows (a).
If is saturated in codimension , then Corollary 9.4 of [6] implies that for all ; since has integral coefficients, it follows that has integral coefficients, proving (b). ∎
3.5 Proposition.
Let , let be a well-formed weighted projective space and let be a homogeneous prime ideal of with . Consider the graded ring and the closed subvariety of . Then is well-formed if and only if is saturated in codimension .
Proof.
Let be the canonical epimorphism. Let . For each prime factor of , let and . It is well known that . Also note that
given any homogeneous prime ideal of , . | (2) |
Suppose that is not saturated in codimension . Then there exists a height homogeneous prime ideal of such that . Let ; then , so . Choose a prime factor of ; then and (by (2)) . We also have , so . Since , we find , so and hence is not well-formed.
Conversely, suppose that is not well-formed. Then , so there exists a homogeneous prime ideal of such that and . Note that and that ; so is a homogeneous prime ideal of of height . Since , there exists a prime divisor of such that and hence . So (2) implies that divides , which implies that is not saturated in codimension . ∎
We generalize an unpublished result of Michela Artebani. See Proposition 4.3.4 in [3].
3.6 Proposition.
Let and consider the graded polynomial ring where is a field, , , and for all . Suppose is irreducible and homogeneous of degree and both and are non-zero. Then is rational over .
Proof.
Let and write where and are the canonical images of and in . Let . Since , we may assume without loss of generality that and that . We define the following elements of the function field of :
We claim that
(3) |
where the second inclusion is obvious. To prove the first inclusion, observe that is generated by elements of the form
(4) |
Consider any element from (4). Since , . So, for some and . We then have
We have
This shows that every element from (4) is an element of and consequently (3) is true. Since , it follows from (3) that . Since , it now suffices to show that .
Let and let . Write
where , and the coefficients (resp ) are not all zero. Then
from which it follows that
noting that the denominator is non-zero because not all the are zero and are algebraically independent over . It follows that which completes the proof.
∎
3.7 Lemma.
Let and suppose . If satisfy , then either or .
Proof.
Assume . Then so . Since , . So or , in which case . ∎
3.8 Corollary.
Let be such that and let where is irreducible and homogeneous of degree . Then is rational over .
Proof.
By Lemma 3.7, where each of and is either zero or is homogeneous of degree . We write where is the canonical image of in . Let , and let and denote the images of and in .
If , then so . Since is irreducible, where are not both 0. We then obtain that which is rational. The same argument shows that is rational if . Assume now that and . Then and are nonzero and the result follows from Proposition 3.6. ∎
3.9 Lemma.
Let be a well-formed quasismooth weighted complete intersection. Let be the graded ring . Then,
for all .
3.10 Proposition.
Let be a well-formed quasismooth weighted complete intersection of dimension that is not contained in a hyperplane. If belongs to the submonoid of , then . Moreover, is not uniruled and not rational.
Proof.
Let be the graded ring and let be a resolution of singularities of . Suppose . If , then . Otherwise, and since is not contained in a hyperplane, contains a nonzero monomial of . We obtain
the first isomorphism by Lemma 3.9, the second since has rational singularities. This shows that . Since has non-zero genus, it has non-negative Kodaira dimension, and hence is not uniruled. It follows that is not uniruled and not rational. ∎
3.11 Example.
3.12 Remark.
In Proposition 2.13 (ii) of [16], the authors prove that if is a quasismooth well-formed weighted complete intersection, and for all , then is not uniruled. They then remark that they do not know whether the assumption that for all is necessary for their result to hold. Proposition 3.10 shows that their assumption can often be relaxed.
3.13 Corollary.
Suppose is a well-formed quasismooth weighted hypersurface of degree .
-
(a)
If , then is rational.
-
(b)
If belongs to the submonoid of then and is not rational.
-
(c)
If or where , is not rational.
Proof.
3.14 Theorem.
Let where and let . Suppose is a well-formed quasismooth hypersurface of degree for some . Then the following are equivalent:
-
(a)
is rational,
-
(b)
,
-
(c)
one of the following holds
-
(i)
, , and ;
-
(ii)
.
-
(i)
Proof.
Let , let , and recall that . Since is well-formed, we have for every subset of of cardinality .
That (a) implies (b) follows from the fact that has rational singularities. Assume (b) holds. Then Corollary 3.13 (b) implies that , so either or . If , (ii) holds. If , Theorem A(ii) implies that and , so (i) holds. This proves that (b) implies (c). We show that (c) implies (a). If (i) holds, then is rational by Corollary 3.8. If (ii) holds, then is rational by Corollary 3.13 (a).
∎
3.15 Remark.
3.16.
Let be a well-formed quasismooth hypersurface. We already noted that is a normal projective variety with cyclic quotient singularities. Since is Cohen-Macaulay, its canonical sheaf coincides with its dualizing sheaf, so Theorem 3.3.4 of [8] implies that , where is the amplitude of . Note that the affine cone is a hypersurface of with only one singular point; so and its coordinate ring which we denote by , are normal. Since is well-formed, Proposition 3.5 implies that is saturated in codimension one and Lemma 3.4 implies that there exists an ample integral divisor such that for all . This implies that . It follows that is a canonical divisor of ; since is integral, , so is a canonical divisor of .
3.17 Corollary.
Let where and let . Suppose is a well-formed quasismooth hypersurface of degree for some . The following are equivalent:
-
(a)
is rational and has ample canonical divisor;
-
(b)
, , , , and .
Proof.
Let . By 3.16, there exists an ample integral divisor such that where . Suppose (a) holds. Then is ample, so , so condition (ii) of Theorem 3.14 is not satisfied. Since is rational, condition (i) of Theorem 3.14 must be satisfied, so (b) holds. Conversely, if (b) holds then is rational by Theorem 3.14, and , so is ample. ∎
3.18 Example.
For any , we can construct a normal rational projective -variety of dimension with quotient singularities and ample canonical divisor. Indeed, let and choose some satisfying the assumptions of Proposition 3.6 such that is well-formed and quasismooth, and such that the amplitude . By 3.16, the weighted hypersurface is a normal projective variety with quotient singularities and ample canonical divisor and by Proposition 3.6, is rational. In particular, the variety is one such example. By Theorem 8.1 in [12], one can produce many such examples.
3.19 Remark.
In Section 5 of [14], Kollr defines a family of weighted hypersurfaces , now known as Kollr hypersurfaces; some of these (see Theorem 39 in [14]) are rational with ample canonical divisor. As far as we know, they represent the first family of rational weighted projective hypersurfaces with ample canonical divisor, with Example 3.18 providing another such family. (Currently, we only know of these two families with this property.) Note the special case of 2-dimensional Kollr hypersurfaces is studied in detail in [19].
In view of Theorem 3.14 and Remark 3.19, we note that we know of no examples of two-dimensional non-rational quasismooth weighted hypersurfaces such that . Hence we ask the following question:
3.20 Question.
Does there exist a non-rational two-dimensional well-formed quasismooth hypersurface such that ? Theorem 3.14 implies that if such an exists and is a hypersurface, the degree of is strictly positive and not divisible by .
4 The Rational Affine Pham-Brieskorn Threefolds
Let . The ring is called a Pham-Brieskorn ring and is called an affine Pham-Brieskorn variety. We apply the results of the previous sections to answer the following question of R.V. Gurjar:
4.1 Question.
For which 4-tuples is a -rational variety?
4.2.
Let , and . Let and let for each . Then is a homogeneous irreducible element of the graded ring , is a graded ring and for each where is the canonical image of .
4.3 Proposition.
Let . Then is rational over if and only if is rational over .
Proof.
Let be the function field of and recall that the function field of is isomorphic to . Assume is rational over . Then and so the function field of is stably rational, hence unirational. By Castelnuovo’s Theorem, is rational. The converse is clear. ∎
4.4 Definition.
Given a tuple , we define and . We define .
4.5.
Let be Pham-Brieskorn ring. Lemma 3.1.14 in [3] shows that there exists a Pham-Brieskorn ring such that and . Moreover, given a Pham-Brieskorn ring , it is straightforward to determine (or equivalently the tuple ) explicitly; in particular, the proof of Lemma 3.1.14 in [3] shows that for all . This is demonstrated in Example 4.8 below. Consequently, to answer Question 4.1, it suffices to consider the special case where .
4.6 Proposition.
[3, Proposition 2.4.25] Let where and for all . Then, the weighted hypersurface is a well-formed quasismooth hypersurface if and only if .
4.7 Theorem.
Suppose and . Then is rational if and only if one of the following holds:
-
(a)
, and ;
-
(b)
.
Proof.
Let . Let and let . Since for each , we obtain that for some . Proposition 4.6 shows that is a well-formed quasismooth hypersurface of degree so satisfies the hypotheses of Theorem 3.14. It is easy to see that condition (a) is equivalent to condition (i) in Theorem 3.14. Since
condition (b) is equivalent to condition (ii) in Theorem 3.14. These two equivalences prove the theorem.
∎
4.8 Example.
We also obtain the following. Note there is no assumption on the cotype.
4.9 Corollary.
Let be a Pham-Brieskorn ring and consider the following statements:
-
(a)
has a rational singularity at the origin;
-
(b)
;
-
(c)
and are rational.
Then .
5 Proof of Theorem A
This section provides the proof of Theorem A. Recall the definition of a well-formed tuple from Definition 2.1.
Theorem A.
Suppose is well-formed, let and let .
-
(i)
If then .
-
(ii)
If and , then and .
The proof of Theorem A is given in paragraphs 5.2–5.16. We preserve the following notation until the end of proof.
5.1 Notation.
Given , we define and . Given , we define and .
5.2 Proposition.
-
(a)
Let and . If and then .
-
(b)
If are relatively prime then .
Proof.
The case of (a) is a well-known result of Frobenius; the general case follows. For (b), note that by the case of statement (6) in the introduction of [1]. Since , we get , implying that divides ; so and (b) follows. ∎
5.3 Assumption.
We assume from this point onward that and is well-formed.
5.4 Lemma.
If are such that , then .
Proof.
Let . Since is relatively prime to and also to , it is relatively prime to . Since divides and is relatively prime to , we obtain , as desired. ∎
Proof of Theorem A(i). We may assume that . We may also assume that , otherwise the result is trivial.
Consider first the case where . Since and divide and (by Lemma 5.4) , we get , so . Since and it follows that and . Note that , because and . We have , so Proposition 5.2(a) gives , as desired.
Next, consider the case where . Proposition 5.2(b) gives , so
We have , so
(5) |
We claim that . Indeed, ; if then , so and , so , a contradiction. This shows that , so (5) gives as required.
5.5 Assumption.
Let and assume that .
5.6 Remark.
5.7.
Assumptions 5.5 immediately imply:
-
(a)
-
(b)
-
(c)
, so in particular .
-
(d)
-
(e)
If are distinct, then .
5.8 Lemma.
If there exist distinct such that , then .
Proof.
Without loss of generality, we may assume that . Then . Let . Define and . We have and , so . Since and , we have , so Proposition 5.2(a) implies that , i.e.,
(6) |
Define for . Since divides , and since divides and divides , we have
, and are pairwise relatively prime. | (7) |
We claim that
(8) |
To see this, first note that for each ; so by (7). Conversely, if a prime power divides then the fact that implies that divides or , so , showing that divides . This proves (8). Define
and note that by (8); so
Since , we have . So (6) gives and hence
(9) |
Since and , we have , so the inequality in (9) is strict; since both sides of this strict inequality are multiples of , it follows that , so
(10) |
Consider the case . Then , so (10) gives , where the last inequality uses . Recall that . If then , so , which contradicts 5.7(b). So , in which case we have , so , so and , showing that . In view of 5.7(d), this shows that if then . So, to complete the proof, it suffices to show that
the case does not occur. | (11) |
From now-on, we assume that . Since divides , we have
(12) |
For each , define . For each , divides and is relatively prime to , so . Thus,
(13) |
We shall now consider three cases (, , ) and show that none of them is possible. Assume that . Note that , because (12) shows that if then is odd. So . This together with (10) gives
In view of (13), it follows that
(14) |
Note that if then both and divide , so in fact , contradicting 5.7(c). So .
If then (14) gives (the last inequality because ), so . We may assume that and ; then and . Since , is odd, so . If then and hence , a contradiction. So . Since and , is odd and , so and hence . This implies that , a contradiction. So the case does not occur.
If then (14) gives , so . Since , is odd, so and are odd. Hence, and . Then , a contradiction. So the case does not occur either.
From now-on, we assume that ; let us show that this leads to a contradicition. The definition implies that , so and hence . So (10) gives , or equivalently (using (13))
Dividing both sides by and using gives
(15) |
If then (using and ) , which contradicts (15). So and . Note that by (7), and ; so
, and are pairwise relatively prime. | (16) |
Substituting in (15) gives
(17) |
Now is equivalent to , which implies that (because , and ). Then (17) gives , so , which contradicts (16). So the case does not occur. This proves (11), and completes the proof of the Lemma. ∎
5.9 Remark.
In order to finish the proof of Theorem A, it suffices to prove that there exist distinct such that . Indeed, if such exist then Lemma 5.8 implies that , which (by Remark 5.6) completes the proof of the Theorem. Our proof that exist is by contradiction. In other words, we shall prove that Assumptions 5.10 lead to a contradiction.
5.10 Assumptions.
We continue to assume that the conditions of 5.3 and 5.5 are satisfied, and we also assume that
no elements satisfy and . |
We will derive a contradiction from the above assumption. Without loss of generality, we also assume that the labeling of is such that . Define positive integers by
Note that (if then contradicts 5.7(c)).
5.11 Lemma.
-
(a)
-
(b)
Proof.
Define for each prime number , and observe that
If is a prime factor of then , so divides exactly two elements of and consequently there exist distinct such that . Thus,
every prime factor of is a factor of . | (18) |
Conversely, suppose that is a prime factor of . Then there exists exactly one choice of elements of such that ; we have , so and hence . Moreover, . Hence,
every prime factor of satisfies . | (19) |
Let be elements of . Then and divides , so . Since are pairwise relatively prime, we obtain , proving (b). ∎
5.12 Lemma.
For every choice of distinct , we have .
Proof.
5.13 Lemma.
Let be such that . If then .
Proof.
Since , Proposition 5.2(a) implies that every integer strictly greater than belongs to and hence to . So , because . So and consequently . Multiplying both sides by gives
Since , the result follows. ∎
5.14 Lemma.
We have for all choices of distinct .
Proof.
Proceeding by contradiction, suppose that there exist such that and . Define , and ; then and
(21) |
Indeed, , , and because ; we have because and , so (21) is true. We have by Lemma 5.11(a), so Lemma 5.13 gives , i.e.,
(22) |
If then , so ; if then (21) implies that , so ; since , (22) gives in both cases, a contradiction. So .
If then it follows from (21) that , so (22) gives , which implies that . Then divides , which contradicts Lemma 5.12. So . To summarize,
Since and , we have
(23) |
We have by (21), so , so .
If then implies that , which is impossible because , and divides by Lemma 5.11(b). So . Since , this means that , so
It follows that divides ; since , we get and hence
(24) |
Proposition 5.2(b) gives . Note that and . Since , we get , so by (24). Since , we obtain , so
Condition (23) and imply that , and (21) gives ; thus, . This implies that (so ) and that . We may assume that and . Then (21) gives and . So (24) implies that , contradicting . ∎
5.15 Lemma.
Proof.
Without loss of generality, we may assume that ; by 5.10, it follows that . Since , we have , so Proposition 5.2(b) gives , so and hence . By contradiction, suppose that . Then (where and are positive integers), so
Also note that and by Lemma 5.4. If then and divide ; since we obtain , which is impossible since . So . If then and divide ; since we obtain , which is impossible since . So . It follows that
If is a prime factor of then and , so and , contradicting . This shows that , and the same argument gives . Thus,
Let . Since , we have , so and hence . So is even; since , and are odd. Thus, . So we can write
If is a prime factor of then , so . The fact that for each prime factor of implies that
Since is odd and divides , we have ; it follows that divides , which divides ; so . Since , we get . The fact that divides implies that ; since , it follows that . So we have , and (because ); this implies that . Since is odd, it follows that and hence . This implies that . So divides , a contradiction. ∎
5.16.
End of the proof of Theorem A. Lemma 5.15 gives , and we have by Lemma 5.11(b). So for some prime numbers and some . Since Lemma 5.11(a) gives where are pairwise relatively prime, it follows that one of is equal to , contradicting Lemma 5.14. This shows that Assumptions 5.10 lead to a contradiction. By Remark 5.9, this completes the proof of Theorem A.
References
- [1] Alfred Brauer. On a problem of partitions. American Journal of Mathematics, 64(1):299–312, 1942.
- [2] I. Cheltsov, J. Park, and Constantin Shramov. Exceptional del Pezzo hypersurfaces. Journal of Geometric Analysis, 20:787–816, 2008.
- [3] Michael Chitayat. Rigidity of Pham-Brieskorn Threefolds. https://ruor.uottawa.ca/handle/10393/44886, 2023. University of Ottawa, Theses and Dissertations.
- [4] Michael Chitayat and Daniel Daigle. On the rigidity of certain Pham-Brieskorn rings. Journal of Algebra, 550:290–308, 2020.
- [5] Michael Chitayat and Daniel Daigle. Locally nilpotent derivations of graded integral domains and cylindricity. Transformation Groups, 2022.
- [6] Daniel Daigle. Rigidity of graded integral domains and of their Veronese subrings, 2023.
- [7] Michel Demazure. Anneaux gradués normaux. In Introduction à la théorie des singularités. II: Méthodes algébriques et géométriques. (Introduction to the theory of singularities. II: Algebraic and geometric methods), pages 35–68. Paris: Hermann, 1988.
- [8] Igor Dolgachev. Weighted projective varieties. In James B. Carrell, editor, Group Actions and Vector Fields, pages 34–71, Berlin, Heidelberg, 1982. Springer Berlin Heidelberg.
- [9] Hubert Flenner and Mikhail Zaidenberg. Rational curves and rational singularities. Mathematische Zeitschrift, 244(3):549–575, 2003.
- [10] Ralf Fröberg, Christian Gottlieb, and Roland Häggkvist. On numerical semigroups. In Semigroup forum, volume 35, pages 63–83. Springer, 1986.
- [11] A Hefez and F Lazzeri. The intersection matrix of Brieskorn singularities. Inventiones mathematicae, 25(2):143–157, 1974.
- [12] A. R. Iano-Fletcher. Working with weighted complete intersections, page 101–174. London Mathematical Society Lecture Note Series. Cambridge University Press, 2000.
- [13] Selmer Martin Johnson. A linear diophantine problem. Canadian Journal of Mathematics, 12:390–398, 1960.
- [14] János Kollár. Is there a topological Bogomolov-Miyaoka-Yau inequality? Pure and Applied Mathematics Quarterly, 4, 02 2006.
- [15] John Milnor. On the 3-dimensional Brieskorn manifolds . Knots, groups, and 3-manifolds, 3:175–225, 1975.
- [16] Victor Vladimirovich Przyjalkowski and Constantin Aleksandrovich Shramov. On automorphisms of quasi-smooth weighted complete intersections. Sbornik: Mathematics, 212(3):374, 2021.
- [17] José Carlos Rosales, Pedro A García-Sánchez, et al. Numerical semigroups, volume 20. Springer, 2009.
- [18] Uwe Storch. Die Picard-zahlen der singularitäten . Journal für die reine und angewandte Mathematik, 350:188–202, 1984.
- [19] Giancarlo Urzúa and José Yáñez. Characterization of Kollár surfaces. Algebra & Number Theory, 12(5):1073–1105, 2018.
- [20] Etsuo Yoshinaga and Masahiko Suzuki. On the topological types of singularities of Brieskorn-Pham type. Science Reports of the Yokohama National University: Yokohama Kokuritsu Daigaku Rika Kiyō. Dai 1-rui, Sūgaku, Butsurigaku, Kagaku. Mathematics, physics, chemistry. Section I, (21-25), 1974.