Quantum Bruhat graphs and tilted Richardson varieties
Abstract.
Quantum Bruhat graph is a weighted directed graph on a finite Weyl group first defined by Brenti-Fomin-Postnikov. It encodes quantum Monk’s rule and can be utilized to study the -point Gromov-Witten invariants of the flag variety. In this paper, we provide an explicit formula for the minimal weights between any pair of permutations on the quantum Bruhat graph, and consequently obtain an Ehresmann-like characterization for the tilted Bruhat order. Moreover, for any ordered pair of permutations and , we define the tilted Richardson variety , with a stratification that gives a geometric meaning to intervals in the tilted Bruhat order. We provide a few equivalent definitions to this new family of varieties that include Richardson varieties, and establish some fundamental geometric properties including their dimensions and closure relations.
1. Introduction
Hilbert’s fifteenth problem, Schubert calculus, concerns the full flag variety
and its Schubert decomposition . The cohomology ring has a linear basis given by the Schubert varieties . The corresponding structure constants ’s, also referred to as the generalized Littlewood-Richardson numbers, are known to be nonnegative from transversal intersection. It has been a long standing open problem to find a combinatorial interpretation of them. The study of flag varieties, Schubert varieties and these structure constants is central in algebraic geometry and algebraic combinatorics.
The small quantum cohomology ring is a deformation of the cohomology ring. It shows up naturally in theoretical physics. The structure constants of with respect to the Schubert basis are known as the 3-point genus-0 Gromov-Witten invariants. They extend the generalized Littlewood-Richardson numbers in “quantum” direction.
The problem of multiplying Schubert classes in can be naturally encoded via the quantum Bruhat graph, first defined by Brenti-Fomin-Postnikov [2] and utilized by Postnikov [12]. The quantum Bruhat graph can be seen as a graphical representation of the quantum Monk’s rule and enjoys very rich algebraic and combinatorial properties. In particular, the minimal degree that appears in the quantum product is the weight of any shortest directed path from to [12]. The quantum Bruhat graph directly gives rise to the tilted Bruhat order [2], and these are our main combinatorial objects of interest for this paper.
Main result 1: weights in the quantum Bruhat graph:
We remark that Theorem 3.3 was also obtained via a combination of Postnikov’s toric Schur polynomials [11] on the quantum cohomology ring of the Grassmannian, and a geometric result by Buch-Chung-Li-Mihalcea [5]. See also [7]. Our proof is independent and combinatorial.
While weights on the quantum Bruhat graph encode important information in the quantum cohomology of the flag variety, we present a novel geometric interpretation of intervals in the tilted Bruhat order with a more classical flavor. For any , we define the tilted Richardson variety and the open tilted Richardson variety which reduce to the well-known (open) Richardson variety if in the Bruhat order.
Main result 2: definitions of the (open) tilted Richardson variety using
-
(1)
rank conditions (4.1);
-
(2)
cyclically rotated Richardson varieties in the Grassmannian (Theorem 4.6);
-
(3)
multi-Plücker coordinates (Theorem 4.12).
The (open) tilted Richardson varieties are our central geometric objects of study. Their geometric properties resemble those of Richardson varieties. However, since an analogue of Schubert varieties do not exist in our setting, most of the analysis requires new insights and techniques.
Main result 3: geometric properties of the (open) tilted Richardson variety:
-
(1)
a stratification that relates tilted Bruhat order (Theorem 5.2);
-
(2)
in the quantum Bruhat graph (Theorem 5.14);
-
(3)
the closure relation (Theorem 5.22).
In a sequel, we connect tilted Richardson varieties with curve neighborhoods . These are subvarieties of introduced by Buch-Chaput-Mihalcea-Perrin in [3] (see also [4], [6], [10] and references therein). They are closely related to computations in and .
Our paper is organized as follows. In Section 2, we introduce background information on quantum Bruhat graphs, tilted Bruhat orders, root systems, Grassmannians, flag varieties, Richardson varieties and Plücker coordinates. In Section 3, 4 and 5, we establish each aforementioned main results respectively on the combinatorics of quantum Bruhat graphs, definitions of the (open) tilted Richardson varieties, and their geometry.
2. Preliminaries
Let be the symmetric group on elements, generated by the simple transpositions . We typically write a permutation using its one-line notation or simplified as . For , let be the Coxeter length of , which is the smallest such that is a product of simple transpositions. Such an expression is called a reduced word of . Let be the set of reduced words of . Let be the inversion set of . It is well-known that equals the number of inversions of . Let be the set of transpositions, or equivalently, conjugates of the simple transpositions .
2.1. The quantum Bruhat graph and the tilted Bruhat orders
Definition 2.1.
The quantum Bruhat graph is a weighted directed graph on with the following two types of edges:
where . Write for the weight.
In other words, if and for every , or , which gives an edge in the Hasse diagram of the strong Bruhat order, or if and for every , . We can unify these two cases together using cyclic intervals.
Definition 2.2.
For , the (open) cyclic interval from to is if , and if . We can similarly define cyclic intervals , and .
Now in the quantum Bruhat graph if and only if for all . It is also clear that if and only if . Therefore, we have the following immediate observation on the cyclic symmetry of the quantum Bruhat graph.
Lemma 2.3.
Let be the long cycle . Then is an automorphism of the unweighted quantum Bruhat graph.
The quantum Bruhat graph for is shown in Figure 1.
For a directed path in , we say that has length , with weight . For , let be the length of a shortest path from to . Note that it is clear that for any , there exists a directed path from to , as one can always go through the identity. Postnikov [12] established some nice properties regarding weights of shortest paths. Here, we write for .
Lemma 2.4 ([12]).
For any , all shortest paths from to have the same weight . Moreover, the weight of any path from to is divisible by . In addition, if a path from to has weight , it must be a shortest path.
Lemma 2.4 is essentially saying that shortest length paths are precisely minimal weight paths. We remark that the last sentence from Lemma 2.4 is not explicitly written done in [12], but follows directly from the proof of Lemma 1 of [12], with much of the main content established in Lemma 6.7 of [2]. From now on, write for the minimal weight from to , where is a -tuple.
Example 2.5.
Let and . There are two shortest paths from to of length : and . We see that both paths have the same weight so . It is straightfroward to check that any other paths from to have weight divisible by (and not equal to) .
Definition 2.6 (tilted Bruhat order [2]).
For , define the tilted Bruhat order to be the graded partial order on such that if
(1) |
Equivalently, if there is a shortest path in the quantum Bruhat graph from to that passes through .
Remark 2.7.
A special case of the tilted Bruhat order is the strong Bruhat order. This is obtained by setting .
The tilted Bruhat order is shown in Figure 2.
Definition 2.8.
For , define the tilted Bruhat interval to be
Remark 2.9.
It follows from (1) that as long as and . Since we always have , we will omit the subscript and write instead of in the remaining part of this paper.
2.2. Root system and reflection ordering
The root system of type consists of with positive roots and simple roots . It’s corresponding Weyl group is identified with the symmetric group , while the reflection across the hyperplane normal to is identified with .
Definition 2.10.
An ordering of (or equivalently, of the reflections ) as is called a reflection ordering if appears (not necessarily consecutively) in the middle of and for all .
The following lemma is very classical. See for example Proposition 3 of [1].
Lemma 2.11.
Reflection orderings are in bijection with reduced words of the longest permutation . Given , its corresponding reflection ordering is constructed via for .
Example 2.12.
Consider the reduced word which corresponds to the reflection ordering written on top of the arrows:
2.3. Grassmaniann, Flag variety, and Plücker coordinates
Define the Grassmaniann to be the space of -dimensional subspaces . The Plücker embedding is a closed embedding that sends the subspace with basis to , the projective equivalence class of in . For any , let be the Plücker coordinate of . For any permutation ,
In particular, this means if for some . For , set where . For any permutation , define
where for . In particular, . Set and for all . More generally, for , set . The variety is the zero locus of the ideal generated by the following Plücker relations.
Definition 2.13.
For any , the Plücker relation associated to is:
Let and be the Borel and opposite Borel subgroup of consisting of invertible upper and lower triangular matrices respectively. Let be the maximal torus of diagonal matrices in .
The complete flag variety is defined to be . Fixing a basis of , we can identify a point with a flag where is the span of the first column vectors of any matrix representative . We define the multi-Plücker embedding to be the composition
that sends to . For any and , define the Plücker coordinate to be . It is also the minor of in the rows indexed by in the first columns. Similar to the Grassmaniann, the complete flag variety is the zero locus of the following incidence Plücker relations:
Definition 2.14 ([8]).
For any with fix , the incidence Plücker relation is:
(2) |
There are two special cases of Equation (2) that will be of particular importance to us. We now rewrite the incidence Plücker relations in these cases for convenience.
Case I.( and ): For where ,
(3) |
Case II.( and ): For with ,
(4) |
Equivalently,
(5) |
2.4. Schubert and Richardson varieties in
Given a permutation , we also view as the permutation matrix with at and everywhere else111We note that in some literature, this is the permutation matrix that corresponds to instead of .. The set of -fixed points on is . Define the Schubert cell to be the Borel orbit of and the Schubert variety to be the closure of the Schubert cell. Similarly, define the opposite Schubert cell and the opposite Schubert variety . Here and .
We will make use of the following equivalent definition of (opposite) Schubert cells and Schubert varieties. For any subset of , let be the projection onto the coordinates with indices in . The Schubert cell is
and the Schubert variety is
Similarly, the opposite Schubert cell is
and the opposite Schubert variety is
The (opposite) Schubert varieties possess a stratification by (opposite) Schubert cells:
where “” denotes the strong Bruhat order on .
It is perhaps easier to visualize Schubert and opposite Schubert varieties in the following way. For any and any , define to be the rank of the submatrix of obtained by taking the bottom rows and left columns. Define similarly to be the rank of the submatrix obtained by taking the top rows and left columns. Let be an matrix representative of such that is the span of the first column vectors of . Then
(6) |
and lies in the (opposite) Schubert cell if (6) holds after replacing “” with “”.
Define the open Richardson variety to be and the Richardson variety to be . In particular, and are non-empty if and only if , in which case we have
Similar to Schubert varieties, we also have
(7) |
where the disjoint union is taken over all Bruhat intervals contained in .
Moreover, as subvarieties of , each and can be defined by vanishing of Plücker coordinates:
(8) | ||||||
2.5. Schubert and Richardson varieties in Grassmannian
For each , define the Grassmannian Schubert variety by
and the Grassmannian Schubert cell by
Define the Grassmannian opposite Schubert variety and opposite Schubert cell by
and
Similar to Schubert varieties in , we have and . For any two -element subsets where and , we say in the Gale order if for all . Then the (opposite) Grassmaniann Schubert varieties are disjoint union of (opposite) Grassmaniann Schubert cells:
When , define the open Grassmaniann Richardson variety and its closure the Grassmaniann Richardson variety . We similarly have
(9) |
One can also define and by vanishing of Plücker coordinates:
(10) | ||||||
3. Combinatorics of the quantum Bruhat graph
3.1. Minimal weights in the quantum Bruhat graph
Our first theorem provides an explicit formula for the minimal weight from any pair of permutation to in .
Definition 3.1.
For with , we construct a lattice path starting at and ending at with steps as follows. For each , the step is
-
•
an upstep if and ,
-
•
a downstep if and ,
-
•
a horizontal step if or .
Define its depth to be the largest number such that this lattice path passes through for some , denoted .
Theorem 3.3.
Let . All shortest paths from to have weight where . Here, .
Example 3.4.
Consider and in . We need to figure out for . For , and so we need to construct a lattice path with an upstep at position and a downstep at position . This lattice path has depth , meaning that . We continue this procedure for all ’s. For example, at , the lattice path is discussed in Example 3.2 with . In the end, we arrive at .
We make use of the following technical tool by Brenti-Fomin-Postnikov. In the quantum Bruhat graph , label each directed edge by . The “label” here does not have indications towards the weight.
Theorem 3.5 ([2]).
Fix a reflection ordering of and fix . Then there is a unique directed path from to in such that its sequence of labels is strictly increasing with respect to . Moreover, this path has length .
Therefore, to prove Theorem 3.3, we pick a specific reflection ordering, and find its corresponding directed path and compute its weight, recalling that shortest paths are precisely minimal weight paths (Lemma 2.4). We need one more definition.
Definition 3.6.
For , let be the shifted linear order on given by
For , define the shifted Gale order as
Proof of Theorem 3.3.
Choose the reflection ordering that starts with all positive roots involving and then and so on. This is a valid reflection order because for any , , and appear in this order. One can also check that this ordering corresponds to the reduced word .
Fix and . Theorem 3.5 says that there is a unique directed path from to in by such that appear in the order of . We describe this unique directed path explicitly. Consider the first roots . After choosing such that we have a directed path , we must need since the rest of positive roots do not involve the index . At the same time, as long as , we can continue finding the path via induction on .
We can choose to be the smallest index greater than (with the convention that ) such that in the shifted linear order on where is declared the largest number. Such choices work because by construction, there is an edge from to in and we inevitably end up at since is the largest number in this linear order. Here is an example with :
We now examine how the weight accumulated. The weight of this path equals if and , and equals if no such exists, i.e. . It’s clear that at most one such exists which is intuitively at the place where the shifted linear order “wraps around”. Denote this weight by . Recall that the weight of a minimal weight path from to is denoted as . Also let be a vector such that as in Definition 3.1.
Our goal is to show that and we use induction on . By Theorem 3.5, , and by induction hypothesis, since . It remains to prove that
(11) |
We study Equation (11) coordinate by coordinate.
Case I: (). There exists a unique such that and , with . In fact, all of are strictly greater than by construction. Now compare the exponent of on both sides of Equation (11). In other words, we will compare the two lattice paths and .
For , is obtained from by deleting its largest element and replacing it by which is smaller than all values in . Thus, the path is strictly below the -axis when the -coordinate is , and is weakly above the -axis when the -coordinate is . The lattice path is obtained from by moving the subpath from to one step up. As a result, as desired. A cartoon for visualization for this scenario is seen in Figure 4.
For , so as desired.
For , and is obtained from by deleting the largest number smaller than , called , and replacing it by . Thus, and only differ from step to step . During this period,
This local change does not modify the depth. So .
Case II: (). Here and we need for all . The sub-case for is exactly the same as the sub-case for in Case 1, and the sub-case for is exactly the same as the sub-case for in Case 1.
The induction step goes through and we conclude that . ∎
3.2. Characterization of the tilted Bruhat order
A crucial consequence of Theorem 3.3 is a succinct description (Theorem 3.9) of the tilted Bruhat order defined by Brenti-Fomin-Postnikov. We now build up some intuition regarding the relationship between the shifted Gale order and the lattice path construction (Definition 3.1).
Lemma 3.7.
For all with , there exists such that . In fact, if and only if the lattice path passes through .
Proof.
Note that in the Gale order if and only if the lattice path does not go below the -axis, i.e. is a Dyck path. Likewise, if and only if the lattice path does not go below the -axis, where where the values are taken modulo . Therefore, for general and with , let the steps of be where each based on Definition 3.1. Then the lattice path is then constructed via the steps in this order. We now see that does not go below the -axis if and only if the lattice path goes through its lowest point at -coordinate equals . ∎
If , let denote the interval in shifted Gale order . The following lemma explains the relation between different shifted Gale orders.
Lemma 3.8.
For all and , if there exists such that and , then the intervals . Moreover, for any ,
Proof.
Without loss of generality assume . Since and , by Lemma 3.7, the lattice path passes through and , where . Since they have the same -coordinate, there are the same number of and between the two points and thus
For any , we have
Therefore,
As a result, the lattice path have the same -coordinate at and . Since , reaches its lowest point at both -coordinate and . Similarly, reaches its lowest point at both -coordinate and . By Lemma 3.7, . Therefore . The opposite direction follows by same reasoning. ∎
Theorem 3.9.
For , the following are equivalent:
-
(1)
;
-
(2)
;
-
(3)
for all sequence such that and for all , we have ;
-
(4)
there exists a sequence such that for all .
Proof.
is clear by definition. We will show that . is immediate given that Lemma 3.7 establishes the existence of ’s satisfying .
Recall that the long cycle is an automorphism of the unweighted quantum Bruhat graph (Lemma 2.3). Fix a sequence such that for all . As , there is a shortest path from to that passes through . As shortest length paths equal minimal weight paths (Lemma 2.4), we also have , where is the exponent vector of the weight of any shortest path from to . Since is an automorphism, the same logic also applies to so
By Theorem 3.3, the coordinate of is given by the depth of the lattice path which is because . As a result, the coordinate of both and must be as well, which translate to and .
The following is immediate from Theorem 3.9:
Corollary 3.10.
Let be any subinterval. Let be any sequence such that for all , then for all ,
4. Tilted Richardson varieties
From this point on, we turn our attention to geometry. The goal of this section is to give three equivalent definitions to (open) tilted Richardson varieties and for any pair of permutations . These varieties of interest will later be proved to provide a geometric meaning to the tilted Bruhat order (Theorem 5.2). In particular, if in the Bruhat order, the (open) tilted Richardson varieties coincide with the usual (open) Richardson varieties and . These three equivalent definitions use:
-
(1)
rank conditions (4.1);
-
(2)
cyclically rotated Richardson varieties in the Grassmannian (Theorem 4.6);
-
(3)
multi-Plücker coordinates (Theorem 4.12).
As an intermediate step, we first work with and and then show that they do not depend on the choice of sequence (4.10). Here, given and a sequence , we write if for all .
When , recall the definition of cyclic intervals in Definition 2.2. For convenience, we extend the definition by setting and .
4.1. The first definition: rank conditions
Our first definition is motivated by our characterization of tilted Bruhat order (Theorem 3.9).
Definition 4.1.
Define the open tilted Richardson variety with respect to to be:
(14) |
Define the tilted Richardson variety with respect to to be:
(17) |
Indeed, for any , . Therefore
In particular, is independent of the choice of . We will see later (4.10) that in fact and are both independent of .
It is easier to visualize tilted Richardson varieties as follows. For any , and , define to be the rank of the submatrix of obtained by taking the rows in and the left columns. Let be a matrix representative of . Then
(18) |
and if we replace “” with “” in (18).
Example 4.2.
Let and . Then for all choices of and . See Figure 5 for an illustration where and represent and respectively. The red horizontal line segment in column represent the cutoff of under for different choices of , where .
Let . For , there are rank conditions imposed on as in (17). The condition is interpreted as the rank of the shaded submatrix in Figure 5 being at most , the number of in said region.
Remark 4.3.
If in strong Bruhat order, namely where , then and are the (open) Richardson variety and respectively.
4.2. The second definition: pullback of cyclically rotated Richardson varieties
For , let be any matrix such that is the column span of . Let be the cyclic rotation such that for
(19) |
For , denote , identifying with .
Definition 4.4.
For any with and such that , define the cyclically rotated (open) Grassmaniann Richardson variety
The cyclically rotated Richardson varieties are instances of Positroid varieties (see [9, Section 6]). Similar to Grassmaniann Richardson varieties, cyclically rotated Richardson varieties can also be defined via vanishing of certain Plücker coordinates.
Proposition 4.5 ([9]).
For , with and ,
The corresponding open cell .
Proof.
For each , define to be the projection onto the -th flag.
Theorem 4.6.
For , we have
Since each is a closed subvariety of and is open, we have the following corollary.
Corollary 4.7.
is a closed subvariety of and is open.
Let and be any two sequences such that and . Our next goal is to assert that the (open) tilted Richardson variety is independent of the choice of . We first need the following lemma. We note that this can be seen as an alternate interpretation of Lemma 3.8.
Lemma 4.8.
For with , suppose and for some . Then and . Furthermore, take any and its matrix representative whose column span equals . Then
where is the -th row of .
Proof.
Since , we only need to prove the closed case. From Proposition 4.5, we have
Since Lemma 3.8 implies , we have .
For the second part, Lemma 3.8 implies that there exists some integer satisfying
By definition, for any , we have
Notice that
and equality holds if and only if the two subspaces and are linearly independent. This concludes the proof. ∎
Example 4.9.
Continuing Example 4.2, Lemma 4.8 implies that both the green shaded area and the purple hatched area in Figure 6 have rank . Moreover, the row spans of the two areas are independent.
Corollary 4.10.
and for and .
As a consequence of 4.10, we will denote the (open) tilted Richardson variety as (). In particular, if in strong Bruhat order, and .
4.3. The third definition: vanishing of Plücker coordinates
Lemma 4.11.
For any flag and subset , if , then there exists a permutation such that , and .
Proof.
Let be an matrix representative of such that is the span of the first column vectors of . The submatrix of in the rows indexed by in the first columns has full rank. Therefore, there exists a submatrix of in the first columns that also has full rank. Denote the row index of this submatrix as . Then and .
Apply this process inductively to find a chain of subsets such that for any . Using similar idea, we can also find a chain such that for . Let be the permutation such that . Then and . ∎
Theorem 4.12.
For any permutations , we have
and the corresponding open cell .
Proof.
Fix a sequence such that . For any and , we first show . By Theorem 3.9, there exists such that . Since , by Proposition 4.5, and . We have proven .
5. Geometric properties of tilted Richardson varieties
In this section, we explore some further geometric properties of the tilted Richardson varieties, analogous to those of the classical Richardson varieties. We do note, however, that most of our analysis are significantly different and more technical than the classical case, due to the lack of an analogue notion of Schubert varieties and the constant usage of the sequence that keeps varying.
5.1. Stratification of by open tilted Richardson varieties
We start with a useful lemma that controls the choices of to some extent.
Lemma 5.1.
For any permutation and any , there exists such that and .
Proof.
Consider the lattice path . Since and , we obtain from by,
-
-
at the -th step, changing a to a or changing a to a ; and
-
-
at the -th step, changing a to a or changing a to a .
In other words, we obtain by moving the lattice points
(20) |
Consider now . By Lemma 3.7, if and only if hits the its lowest point with -coordinate in . Since the -coordinate changes by at most from to , if , then all lattice points in with -coordinate are moved up by and all lattice points with -coordinate are moved down by . This is impossible by (20). Therefore and there exists such that and . ∎
Theorem 5.2.
.
Proof.
It is straightforward from definition that the right hand side is a disjoint union and that for all . To prove the direction, pick . We will show that for some . Pick such that , for , set
Then . In particular, for all . Furthermore, implies that is a subinterval in the shifted Gale order .
Fix , by Lemma 3.8 and 4.10, the sets and are independent of the choice of as long as . Combining with Lemma 5.1, we can choose such that . Let be any matrix representative of and let and denote the submatrix of consisting of the first and columns respectively. If
then row of lies in the row span of with row index in . Thus row of also lies in the row span of with row index in . This implies that . The claim follows from similar reasoning.
Let be permutations such that and for all . It then follows from definition of and that where and . Since for all , namely , we conclude that any lies in for some . ∎
5.2. Dimension of and
In this subsection, we show that and have dimension (Theorem 5.14), the distance between in the quantum Bruhat graph (Section 2). We do this by analyzing from different charts.
For any permutation , the permuted opposite Schubert cell is the set of flags satisfying . These could also be realized as matrices with ’s in for all and ’s to the right of ’s.
Example 5.3.
Let , then can be identified as the following affine space with each being a copy of :
Proposition 5.4.
For any permutations ,
-
(1)
if , then ,
-
(2)
.
Proof.
This follows directly from Theorem 4.12. ∎
Definition 5.5.
For , define to be the tilted Rothe diagrams
Example 5.6.
We demonstrate 5.5 with and using diagrams in Figure 7(A) and Figure 7(B). Put in position and . Draw a red horizontal line in column immediately above . These red lines represent the “floor” in each column. For , draw death rays to the right and down of each until they hit the red horizontal line or right boundary. Similarly, draw death rays to the right and up for . The boxes remain are and .
One may notice similarities between Figure 7(A) and Rothe diagram of a permutation. Indeed, if , then is precisely the Rothe diagram . Moreover, on , the vanishing of Plücker coordinates as in 5.7(1) gives us the parametrization of (see e.g. [13, Section 2.2]).
Definition 5.7.
For every pair of permutations and every choice of such that , define as the following set of equations:
-
(1)
for every box , set ,
-
(2)
for every box , set .
Remark 5.8.
An alternative way to phrase is, for column :
-
•
under the chart as in Example 5.3, set entries in the diagram to be .
-
•
under the chart , set entries in the diagram to be .
Up until now, we have been working with any sequence such that . There are many such choices for and any one of them works. However, we are now going to distinguish some choices from the rest, that are particularly nice.
Definition 5.9.
For a pair of permutations , a sequence is flat if
-
•
and
-
•
for all .
We note that this is equivalent to choosing whenever possible. These are also the choices of ’s such that the number of equations in is maximized.
Lemma 5.10.
For any pair of permutations , there exists that is flat. Moreover, for any such , it is also flat with respect to all pairs of such that .
Lemma 5.11.
For any and any flat , there are equations in .
Proof.
We proceed by induction on . If , we have and any sequence is flat. For any and any , the number of entries in column of and sum up to . Therefore consists of equations.
Suppose now that the statement holds when . For any pair such that , let be any permutation such that . Fix any flat with respect to and , by Lemma 5.10, is also flat for . We are then left to show that there is one more equation from Definition 5.7 in than in . We compare the diagrams and in each column .
For or , since and ,
(21) |
Consider now . In this case we still have . Since is an edge in quantum Bruhat graph, we have . Since , for , . Therefore and thus . Therefore either both , in which case
(22) |
or , in which case
(23) |
In both cases, and have the same number of boxes in column .
We are left to consider column and . Since and ,
(24) |
Since is flat, and thus . Therefore
(25) |
Since for all ,
Therefore has one more box than in column and combined.
Example 5.12.
We use the following example to help understand the proof of Lemma 5.11. Let and . One can verify that and that . We draw and as in 5.6. Notice that both diagrams have the same number of boxes in columns , and the number of boxes in column combined differ by .
Proposition 5.13.
For any and any flat , , where is the vanishing locus of equations in .
Proof.
We first show . This is equivalent to proving that for every flag , satisfies the equations in . There are two type of equations in :
Type (1). For , since , by Proposition 4.5
Type (2). For , since , by Proposition 4.5
This implies . Combining with Proposition 5.4, we are done.
We now show . It is enough to show that on the chart for all . We proceed by induction on . Define to be the subset of equations that correspond to boxes in the -th column of and . For , if and only if for all . Notice that these are precisely the equations in . Therefore .
The induction step is to show that for any :
Since is flat, by Lemma 4.8,
We wish to show that if or then vanishes on . We first fix any and consider the incidence Plücker relation in (3) associated to and :
(26) |
We claim that the right hand side of (26) vanishes. There are two cases:
-
(1)
If . Since , we have . This implies that vanishes since ;
-
(2)
If . Then is a box in and vanishes.
Therefore the both sides of (26) vanish. Since , and thus vanishes on . The case where follows from the same reasoning. ∎
Theorem 5.14.
is equidimensional of dimension .
Proof.
Since is carved out by equations in Proposition 5.13, by Krull’s principal ideal theorem, every irreducible component of has dimension at least .
Now we need to prove . If not, let be an irreducible component with . Denote as the closure of in and . Since is closed in the chart (by Proposition 5.13), we have . There are two cases.
-
(1)
. Since is the intersection of and a union of hyperplanes , the dimensions of and differ by at most one: . However, since and by Theorem 5.2, by induction on , which is a contradiction.
-
(2)
. This implies that is a projective variety. On the other hand, is quasi-affine. This cannot happen unless , contradicting .
Since we reach a contradiction in both cases, we conclude that . ∎
5.3. Closure of
Certainly, we expect (Theorem 5.22). One direction is clear. For the other direction, by Theorem 5.2 and induction hypothesis, it suffices to show that for such that , and dually, for such that . We focus on such an .
Throughout this section, let such that .
Lemma 5.15.
.
Proof.
The rest of this section is mainly devoted to controling the dimensions of this quasi-affine variety in Lemma 5.15 by finding explicit equations in said charts.
Definition 5.16.
For every pair of permutations and every choice of flat such that , let such that . Assume for . Define as the following set of equations:
-
(1)
for every box , set ,
-
(2)
for every box that is also in , set ,
-
(3)
for every box that is not in there are two cases:
-
(a)
and , set ,
-
(b)
and , set .
-
(a)
Example 5.17.
We demonstrate equations of type and in 5.16 using as in 5.12. Here, and . On , equations from correspond to having ’s in the green shaded boxes in Figure 9(C). Equations from and correspond to having in position and vanishing of the minor in blue brackets in Figure 9(C).
We need the following technical lemma and its consequence to prove Proposition 5.20.
Lemma 5.18.
For any with , if there exists and such that for some , then
() |
Proof.
Fix any such that . Then Equation ( ‣ 5.18) is equivalent to
By expanding using (5), this is equivalent to
(27) |
Since and , only if for any . Thus only if . Equation (27) is then equivalent to
By the same reasoning, this is equivalent to
(28) |
Since for by (4), Equation 28 and thus ( ‣ 5.18) holds. ∎
Corollary 5.19.
Given , for any with , if flag satisfies for every , then
() |
Proof.
By Lemma 5.10, there is a flat such that . By Lemma 5.18,
Moreover, for every , by flatness of :
By summing the above equations and subtracting appropriate times, we obtain ( ‣ 5.19). ∎
Proposition 5.20.
For any flat , .
Proof.
We first show . This is equivalent to proving that satisfies the equations in if . There are four types of equations in :
Type (1). Here . Since , we have , by Proposition 4.5
Type (2). Here . Since and if , we have , and
Type (3a). Here where and . Since , we have , and
For , the corresponding term in right hand side of (29) is
For , since and , we have and thus . Therefore for all .
For , if , then and . Similarly, if , then and . Therefore, for each ,
(30) |
Since for ,
The right hand side of (30) equals
Since , this is by 5.19. Therefore
Since we have exhausted all equations in , we conclude the proof of direction.
We now prove the direction. Namely for and , if then . By the same reasoning in 5.13, if then for all such that . We can then focus on Equations in of type and as in 5.16. It is enough to show that if then for all .
We proceed by induction on . For , . Therefore . Suppose the statement holds for , we fix such that and consider the following two cases:
Case I (): By (3), we have
(31) |
If , then by of 5.16. If , then . Since is flat, and thus by inductive hypothesis. The right hand side of (31) is then . Since , . Thus .
Case II (): Again by (3),
(32) |
If , then either or . In both cases, we have . If , then and by inductive hypothesis. The right hand side of (32) then equals
(33) |
In order to show the above equation vanishes, we wish to multiply by and apply the equation in of 5.16. However, it is not guaranteed that for . So we further divide into two cases.
Case IIA (): Using from 5.16, we have
(34) |
By (4), Equation 34 equals . Since for and for , we have
Since and are disjoint, by 5.19, we have
Case IIB (): For , since we have , we have . Notice by 5.7 and 5.16, these are the equations in . Therefore
By Lemma 5.15, we have as desired. ∎
Proposition 5.21.
is equidimensional of dimension .
Proof.
Since is the zero locus of equations by Proposition 5.20, every irreducible component has dimension . On the other hand, Theorem 5.14 and Lemma 5.15 implies that every irreducible component has dimension at most . ∎
Theorem 5.22.
.
Proof.
We prove by induction on . For , and . Now assume . By Theorem 5.2, it is enough to show that for all such that . Pick any such , by Lemma 5.15, we have
as quasi-affine varieties in . Let be any irreducible component. Since by Proposition 5.21, . Since is irreducible, , and since this holds for all irreducible components , . Thus, as desired. ∎
Acknowledgements
We are grateful to Alex Postnikov for introducing us to quantum Bruhat graphs. We thank Anders Buch, Allen Knutson, Thomas Lam, Leonardo Mihalcea, Lauren Williams, Weihong Xu and Alexander Yong for many helpful conversations. SG is partially supported by an NSF Graduate Research Fellowship under grant No. DGE-1746047.
References
- [1] Anders Björner. Orderings of Coxeter groups. In Combinatorics and algebra (Boulder, Colo., 1983), volume 34 of Contemp. Math., pages 175–195. Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, RI, 1984.
- [2] Francesco Brenti, Sergey Fomin, and Alexander Postnikov. Mixed Bruhat operators and Yang-Baxter equations for Weyl groups. Internat. Math. Res. Notices, (8):419–441, 1999.
- [3] Anders S. Buch, Pierre-Emmanuel Chaput, Leonardo C. Mihalcea, and Nicolas Perrin. Finiteness of cominuscule quantum -theory. Ann. Sci. Éc. Norm. Supér. (4), 46(3):477–494, 2013.
- [4] Anders S. Buch, Pierre-Emmanuel Chaput, Leonardo C. Mihalcea, and Nicolas Perrin. Projected Gromov-Witten varieties in cominuscule spaces. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 146(9):3647–3660, 2018.
- [5] Anders S. Buch, Sjuvon Chung, Changzheng Li, and Leonardo C. Mihalcea. Euler characteristics in the quantum -theory of flag varieties. Selecta Math. (N.S.), 26(2):Paper No. 29, 11, 2020.
- [6] Anders S. Buch and Leonardo C. Mihalcea. Curve neighborhoods of Schubert varieties. J. Differential Geom., 99(2):255–283, 2015.
- [7] W. Fulton and C. Woodward. On the quantum product of Schubert classes. J. Algebraic Geom., 13(4):641–661, 2004.
- [8] William Fulton. Young tableaux, volume 35 of London Mathematical Society Student Texts. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1997. With applications to representation theory and geometry.
- [9] Allen Knutson, Thomas Lam, and David E. Speyer. Positroid varieties: juggling and geometry. Compos. Math., 149(10):1710–1752, 2013.
- [10] Changzheng Li and Leonardo C. Mihalcea. K-theoretic Gromov-Witten invariants of lines in homogeneous spaces. Int. Math. Res. Not. IMRN, (17):4625–4664, 2014.
- [11] Alexander Postnikov. Affine approach to quantum Schubert calculus. Duke Math. J., 128(3):473–509, 2005.
- [12] Alexander Postnikov. Quantum Bruhat graph and Schubert polynomials. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., 133(3):699–709, 2005.
- [13] Alexander Woo and Alexander Yong. A Gröbner basis for Kazhdan-Lusztig ideals. Amer. J. Math., 134(4):1089–1137, 2012.