This paper was converted on www.awesomepapers.org from LaTeX by an anonymous user.
Want to know more? Visit the Converter page.

Quantifier elimination in II1 factors

Ilijas Farah Department of Mathematics and Statistics, York University, 4700 Keele Street, Toronto, Ontario, Canada, M3J 1P3 Matematički Institut SANU, Kneza Mihaila 36, 11 000 Beograd, p.p. 367, Serbia email: [email protected] http://www.math.yorku.ca/\simifarah To the memory of Eberhard Kirchberg.
Abstract.

No type II1 tracial von Neumann algebra has theory that admits quantifier elimination.

Partially supported by NSERC
ORCID iD https://orcid.org/0000-0001-7703-6931

Model theory is largely the study of definable sets, more precisely sets definable by first order (continuous or discrete) formulas. If the theory of a structure admits elimination of quantifiers, then its definable subsets are definable by quantifier-free formulas and therefore easier to grasp. This is the case with atomless Boolean algebras, dense linear orderings without endpoints, real closed fields, divisible abelian groups…See for example [37]. Quantifier elimination is equivalent to an assertion about embeddings between finitely-generated substructures of an ultrapower that resembles the well-known fact that all embeddings of the hyperfinite II1 factor into its ultrapower are unitarily equivalent (Proposition 1.2, Proposition 3.2). Our motivation for studying quantifier elimination in tracial von Neumann stems from Jekel’s work on 1-bounded entropy in W\mathrm{W}^{*}-algebras defined on types ([31], [30]). Our main result implies that 1-bounded entropy is a genuine generalization of Hayes’s 1-bounded entropy (see [27], [28]). This is because the latter is defined for quantifier-free types, while the former is defined for full types.

In [24, Theorem 2.1] it was proven that the theory of the hyperfinite II1 factor does not admit quantifier elimination (see §1) and that if NN is a II1 McDuff factor such that every separable II1 factor is N𝒰N^{\mathcal{U}}-embeddable111All ultraproducts in this paper are associated to nonprincipal ultrafilters on {\mathbb{N}} and almost all of them are tracial. then the theory of NN does not admit elimination of quantifiers ([24, Theorem 2.2]).

In spite of the slow start, the question of quantifier elimination in C\mathrm{C}^{*}-algebras has been answered completely. In [17, Theorem 1.1] it was proven that the only C\mathrm{C}^{*}-algebras whose theories in the language of unital C\mathrm{C}^{*}-algebras admit quantifier elimination are (with KK denoting the Cantor space) {\mathbb{C}}, 2{\mathbb{C}}^{2}, M2()M_{2}({\mathbb{C}}) and C(K)C(K), and that the only C\mathrm{C}^{*}-algebras whose theories in the language without a symbol for a unit admit quantifier elimination are {\mathbb{C}} and C0(K{0})C_{0}(K\setminus\{0\}).

The key component of [17] is an observation due to Eberhard Kirchberg,222This is the paragraph with norm ultraproducts. that there are two very different embeddings of Cr(F2)\mathrm{C}^{*}_{r}(F_{2}) into the ultrapower of the Cuntz algebra 𝒪2\mathcal{O}_{2}. First, by [36], every exact C\mathrm{C}^{*}-algebra embeds into 𝒪2\mathcal{O}_{2} and diagonally into its ultrapower. Second, by [25], Cr(F2)\mathrm{C}^{*}_{r}(F_{2}) embeds into 𝒰Mn()\prod_{\mathcal{U}}M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}), giving a nontrivial embedding into the ultrapower of 𝒪2\mathcal{O}_{2}.

Later on, in [23], paragraph preceding Lemma 5.2, it was pointed out without a proof that the argument from [24] implies that no McDuff II1 factor admits elimination of quantifiers. Also, in [22, Proposition 4.17] it was proven that if NN is a II1 factor such that NN and M2(N)M_{2}(N) have the same universal theory and NN is existentially closed for its univeral theory, then NN is McDuff. This implies that if NN is not McDuff and M2(N)M_{2}(N) embeds unitally into N𝒰N^{\mathcal{U}}, then NN does not admit elimination of quantifiers.

During a reading seminar on model theory and free probability based on [31] at York University in the fall semester of 2022, the author (unaware of the recent developments described in the last paragraph) rediscovered an easy argument that the theory of a non-McDuff factor NN such that M2(N)M_{2}(N) embeds unitally into N𝒰N^{\mathcal{U}}, does not admit quantifier elimination and asserted that closer introspection of the proof of [24, Theorem 2.1] ought to yield the same result for all II1 factors. This is indeed the case; the following answers the [31, Question 2.18] in case of tracial von Neumann algebras of type II1.

Theorem 1.

If NN is a tracial von Neumann algebra with a direct summand of type II1, then the theory of NN does not admit elimination of quantifiers.

The key lemma is proven in §2 and the proof of Theorem 1 can be found at the end of this section. The well-known criterion for quantifier elimination is proven in §3 (in spite of it being well-known, a self-contained proof of this fact was not available in the literature until it appeared in [26, Proposition 9.4]). In §4 we state conjectures on when the theory of a tracial von Neumann algebra is model-completene and when it admits quantifier elimination.

Our terminology is standard. For model theory see [9], [26], for general operator algebras [12], for II1 factors [1], and for model theory of tracial von Neumann algebras [31] and [23].

For simplicity of notation, every tracial state is denoted τ\tau, except those on Mn()M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}), denoted trn{\rm tr}_{n}.

A tracial von Neumann algebra is R𝒰R^{\mathcal{U}}-embeddable if it embeds into some (equivalently, any) ultrapower of the hyperfinite II1 factor RR associated with a nonprincipal ultrafilter on {\mathbb{N}}. By [32], not all tracial von Neumann algebras with separable dual are R𝒰R^{\mathcal{U}}-embeddable.

A personal note

Two personal notes are in order. First, at a dinner in Oberwolfach I pointed out, politely and enthusiastically, that much of [35] can be construed as model theory. Let’s just say that Eberhard made it clear (politely) that he did not share my enthusiasm. A couple of years later we collaborated on a model theory paper ([17]). The present note does for type II1 factors what [17] did for C\mathrm{C}^{*}-algebras. Second, I wish that I recorded all conversations that I had with Eberhard. It took me weeks to process some of the enlightening raw information that he dumped on me, parts of which may be lost for posterity. He will be missed.

Acknowledgments

I am indebted to the participants of the seminar on Model Theory and Free Probability held at York University in the fall semester 2022, and in particular to Saeed Ghasemi, Pavlos Motakis, and Paul Skoufranis for some insightful remarks. I would also like to thank Srivatsav Kunnawalkam Elayavalli for informing me that he proved Lemma 2.1 independently in February 2023 and for useful remarks on an early draft of this paper, and to Isaac Goldbring for remarks on the first version of this paper and to the referee for a delightfully opinionated (and very useful) report.

1. Quantifier elimination in II1 factors

We specialize the definitions from [21, §2.6] to the case of tracial von Neumann algebras. The ongoing discussion applies to any other countable continuous language {\mathcal{L}} and, with obvious modifications, to any continuous language {\mathcal{L}}. For simplicity, we consider only formulas in which all free variables range over the (operator) unit ball. This is not a loss of generality, as an easy rescaling argument shows.

For n0n\geq 0 and an nn-tuple of variables x¯=x0,,xn1\bar{x}=\langle x_{0},\dots,x_{n-1}\rangle (if n=0n=0 this is the empty sequence) let 𝔉x¯\operatorname{\mathfrak{F}^{\bar{x}}} be the \mathbb{R}-algebra of formulas in the language of tracial von Neumann algebras with free variables included in x¯\bar{x}. For a fixed tracial von Neumann algebra NN define a seminorm N\|\cdot\|_{N} on 𝔉x¯\operatorname{\mathfrak{F}^{\bar{x}}} by (φM(a¯)\varphi^{M}(\bar{a}) denotes the evaluation of φ(x¯)\varphi(\bar{x}) at a¯\bar{a} in MM)

φ(x¯)N=supφN𝒰(a¯)\|\varphi(\bar{x})\|_{N}=\sup\varphi^{N^{\mathcal{U}}}(\bar{a})

where a¯\bar{a} ranges over all nn-tuples in the unit ball of N𝒰N^{\mathcal{U}}. (The standard definition takes supremum over all structures MM elementarily equivalent to NN and all nn-tuples in MM of the appropriate sort, but by the universality of ultrapowers and the Downward Löwenheim–Skolem theorem, the seminorms coincide.)

Let 𝔉QFx¯\operatorname{\mathfrak{F}_{QF}^{\bar{x}}} denote the \mathbb{R}-algebra of all quantifier-free formulas in 𝔉x¯\operatorname{\mathfrak{F}^{\bar{x}}}. This is clearly a subalgebra of 𝔉x¯\operatorname{\mathfrak{F}^{\bar{x}}}.

If MM is a subalgebra of NN and a¯\bar{a} in MM, it is said that MM is an elementary submodel of NN if φM(a¯)=φN(a¯)\varphi^{M}(\bar{a})=\varphi^{N}(\bar{a}) for all φ𝔉x¯\varphi\in\operatorname{\mathfrak{F}^{\bar{x}}}. An isometric embedding is elementary if its range is an elementary submodel. For quantifier-free formulas this equality is automatic, but this is a strong assumption in general. For example, any two elementary embeddings of a separable structure into an ultrapower333Ultrapower of a separable structure associated with a nonprincipal ultrafilter on {\mathbb{N}}. are conjugate by an automorphism of the latter if the Continuum Hypothesis holds444Continuum Hypothesis has little bearing on the relations between separable structures by Shoenfield’s Absoluteness Theorem; see e.g., [34]. ([18, Corollary 16.6.5]).

Definition 1.1.

The theory of a tracial von Neumann algebra NN admits elimination of quantifiers if 𝔉QFx¯\operatorname{\mathfrak{F}_{QF}^{\bar{x}}} is N\|\cdot\|_{N}-dense in 𝔉x¯\operatorname{\mathfrak{F}^{\bar{x}}} for every x¯\bar{x}.

Proposition 1.2 below is essentially a special case [9, Proposition 13.6] stated with a reference to [29, pp. 84–91] in lieu of a proof; see also [31, Lemma 2.14]. Until recently, a self-contained proof of this fact could not be found in the literature. This has finally been remedied in [26, Proposition 9.4]. For reader’s convenience I include a proof using ultrapowers instead of elementary extensions (see Proposition 3.2, the equivalence of (1), (2), and (3)).

Proposition 1.2.

For every tracial von Neumann algebra555Needless to say, the analogous statement holds for C\mathrm{C}^{*}-algebras and for any other axiomatizable category. NN the following are equivalent.

  1. (1)

    The theory of NN admits elimination of quantifiers.

  2. (2)

    For every finitely generated W\mathrm{W}^{*}-subalgebra GG of N𝒰N^{{\mathcal{U}}}, every trace-preserving embedding Φ:FN𝒰\Phi\colon F\to N^{\mathcal{U}} of a finitely generated W\mathrm{W}^{*}-subalgebra FF of GG extends to a trace-preserving embedding Ψ:GN𝒰\Psi\colon G\to N^{\mathcal{U}}.

    GGN𝒰N^{\mathcal{U}}FFN𝒰N^{\mathcal{U}}\subseteq\subseteqΦ\PhiΨ\Psi
  3. (3)

    Same as (2), but for arbitrary separable substructures.

Clause (2) resembles the well-known property of the hyperfinite II1 factor RR, that any two copies of RR in R𝒰R^{\mathcal{U}} are unitarily conjugate ([33], [14]), the analogous (well-known) fact about strongly self-absorbing C\mathrm{C}^{*}-algebras, as well as the defining property of ‘Generalized Jung factors’ (in this case, automorphisms are not required to be inner, see [4], also see [3]) but it is strictly stronger since neither RR nor any of the strongly self-absorbing C\mathrm{C}^{*}-algebras admit quantifier elimination. The point is that FF and GG in (2) range over arbitrary finitely-generated substructures of the ultrapower.

2. Topological dynamical systems associated to II1 factors

Lemma 2.1 below is proven by unravelling of the proof of [14, Corollary 6.11]. Modulo the standard results (Proposition 1.2, Proposition 3.2) it implies Theorem 1.

Lemma 2.1.

There are a II1 factor M1M_{1} with separable predual, a subfactor M0M_{0} of M1M_{1}, and an automorphism α\alpha of M1M_{1} such that

  1. (1)

    αM0=idM0\alpha\restriction M_{0}=\operatorname{id}_{M_{0}}, but αidM1\alpha\neq\operatorname{id}_{M_{1}},

and for every type II1 tracial von Neumann algebra NN and every ultrapower N𝒰N^{{\mathcal{U}}} the following two conditions hold.

  1. (2)

    There is a trace-preserving embedding Φ:M1N𝒰\Phi\colon M_{1}\to N^{{\mathcal{U}}} such that

    N𝒰Φ[M0]=N𝒰Φ[M1].N^{{\mathcal{U}}}\cap\Phi[M_{0}]^{\prime}=N^{{\mathcal{U}}}\cap\Phi[M_{1}]^{\prime}.
  2. (3)

    There is a trace-preserving embedding Φ1\Phi_{1} of the crossed product M1αM_{1}\rtimes_{\alpha}{\mathbb{Z}} into N𝒰N^{\mathcal{U}}, and N𝒰Φ1[M0]N𝒰Φ1[M1]N^{{\mathcal{U}}}\cap\Phi_{1}[M_{0}]^{\prime}\neq N^{{\mathcal{U}}}\cap\Phi_{1}[M_{1}]^{\prime}.

Moreover, one can choose M0=L(SL(2k+1,))M_{0}=L(\operatorname{SL}(2k+1,{\mathbb{Z}})) for any k1k\geq 1 and (regardless on the choice of M0M_{0}) M1=M0PM_{1}=M_{0}*P, for any R𝒰R^{\mathcal{U}}-embeddable tracial von Neumann algebra PP with separable predual PP.

By for example taking P=L([0,1])P=L^{\infty}([0,1]), we can take M0=L(SL(3,)M_{0}=L(\operatorname{SL}(3,{\mathbb{Z}}) and M1=L(SL3())M_{1}=L(\operatorname{SL}_{3}({\mathbb{Z}})*{\mathbb{Z}}).

Proof.

Let Γ\Gamma be a property (T) group with infinitely many inequivalent irreducible representations on finite-dimensional Hilbert spaces. For the ‘moreover’ part, fix k1k\geq 1 and an R𝒰R^{\mathcal{U}}-embeddable tracial von Neumann algebra PP with separable predual, let Γ=SL(2k+1,)\Gamma=\operatorname{SL}(2k+1,{\mathbb{Z}}) for any k1k\geq 1, let M0=L(Γ)M_{0}=L(\Gamma), M1=L(Γ)PM_{1}=L(\Gamma)*P, and α=idM0α0\alpha=\operatorname{id}_{M_{0}}*\alpha_{0}, for some nontrivial automorphism α0\alpha_{0} of L()L({\mathbb{Z}}). Thus (1) holds. Since M1M_{1} is R𝒰R^{{\mathcal{U}}}-embeddable, (3) follows by [2, Proposition 3.4(2)].

It remains to prove (2). For n2n\geq 2 let ρn:Γ2(n)\rho_{n}\colon\Gamma\curvearrowright\ell_{2}(n) be an irreducible action of Γ\Gamma on 2(n)\ell_{2}(n), if such action exists, and trivial action otherwise. (The choice of ρn\rho_{n} in the latter case will be completely irrelevant.) Then ρn\rho_{n} defines a unital *-homomorphism of the group algebra Γ{\mathbb{C}}\Gamma into Mn()M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}), also denoted ρn\rho_{n}. Let ρ=nρn:ΓnMn()\rho=\bigoplus_{n}\rho_{n}\colon{\mathbb{C}}\Gamma\to\prod_{n}M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}).

Fix a nonprincipal ultrafilter 𝒰{\mathcal{U}} on {\mathbb{N}} that concentrates on the set {nρn\{n\mid\rho_{n} is irreducible}\}. If q:nMn()𝒰Mn()q\colon\prod_{n}M_{n}({\mathbb{C}})\to\prod^{\mathcal{U}}M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}) is the quotient map, then qρ:Γ𝒰Mn()q\circ\rho\colon{\mathbb{C}}\Gamma\to\prod^{\mathcal{U}}M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}) is a unital *-homomorphism. Let M0M_{0} be the ultraweak closure of qρ[Γ]q\circ\rho[{\mathbb{C}}\Gamma]. If Γ=SL(2k+1,)\Gamma=\operatorname{SL}(2k+1,{\mathbb{Z}}), then [6, Theorem 1] implies that M0M_{0} isomorphic to the group factor L(Γ)L(\Gamma); this nice fact however does not affect the remaining part of our proof.

For gΓg\in\Gamma we have a representation (u(g)n)/𝒰(u(g)_{n})/{\mathcal{U}}, where u(g)n=ρn(g)u(g)_{n}=\rho_{n}(g) is a unitary in Mn()M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}) for every nn. Since PP is R𝒰R^{\mathcal{U}}-embeddable, it is also embeddable into 𝒰Mn()\prod^{\mathcal{U}}M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}). Let K𝒰Mn()K\subseteq\prod^{\mathcal{U}}M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}) be a countable set that that generates an isomorphic copy of PP.

Our copy of M0M_{0} in 𝒰Mn()\prod^{\mathcal{U}}M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}) and the copy of PP generated by KK need not generate an isomorphic copy of M1=M0PM_{1}=M_{0}*P. In order to ‘correct’ this, we invoke some standard results.

At this point we need terminology from free probability. A unitary uu in a tracial von Neumann algebra (M,τ)(M,\tau) is a Haar unitary if τ(um)=0\tau(u^{m})=0 whenever m0m\neq 0. Such Haar unitary is free from some XMX\subseteq M if for every m1m\geq 1, if aja_{j} is such that τ(aj)=0\tau(a_{j})=0 and in the linear span of XX and if k(j)0k(j)\neq 0 for 0j<m0\leq j<m, then (note that τ(uk(j))=0\tau(u^{k(j)})=0 since uu is a Haar unitary)

τ(a0uk(0)a1uk(1)am1uk(m1))=0.\tau(a_{0}u^{k(0)}a_{1}u^{k(1)}\dots a_{m-1}u^{k(m-1)})=0.

More generally, if XX and YY are subsets of MM then XX is free from YY if for every m1m\geq 1, if aja_{j} is such that τ(aj)=0\tau(a_{j})=0 and in the linear span of XX and bjb_{j} is such that τ(bj)=0\tau(b_{j})=0 and in the linear span of YY for j<mj<m, then

τ(a0b0a1b1am1bm1)=0.\tau(a_{0}b_{0}a_{1}b_{1}\dots a_{m-1}b_{m-1})=0.

Since Γ\Gamma is a Kazhdan group ([7]), we can fix a Kazhdan pair F,εF,\varepsilon for Γ\Gamma. By [39, Theorem 2.2], there is a Haar unitary w𝒰Mn()w\in\prod^{\mathcal{U}}M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}) free from X={(u(g)n)/𝒰gF}{K}X=\{(u(g)_{n})/{\mathcal{U}}\mid g\in F\}\cup\{K\}.

A routine calculation shows that K={wawaK}K^{\prime}=\{waw^{*}\mid a\in K\} is free from XX and that KK^{\prime} generates an isomorphic copy of PP. Therefore the W\mathrm{W}^{*}-subalgebra of 𝒰Mn()\prod^{\mathcal{U}}M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}) generated by {(u(g)n)/𝒰gF}{K}\{(u(g)_{n})/{\mathcal{U}}\mid g\in F\}\cup\{K^{\prime}\} is isomorphic to M1M0PM_{1}\cong M_{0}*P. This defines an embedding Φ0:M1𝒰Mn()\Phi_{0}\colon M_{1}\to\prod^{\mathcal{U}}M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}).

Fix a type II1 tracial von Neumann algebra NN. In order to find an embedding of M1M_{1} into N𝒰N^{\mathcal{U}} as required in (2), for every n1n\geq 1 write N=Mn()¯N1/nN=M_{n}({\mathbb{C}})\bar{\otimes}N^{1/n} (where N1/nN^{1/n} is the corner of NN associated to a projection whose center-valued trace is 1/n1/n). Define an embedding of 𝒰Mn()\prod^{\mathcal{U}}M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}) into N𝒰N^{\mathcal{U}} by (the far right side is N𝒰N^{\mathcal{U}} in disguise)

𝒰Mn()(an)/𝒰(an1N1/n)/𝒰𝒰(Mn()¯N1/n).\textstyle\prod^{{\mathcal{U}}}M_{n}({\mathbb{C}})\ni(a_{n})/{\mathcal{U}}\mapsto(a_{n}\otimes 1_{N^{1/n}})/{\mathcal{U}}\in\prod^{{\mathcal{U}}}(M_{n}({\mathbb{C}})\bar{\otimes}N^{1/n}).

Let Φ:M1N𝒰\Phi\colon M_{1}\to N^{\mathcal{U}} be the composition of the embedding Φ0\Phi_{0} of M1M_{1} into 𝒰Mn()\prod^{\mathcal{U}}M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}) with this embedding.

It remains to prove that N𝒰Φ[M0]=N𝒰Φ[M1]N^{\mathcal{U}}\cap\Phi[M_{0}]^{\prime}=N^{\mathcal{U}}\cap\Phi[M_{1}]^{\prime}. Since M0M1M_{0}\subseteq M_{1}, only the forward inclusion requires a proof. Suppose that bN𝒰Φ[M0]b\in N^{\mathcal{U}}\cap\Phi[M_{0}]^{\prime} and fix a representing sequence (bn)(b_{n}) for bb. Fix for a moment δ>0\delta>0. Then the set (F,εF,\varepsilon is a Kazhdan pair for Γ\Gamma)

Zδ={nmaxgFungbnbnung2<εδ}Z_{\delta}=\{n\mid\max_{g\in F}\|u^{g}_{n}b_{n}-b_{n}u^{g}_{n}\|_{2}<\varepsilon\delta\}

belongs to 𝒰{\mathcal{U}}.666The set ZδZ_{\delta} would have belonged to 𝒰{\mathcal{U}} regardless of whether the maximum had been taken over FF or some other finite subset of Γ\Gamma. The maximum has been taken over FF because we need to bound the norm of the commutator of bb with all elements of FF, and not elements of some other finite subset of Γ\Gamma.

For each nn we define an action σn:ΓL2(N,τ)\sigma_{n}\colon\Gamma\curvearrowright L^{2}(N,\tau) as follows. For fΓf\in\Gamma let ρ~n(f)=ρn(f)1N1/n\tilde{\rho}_{n}(f)=\rho_{n}(f)\otimes 1_{N^{1/n}}. For cNc\in N, let

f.c=ρ~n(f)cρ~n(f).f.c=\tilde{\rho}_{n}(f)c\tilde{\rho}_{n}(f)^{*}.

This gives an action by isometries of Γ\Gamma on (N,2,τ)(N,\|\cdot\|_{2,\tau}), which continuously extends to action σn\sigma_{n} of Γ\Gamma on L2(N,τ)L^{2}(N,\tau).

For gFg\in F and nZδn\in Z_{\delta} we have g.bnbn2=ungbnbnung2<εδ\|g.b_{n}-b_{n}\|_{2}=\|u^{g}_{n}b_{n}-b_{n}u^{g}_{n}\|_{2}<\varepsilon\delta. Since ρn\rho_{n} is an irreducible representation, the space of σn\sigma_{n}-invariant vectors in L2(N,τ)L^{2}(N,\tau) is equal to 1Mn()L2(N1/n,τ)1_{M_{n}({\mathbb{C}})}\otimes L^{2}(N^{1/n},\tau). Let PnP_{n} be the projection onto this space. Since F,εF,\varepsilon is a Kazhdan pair for Γ\Gamma, by [13, Proposition 12.1.6] (with Γ=Λ\Gamma=\Lambda) or [7, Proposition 1.1.9] (the case when FF is compact, and modulo rescaling) we have bnPn(bn)2<ε\|b_{n}-P_{n}(b_{n})\|_{2}<\varepsilon.

Therefore (Pn(bn))/𝒰=(bn)/𝒰(P_{n}(b_{n}))/{\mathcal{U}}=(b_{n})/{\mathcal{U}} belongs to 𝒰(1Mn()¯N1/n)\prod^{\mathcal{U}}(1_{M_{n}({\mathbb{C}})}\bar{\otimes}N^{1/n}), which is equal to N𝒰(𝒰Mn())N^{\mathcal{U}}\cap(\prod^{{\mathcal{U}}}M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}))^{\prime}. Recall that Φ[M1]𝒰Mn()\Phi[M_{1}]\subseteq\prod^{\mathcal{U}}M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}). Since bb in N𝒰Φ[M0]N^{\mathcal{U}}\cap\Phi[M_{0}]^{\prime} was arbitrary, N𝒰Φ[M0]N^{\mathcal{U}}\cap\Phi[M_{0}]’ is included in N𝒰Φ[M1]N^{\mathcal{U}}\cap\Phi[M_{1}]^{\prime} (and is therefore equal to it), as required. ∎

Lemma 2.1 shows, in terminology of [14, Corollary 6.11] (also [15]), that for all type II1 tracial von Neumann algebras NN, all k1k\geq 1, and all R𝒰R^{\mathcal{U}}-embeddable tracial von Neumann algebras with separable predual MM, for the natural action of AutM\operatorname{Aut}M on Hom(L(SL(2k+1,)M,N𝒰){\rm Hom}(L(\operatorname{SL}(2k+1,{\mathbb{Z}})*M,N^{\mathcal{U}}) there is an extreme point with trivial stabilizer.

Proof of Theorem 1.

Suppose for a moment that NN is of type II1. Let M0M_{0} and M1M_{1} be as in Lemma 2.1. The embeddings of M1M_{1} and M1αM_{1}\rtimes_{\alpha}{\mathbb{Z}} into N𝒰N^{\mathcal{U}} provided by (2) and (3) of this lemma satisfy (2) of Proposition 1.2, and therefore the theory of NN does not admit elimination of quantifiers.

In the general case, when NN has a type II1 summand, we can write it as N=N0N1N=N_{0}\oplus N_{1}, where N0N_{0} is type I and N1N_{1} is type II1 (e.g., [12, §III.1.4.7]). Then N𝒰=N0𝒰N1𝒰N^{\mathcal{U}}=N_{0}^{\mathcal{U}}\oplus N_{1}^{\mathcal{U}}. Let r=τ(1N1)r=\tau(1_{N_{1}}), P0=M1P_{0}={\mathbb{C}}\oplus M_{1}, and P1=M1αP_{1}={\mathbb{C}}\oplus M_{1}\rtimes_{\alpha}{\mathbb{Z}}, with the tracial states τ0\tau_{0} and τ1\tau_{1} such that τ0(1M1)=τ1(1M1α)=r\tau_{0}(1_{M_{1}})=\tau_{1}(1_{M_{1}\rtimes_{\alpha}{\mathbb{Z}}})=r. Since type II1 algebra cannot be embedded into one of type I, this choice of tracial states forces that every embedding of M1M_{1} into N𝒰N^{\mathcal{U}} sends 1M11_{M_{1}} to the image of 1N11_{N_{1}} under the diagonal map. An analogous fact holds for M1αM_{1}\rtimes_{\alpha}{\mathbb{Z}}. Therefore, as in the factorial case, Proposition 1.2 implies that the theory of NN does not admit elimination of quantifiers. ∎

3. Proof of Proposition 1.2

As promised, here is a long overdue self-contained proof of [9, Proposition 13.6] (Proposition 3.2 below). We provide a proof in case when the language {\mathcal{L}} is single-sorted and countable. The former is a matter of convenience777Although the language of tracial von Neumann algebras has a sort for every operator nn-ball, by homogeneity one can assume that all free variables range over the unit ball anyway. and the latter requires a minor change of the statement, considering sufficiently saturated models instead of ultrapowers (see [9, Proposition 13.6]).

Let a¯\bar{a} be an nn-tuple of elements in a metric structure MM and let x¯\bar{x} be an nn-tuple of variables. Each expression of the form (φ(x¯,y)\varphi(\bar{x},y) is a formula and rr\in\mathbb{R})

φ(a¯,y)=r,φ(a¯,y)r,φ(a¯,y)r\varphi(\bar{a},y)=r,\qquad\varphi(\bar{a},y)\geq r,\qquad\varphi(\bar{a},y)\leq r

is a condition (in some contexts called closed condition) in yy over a¯\bar{a}. A set of conditions over a¯\bar{a} is a type over a¯\bar{a}. If all formulas occurring in conditions of a type are quantifier-free, then the type is said to be quantifier-free. Some cN𝒰c\in N^{\mathcal{U}} satisfies condition φ(a¯,y)=r\varphi(\bar{a},y)=r if φN𝒰(a¯,c)=r\varphi^{N^{\mathcal{U}}}(\bar{a},c)=r, and it realizes the type 𝗍(y)\mathsf{t}(y) if it satisfies all of its conditions. A type 𝗍(y)\mathsf{t}(y) over a¯\bar{a} in some metric structure MM is consistent if for every finite set of conditions in 𝗍(y)\mathsf{t}(y) and every ε>0\varepsilon>0 some element of MM approximately realizes each of these conditions, up to ε\varepsilon.

The salient property of ultrapowers (associated with nonprincipal ultrafilters on {\mathbb{N}}) is that they are countably saturated: every consistent type over a separable set is realized (e.g., [9], [21], [18]).

The quantifier-free type of an nn-tuple a¯\bar{a} in MM is the set of all conditions of the form φM(x¯)=φM(a¯)\varphi^{M}(\bar{x})=\varphi^{M}(\bar{a}), when φ\varphi ranges over 𝔉QFx¯\operatorname{\mathfrak{F}_{QF}^{\bar{x}}}. The full type of an nn-tuple a¯\bar{a} in MM is the set of all conditions of the form φM(x¯)=φM(a¯)\varphi^{M}(\bar{x})=\varphi^{M}(\bar{a}), when φ\varphi ranges over 𝔉x¯\operatorname{\mathfrak{F}^{\bar{x}}}. Quantifier-free and full types are naturally identified with a homomorphism from 𝔉QFx¯\operatorname{\mathfrak{F}_{QF}^{\bar{x}}} (𝔉x¯\operatorname{\mathfrak{F}^{\bar{x}}}, respectively) into \mathbb{R} (see [21]). If XX is a subset of a metric structure MM, we may expand the language of MM by constant symbols for the element of XX. The type of a¯\bar{a} in MM in the expanded language is called the type of a¯\bar{a} over XX.

The following well-known and straightforward lemma is somewhat illuminating.

Lemma 3.1.

Suppose that a¯\bar{a} and a¯\bar{a}^{\prime} are nn-tuples in metric structures in the same language. Then ajaja_{j}\mapsto a^{\prime}_{j} for j<nj<n defines an isometric isomorphism between the structures generated by a¯\bar{a} and a¯\bar{a}^{\prime} if and only if a¯\bar{a} and a¯\bar{a}^{\prime} have the same quantifier-free type. ∎

While the quantifier-free type of a tuple codes only the isomorphism type of an algebra generated by it, the full type codes first-order properties such as the existence of square roots of unitaries and Murray–von Neumann equivalence of projections. These existential properties are coded by K-theory, at least in unital C\mathrm{C}^{*}-algebras for which Groethendieck maps are injective. In this case, a unitary uu has the nn-th root if and only if the K1K_{1}-class [u]1[u]_{1} is divisible by nn, and projections pp and qq are Murray–von Neumann equivalent if and only if [p]0=[q]0[p]_{0}=[q]_{0} (see [38] or [11]). However, the information coded by theory and types is different from that coded by K-theory. On the one hand, there are separable AF-algebras with nonisomorphic K0K_{0} groups ([16]) and on the other hand there are separable, nuclear C\mathrm{C}^{*}-algebras with the same Elliott invariant but different theories. All known counterexamples to the Elliott program fall into this category; see ‘The theory as an invariant’ in [21, p. 4–5].

In the following \equiv denotes the relation of elementary equivalence (i.e., sharing the same theory).

Proposition 3.2.

If {\mathcal{L}} is a countable metric language, then for every {\mathcal{L}}-structure NN the following are equivalent.

  1. (1)

    The theory of NN admits elimination of quantifiers.

  2. (2)

    For every finitely generated {\mathcal{L}}-substructure GG of an ultrapower888Again, this ultrapower is associated to a nonprincipal ultrafilter on {\mathbb{N}}. N𝒰N^{{\mathcal{U}}}, every isometric embedding of a finitely generated {\mathcal{L}}-substructure FF of GG into N𝒰N^{\mathcal{U}} extends to an isometric embedding of GG.

  3. (3)

    Same as (2), but for arbitrary separable substructures.

  4. (4)

    For every finitely generated {\mathcal{L}}-substructure GG of some M1NM_{1}\equiv N, for every isometric embedding of a finitely generated {\mathcal{L}}-substructure FF of GG into M2NM_{2}\equiv N there is an elementary extension M3M_{3} of M2M_{2} such that the embedding of FF into M3M_{3} extends to an embedding of GG into M3M_{3}.

  5. (5)

    If φ(x¯,y)\varphi(\bar{x},y) is quantifier free {\mathcal{L}}-formula, then the formula infyφ(x¯,y)\inf_{y}\varphi(\bar{x},y) is a N\|\cdot\|_{N}-limit of quantifier free formulas.

Proof.

The equivalence of (2) and (4) is a well-known consequence of saturation of ultraproducts (see [18, §16]), and (4) will not be used in this paper (it is included only for completeness).

For simplicity and without loss of generality we assume that the language {\mathcal{L}} is single-sorted. Assume (1) and fix finitely generated {\mathcal{L}}-substructures FGN𝒰F\leq G\leq N^{\mathcal{U}} and an isometric embedding Φ:FN𝒰\Phi\colon F\to N^{\mathcal{U}}. By Lemma 3.1, a¯\bar{a} and Φ(a¯)\Phi(\bar{a}) have the same quantifier-free type (over the empty set). It suffices to prove that Φ\Phi extends to an isometric embedding of GG in case when GG is generated by bb and FF for a single element bb.

Let rφ=φ(a¯,b)r_{\varphi}=\varphi(\bar{a},b) for every φ(x¯,y)𝔉QFx¯,y\varphi(\bar{x},y)\in\operatorname{\mathfrak{F}_{QF}^{\bar{x},y}}. Consider the following quantifier-free type over Φ(a¯)\Phi(\bar{a}),999Since the formulas are quantifier-free, we do not need to specify the algebra in which they are being evaluated.

𝗍(y)\displaystyle\mathsf{t}(y) ={φ(Φ(a¯),y)=rφφ(x¯,y)𝔉QFx¯,y)}.\displaystyle=\{\varphi(\Phi(\bar{a}),y)=r_{\varphi}\mid\varphi(\bar{x},y)\in\operatorname{\mathfrak{F}_{QF}^{\bar{x},y}})\}.

This type is uncountable, but separable in N\|\cdot\|_{N} since the space 𝔉x¯\operatorname{\mathfrak{F}^{\bar{x}}} is separable in N\|\cdot\|_{N}.

In order to prove that 𝗍(y)\mathsf{t}(y) is satisfiable, fix a finite set of conditions in 𝗍(x)\mathsf{t}(x), say φj(a¯,y)=rj\varphi_{j}(\bar{a},y)=r_{j} for j<mj<m, m1m\geq 1. Consider the formula

ψ(x¯)=infymaxj<m|φj(x¯,y)rj|.\psi(\bar{x})=\inf_{y}\max_{j<m}|\varphi_{j}(\bar{x},y)-r_{j}|.

Then ψN𝒰(a¯)=0\psi^{N^{\mathcal{U}}}(\bar{a})=0, as witnessed by bb. Since the theory of NN admits elimination of quantifiers, there are quantifier-free formulas ψk(x¯)\psi_{k}(\bar{x}), for k1k\geq 1, such that ψ(x¯)ψk(x¯)N<1/k\|\psi(\bar{x})-\psi_{k}(\bar{x})\|_{N}<1/k for all nn. Therefore, since Φ\Phi is an isometry between the structures generated by a¯\bar{a} and Φ(a¯)\Phi(\bar{a}), we have

ψN𝒰(Φ(a¯))=limnψn(Φ(a¯))=limnψn(a¯)=ψN𝒰(a¯)=0.\psi^{N^{\mathcal{U}}}(\Phi(\bar{a}))=\lim_{n}\psi_{n}(\Phi(\bar{a}))=\lim_{n}\psi_{n}(\bar{a})=\psi^{N^{\mathcal{U}}}(\bar{a})=0.

Thus 𝗍(y)\mathsf{t}(y) is consistent, and by countable saturation ([18, §16])some cN𝒰c\in N^{\mathcal{U}} realizes it. Thus a¯,b\bar{a},b and Φ(a¯),c\Phi(\bar{a}),c have the same quantifier-free type. By mapping bb to cc and Lemma 3.1, one finds an isometric extension of Φ\Phi to GG as required.

To prove that (2) implies (5), assume that (5) fails. Fix a quantifier-free formula φ(x¯,y)\varphi(\bar{x},y) in n+1n+1 variables and ε>0\varepsilon>0 such that every ψ𝔉QFx¯\psi\in\operatorname{\mathfrak{F}_{QF}^{\bar{x}}} satisfies

infyφ(x¯,y)ψ(x¯)Nε.\|\inf_{y}\varphi(\bar{x},y)-\psi(\bar{x})\|_{N}\geq\varepsilon.

Let 𝗍(x¯(0),x¯(1))\mathsf{t}(\bar{x}(0),\bar{x}(1)) be the type in 2n2n variables with the following conditions.

ψ(x¯(0))ψ(x¯(1))\displaystyle\psi(\bar{x}(0))-\psi(\bar{x}(1)) =0, for all ψ𝔉QFx¯, and\displaystyle=0,\text{ for all $\psi\in\operatorname{\mathfrak{F}_{QF}^{\bar{x}}}$, and }
min(ε,infyφ(x¯(1),y)infyφ(x¯(0),y))\displaystyle\min(\varepsilon,\inf_{y}\varphi(\bar{x}(1),y)-\inf_{y}\varphi(\bar{x}(0),y)) ε.\displaystyle\geq\varepsilon.

This type is consistent by our assumptions, and by countable saturation it is realized in N𝒰N^{\mathcal{U}} by some a¯(0),a¯(1)\bar{a}(0),\bar{a}(1). With FF denoting the {\mathcal{L}}-structure generated by a¯(0)\bar{a}(0), we have an isometric embedding Φ\Phi of FF into N𝒰N^{\mathcal{U}} that sends a¯(0)\bar{a}(0) to a¯(1)\bar{a}(1).

By using countable saturation again, we can find bN𝒰b\in N^{\mathcal{U}} such that infyφ(a¯(1),y)φ(a¯(0),b)ε\inf_{y}\varphi(\bar{a}(1),y)-\varphi(\bar{a}(0),b)\geq\varepsilon. Let GG be the {\mathcal{L}}-structure generated by a¯(0)\bar{a}(0) and bb. Then Φ\Phi cannot be extended to an isometric embedding of GG into N𝒰N^{\mathcal{U}}, and (2) fails.

Since (5) implies that for every quantifier-free formula φ(x¯,y)\varphi(\bar{x},y), the formula supyφ(x¯,y)\sup_{y}\varphi(\bar{x},y) is a uniform N\|\cdot\|_{N}-limit of quantifier-free formulas (by replacing φ\varphi with φ-\varphi), the proof that (5) implies (1) follows by induction on complexity of formulas (see [9]). ∎

4. Concluding remarks

The theory of L[0,1]L^{\infty}[0,1] (with respect to the Lebesgue trace) admits elimination of quantifiers ([31, Theorem 2.13], see also [8, Fact 2.10] and [10, Example 4.3]). By [31, Lemma 2.17], every matrix algebra Mn()M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}) admits elimination of quantifiers. However, if mnm\neq n then the algebra Mm()Mn()M_{m}({\mathbb{C}})\oplus M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}), with respect to the tracial state τ=12(trm+trn)\tau=\frac{1}{2}({\rm tr}_{m}+{\rm tr}_{n}) (where trk{\rm tr}_{k} is the normalized trace on Mk()M_{k}({\mathbb{C}})), does not admit elimination of quantifiers. This is because the units of the two summands have the same quantifier-free type (the quantifier-free type of a projection is determined by its trace by Lemma 3.1), but if m>nm>n then there is no isometric embedding from Mm()M_{m}({\mathbb{C}}) into Mm()Mn()M_{m}({\mathbb{C}})\oplus M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}) that sends 1m1_{m} to 1n1_{n}. On the other hand, we have the following.

Proposition 4.1.

Suppose that Mm()Mn()M_{m}({\mathbb{C}})\oplus M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}) is equipped with a tracial state τ\tau which has the property that two projections pp and qq in Mm()Mn()M_{m}({\mathbb{N}})\oplus M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}) are Murray–von Neumann equivalent if and only if τ(p)=τ(q)\tau(p)=\tau(q).

Then the theory of this algebra admits elimination of quantifiers.

If it is not obvious that tracial states with the property required in Proposition 4.1 exist, it may be easier to prove that there are only finitely many tracial states that do not have this property. To wit, there are only finitely many Murray-von Neumann equivalence classes of projections in Mm()Mn()M_{m}({\mathbb{C}})\oplus M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}). For any two such distinct classes [p][p] and [q][q], there is at most one tracial state τ\tau such that τ(p)=τ(q)\tau(p)=\tau(q). (Consider the system of two linear equations in two variables xx and yy, corresponding to the values of τ\tau at rank-1 projections of Mm()M_{m}({\mathbb{C}}) and Mn()M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}). It has infinitely many solutions if and only if [p]=[q][p]=[q].)

Proof of Proposition 4.1.

Suppose that τ\tau satisfies the assumption, FF is a C\mathrm{C}^{*}-subalgebra of Mm()Mn()M_{m}({\mathbb{C}})\oplus M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}), and Φ:FMm()Mn()\Phi\colon F\to M_{m}({\mathbb{C}})\oplus M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}) is a trace-preserving embedding. Then FF is a direct sum of matrix algebras. Let pjp_{j}, for j<kj<k, be the units of these matrix algebras. Then τ(pj)=τ(Φ(pj))\tau(p_{j})=\tau(\Phi(p_{j})) for all jj. By the assumption on τ\tau there is a partial isometry vjv_{j} such that vjvj=pjv_{j}^{*}v_{j}=p_{j} and vjvj=Φ(pj)v_{j}v_{j}^{*}=\Phi(p_{j}). Therefore u=j<kvju=\sum_{j<k}v_{j} is a unitary such that upju=Φ(pj)up_{j}u^{*}=\Phi(p_{j}) for j<kj<k. Since every automorphism of a matrix algebra is implemented by a unitary, for every j<kj<k there is wjw_{j} such that wjwj=wjwj=pjw_{j}^{*}w_{j}=w_{j}w_{j}^{*}=p_{j} and for apjFa\in p_{j}F we have wjvjavjwj=Φ(a)w_{j}v_{j}av_{j}^{*}w_{j}^{*}=\Phi(a). Therefore Φ\Phi coincides with conjugation by the unitary u=j<kwjvju^{\prime}=\sum_{j<k}w_{j}v_{j}. This implies that Φ\Phi automatically extends to an embedding of any GG such that FGMm()Mn()F\subseteq G\subseteq M_{m}({\mathbb{C}})\oplus M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}) into Mm()Mn()M_{m}({\mathbb{C}})\oplus M_{n}({\mathbb{C}}). ∎

The fact that the theory of a fixed structure may or may not admit elimination of quantifiers, depending on the choice of a language, is hardly surprising. After all, this is exactly what happens with the full matrix algebras, as we pass from the language of tracial von Neumann algebras to the language of C\mathrm{C}^{*}-algebras.

The idea of the proof of Proposition 4.1 should provide the first step towards a confirmation of the following conjecture and a complete answer to [31, Question 2.18].

Conjecture 4.2.

If TT is the theory of a tracial von Neumann algebra, then the following are equivalent.

  1. (1)

    TT admits elimination of quantifiers.

  2. (2)

    Every model NN of TT is of type I, and if NN has separable predual then two projections pp and qq in NN are conjugate by a trace preserving automorphism if and only if τ(p)=τ(q)\tau(p)=\tau(q).

Model completeness is a useful weakening of quantifier elimination. A theory is model complete if every embedding between its models is elementary. As the referee pointed out, the following can be extracted from a well-known semantic characterization of elementary embeddings (see the paragraph between Fact 2.1.2 and Fact 2.1.3 in [5]), but there is some merit in stating it explicitly.

Proposition 4.3.

Assume the Continuum Hypothesis. For a continuous theory TT in a complete language the following are equivalent.

  1. (1)

    The theory TT is model-complete.

  2. (2)

    If MM and NN are separable models of TT and Φ:MN\Phi\colon M\to N is an isometric embedding, then there is an isomorphism Ψ:M𝒰N𝒰\Psi\colon M^{\mathcal{U}}\to N^{\mathcal{U}} such that the following diagram commutes (the horizontal arrows are diagonal embeddings)

    MMM𝒰M^{\mathcal{U}}NNN𝒰N^{\mathcal{U}}Φ\PhiΨ\Psi

The use of Continuum Hypothesis in (2) is innocuous, as it has no effect on projective statements. This is a forcing argument well-known to set theorists but poorly documented in the literature; see for example [17, Lemma 5.20]. It is also a red herring, since in its absence (2) can be replaced with a considerably more complex, but (once mastered) equally useful, assertion about the existence of a σ\sigma-complete back-and-forth system of partial isomorphisms between separable subalgebras of M𝒰M^{\mathcal{U}} and N𝒰N^{\mathcal{U}} (see [18, §8.2, Theorem 16.6.4])

Proof.

Assume (1). Then Φ[M]\Phi[M] is a separable elementary submodel of  N𝒰N^{\mathcal{U}}, and the Continuum Hypothesis implies that M𝒰N𝒰M^{\mathcal{U}}\cong N^{\mathcal{U}}, via an isomorphism Ψ\Psi that sends the diagonal copy of MM onto Φ[M]\Phi[M]. The C\mathrm{C}^{*}-algebra case is proven in [18, Theorem 16.7.5], and the proof of the general case is virtually identical.

Assume (2) and let Φ:MN\Phi\colon M\to N be an embedding between models of TT. We need to prove that Φ\Phi is elementary. By replacing MM and NN with separable elementary submodels large enough to detect a given failure of elementarity, we may assume they are separable. With Ψ\Psi as guaranteed by (2), the embedding of MM into N𝒰N^{\mathcal{U}} is, being the composition of an elementary embedding and an isomorphism, elementary. Since the diagonal image of NN in N𝒰N^{\mathcal{U}} is elementary, it follows that Φ\Phi is elementary. ∎

Conjecture 4.4.

The theory of a tracial von Neumann algebra NN is model complete if and only if NN is of type I.

A fact relevant to both conjectures is that by [20, Proposition 3.1], elementarily equivalent type I tracial von Neumann algebras with separable preduals are isometrically isomorphic. Following a referee’s advice, we state the following one-time side remark in the theorem environment, with a proof.

Proposition 4.5.

The theory of every type I tracial von Neumann algebra is model complete.

Proof.

This is an immediate consequence of the results of [20]. Fix a type I tracial von Neumann algebra MM.

If MM is abelian, then ML(μ)M\cong L^{\infty}(\mu) for a probability measure μ\mu. Then [20, Lemma 3.2] implies that theory of MM determines the measures of the atoms of μ\mu (these are the values of ρ(1,n)\rho(1,n) for n1n\geq 1, using the notation from this lemma and taken in the decreasing order; ρ(1,0)\rho(1,0) is the measure of the diffuse part).

Therefore if NMN\equiv M then NL(ν)N\cong L^{\infty}(\nu), and the measures of the atoms of ν\nu (if any) are exactly the same as the measures of the atoms of μ\mu. Every trace-preserving *-homomorphism Φ\Phi from MM into NN has to send the diffuse part to the diffuse part. Since these parts are of the same measure, it also sends atomic part to the atomic part. Finally, since the atoms in MM and NN have the same measures (with multiplicities), and since we are dealing with a probability measure, the restriction of Φ\Phi to the atomic part is an isomorphism. The theory of LL^{\infty} space of a diffuse measure admits elimination of quantifiers, hence the restriction of Φ\Phi to the diffuse part is elementary. Thus Φ\Phi can be decomposed as a direct sum of two elementary embeddings, and is therefore elementary by the second part of [20, Corollary 2.6].

This proves Proposition in case when MM is abelian.

In general, when MM is not necessarily abelian, it is isomorphic to nXAnM\bigoplus_{n\in X}A^{M}_{n}, where X[1,)X\subseteq[1,\infty), and for every nXn\in X we have AnMMn(BnM)A^{M}_{n}\cong M_{n}(B^{M}_{n}), for a commutative von Neumann algebra BnMB^{M}_{n}. Suppose that MNM\equiv N. Then [20, Lemma 3.2] implies that NnXAnNN\cong\bigoplus_{n\in X}A^{N}_{n} (with the same set XX) and that τ(1AnM)=τ(1AnN)\tau(1_{A^{M}_{n}})=\tau(1_{A^{N}_{n}}) for all nXn\in X. (Using the notation from [20, Lemma 3.2], these quantities are both equal to kρM(n,k)\sum_{k}\rho_{M}(n,k), for every nXn\in X.)

Now assume that Φ:MN\Phi\colon M\to N is a trace-preserving *-homomorphism. For n<nn^{\prime}<n in XX we have that Φ(1AnM)\Phi(1_{A^{M}_{n}}) and 1AnN1_{A^{N}_{n^{\prime}}} are orthogonal. By induction on nXn\in X, this implies that Φ(1AnM)=1AnN\Phi(1_{A^{M}_{n}})=1_{A^{N}_{n}} for all nn.

By the abelian case, the restriction of Φ\Phi to AnMA^{M}_{n} is elementary for every nn. By the second part of [20, Corollary 2.6], Φ\Phi is elementary. ∎

The original version of this paper contained an appendix by Srivatsav Kunnawalkam Elayavalli, removed following a suggestion of the referee. The appendix was concerned with the two notions that seem to be sensitive to the choice of additional axioms of ZFC, and the author’s strong opinion on such definitions is expressed in a long footnote on p. 12 of [19].

References

  • [1] C. Anantharaman and S. Popa. An introduction to II1 factors. available at https://idpoisson.fr/anantharaman/publications/IIun.pdf, 2017.
  • [2] C. Anantharaman-Delaroche. Amenable correspondences and approximation properties for von neumann algebras. Pacific Journal of Mathematics, 171(2):309–341, 1995.
  • [3] S. Atkinson and S. K. Elayavalli. On ultraproduct embeddings and amenability for tracial von Neumann algebras. International Mathematics Research Notices, 2021(4):2882–2918, 2021.
  • [4] S. Atkinson, I. Goldbring, and S. K. Elayavalli. Factorial relative commutants and the generalized Jung property for II1 factors. Advances in Mathematics, 396:108107, 2022.
  • [5] Scott Atkinson, Isaac Goldbring, and Srivatsav Kunnawalkam Elayavalli. Factorial relative commutants and the generalized jung property for II1II_{1} factors. Advances in Mathematics, 396:108107, 2022.
  • [6] B. Bekka. Operator-algebraic superridigity for SLn(){\textrm{S}L}_{n}({\mathbb{Z}}), n3n\geq 3. Inventiones mathematicae, 2(169):401–425, 2007.
  • [7] B. Bekka, P. de La Harpe, and A. Valette. Kazhdan’s property (T). Cambridge university press, 2008.
  • [8] I. Ben Yaacov. On theories of random variables. Israel Journal of Mathematics, 194:957–1012, 2013.
  • [9] I. Ben Yaacov, A. Berenstein, C.W. Henson, and A. Usvyatsov. Model theory for metric structures. In Z. Chatzidakis et al., editors, Model Theory with Applications to Algebra and Analysis, Vol. II, number 350 in London Math. Soc. Lecture Notes Series, pages 315–427. London Math. Soc., 2008.
  • [10] I. Ben Yaacov and A. Usvyatsov. Continuous first order logic and local stability. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 362(10):5213–5259, 2010.
  • [11] B. Blackadar. K-theory for operator algebras, volume 5 of MSRI Publications. Cambridge University Press, 1998.
  • [12] B. Blackadar. Operator algebras, volume 122 of Encyclopaedia of Mathematical Sciences. Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 2006. Theory of C\mathrm{C}^{*}-algebras and von Neumann algebras, Operator Algebras and Non-commutative Geometry, III.
  • [13] N. Brown and N. Ozawa. C\mathrm{C}^{*}-algebras and finite-dimensional approximations, volume 88 of Graduate Studies in Mathematics. American Mathematical Society, 2008.
  • [14] N.P. Brown. Topological dynamical systems associated to II1II_{1} factors. Adv. Math., 227(4):1665–1699, 2011. With an appendix by Narutaka Ozawa.
  • [15] N.P. Brown and V. Capraro. Groups associated to II1-factors. Journal of Functional Analysis, 264(2):493–507, 2013.
  • [16] B. De Bondt, A. Vaccaro, B. Veličković, and A. Vignati. Games on AF-Algebras. International Mathematics Research Notices, 11 2022. rnac313.
  • [17] C. J. Eagle, I. Farah, E. Kirchberg, and A. Vignati. Quantifier elimination in C\mathrm{C}^{*}-algebras. International Mathematics Research Notices, 2017(24):7580–7606, 2017.
  • [18] I. Farah. Combinatorial Set Theory and C\mathrm{C}^{*}-algebras. Springer Monographs in Mathematics. Springer, 2019.
  • [19] I. Farah. Quantifier elimination in II1 factors. version 2, with appendix by Srivatsav Kunnawalkam Elayavalli, arXiv preprint arXiv:2304.11371, https://arxiv.org/abs/2304.11371v2, 2023.
  • [20] I. Farah and S. Ghasemi. Preservation of elementarity by tensor products of tracial von Neumann algebras. arXiv preprint arXiv:2304.08437, 2023.
  • [21] I. Farah, B. Hart, M. Lupini, L. Robert, A. Tikuisis, A. Vignati, and W. Winter. Model theory of C\mathrm{C}^{*}-algebras. Mem. Amer. Math. Soc., 271(1324):viii+127, 2021.
  • [22] I. Goldbring and B. Hart. On the theories of Mcduff’s II1 factors. International Mathematics Research Notices, 2017(18):5609–5628, 2017.
  • [23] I. Goldbring and B. Hart. A survey on the model theory of tracial von Neumann algebras. arXiv preprint arXiv:2210.15508, 2022.
  • [24] I. Goldbring, B. Hart, and T. Sinclair. The theory of tracial von Neumann algebras does not have a model companion. J. Symbolic Logic, 78(3):1000–1004, 2013.
  • [25] U. Haagerup and S. Thorbjørnsen. A new application of random matrices: Ext(Cred(F2)){\mathrm{Ext}}(C^{*}_{\mathrm{red}}(F_{2})) is not a group. Ann. of Math. (2), pages 711–775, 2005.
  • [26] B. Hart. An introduction to continuous model theory. arXiv preprint arXiv:2303.03969, 2023.
  • [27] B. Hayes. 1-bounded entropy and regularity problems in von neumann algebras. International Mathematics Research Notices, 2018(1):57–137, 11 2016.
  • [28] B. Hayes, D. Jekel, B. Nelson, and T. Sinclair. A random matrix approach to absorption in free products. International Mathematics Research Notices, 2021(3):1919–1979, 2021.
  • [29] C.W. Henson and J. Iovino. Ultraproducts in analysis. In Catherine Finet and Christian Michaux, editors, Analysis and Logic, number 262 in London Mathematical Society Lecture Notes Series.
  • [30] D. Jekel. Covering entropy for types in tracial W\mathrm{W}^{*}-algebras. arXiv preprint arXiv:2204.02582, 2022.
  • [31] D. Jekel. Free probability and model theory of tracial W\mathrm{W}^{*}-algebras. arXiv preprint arXiv:2208.13867, 2022.
  • [32] Z. Ji, A. Natarajan, T. Vidick, J. Wright, and H. Yuen. MIP*= RE. arXiv preprint arXiv:2001.04383, 2020.
  • [33] K. Jung. Amenability, tubularity, and embeddings into RωR^{\omega}. Mathematische Annalen, 338(1):241–248, 2007.
  • [34] A. Kanamori. The higher infinite: large cardinals in set theory from their beginnings. Perspectives in Mathematical Logic. Springer, Berlin–Heidelberg–New York, 1995.
  • [35] E. Kirchberg. Central sequences in C\mathrm{C}^{*}-algebras and strongly purely infinite algebras. In Operator Algebras: The Abel Symposium 2004, volume 1 of Abel Symp., pages 175–231. Springer, Berlin, 2006.
  • [36] E. Kirchberg and N.C. Phillips. Embedding of exact C\mathrm{C}^{*}-algebras in the Cuntz algebra 𝒪2{\mathcal{O}}_{2}. J. Reine Angew. Math., 525:17–53, 2000.
  • [37] D. Marker. Model theory, volume 217 of Graduate Texts in Mathematics. Springer-Verlag, New York, 2002.
  • [38] M. Rørdam, F. Larsen, and N.J. Laustsen. An Introduction to K-theory for C algebras. Number 49 in London Mathematical Society Student Texts. Cambridge University Press, 2000.
  • [39] D. Voiculescu. A strengthened asymptotic freeness result for random matrices with applications to free entropy. International Mathematics Research Notices, 1998(1):41–63, 1998.