Proper maps of ball complements & differences and rational sphere maps
Abstract.
We consider proper holomorphic maps of ball complements and differences in complex euclidean spaces of dimension at least two. Such maps are always rational, which naturally leads to a related problem of classifying rational maps taking concentric spheres to concentric spheres, what we call -fold sphere maps; a proper map of the difference of concentric balls is a -fold sphere map. We prove that proper maps of ball complements are in one to one correspondence with polynomial proper maps of balls taking infinity to infinity. We show that rational -fold sphere maps of degree less than (or polynomial maps of degree or less) must take all concentric spheres to concentric spheres and we provide a complete classification of them. We prove that these degree bounds are sharp.
Key words and phrases:
rational sphere maps, proper holomorphic mappings2020 Mathematics Subject Classification:
32H35, 32A08, 32H021. Introduction
Studying proper holomorphic maps between domains is a common problem in several complex variables. In general, such maps do not exist unless we choose specific domains. If the domain has many symmetries, such as the unit ball , many maps exist. Alexander [alexander-1977-proper] proved that every proper holomorphic map , , is an automorphism, and hence rational. On the other hand, Dor [dor-1990-proper] showed that there exist proper holomorphic maps from to that are continuous up to the boundary and are not rational. Forstnerič [forstneric-1989-extending] proved that if for some neighborhood of a point on the sphere, a sufficiently smooth is holomorphic on and , then is rational and extends to a proper map of to . Moreover, the degree of is bounded by a function of and alone. We will make extensive use of Forstnerič’s result in this work. For simplicity, by a proper map of balls, we will always mean a proper holomorphic map . Rudin [rudin-1984-homogeneous] proved that every homogeneous polynomial proper map of balls is unitarily equivalent to the symmetrized -fold tensor product of the identity map, while D’Angelo [dangelo-1988-polynomial] found a much simpler proof of Rudin’s result and moreover gave complete procedure for constructing all polynomial proper maps of balls. A key idea in D’Angelo’s work, and one that we will make use of, is that given two vector valued polynomials and such that for all , there is a unitary map such that . By we mean we add zero components if they are needed to match the target dimensions. For more information on this subject, see [faran-1982-maps, forstneric-1993-proper, huang-1999-linearity, hamada-2005-rational, huang-2006-new, huang-2014-third, lebl-2024-exhaustion] and the references therein. In particular, the books by D’Angelo [dangelo-1993-several, dangelo-2019-hermitian, dangelo-2021-rational] are relevant.
We change the point of view slightly and consider the complements of balls and the differences of balls, that is, without loss of generality we study maps between the sets of the form and , where denotes the ball of radius centered at . As before, we say proper map of ball complements to mean a proper holomorphic map . Similarly, by proper map of ball differences we mean a proper holomorphic map . We remark that proper maps to domains that are complements of balls have been studied previously; see [forstnerivc-2014-oka]. However, we wish the domain of the map to also be a ball complement. First, we characterize all proper maps of ball complements.
Theorem 1.1.
Suppose , , is a proper holomorphic map. Then is a polynomial map, and when this polynomial is restricted to , it gives a proper map to .
Conversely, suppose is a polynomial that takes to properly. Then
-
(i)
, and
-
(ii)
if also as , then is a proper map of to .
The condition on the norm is clearly satisfied for proper maps of complements, but it is not clear if it is automatically true for polynomial proper maps of balls. We prove that the condition is satisfied if the polynomial takes the origin to the origin, or more trivially, if the top degree terms of do not vanish on the sphere.
That the proper map of ball complements is polynomial follows from a combination of the Hartogs phenomenon and Forstnerič’s theorem mentioned above. The key is then to show that polynomial maps of balls are precisely those that also take the outside to the outside. The theorem does not hold if : is biholomorphic to the punctured disc , which properly, and certainly not rationally, embeds into via the classical theorem of Remmert–Bishop–Narasimhan (see [forstneric-2017-stein-manifolds]*Theorem 2.4.1 and also Alexander [alexander-1977-punctured-disc] for an explicit embedding into ). Such a map certainly avoids some small closed ball. A more complicated example where the sphere in the boundary of the target plays a role can be constructed via modifying the technique in the examples following Proposition 1.5. What is true, even in one dimension, is that a rational map that restricts to a proper map of to takes all the (nonpole) points of to ; see Lemma 2.1.
Proper maps of differences of balls are somewhat more complicated. Via a similar argument, again heavily dependent on the result of Forstnerič, we prove the following result.
Theorem 1.2.
Suppose and , are two balls such that and . Suppose is a proper holomorphic map. Then is rational and extends to a rational proper map of balls that takes the sphere to the sphere . If and and is written in lowest terms, then . Conversely, every proper holomorphic map that takes the sphere to the sphere is rational and restricts to a proper map of to .
If , the theorem need not hold. For example the function takes an annulus centered at the origin to an annulus, swaps the inside and outside circles and does not extend to the entire disc. The theorem leads us to study what we call rational -fold sphere maps.
Definition 1.3.
A rational map is an -fold sphere map if there exist numbers and , such that the pole set of misses (and therefore for all ) and for all . If there are infinitely many such numbers and , then we say that is an -fold sphere map. We will call spheres such as zero-centric spheres and balls such as zero-centric balls.
In light of this definition, the theorem above says that every proper holomorphic map of ball complements centered at the origin is a rational -fold sphere map. We remark that by Proposition 3.2, we can assume that .
For the tensor of two polynomial maps we find that . Hence , and so is a homogeneous -fold sphere map. The map does not have linearly independent components for , but after applying a unitary and a projection we find a symmetrized homogeneous map with linearly independent components such that , where the number of components of is the rank of the underlying hermitian form of . For example in , is symmetrized to . See D’Angelo [dangelo-1993-several].
By Rudin’s theorem we mentioned above, a homogeneous -fold sphere map is unitarily equivalent to a scalar multiple of . Thus every homogeneous -fold sphere map is an -fold sphere map. Similarly, if we take a direct sum of properly scaled homogeneous sphere maps, we get an -fold sphere map. In fact, we have the following:
Theorem 1.4.
Suppose that , , is a rational -fold sphere map, where .
-
(i)
If and is a polynomial map of degree or less, then is an -fold sphere map.
-
(ii)
If and is a rational map of degree or less, then is an -fold sphere map.
If is an -fold sphere map, then is polynomial and for every there exists an such that . Moreover, there exists a unitary and homogeneous sphere maps (possibly constant) , and where , such that
The question then arises about the existence of other maps than the -fold sphere maps. For every and , we will show that there exists a rational (nonpolynomial) -fold sphere map of degree that is not a -fold sphere map. In particular, every first-degree rational proper map of the difference of zero-centric balls is a unitary composed with an affine linear embedding; however, there exist nonpolynomial second-degree rational maps of a difference of balls. We will also show (Lemma 3.10) that the denominator of a -fold sphere map for must be necessarily of a lower degree than the numerator, extending the analogous result by D’Angelo (see e.g. [dangelo-2019-hermitian]*Proposition 5.1) for sphere maps that also fix the origin.
Finally, we consider proper maps of ball differences to ball complements and vice versa. Using the result of Forstnerič, one can prove that when dimension is at least , no proper holomorphic maps exist between the two different sets.
Proposition 1.5.
Suppose , , and . There exist no proper holomorphic maps nor .
If , start with a proper embedding of the disc into (e.g. Remmert–Bishop–Narasimhan again). We can construct a nonrational proper map from to : Take a proper holomorphic embedding . Take a small closed ball so that is a connected set with more than one point and is connected. Then it is classical that the doubly connected domain is biholomorphic to an annulus for some . Composition of the maps and taking to the unit ball obtains the desired map. To construct the second map when , is biholomorphic to the punctured disc , which can be properly embedded into some in many ways (e.g., linearly).
Interestingly, it is not difficult to construct many nontrivial proper maps of to when , but the proposition says that if , there is no way to properly map the annulus to the complement of the ball.
2. Proper mappings of ball complements
We start with a lemma about where rational proper holomorphic maps of balls take the complement of the ball. We remark that unlike many of the results we consider, this lemma still holds in .
Lemma 2.1.
If is a rational map such that the restriction of to is a proper map to , then for every that is not a pole of .
Proof.
Write for polynomials and . As takes the sphere to the sphere , there is a real polynomial such that
outside the set where . Polarization gives us
where is the standard symmetric dot product.
Suppose is not a pole of . Set so that . As has no poles in the ball, . Hence and . Then
(1) |
Cauchy-Schwarz inequality gives
The lemma proves the converse statement of Theorem 1.1. That is, if is a polynomial map such that its restriction to is a proper map to , it takes the sphere to the sphere , and the lemma says that it takes to . If we furthermore assume that as , we find that is proper.
It is not clear if the norm of a polynomial proper of balls always goes to infinity at infinity thereby giving a proper map of to . We provide a proof in some natural special cases.
Proposition 2.2.
Suppose is a polynomial which is also a proper map of to . Suppose that
-
(i)
, or
-
(ii)
is the decomposition into homogeneous parts and is not zero on the unit sphere.
Then as .
Proof.
Suppose first that and suppose for contradiction that the conclusion does not hold. Then without loss of generality, there is a sequence such that and . Letting in the reflection principle 1 with , we get , a contradiction.
Next, suppose that is not zero on the unit sphere. Let be a lower bound for for . Writing any as with and , we have
As is the top degree homogeneous part of , we find that as . ∎
We remark that the conclusion of the proposition also follows if the polynomial proper map of balls is constructed using tensoring only starting with the identity in the procedure of D’Angelo [dangelo-1988-proper].
The rest of Theorem 1.1 follows from the following lemma.
Lemma 2.3.
Suppose , , is a proper holomorphic map. Then is a polynomial map, and when this polynomial is restricted to , it gives a proper map to .
Proof.
The Hartogs phenomenon says that extends to a holomorphic map of to . By the properness of , we have and therefore the map when restricted to gives a proper map to . The theorem of Forstnerič says that is rational. As is holomorphic on , it must necessarily be polynomial. ∎
3. -fold sphere maps
This section is split into two parts. In the first part, we consider polynomial -fold sphere maps, proving Theorem 1.4 for polynomials. We then give a construction of maps of higher degree showing that the bound is sharp. In the second part of the section, we extend the results to rational maps and give the construction showing that the result is sharp also in the rational case.
3.1. Polynomial -fold sphere maps
We remark that unlike many of the results we consider and except for Propositions 3.2 and 3.7, the results in this section still hold in .
Definition 3.1.
For , distinct s and for , we define the divided differences as
For , we write
and define the degree- Newton polynomial of the indeterminate as the real polynomial
Proposition 3.2.
Let , and be a nonconstant rational -fold sphere map, that is, it takes -spheres to -spheres, where all s are distinct and for . Then implies , and in particular, the divided differences and are positive.
Proof.
We notice that
Suppose that . As is a nonconstant rational map that takes -sphere to -sphere, it is a rational sphere map and hence a rational proper map of -ball to -ball. As , , so that .
In particular,
In the following few results, we will obtain convenient expressions of reminiscent of a Newton polynomial of indeterminate for the polynomial -fold sphere map . By bidegree of a polynomial , we mean a pair where is the degree in and is the degree in .
Lemma 3.3.
Let and be a polynomial -fold sphere map of degree , that is, it takes -spheres to -spheres, where all s are distinct and for . Let . Then for , there is a real polynomial of bidegree such that
which becomes
and for , is constant on the -sphere and equals .
Proof.
We prove the result by induction on . For , on the -sphere, equals and so is constant on the -sphere. Thus there is a real polynomial such that
that is,
As is of bidegree and is of bidegree , is of bidegree . As for , is constant and equals on the -sphere, is constant on the -sphere and equals
Suppose that for some , , there is a real polynomial such that is of bidegree , and for , is constant on the -sphere and equals .
Now, is constant on the -sphere. Thus there is a real polynomial such that
As is of bidegree and is of bidegree , is of bidegree . As for , is constant on the -sphere and equals , is constant on the -sphere and equals
Moreover, , that is,
The result then follows by induction. ∎
Lemma 3.4.
Let and be a polynomial -fold sphere map of degree , that is, it takes -spheres to -spheres, where all s are distinct and for . Then
for a real polynomial of bidegree . In other words, can be written as a Newton polynomial of with the leading coefficient replaced by a bidegree- real polynomial.
Proof.
Let . By Lemma 3.3, for , there is a real polynomial of bidegree such that
Inductively, we get
where is a real polynomial of bidegree . This is formally a degree- Newton polynomial of that passes through the points . ∎
As an immediate consequence, we obtain the following, proving the first part of Theorem 1.4.
Theorem 3.5.
Let be a polynomial -fold sphere map of degree . Then is a polynomial of . In particular, is an -fold sphere map. In fact, takes all zero-centric spheres to zero-centric spheres.
Proof.
The from Lemma 3.4 is of bidegree , that is, a constant. So is a polynomial of , and hence takes all zero-centric spheres to zero-centric spheres. In particular, is an -fold sphere map. ∎
This gives us the following:
Corollary 3.6.
A polynomial -fold sphere map takes all zero-centric spheres to zero-centric spheres.
Proof.
Let be a polynomial -fold sphere map of degree . Then it is a polynomial -fold sphere map. By Theorem 3.5, it takes all zero-centric spheres to zero-centric spheres. ∎
The -fold requirement in Theorem 3.5 is necessary. In fact, we have the following:
Theorem 3.7.
Let , . Then there exist some and monomial maps (see 2 below) of degree from to that are -fold sphere maps, but not -fold sphere maps. In particular, these maps do not take all zero-centric spheres to zero-centric spheres.
Proof.
Take arbitrary distinct for . Consider the bidegree- real polynomial
which is constant on for all . Choose such that
write
and consider
where
We see that is constant on for only due to the term, and is of bidegree . Moreover, each and each , so that each . This lets us write as a sum of squared norms of polynomial maps, that is,
is the squared norm of the map
Finally, we form
where
so that each , as and . We see that is constant on for only , and is of bidegree .
As mentioned in the introduction, is the squared norm of the map . We get that is the squared norm of the map
(2) |
This defines a family of maps for some , where each member is a monomial -fold sphere map of degree of that is not a -fold sphere map. ∎
3.2. Rational -fold sphere maps
In the following few results, we will obtain convenient expressions of reminiscent of a Newton polynomial of indeterminate for the rational -fold sphere map .
Notation 3.8.
We write to denote the bidegree- homogeneous part of a real polynomial , and write to denote the degree- homogeneous part of a polynomial .
Remark 3.9.
For convenience, we consider the zero real polynomial as a bidegree- real polynomial in .
Lemma 3.10.
Let , , and be a rational -fold sphere map of degree in reduced terms, that is, it takes -spheres to -spheres, where all s are distinct and for . Let . Then for , there is a real polynomial of bidegree at most such that
which becomes
and for , is constant on the -sphere and equals .
Moreover, if , then is of degree at most .
We remark that by Proposition 3.2, both and are always nonzero, so an immediate consequence is that if is a rational -fold sphere map, then .
Proof.
The result is trivial if is constant, so we assume otherwise. The proof is essentially the same as that of Lemma 3.3. We prove the result by induction on . For , on the -sphere, equals and so is constant on the -sphere. Rearranging,
on the -sphere, so that there is a real polynomial such that
that is,
We get
outside the pole set.
As is a nonconstant rational map that takes -sphere to -sphere, it is a rational proper map of to . By [dangelo-2019-hermitian]*Proposition 5.1, . As is of bidegree and is of bidegree at most , is of bidegree . As for , is constant and equals on the -sphere, is constant on the -sphere and equals
Suppose that for some , , there is a real polynomial of bidegree at most such that
and for , is constant on the -sphere and equals .
Now, is constant on the -sphere. Rearranging,
on the -sphere, so that there is a real polynomial such that
(3) |
We get
outside the pole set.
As for , is constant on the -sphere and equals , is constant on the -sphere and equals
Moreover, , that is,
If , then
As is of bidegree at most , is of bidegree at most .
If , suppose for contradiction that the degree of is bigger than . As is of bidegree at most and is of bidegree , is of bidegree . Collecting bidegree- terms on both sides of 3 and using the notation from 3.8, we get
By Huang’s lemma [huang-1999-linearity]*Lemma 3.2, a product of that is not zero cannot be a sum or difference of fewer than hermitian squares, and so
as and , contradicting . Thus is of degree at most . As both and are of bidegree at most , is of bidegree at most . The result then follows by induction. ∎
Lemma 3.11.
Let , , and be a rational -fold sphere map of degree in reduced terms, that is, it takes -spheres to -spheres, where all s are distinct and for . Then
for a real polynomial of bidegree at most . In other words, can be written as a Newton polynomial of with the leading coefficient replaced by a real polynomial of bidegree and the rest of the Newton polynomial multiplied by .
Proof.
Let . By Lemma 3.10, for , there is a real polynomial of bidegree at most such that
Inductively, we get
where is a real polynomial of bidegree at most . For , this becomes formally a degree- Newton polynomial of that passes through the points . ∎
As a consequence, we obtain the following, proving the second part of Theorem 1.4.
Theorem 3.12.
Let and be a rational -fold sphere map of degree . Then is a polynomial -fold sphere map. In particular, it takes all zero-centric spheres to zero-centric spheres.
Proof.
By Lemma 3.11,
where
is a polynomial of , and is of bidegree at most , hence zero. Thus outside the set where , we have .
Suppose that is in lowest terms. As takes -sphere to -sphere, is not zero, and so has a power series expansion at the origin, and hence so does . The (infinite) matrix of coefficients of this power series is positive semidefnite (being a squared norm) and as the matrix of coefficients of is a principal submatrix of this infinite matrix, it is itself positive semidefinite. Thus there is a polynomial map such that . But then for some unitary matrix near the origin, again using the result of D’Angelo. This means that and so is a polynomial.
Since is a polynomial -fold sphere map, it is a polynomial -fold sphere map, so by Theorem 3.5, it is an -fold sphere map and takes all zero-centric spheres to zero-centric spheres. ∎
This gives us the following, generalizing Corollary 3.6.
Corollary 3.13.
A rational -fold sphere map takes all zero-centric spheres to zero-centric spheres.
Proof.
Let be a rational -fold sphere map of degree . Then it is a rational -fold sphere map. By Theorem 3.12, it takes all zero-centric spheres to zero-centric spheres. ∎
The -fold requirement in Theorem 3.12 is necessary. In fact, we have the following:
Theorem 3.14.
Let , . Then there exist an integer and rational maps (see 4 below) of degree from to that are -fold sphere maps, but not -fold sphere maps. In particular, these maps do not take all zero-centric spheres to zero-centric spheres.
Proof.
Take any arbitrary degree- polynomial function , that is, of the form , which after a unitary transformation becomes with , which after another unitary transformation becomes with . If is the denominator of a rational map, can be scaled to have . Thus without loss of generality, assume that .
Take arbitrary distinct for . Consider the bidegree- real polynomial
which is constant on for all . Choose such that
write
and consider
where
We see that for , each , so that each , and for , each and each , so that each . Thus the matrix of coefficients of is positive definite.
Now consider
As , we get that , and the matrix approaches , which is positive definite. This means that is also positive definite for small enough . Thus there is a polynomial map such that .
Finally, we form
This gives us
Now, has a finite bidegree and hence can be divisible by for only a finite number of values of . So assume that is small enough so that does not divide . We see that is constant on for only due to the term and gives a rational map in reduced terms
Replacing with a more general denominator with small enough nonzero gives a rational map in reduced terms
(4) |
This defines a family of maps for some , where each member is a rational -fold sphere map of degree of that is not a -fold sphere map. ∎
The description of in Theorem 3.5 enables us to obtain a normal form of when is a rational -fold sphere map, proving the last part of Theorem 1.4.
Theorem 3.15.
If is a rational -fold sphere map, then is polynomial and for every there exists an such that . Moreover, there exists a unitary and homogeneous sphere maps (possibly constant) , and where , such that
(5) |
Proof.
The first part of the statement follows from Theorem 3.12.
Suppose the degree of the polynomial is . To obtain the stated presentation of , we use the expression of in Theorem 3.5:
where is a constant, and maps a sphere of radius centered at the origin to a sphere of radius centered at the origin.
Now as is a degree- polynomial, is a bidegree- polynomial in the coordinates , and it must be of the above form. Thus is of the form:
where the s are nonnegative real numbers, and since is a polynomial mapping of degree . Set (where is the constant mapping ), the scaled and symmetrized -fold tensor of the identity map with itself. Suppose are exactly the degrees for which . Let . Then is a -fold sphere map with linearly independent components. We have that for all , thus by a result of D’Angelo [dangelo-1993-several], after possibly adding zero components to , there is a unitary such that (5) holds. ∎
Remark 3.16.
Let . Given any nonconstant rational map that takes -sphere to -sphere, we can scale it by , giving us a rational sphere map and hence a rational proper map of balls .
Thus our results can be stated for rational proper maps of balls as the following:
Theorem 3.17.
Let . Let be a rational proper map of balls that takes zero-centric spheres in to zero-centric spheres in .
-
(i)
If is rational of degree less than , then is a polynomial and takes all zero-centric spheres to zero-centric spheres. The limit is strict.
-
(ii)
If is polynomial of degree at most , then takes all zero-centric spheres to zero-centric spheres. The limit is strict.
4. Proper mappings of ball differences
The first part of Theorem 1.2 is the following lemma.
Lemma 4.1.
Suppose and , are two balls such that and . Suppose is a proper holomorphic map. Then is rational and extends to a rational proper map of balls that takes the sphere to the sphere .
Proof.
Since is nonempty and is defined on the pseudoconcave side of it, we find that extends locally past at some point. As is proper it means that must take a small piece of to some piece of the boundary of . As the derivative of is of full rank at most points, we find that must take this small piece of the sphere to the pseudoconcave part of , that is, it must go to some part of . Via Forstnerič’s result, we find that is rational, and extends to a proper map of to . In particular, extends past the boundary at some points of . Then again it must take those points to the sphere via the same argument as above, and again it extends to a rational proper map of to . That it takes to follows as the map we started with was proper. ∎
If the two spheres are concentric with the unit ball, that is, and , then the hypotheses on the spheres mean that and . The conclusion of the lemma is then that is a rational proper map of the unit balls, hence takes to . Moreover, the lemma says that also takes to , and thus is a rational -fold sphere map. Hence, by Lemma 3.10, we find that the degree of the denominator is less than the degree of the numerator, proving the next part of Theorem 1.2.
For the last part of Theorem 1.2 we prove the following lemma.
Lemma 4.2.
Suppose and , are two balls such that and . Suppose is a holomorphic proper map that takes the sphere to the sphere . Then is rational and restricts to a proper map of to .
Proof.
The first part of the theorem follows by Forstnerič’s result again as we get that the piece of the sphere is taken to the piece of the sphere . So is rational. As is a rational proper map of balls to , it extends past the boundary by the result of Cima–Suffridge [cima-1990-boundary], and hence takes the the sphere to the sphere . Similarly, as the application of Forstnerič’s theorem gave a proper rational map of to , we get that takes to . To be a proper map of the differences, we need no point of to go to a point of . An even stronger conclusion holds, as is a proper rational map of to , Lemma 2.1 gives that no point of the complement of in can go to . ∎
Theorem 1.2 is now proved. Finally, we prove Proposition 1.5: there are no proper maps from the difference of balls to the complement of balls or vice-versa.
Proposition 4.3.
Suppose , , and . There exist no proper holomorphic maps nor .
Proof.
First, suppose is a proper holomorphic map. As before, extends holomorphically across some piece of the pseudoconcave boundary . Hence it takes some piece of to a bounded set, and as the map is proper it must go to the boundary of the target, that is, . By the theorem of Forstnerič, is rational. As is rational, we can also extend to most points of . But this means that this extension is a holomorphic map that takes a piece of the sphere to the finite part of the boundary, that is, . Again, Forstnerič says that this map is actually a proper map of . That is impossible as takes to the complement of .
Next, suppose that we are given a proper holomorphic map . By Hartogs, extends to all of . By the maximum principle takes to , but that violates Liouville’s theorem. ∎