This paper was converted on www.awesomepapers.org from LaTeX by an anonymous user.
Want to know more? Visit the Converter page.

Projection spaces and twisted Lie algebras

Ben Knudsen
Abstract.

A projection space is a collection of spaces interrelated by the combinatorics of projection onto tensor factors in a symmetric monoidal background category. Examples include classical configuration spaces, orbit configuration spaces, the graphical configuration spaces of Eastwood–Huggett, the simplicial configuration spaces of Cooper–de Silva–Sazdanovic, the generalized configuration spaces of Petersen, and Stiefel manifolds. We show that, under natural assumptions on the background category, the homology of a projection space is calculated by the Chevalley–Eilenberg complex of a certain generalized Lie algebra. We identify conditions on this Lie algebra implying representation stability in the classical setting of finite sets and injections.

1. Introduction

Experience has proven the value of studying configuration spaces in families. When organized correctly, these spaces exhibit emergent algebraic structure that imposes strong constraints on their topological invariants. One important means of organization involves the background space in an essential way; one speaks of operads and their algebras and modules [22, 28], or of adding a particle near the boundary of a manifold [29] or onto an edge of a graph [2]. Here, we pursue an orthogonal organizing principle, namely that of the underlying combinatorics.

1.1. Context and motivation

As a motivating example, consider the ordinary configuration space ConfI(X)\mathrm{Conf}_{I}(X), defined as the space of injections from the finite set II into the topological space XX. The composite of injections being an injection, the collection of all such spaces forms a presheaf on the category \mathcal{FI} of finite sets and injections. In many examples of interest, this combinatorial structure forces the rational (co)homology of configuration spaces to exhibit representation stability [6].

There are now a number of machines devoted to the study of stability phenomena in various contexts [19, 35]. Unfortunately, most of these machines are adapted to the study of automorphism groups, rather than configuration spaces. The goal of this paper is to develop a framework better adapted to examples such as those listed in the following table.

Combinatorics Configuration space
Sets Ordinary
GG-sets Orbit
Graphs Graphical [10]
Simplicial complexes Simplicial [7]
Collision structures Generalized [32]
Vector spaces Stiefel

We proceed from the observation that the projection ConfJ(X)ConfI(X)\mathrm{Conf}_{J}(X)\to\mathrm{Conf}_{I}(X) induced by the injection f:IJf:I\to J is subsumed by the map that splits an II-indexed configuration into a configuration indexed by the image of ff and one indexed by its complement. The collection of all such splitting maps can be regarded as a kind of cocommutative comultiplication, which, according to the philosophy of Koszul duality, is governed by its Lie algebra of (derived) primitives.

The resulting interpretation of the homology of ordinary configuration spaces as Lie algebra homology has proven quite fruitful [4, 9, 15, 23, 24, 25]. This success motivates us to generalize the relationship, showing that the homology of something sufficiently like a configuration space is governed by something like a Lie algebra.

1.2. Framework and results

Our first step is to generalize the relationship between bijections and injections among finite sets in the relationship between a symmetric monoidal category 𝒞\mathcal{C} and its projection category Pr(𝒞)\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C}). Roughly, a morphism in Pr(𝒞)\Pr(\mathcal{C}) is (opposite to) a projection onto a tensor factor in 𝒞\mathcal{C} (see Section 2.1 for details). We then make the following definition, which encompasses all of the spaces listed in the table above (see Section 6.1).

Definition 1.1.

A projection space over 𝒞\mathcal{C} is a functor X:Pr(𝒞)op𝒯opX:\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C})^{\mathrm{op}}\to\mathcal{T}\mathrm{op}. We say that XX is reduced if its value on the monoidal unit is a singleton.

The bulk of the paper is spent in constructing the following composite functor, which associates to each projection space XX a 𝒞\mathcal{C}-twisted Lie algebra L(X)L(X) of rational primitives:

L:Fun(Pr(𝒞)op,𝒯op)\textstyle{L:\mathrm{Fun}(\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C})^{\mathrm{op}},\mathcal{T}\mathrm{op})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}\scriptstyle{\cong}Funoplax(𝒞op,𝒯op)\textstyle{\mathrm{Fun}^{\mathrm{oplax}}(\mathcal{C}^{\mathrm{op}},\mathcal{T}\mathrm{op})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}A\scriptstyle{A_{*}}Funoplax(𝒞op,𝒞h)\textstyle{\mathrm{Fun}^{\mathrm{oplax}}(\mathcal{C}^{\mathrm{op}},\mathcal{C}\mathrm{h}_{\mathbb{Q}})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}\scriptstyle{\cong}CoalgCom(Fun(𝒞op,𝒞h))\textstyle{\mathrm{Coalg}_{\mathrm{Com}}(\mathrm{Fun}(\mathcal{C}^{\mathrm{op}},\mathcal{C}\mathrm{h}_{\mathbb{Q}}))\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}Q\scriptstyle{\mathrm{Q}}AlgLie(Fun(𝒞op,𝒞h)).\textstyle{\mathrm{Alg}_{\mathrm{Lie}}(\mathrm{Fun}(\mathcal{C}^{\mathrm{op}},\mathcal{C}\mathrm{h}_{\mathbb{Q}})).}

Briefly, the first functor witnesses a universal property of the projection category (Corollary 4.3); the second is the functor of Sullivan chains, a suitable rational replacement for singular chains (Corollary A.5); the third relies on a variant of Day convolution (Corollary 4.12); and the fourth is Quillen’s Koszul duality functor [33]. The main result is as follows—see Section 5 for undefined terms.

Theorem 1.2.

Let XX be a reduced projection space over the combinatorial symmetric monoidal category 𝒞\mathcal{C}. There is a canonical isomorphism of 𝒞\mathcal{C}-twisted cocommutative coalgebras

H(X;)HLie(L(X)).H_{*}(X;\mathbb{Q})\cong H_{*}^{\mathrm{Lie}}(L(X)).

As a consequence, the homology of generalized configuration spaces is calculated by the Chevalley–Eilenberg complex of a certain Lie algebra. This general connection to Lie algebras may at first seem surprising. Indeed, for ordinary configuration spaces, it is natural to view the connection as arising by combining the Goresky–MacPherson formula, expressing the homology of a stratified space in terms of poset homology, with the identification of the Lie operad with the homology of the partition posets [32]. In the more general setting, the resulting poset homology has no obvious relation to the Lie operad, yet the connection persists.

As foreshadowed above, we imagine Theorem 1.2 as a source and organizing principle for stability phenomena. As a proof of concept, we show that our framework encompasses representation stability. Specifically, stability is tied to the eventual high connectivity of the Lie algebra of rational primitives.

Theorem 1.3.

Let XX be a reduced op\mathcal{FI}^{\mathrm{op}}-space taking values in path connected spaces. Suppose that L(X)L(X) satisfies the following conditions.

  1. (1)

    Hi(L(X)k)H_{i}(L(X)_{k}) is finite dimensional for every i0i\geq 0 and k0k\geq 0.

  2. (2)

    H0(L(X)k)=0H_{0}(L(X)_{k})=0 for k>1k>1.

  3. (3)

    Hi(L(X)k)=0H_{i}(L(X)_{k})=0 for ii fixed and kk sufficiently large.

Then H(X;)H^{*}(X;\mathbb{Q}) is representation stable.

We deduce this theorem from a more general result encompassing projection spaces with path disconnected values—see Theorem 6.14.

1.3. Future directions

Our work leaves a rather large number of natural questions unanswered (but see [20] and [21] for closely related work). The following three extensions at least are likely within easy reach.

  1. (1)

    Integer coefficients. Our program relies crucially on a strictly symmetric replacement for the oplax monoidal functor of singular chains. In characteristic zero, such a replacement is within easy reach (see Appendix A). With a bit less laziness, one should be able to work integrally, as in [32], after minor modifications of the techniques of [36]—see also Remark A.6.

  2. (2)

    Classical primitives. Let MM be a (for simplicity) orientable nn-manifold. In view of a myriad of (semi-)classical results, it seems a virtual certainty that the Lie algebra associated to the ordinary configuration spaces of MM is (quasi-isomorphic to) the tensor product of the compactly supported Sullivan cochains of MM with a free twisted Lie algebra on one generator in degree n1n-1 and weight 11 [13, 16, 23, 32]. It is likely possible to deduce this claim easily from either of the last two references with a little care taken in comparing models.

  3. (3)

    Orbit primitives. The results of [3] suggest that the same description is valid verbatim for orbit configuration spaces, save that the phrase “free twisted Lie algebra” should be interpreted with respect to the category of equivariant bijections among free GG-sets.

In more exotic settings, it is less clear what one should expect.

  1. (4)

    Generalized primitives. What is the Lie algebra associated to generalized configuration spaces? Petersen’s results in [32] suggest an expression in terms of the homology of the order complex associated to a collision structure. One imagines that the Chevalley–Eilenberg complex for this Lie algebra comprises the complexes described by Petersen, in the same way that the various Totaro spectral sequences [38] assemble into the Chevalley–Eilenberg complex of the Lie algebra described above in the case of ordinary configuration spaces [22].

One imagines that Theorem 1.3 is merely the beginning of a robust connection between stability phenomena and the twisted Chevalley–Eilenberg complex.

  1. (5)

    \mathcal{FI}-homology. We show that sufficient connectivity of L(X)L(X) implies representation stability. Is there a direct connection between this Lie algebra and \mathcal{FI}-(hyper)homology [5]?

  2. (6)

    Higher stability. Is there an analogue of Theorem 1.3 characterizing higher order representation stability in terms of L(X)L(X) [30]?

  3. (7)

    Beyond representation stability. What finite generation properties does L(X)L(X) dictate for projection spaces in more exotic contexts? What homological asymptotics do they imply? Pursuit of this direction almost certainly entails grappling with thorny Noetherianity problems for 𝒞\mathcal{C}-twisted commutative algebras, already notoriously difficult (and mostly unsolved) in the classical case 𝒞=\mathcal{C}=\mathcal{FB} [31].

It is likely that our framework and examples can be expanded considerably.

  1. (8)

    Local coefficients. One imagines a theory in the vein of [35] treating the homology of projection spaces with compatibly twisted coefficients. Stability phenomena in the twisted (co)homology of configuration spaces is of considerable interest—see [11], for example.

  2. (9)

    Linear collision structures. It is likely that a linear version of the theory developed in Section 3 would permit the expression of the homology of subspace arrangements as twisted Lie algebra homology.

  3. (10)

    Rational homotopy theory. In the language of [1], the Day convolution and pointwise tensor products endow the category of presheaves of chain complexes with the structure of a 22-monoidal category, and the singular chains of a projection space carry the structure of a double coalgebra in this category, with the second comultiplication induced by the objectwise diagonal. Does this structure provide a faithful algebraic model for the homotopy theory of rationalized projection spaces [33]?

1.4. Conventions

Chain complexes are bounded below and homologically graded. The rr-fold homological suspension is denoted [r][r]. When working with monoidal categories, we suppress the associator whenever possible. We use the symbols \otimes and 𝟙\mathbb{1} for the tensor product and unit of a generic monoidal category, employing subscripts (rarely) to disambiguate as necessary (e.g., 𝒞\otimes_{\mathcal{C}}). An additive tensor category is an additive category equipped with a symmetric monoidal structure whose tensor product distributes over finite coproducts. We write Γk(V)=(Vk)Σk\Gamma^{k}(V)=(V^{\otimes k})^{\Sigma_{k}}, Symk(V)=VΣkk\mathrm{Sym}^{k}(V)=V^{\otimes k}_{\Sigma_{k}}, Γ(V)=k0Γk(V)\Gamma(V)=\bigoplus_{k\geq 0}\Gamma^{k}(V), and Sym(V)=k0Symk(V)\mathrm{Sym}(V)=\bigoplus_{k\geq 0}\mathrm{Sym}^{k}(V).

1.5. Acknowledgements

The author thanks Najib Idrissi and Roberto Pagaria for helpful conversations related to this work and the anonymous referee for her feedback. This paper was written for the proceedings of the conference “Compactifications, Configurations, and Cohomology,” held at Northeastern University in October of 2021. The author extends his heartfelt gratitude to the organizers, Peter Crooks and Alex Suciu, for the opportunity to speak, to write, and to be reminded that face-to-face interaction in mathematics is a precious, even indispensable, commodity. This work was supported by NSF grant DMS-1906174.

2. Projection categories

In this section, we introduce the projection category Pr(𝒞)\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C}) associated to a monoidal category 𝒞\mathcal{C}. We then explore a selection of simple examples.

2.1. Definitions

Roughly speaking, we wish for a presheaf on the projection category Pr(𝒞)\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C}) to carry a structure map for each projection of an object onto a tensor factor. The following definition makes this idea precise.

Definition 2.1.

Let C1C_{1} and C2C_{2} be objects in the monoidal category 𝒞\mathcal{C}.

  1. (1)

    A complementary morphism from C1C_{1} to C2C_{2} is the data of an object DD of 𝒞\mathcal{C} together with a morphism f:C1DC2f:C_{1}\otimes D\to C_{2}.

  2. (2)

    The composite of the complementary morphisms f1:C1D1C2f_{1}:C_{1}\otimes D_{1}\to C_{2} and f2:C2D2C3f_{2}:C_{2}\otimes D_{2}\to C_{3} is the complementary morphism f2(f1D2):C1D1D2C2f_{2}\circ(f_{1}\otimes D_{2}):C_{1}\otimes D_{1}\otimes D_{2}\to C_{2}.

  3. (3)

    An elementary equivalence from the complementary morphism f:C1DC2f:C_{1}\otimes D\to C_{2} to the complementary morphism f:C1DC2f^{\prime}:C_{1}\otimes D^{\prime}\to C_{2} is a map g:DDg:D\to D^{\prime} fitting into the commutative diagram

    C1D\textstyle{C_{1}\otimes D\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}f\scriptstyle{f}C1g\scriptstyle{C_{1}\otimes g}C1D\textstyle{C_{1}\otimes D^{\prime}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}f\scriptstyle{f^{\prime}}C2\textstyle{C_{2}}
  4. (4)

    We say that two complementary morphisms are equivalent if they differ by a finite sequence of elementary equivalences.

We emphasize that the arrow gg in the definition of an elementary equivalence is not required to be an isomorphism—see Remark 2.6 below for more on this point.

Remark 2.2.

The definition of a complementary morphism is biased by mapping order, i.e., whether to consider C1DC2C_{1}\otimes D\to C_{2} or C1C2DC_{1}\to C_{2}\otimes D. Up to opposites, the two choices produce essentially the same result. The definition is also biaed by tensor order, i.e., whether to consider C1DC_{1}\otimes D or DC1D\otimes C_{1}. Following this section, we will assume that 𝒞\mathcal{C} is symmetric monoidal, so this bias will play no role.

Lemma 2.3.

Composition is associative and unital up to equivalence and well-defined on equivalence classes.

Proof.

We give only an outline, leaving the (easy) details to the reader. For associativity, one uses the associator of 𝒞\mathcal{C} to produce an elementary equivalence between the two composites, and the compositional unit is the unitor CC𝟙C\cong C\otimes\mathbb{1}. Well-definition in one composition factor follows from the commuting diagram

C1D1D2\textstyle{C_{1}\otimes D_{1}\otimes D_{2}^{\prime}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}C1D1g\scriptstyle{C_{1}\otimes D_{1}\otimes g}C2D2\textstyle{C_{2}\otimes D_{2}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}C2g\scriptstyle{C_{2}\otimes g}C3\textstyle{C_{3}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}C1D1D2\textstyle{C_{1}\otimes D_{1}\otimes D_{2}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}C2D2\textstyle{C_{2}\otimes D_{2}^{\prime}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}C3,\textstyle{C_{3},}

and a similar diagram establishes well-definition in the second factor. ∎

The lemma allows us our main definition.

Definition 2.4.

Let 𝒞\mathcal{C} be a monoidal category. The projection category of 𝒞\mathcal{C} is the category Pr(𝒞)\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C}) with the same objects as 𝒞\mathcal{C} and arrows the equivalence classes of complementary morphisms under composition.

The projection category is functorial for strong monoidal functors. Briefly, given such a functor F:𝒞𝒟F:\mathcal{C}\to\mathcal{D}, we define Pr(F)=F\mathrm{Pr}(F)=F on objects, and we declare that Pr(F)\mathrm{Pr}(F) send the equivalence class of the complementary morphism C1DC2C_{1}\otimes D\to C_{2} to the equivalence class of the composite F(C1)F(D)F(C1D)F(C2)F(C_{1})\otimes F(D)\cong F(C_{1}\otimes D)\to F(C_{2}). It is a simple matter to check that Pr(F)\mathrm{Pr}(F) is a well-defined functor.

Remark 2.5.

The functoriality described above is a shadow of a larger structure. Specifically, the projection category Pr(𝒞)\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C}) is the truncation of an obvious bicategory, and an elaboration of the considerations of Section 4.1 shows that a lax monoidal functor between monoidal categories induces a pseudofunctor at the level of bicategories. We make no use of this extended functoriality.

Remark 2.6.

The projection category is closely related to a construction due to Quillen [18] (see also [35, p. 11]). More precisely, the projection category is obtained from the bicategory described in Remark 2.5 by replacing the morphism categories by their connected components, while Quillen’s construction (in the case of a self-action) is obtained by replacing them with the connected components of their maximal subgroupoids—see Example 2.7 for a simple example illustrating the difference. In particular, one should expect the two to coincide only when 𝒞\mathcal{C} is itself a groupoid. The use of the full morphism category is essential to the universal property of Theorem 4.2—see Remark 4.6 and Example 4.7.

Example 2.7.

Let Δ1\Delta^{1} denote the walking arrow, i.e., the category with objects 0 and 11 and a unique non-identity morphism e:01e:0\to 1. The usual rules of integer multiplication extend to a unique symmetric monoidal structure on Δ1\Delta^{1}. With this monoidal structure, one finds that there are the exactly five complementary morphisms. Since Δ1\Delta^{1} has no non-identity isomorphisms, these five morphisms are distinct in Quillen’s category. One checks that the resulting category is the walking retract, i.e., the category generated by the arrows i:01i:0\to 1 and r:10r:1\to 0 subject only to the relation ri=idr\circ i=\mathrm{id}, where i=[00𝑒1]i=[0\otimes 0\xrightarrow{e}1] and r=[10id0]r=[1\otimes 0\xrightarrow{\mathrm{id}}0]. In contrast, the commutative diagram

100\textstyle{1\otimes 0\otimes 0\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}e\scriptstyle{e}1e\scriptstyle{1\otimes e}11\textstyle{1\otimes 1\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}id\scriptstyle{\mathrm{id}}1\textstyle{1}

is a simple equivalence demonstrating the relation ir=idi\circ r=\mathrm{id} in Pr(Δ1)\mathrm{Pr}(\Delta^{1}). Thus, the projection category is instead the walking isomorphism.

2.2. Groupoid examples

We begin with the primordial motivating example. Although this result is subsumed in Proposition 2.9, we include an independent proof, both for tactility and for later use.

Proposition 2.8.

There is a canonical isomorphism of categories

Pr().\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{FB})\cong\mathcal{FI}.
Proof.

The two categories have the same objects. We define a functor from left to right on arrows by sending the equivalence class of the complementary morphism f:I1JI2f:I_{1}\sqcup J\cong I_{2} to the injection f|I1f|_{I_{1}}. One checks immediately that this prescription is invariant under equivalence and respects identities. As for composition, the complementary morphisms f:I1J1I2f:I_{1}\sqcup J_{1}\cong I_{2} and g:I2J2I3g:I_{2}\sqcup J_{2}\cong I_{3} compose to give g(fJ2):I1J1J2I3g\circ(f\sqcup J_{2}):I_{1}\sqcup J_{1}\sqcup J_{2}\to I_{3}, and

(g(fJ2))I1=g(fJ2)I1=g|I2f|I1,\left(g\circ(f\sqcup J_{2})\right)\mid_{I_{1}}=g\circ(f\sqcup J_{2})\mid_{I_{1}}=g|_{I_{2}}\circ f|_{I_{1}},

as required. To define the functor from right to left, we send the injection i:I1I2i:I_{1}\to I_{2} to the equivalence class of the complementary morphism I1(I2im(i))I2I_{1}\sqcup\left(I_{2}\setminus\mathrm{im}(i)\right)\cong I_{2}. The injection I=II=I is sent to the equivalence class of III\sqcup\varnothing\cong I, which is the identity of II in Pr()\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{FB}), and the composite of i:I1I2i:I_{1}\to I_{2} and j:I2I3j:I_{2}\to I_{3} is sent to the equivalence class of I1(I3im(ji))I3I_{1}\sqcup\left(I_{3}\setminus\mathrm{im}(j\circ i)\right)\cong I_{3}, which is equivalent to the appropriate composite via the bijection

I2im(i)I3im(j)I3im(ji)I_{2}\setminus\mathrm{im}(i)\sqcup I_{3}\setminus\mathrm{im}(j)\cong I_{3}\setminus\mathrm{im}(j\circ i)

induced by jj.

We have shown that both assignments are functors, and the composite functors are the respective identities on objects by construction. On arrows, given f:I1JI2f:I_{1}\sqcup J\cong I_{2}, we have

I2im(f|I1)=f(J),I_{2}\setminus\mathrm{im}(f|_{I_{1}})=f(J),

and f1|f(J)f^{-1}|_{f(J)} provides an equivalence between our original complementary morphism and the complementary morphism I1f(J)I2I_{1}\sqcup f(J)\cong I_{2}, which represents its image under the composite functor. We leave it to the reader to check that the other composite is also the identity on arrows. ∎

We now consider a class of example recurrent throughout the study of stability phenomena. In the next result, the assumption that 𝒞\mathcal{C} be skeletal is made solely for simplicity of exposition.

Proposition 2.9.

Let 𝒞\mathcal{C} be a skeletal symmetric monoidal groupoid. There is a canonical bijection

HomPr(𝒞)(C1,C2)C2=C1DAut(C2)/Aut(D)\mathrm{Hom}_{\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C})}(C_{1},C_{2})\cong\coprod_{C_{2}=C_{1}\otimes D}\mathrm{Aut}(C_{2})/\mathrm{Aut}(D)

under which composition is given by the dashed filler in the following commutative diagram:

Aut(C2)×Aut(C3)\textstyle{\mathrm{Aut}(C_{2})\times\mathrm{Aut}(C_{3})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}(D2)×id\scriptstyle{(-\otimes D_{2})\times\mathrm{id}}Aut(C3)×Aut(C3)\textstyle{\mathrm{Aut}(C_{3})\times\mathrm{Aut}(C_{3})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}\scriptstyle{\circ}Aut(C3)\textstyle{\mathrm{Aut}(C_{3})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}Aut(C2)/Aut(D1)×Aut(C3)/Aut(D2)\textstyle{\mathrm{Aut}(C_{2})/\mathrm{Aut}(D_{1})\times\mathrm{Aut}(C_{3})/\mathrm{Aut}(D_{2})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}Aut(C3)/Aut(D1D2).\textstyle{\mathrm{Aut}(C_{3})/\mathrm{Aut}(D_{1}\otimes D_{2}).}
Proof.

For each object DD such that C2=C1DC_{2}=C_{1}\otimes D, an automorphism of C2C_{2} determines a complementary morphism C1DC2C_{1}\otimes D\cong C_{2}, and every complementary morphism is determined in this way. Thus, we have a canonical surjection

C2=C1DAut(C2)HomPr(𝒞)(C1,C2).\coprod_{C_{2}=C_{1}\otimes D}\mathrm{Aut}(C_{2})\to\mathrm{Hom}_{\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C})}(C_{1},C_{2}).

By definition, two automorphisms of C2C_{2} differ by an automorphism of the form C1g{C_{1}}\otimes g for gAut(D)g\in\mathrm{Aut}(D) if and only if the corresponding complementary morphisms are equivalent. It follows that the above surjection descends to the indicated disjoint union of orbit sets, and that each of the resulting functions Aut(C2)/Aut(D)HomPr(𝒞)(C1,C2)\mathrm{Aut}(C_{2})/\mathrm{Aut}(D)\to\mathrm{Hom}_{\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C})}(C_{1},C_{2}) is injective. Since 𝒞\mathcal{C} is skeletal, complementary morphisms indexed by different choices of DD are never equivalent, so the function as a whole is injective, implying the first claim. The (essentially immediate) verification of the second claim is left to the reader. ∎

In the following result, G\mathcal{FI}_{G} denotes the category of equivariant injections among free GG-sets with finitely many orbits, where GG is a fixed group, and 𝒱𝔽\mathcal{VI}_{\mathbb{F}} denotes the category of linear injections among finite dimensional vector spaces over a fixed vector space 𝔽\mathbb{F} (resp. G\mathcal{FB}_{G}, 𝒱𝔽\mathcal{VB}_{\mathbb{F}}, bijections).

Corollary 2.10.

Let GG be a group and 𝔽\mathbb{F} a field. There are the following canonical isomorphisms of categories:

Pr(G)\displaystyle\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{FB}_{G}) G\displaystyle\cong\mathcal{FI}_{G}
Pr(𝒱𝔽)\displaystyle\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{VB}_{\mathbb{F}}) 𝒱𝔽.\displaystyle\cong\mathcal{VI}_{\mathbb{F}}.

2.3. The projection category of a deformation

We close this section with an observation on the relationship between the formation of projection categories and subcategories of a certain type.

Definition 2.11.

A subcategory ι:𝒞0𝒞\iota:\mathcal{C}_{0}\subseteq\mathcal{C} is a deformation of 𝒞\mathcal{C} if there is a functor R:𝒞𝒞0R:\mathcal{C}\to\mathcal{C}_{0} and a natural transformation τ:ιRid\tau:\iota\circ R\to\mathrm{id}.

Note that any subcategory containing a deformation is itself a deformation.

Proposition 2.12.

Let 𝒞\mathcal{C} be a monoidal category and 𝒞0𝒞\mathcal{C}_{0}\subseteq\mathcal{C} a full subcategory containing 𝟙\mathbb{1} and closed under tensor products. If 𝒞0\mathcal{C}_{0} is a deformation of 𝒞\mathcal{C}, then the induced functor Pr(𝒞0)Pr(𝒞)\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C}_{0})\to\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C}) is fully faithful with image the subcategory Pr(𝒞)0Pr(𝒞)\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C})_{0}\subseteq\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C}) with objects the objects of 𝒞0\mathcal{C}_{0} and morphisms the equivalence classes of complementary morphisms f:C1DC2f:C_{1}\otimes D\to C_{2} such that DD lies in 𝒞0\mathcal{C}_{0}.

Proof.

Prerequisitely, we note that Pr(𝒞)0\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C})_{0} is, in fact, a subcategory by closure under tensor products. This same assumption, together with fullness and the assumption that 𝟙𝒞0\mathbb{1}\in\mathcal{C}_{0}, implies that the tensor product of 𝒞\mathcal{C} restricts to a monoidal structure on 𝒞0\mathcal{C}_{0} with the same unit and coherence isomorphisms, so Pr(𝒞0)\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C}_{0}) is defined, and the inclusion 𝒞0𝒞\mathcal{C}_{0}\subseteq\mathcal{C} is strong monoidal, so Pr(𝒞0)Pr(𝒞)\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C}_{0})\to\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C}) is defined. We claim that this functor factors through the inclusion of Pr(𝒞)0\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C})_{0} as an isomorphism. The existence, surjectivity on objects, and fullness of the factorization being essentially immediate, the main point is to verify faithfulness. Consider the zig-zag of simple equivalences of the form

C1D\textstyle{C_{1}\otimes D\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}f\scriptstyle{f}C1g\scriptstyle{C_{1}\otimes g}C1D\textstyle{C_{1}\otimes D^{\prime}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}f\scriptstyle{f^{\prime}}C1D′′\textstyle{C_{1}\otimes D^{\prime\prime}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}f′′\scriptstyle{f^{\prime\prime}}C1g\scriptstyle{C_{1}\otimes g^{\prime}}C2,\textstyle{C_{2},}

with all objects but DD^{\prime} lying in 𝒞0\mathcal{C}_{0}. By assumption, there is a functor R:𝒞𝒞0R:\mathcal{C}\to\mathcal{C}_{0} and a natural transformation τ:ιRid\tau:\iota\circ R\to\mathrm{id}, from which we derive the enlarged diagram

C1R(D)\textstyle{C_{1}\otimes R(D)\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}C1τ\scriptstyle{C_{1}\otimes\tau}C1R(g)\scriptstyle{C_{1}\otimes R(g)}C1R(D)\textstyle{C_{1}\otimes R(D^{\prime})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}C1τ\scriptstyle{C_{1}\otimes\tau}C1R(D′′)\textstyle{C_{1}\otimes R(D^{\prime\prime})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}C1τ\scriptstyle{C_{1}\otimes\tau}C1R(g)\scriptstyle{C_{1}\otimes R(g^{\prime})}C1D\textstyle{C_{1}\otimes D\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}f\scriptstyle{f}C1g\scriptstyle{C_{1}\otimes g}C1D\textstyle{C_{1}\otimes D^{\prime}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}f\scriptstyle{f^{\prime}}C1D′′\textstyle{C_{1}\otimes D^{\prime\prime}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}f′′\scriptstyle{f^{\prime\prime}}C1g\scriptstyle{C_{1}\otimes g^{\prime}}C2.\textstyle{C_{2}.}

This diagram supplies the following chain of simple equivalences:

ffC1τfC1τf′′C1τf′′,f\sim f\circ C_{1}\otimes\tau\sim f^{\prime}\circ C_{1}\otimes\tau\sim f^{\prime\prime}\circ C_{1}\otimes\tau\sim f^{\prime\prime},

all of which lie in 𝒞0\mathcal{C}_{0}. In the same way, an arbitrary zig-zag of simple equivalences expressing the equivalence in 𝒞\mathcal{C} of two complementary morphisms with source and target in 𝒞0\mathcal{C}_{0} may be replaced by a (perhaps longer) zig-zag of simple equivalences in 𝒞0\mathcal{C}_{0}. In other words, complementary morphisms in 𝒞0\mathcal{C}_{0} are equivalent if and only if they are equivalent as complementary morphisms in 𝒞\mathcal{C}, which is faithfulness. ∎

3. Collision structures

In this section, we develop a general combinatorial framework encompassing all of our examples. Inspired by [32], we define a collision structure to be a set of partitions of a finite set closed under merging blocks. We define a notion of morphism between collision structures and calculate the projection category associated to the category of collision structures and bijections (Theorem 3.11).

3.1. Definitions

We begin by recalling a few standard ideas regarding partitions.

Definition 3.1.

Let II be a set. A partition of II is a set PP of nonempty subsets of II, called blocks, such that every element of II is contained in exactly one block of PP. We say that PP is a refinement of PP^{\prime}, written PPP\leq P^{\prime}, if every block of PP^{\prime} is a union of blocks of PP.

The data of a partition PP of II is equivalent to the data of the equivalence relation P\sim_{P} on II given by declaring that two elements are equivalent provided they lie in the same block of PP. Note that the empty set admits a unique partition, which is itself empty.

Partitions of II form a poset ΠI\Pi_{I} under refinement, which has the unique minimum {{i}}iI\{\{i\}\}_{i\in I} and, if II is nonempty, the unique maximum {I}\{I\}.

Definition 3.2.

A collision structure on the set II is an upward closed subset SΠIS\subseteq\Pi_{I}, i.e., such that PSP^{\prime}\in S whenever PSP\in S and PPP\leq P^{\prime}.

We think of a collision structure as prescribing which collisions among elements of the underlying set are forbidden. From this point of view, the requirement of upward closure is obvious.

The intersection or union of collision structures on a fixed set is again a collision structure; therefore, it is sensible to speak of the largest and smallest collision structure with a given property, and of the collision structure generated by a set of partitions.

Example 3.3.

The trivial collision structure ΠI\varnothing\subseteq\Pi_{I} is initial among collision structures on II.

Given a partition PP of II and an injection f:IJf:I\to J, we write fPf_{*}P for the partition of JJ given by the images under ff of the blocks of PP, together with the singletons in the complement of the image of ff. Given a subset SΠIS\subseteq\Pi_{I}, we write fSf_{*}S for the collision structure generated by the set {fP:PS}.\{f_{*}P:P\in S\}.

Definition 3.4.

Let SS and TT be collision structures on II and JJ. We say that an injection f:IJf:I\to J is a map of collision structures if fSTf_{*}S\subseteq T.

Since we clearly have gfS=(gf)Sg_{*}f_{*}S=(g\circ f)_{*}S, maps of collision structures on finite sets form a category 𝒞𝒮\mathcal{CSI}. We will also be interested in the wide subcategory 𝒞𝒮\mathcal{CSB} of bijective maps of collision structures.

As we will see below in Section 6.1, a collision structure SS has an associated configuration space, in which collisions among particles are forbidden if the resulting partition lies in SS. These spaces are precisely the generalized configuration spaces of [32]. We close this section by observing that the category of collision structures subsumes the combinatorics underlying the graphical configuration spaces of [10] and the simplicial configuration spaces of [7]

Example 3.5.

A graph Γ\Gamma determines a collision structure SΓS_{\Gamma} on its set VV of vertices by declaring that PΠVP\in\Pi_{V} lies in SΓS_{\Gamma} if and only if some block of PP contains an edge. An injection between vertex sets is a map of collision structures if and only if it is a graph homomorphism.

Example 3.6.

A simplicial complex KK determines a collision structure SKS_{K} on its set VV of vertices by declaring that PΠVP\in\Pi_{V} lies in SKS_{K} if and only if some block of PP is not a simplex of KK (we use that the set of simplices is closed under the formation of subsets). An injection between vertex sets is a map of collision structures if and only if it preserves non-simplices.111Maps of this kind are called “cosimplicial” in [7]. We avoid this terminology for reasons that are likely obvious.

Note that the collision structure associated to a graph according to Example 3.5 coincides with the collision structure associated to its independence complex according to Example 3.6.

From these examples, we obtain the categories 𝒢\mathcal{GI} and 𝒮𝒞\mathcal{SCI} of injections among graphs and simplicial complexes, respectively, both full subcategories of 𝒞𝒮\mathcal{CSI}, and similarly for bijections.

3.2. Monoidal structure and projection category

The main result of this section identifies the projection category of the category 𝒞𝒮\mathcal{CSB} of collision structures and bijections. In order to formulate such a result, we first require a monoidal structure.

Definition 3.7.

Let SS and TT be collision structures on II and JJ, respectively. The disjoint union of SS and TT is the collision structure STΠIJS\sqcup T\subseteq\Pi_{I\sqcup J} generated by (ιI)S(ιJ)T(\iota_{I})_{*}S\cup(\iota_{J})_{*}T, where ιI:IIJ\iota_{I}:I\to I\sqcup J denotes the inclusion (resp. JJ).

This definition is arranged so that ιI\iota_{I} and ιJ\iota_{J} are maps of collision structures.

Lemma 3.8.

Disjoint union of collision structures extends to a unique symmetric monoidal structure such that the forgetful functor 𝒞𝒮\mathcal{CSB}\to\mathcal{FB} is strong monoidal.

Proof.

The main point is to verify that the (suppressed) associator of finite sets is an isomorphism of collision structures, but it is not difficult to check, given collision structures SiS_{i} on IiI_{i} for i{1,2,3}i\in\{1,2,3\}, that (S1S2)S3(S_{1}\sqcup S_{2})\sqcup S_{3} and S1(S2S3)S_{1}\sqcup(S_{2}\sqcup S_{3}) are both generated by the set i=13(ιIi)Si\bigcup_{i=1}^{3}(\iota_{I_{i}})_{*}S_{i}. ∎

By functoriality for strong monoidal functors, we obtain an induced functor at the level of projection categories, concerning which we have the following result.

Lemma 3.9.

The induced functor Pr(𝒞𝒮)Pr()\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{CSB})\to\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{FB}) is faithful.

Proof.

For i{1,2}i\in\{1,2\}, let SiS_{i} and TiT_{i} be collision structures on IiI_{i} and JiJ_{i}, respectively. Consider the following diagram of bijections:

I1J1\textstyle{I_{1}\sqcup J_{1}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}f1\scriptstyle{f_{1}}I1g\scriptstyle{I_{1}\sqcup g}I1J2\textstyle{I_{1}\sqcup J_{2}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}f2\scriptstyle{f_{2}}I2.\textstyle{I_{2}.}

It suffices to show, assuming that f1f_{1} and f2f_{2} are maps of collision structures (and gg not necessarily so), that f1f_{1} and f2f_{2} are equivalent as complementary morphisms in 𝒞𝒮\mathcal{CSB}. Let T3T_{3} denote the collision structure on J2J_{2} generated by gT1g_{*}T_{1} and T2T_{2}. Then gg is a map of collision structures from T1T_{1} to T3T_{3}, and the identity is a map of collision structures from T2T_{2} to T3T_{3}. We claim that f2f_{2} is a map of collision structures from S1T3S_{1}\sqcup T_{3} to S2S_{2}, for which it suffices to verify the following three containments:

(f2)(ιI1)S1\displaystyle(f_{2})_{*}(\iota_{I_{1}})_{*}S_{1} S2\displaystyle\subseteq S_{2}
(f2)(ιJ2)gT1\displaystyle(f_{2})_{*}(\iota_{J_{2}})_{*}g_{*}T_{1} S2\displaystyle\subseteq S_{2}
(f2)(ιJ2)T2\displaystyle(f_{2})_{*}(\iota_{J_{2}})_{*}T_{2} S2.\displaystyle\subseteq S_{2}.

The first and third containment are the assumption that f2f_{2} is a map of collision structures, and the second follows from the assumption that f1f_{1} is so, since f2ιJ2g=f1ιJ1f_{2}\circ\iota_{J_{2}}\circ g=f_{1}\circ\iota_{J_{1}} by commutativity. We have established the existence of the commutative diagram

S1T1\textstyle{S_{1}\sqcup T_{1}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}f1\scriptstyle{f_{1}}I1g\scriptstyle{I_{1}\sqcup g}S1T3\textstyle{S_{1}\sqcup T_{3}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}f2\scriptstyle{f_{2}}S1T2\textstyle{S_{1}\sqcup T_{2}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}f2\scriptstyle{f_{2}}id\scriptstyle{\mathrm{id}}I2\textstyle{I_{2}}

of collision structures, which represents a pair of elementary equivalences connecting f1f_{1} and f2f_{2}. ∎

Example 3.10.

Via Examples 3.5 and 3.6, the disjoint union of graphs and of simplicial complexes corresponds to the disjoint union of collision structures. In other words, the inclusions 𝒢𝒞𝒮\mathcal{GB}\subseteq\mathcal{CSB} and 𝒮𝒞𝒞𝒮\mathcal{SCB}\subseteq\mathcal{CSB} are strong monoidal.

We come now to the main result of this section.

Theorem 3.11.

There is a canonical isomorphism of categories

Pr(𝒞𝒮)𝒞𝒮.\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{CSB})\cong\mathcal{CSI}.
Proof.

The two categories have the same objects, and we wish to extend this equality to an isomorphism of categories. Forgetting collision structures determines the vertical functors in the diagram

Pr(𝒞𝒮)\textstyle{\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{CSB})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}𝒞𝒮\textstyle{\mathcal{CSI}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}Pr()\textstyle{\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{FB})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}\scriptstyle{\cong},\textstyle{\mathcal{FI},}

where the bottom functor is the isomorphism of Proposition 2.8. Since the vertical functors are faithful by Lemma 3.9 and by definition, respectively, the dashed functor (extending the identity on objects) is unique if it exists.

By definition, an arrow from S1S_{1} to S2S_{2} in the source of the putative functor is represented by a bijection f:I1JI2f:I_{1}\sqcup J\cong I_{2} such that f(S1T)S2f_{*}(S_{1}\sqcup T)\subseteq S_{2}. We have

(f|I1)S1=(fιI1)S1=f(ιI1)S1f(S1T)S2,(f|_{I_{1}})_{*}S_{1}=(f\circ\iota_{I_{1}})_{*}S_{1}=f_{*}(\iota_{I_{1}})_{*}S_{1}\subseteq f_{*}(S_{1}\sqcup T)\subseteq S_{2},

so the injection f|I1f|_{I_{1}} defines a morphism from S1S_{1} to S2S_{2} in 𝒞𝒮\mathcal{CSI}. Thus, the dashed functor exists. To obtain its inverse, it suffices for the same reasons to note, given an injection i:I1I2i:I_{1}\to I_{2} with iS1S2i_{*}S_{1}\subseteq S_{2}, that the bijection I1(I2im(i))I2I_{1}\sqcup(I_{2}\setminus\mathrm{im}(i))\cong I_{2} lifts uniquely to a complementary morphism in 𝒞𝒮\mathcal{CSB}. For existence, we note that the bijection in question is a map of collision structures when I2im(i)I_{2}\setminus\mathrm{im}(i) carries the empty collision structure. For uniqueness, we note that, for any collision structure TT on I2im(i)I_{2}\setminus\mathrm{im}(i), any permutation of this set defines a morphism of collision structures T\varnothing\to T; therefore, any lift of I1(I2im(i))I2I_{1}\sqcup(I_{2}\setminus\mathrm{im}(i))\cong I_{2} to a complementary morphism is equivalent to the lift constructed above. ∎

Corollary 3.12.

There are the following canonical isomorphisms of categories:

Pr(𝒢)\displaystyle\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{GB}) 𝒢\displaystyle\cong\mathcal{GI}
Pr(𝒮𝒞)\displaystyle\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{SCB}) 𝒮𝒞.\displaystyle\cong\mathcal{SCI}.
Proof.

We aim to use Proposition 2.12, the main point being to verify that 𝒢\mathcal{GB} and 𝒮𝒞\mathcal{SCB} are deformations of 𝒞𝒮\mathcal{CSB}. We begin by observing that the assignment of a finite set to its trivial collision structure defines a fully faithful functor 𝒞𝒮\mathcal{FB}\to\mathcal{CSB}, which is a section of the forgetful functor. Identifying \mathcal{FB} with its essential image under this functor, we observe that \mathcal{FB} is a deformation of 𝒞𝒮\mathcal{CSB}, since the trivial collision structure is initial. Moreover, we have the containment 𝒢𝒮𝒞\mathcal{FB}\subseteq\mathcal{GB}\cap\mathcal{SCB}; indeed, the trivial collision structure on II corresponds to the discrete graph on II and to the simplex spanned by II. Since a subcategory containing a deformation is itself a deformation, the proof is complete.

4. Monoidal matters

In this section, we consider interactions among various tensor products. First, we prove the structural result that the opposite of the projection category represents oplax symmetric monoidal functors with Cartesian target (Corollary 4.3). Second, we show that, under restrictive but applicable hypotheses, a variant of Day convolution identifies such oplax functors with certain coalgebras (Corollary 4.12). These two results form the bridge from combinatorial structure to algebraic structure underpinning our proof of Theorem 1.2.

4.1. Projection categories and lax structures

The goal of this section is to establish a universal property of the projection category in the symmetric setting. Before articulating this universal property in Theorem 4.2 below, we pause to establish notation regarding a few standard concepts.

Definition 4.1.

Let 𝒞\mathcal{C} and 𝒟\mathcal{D} be monoidal categories.

  1. (1)

    A lax (monoidal) structure on a functor F:𝒞𝒟F:\mathcal{C}\to\mathcal{D} is a natural transformation μ:FFF\mu:F\otimes F\to F\circ\otimes and a morphism η:𝟙F(𝟙)\eta:\mathbb{1}\to F(\mathbb{1}) such that the following diagrams commute for all C1,C2,C3𝒞C_{1},C_{2},C_{3}\in\mathcal{C}.

    F(C1(C2C3))\textstyle{F(C_{1}\otimes(C_{2}\otimes C_{3}))\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}\scriptstyle{\sim}F((C1C2)C3)\textstyle{F((C_{1}\otimes C_{2})\otimes C_{3})}F(C1)F(C2C3)\textstyle{F(C_{1})\otimes F(C_{2}\otimes C_{3})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}μ\scriptstyle{\mu}F(C1C2)F(C3)\textstyle{F(C_{1}\otimes C_{2})\otimes F(C_{3})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}μ\scriptstyle{\mu}F(C1)(F(C2)F(C3))\textstyle{F(C_{1})\otimes(F(C_{2})\otimes F(C_{3}))\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}F(C1)μ\scriptstyle{F(C_{1})\otimes\mu}\scriptstyle{\sim}(F(C1)F(C2))F(C3)\textstyle{(F(C_{1})\otimes F(C_{2}))\otimes F(C_{3})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}μF(C3)\scriptstyle{\mu\otimes F(C_{3})}
    F(C1𝟙)\textstyle{F(C_{1}\otimes\mathbb{1})}F(C1)F(𝟙)\textstyle{F(C_{1})\otimes F(\mathbb{1})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}μ\scriptstyle{\mu}F(C1)\textstyle{F(C_{1})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}\scriptstyle{\sim}\scriptstyle{\wr}F(C1)𝟙.\textstyle{F(C_{1})\otimes\mathbb{1}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces.}F(C1)η\scriptstyle{F(C_{1})\otimes\eta}

    A lax (monoidal) functor is a functor equipped with a (typically suppressed) lax structure.

  2. (2)

    Suppose that 𝒞\mathcal{C} and 𝒟\mathcal{D} are symmetric monoidal. We say that the lax functor F:𝒞𝒟F:\mathcal{C}\to\mathcal{D} is symmetric if the following diagram commutes:

    F(C1C2)\textstyle{F(C_{1}\otimes C_{2})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}\scriptstyle{\sim}F(C2C1)\textstyle{F(C_{2}\otimes C_{1})}F(C1)F(C2)\textstyle{F(C_{1})\otimes F(C_{2})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}μ\scriptstyle{\mu}\scriptstyle{\sim}F(C2)F(C1).\textstyle{F(C_{2})\otimes F(C_{1})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces.}μ\scriptstyle{\mu}
  3. (3)

    Let F1F_{1} and F2F_{2} be lax functors. A natural transformation τ:F1F2\tau:F_{1}\to F_{2} is monoidal if the following diagrams commute:

    F1(C1C2)\textstyle{F_{1}(C_{1}\otimes C_{2})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}τ\scriptstyle{\tau}F2(C1C2)\textstyle{F_{2}(C_{1}\otimes C_{2})}F1(𝟙)\textstyle{F_{1}(\mathbb{1})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}τ\scriptstyle{\tau}F2(𝟙)\textstyle{F_{2}(\mathbb{1})}F1(C1)F1(C2)\textstyle{F_{1}(C_{1})\otimes F_{1}(C_{2})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}μ\scriptstyle{\mu}ττ\scriptstyle{\tau\otimes\tau}F2(C1)F2(C2)\textstyle{F_{2}(C_{1})\otimes F_{2}(C_{2})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}μ\scriptstyle{\mu}𝟙\textstyle{\mathbb{1}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}η\scriptstyle{\eta}η\scriptstyle{\eta}
  4. (4)

    A (symmetric) oplax structure on F:𝒞𝒟F:\mathcal{C}\to\mathcal{D} is a (symmetric) lax structure on FopF^{\mathrm{op}}.

It is immediate from the definitions that monoidality and symmetry is closed under composition; therefore, lax symmetric monoidal functors and monoidal natural transformations form a category Funlax(𝒞,𝒟)\mathrm{Fun}^{\mathrm{lax}}(\mathcal{C},\mathcal{D}). Likewise, we have the category Funoplax(𝒞,𝒟)=Funlax(𝒞op,𝒟op)op\mathrm{Fun}^{\mathrm{oplax}}(\mathcal{C},\mathcal{D})=\mathrm{Fun}^{\mathrm{lax}}(\mathcal{C}^{\mathrm{op}},\mathcal{D}^{\mathrm{op}})^{\mathrm{op}} of oplax symmetric monoidal functors. The reader should note that we do not reflect the condition of symmetry in the notation, since we will have no cause to consider nonsymmetric (op)lax functors.

Theorem 4.2.

Let 𝒞\mathcal{C} be a symmetric monoidal category and 𝒟\mathcal{D} a category with finite coproducts. There is a canonical isomorphism of categories

Fun(Pr(𝒞),𝒟)Funlax(𝒞,𝒟).\mathrm{Fun}(\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C}),\mathcal{D})\cong\mathrm{Fun}^{\mathrm{lax}}(\mathcal{C},\mathcal{D}).

In our application, it will be the dual version of this result that will be of most interest.

Corollary 4.3.

Let 𝒞\mathcal{C} be a symmetric monoidal category and 𝒟\mathcal{D} a category with finite products. There is a canonical isomorphism of categories

Fun(Pr(𝒞)op,𝒟)Funoplax(𝒞op,𝒟).\mathrm{Fun}(\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C})^{\mathrm{op}},\mathcal{D})\cong\mathrm{Fun}^{\mathrm{oplax}}(\mathcal{C}^{\mathrm{op}},\mathcal{D}).
Proof.

By our assumption on 𝒟\mathcal{D}, the opposite category 𝒟op\mathcal{D}^{\mathrm{op}} has finite coproducts, so Theorem 4.2 supplies the middle of the three isomorphisms of categories:

Fun(Pr(𝒞)op,𝒟)Fun(Pr(𝒞),𝒟op)opFunlax(𝒞,𝒟op)opFunoplax(𝒞op,𝒟).\mathrm{Fun}(\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C})^{\mathrm{op}},\mathcal{D})\cong\mathrm{Fun}(\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C}),\mathcal{D}^{\mathrm{op}})^{\mathrm{op}}\cong\mathrm{Fun}^{\mathrm{lax}}(\mathcal{C},\mathcal{D}^{\mathrm{op}})^{\mathrm{op}}\cong\mathrm{Fun}^{\mathrm{oplax}}(\mathcal{C}^{\mathrm{op}},\mathcal{D}).

We begin the proof of the theorem by observing that 𝒞\mathcal{C} is the source of a natural functor to its own projection category.

Lemma 4.4.

The assignments ι(C)=C\iota(C)=C and ι(C1C2)=[C1𝟙C1C2]\iota(C_{1}\to C_{2})=[C_{1}\otimes\mathbb{1}\cong C_{1}\to C_{2}] determine a functor ι:𝒞Pr(𝒞)\iota:\mathcal{C}\to\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C}).

Proof.

It is immediate that ι\iota preserves identities. For composition, we appeal to the commutative diagram

C1𝟙𝟙\textstyle{C_{1}\otimes\mathbb{1}\otimes\mathbb{1}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}\scriptstyle{\sim}\scriptstyle{\wr}C1𝟙\textstyle{C_{1}\otimes\mathbb{1}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}\scriptstyle{\wr}C2𝟙\textstyle{C_{2}\otimes\mathbb{1}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}\scriptstyle{\wr}\scriptstyle{\sim}C2\textstyle{C_{2}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}C1𝟙\textstyle{C_{1}\otimes\mathbb{1}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}\scriptstyle{\sim}C1\textstyle{C_{1}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}C2\textstyle{C_{2}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}C3\textstyle{C_{3}}

The composite in the bottom row represents ι(C1C2C3)\iota(C_{1}\to C_{2}\to C_{3}), while the full clockwise composite represents ι(C2C3)ι(C1C2)\iota(C_{2}\to C_{3})\circ\iota(C_{1}\to C_{2}). Since the leftmost vertical arrow is the identity of C1C_{1} tensored with the unitor, commutativity implies that the two complementary morphisms are equivalent, as desired. ∎

The equivalence of Theorem 4.2 will be given by restriction along the functor ι\iota of Lemma 4.4. The following result will allow us to make sense of this idea.

Lemma 4.5.

Let 𝒟\mathcal{D} be category with finite coproducts.

  1. (1)

    Given a functor G:Pr(𝒞)𝒟G:\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C})\to\mathcal{D}, the restriction ιG\iota^{*}G carries a canonical lax structure, which is symmetric.

  2. (2)

    Given a natural transformation τ:G1G2\tau:G_{1}\to G_{2} in Fun(Pr(𝒞),𝒟)\mathrm{Fun}(\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C}),\mathcal{D}), the restriction ιτ\iota^{*}\tau is monoidal.

Proof.

Since the unit in 𝒟\mathcal{D} is initial, we have the unique map 𝟙G(𝟙)\mathbb{1}\to G(\mathbb{1}). The identity and the symmetry of 𝒞\mathcal{C} determine complementary morphisms from C1C_{1} and C2C_{2} to C1C2C_{1}\otimes C_{2}, respectively. Applying GG and invoking the universal property of the coproduct in 𝒟\mathcal{D}, we obtain a family of maps of the form G(C1)G(C2)G(C1C2)G(C_{1})\sqcup G(C_{2})\to G(C_{1}\otimes C_{2}). The verification that these maps form a natural transformation, although straightforward, reveals a subtle asymmetry, which may at first be surprising; for this reason, we choose to include some details. The verification of the axioms of a symmetric lax structure and a monoidal natural transformation are left to the enthusiastic reader.

By the universal property of the coproduct, naturality in the first variable amounts to the commutativity of the diagrams obtained by applying GG to the following two diagrams in Pr(𝒞)\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C}):

C1\textstyle{C_{1}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}[C1C2=C1C2]\scriptstyle{[C_{1}\otimes C_{2}=C_{1}\otimes C_{2}]}[C1𝟙C1𝑓C1]\scriptstyle{[C_{1}\otimes\mathbb{1}\cong C_{1}\xrightarrow{f}C_{1}^{\prime}]}C1\textstyle{C_{1}^{\prime}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}[C1C2=C1C2]\scriptstyle{[C_{1}^{\prime}\otimes C_{2}=C_{1}^{\prime}\otimes C_{2}]}C1C2\textstyle{C_{1}\otimes C_{2}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}[C1C2𝟙C1C2fC2C1C2]\scriptstyle{[C_{1}\otimes C_{2}\otimes\mathbb{1}\cong C_{1}\otimes C_{2}\xrightarrow{f\otimes C_{2}}C_{1}^{\prime}\otimes C_{2}]}C1C2.\textstyle{C_{1}^{\prime}\otimes C_{2}.}
C2\textstyle{C_{2}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}[C2C1C1C2]\scriptstyle{[C_{2}\otimes C_{1}\cong C_{1}\otimes C_{2}]\qquad}[C2C1C1C2]\scriptstyle{\qquad[C_{2}\otimes C_{1}^{\prime}\cong C_{1}^{\prime}\otimes C_{2}]}C1C2\textstyle{C_{1}\otimes C_{2}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}[C1C2𝟙C1C2fC2C1C2]\scriptstyle{[C_{1}\otimes C_{2}\otimes\mathbb{1}\cong C_{1}\otimes C_{2}\xrightarrow{f\otimes C_{2}}C_{1}^{\prime}\otimes C_{2}]}C1C2\textstyle{C_{1}^{\prime}\otimes C_{2}}

The composites in the first diagram are represented by the respective rows of the following commutative diagram in 𝒞\mathcal{C}:

C1𝟙C2\textstyle{C_{1}\otimes\mathbb{1}\otimes C_{2}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}\scriptstyle{\wr}\scriptstyle{\sim}C1C2\textstyle{C_{1}\otimes C_{2}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}fC2\scriptstyle{f\otimes C_{2}}C1C2\textstyle{C_{1}^{\prime}\otimes C_{2}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}C1C2𝟙\textstyle{C_{1}\otimes C_{2}\otimes\mathbb{1}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}\scriptstyle{\sim}C1C2\textstyle{C_{1}\otimes C_{2}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}fC2\scriptstyle{f\otimes C_{2}}C1C2.\textstyle{C_{1}^{\prime}\otimes C_{2}.}

As indicated, the symmetry of 𝒞\mathcal{C} supplies an elementary equivalence between the two, establishing the desired commutativity. On other hand, the counterclockwise composite and righthand diagonal arrow in the second diagram are represented by the clockwise composite and bottom arrow, respectively, of the following commutative diagram in 𝒞\mathcal{C}:

C2C1𝟙\textstyle{C_{2}\otimes C_{1}\otimes\mathbb{1}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}\scriptstyle{\wr}\scriptstyle{\sim}C1C2𝟙\textstyle{C_{1}\otimes C_{2}\otimes\mathbb{1}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}\scriptstyle{\wr}C2C1\textstyle{C_{2}\otimes C_{1}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}C2f\scriptstyle{C_{2}\otimes f}\scriptstyle{\sim}C1C2\textstyle{C_{1}\otimes C_{2}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}fC2\scriptstyle{f\otimes C_{2}}C2C1\textstyle{C_{2}\otimes C_{1}^{\prime}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}\scriptstyle{\sim}C1C2.\textstyle{C_{1}^{\prime}\otimes C_{2}.}

The lefthand vertical composite gives a simple equivalence between the two, establishing the claim. Naturality in the second variable is similar. ∎

Note that the arrow providing the final simple equivlanece of this proof is in general not an isomorphism—see Remark 4.6 below.

Proof of Theorem 4.2.

Invoking Lemma 4.5, we obtain the (abusively named) functor

ι:Fun(Pr(𝒞),𝒟)Funlax(𝒞,𝒟),\iota^{*}:\mathrm{Fun}(\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C}),\mathcal{D})\to\mathrm{Fun}^{\mathrm{lax}}(\mathcal{C},\mathcal{D}),

which we claim to be an isomorphism. To prove this claim, we construct an inverse isomorphism explicitly. Given a symmetric lax functor F:𝒞𝒟F:\mathcal{C}\to\mathcal{D}, we define the value of F¯:Pr(𝒞)𝒟\overline{F}:\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C})\to\mathcal{D} on the equivalence class of f:C1DC2f:C_{1}\otimes D\to C_{2} to be the composite

F(C1)F(C1)F(D)𝜇F(C1D)F(f)F(C2).F(C_{1})\to F(C_{1})\sqcup F(D)\xrightarrow{\mu}F(C_{1}\otimes D)\xrightarrow{F(f)}F(C_{2}).

One checks immediately that this definition is independent of the choice of representative and that F¯\overline{F}, so defined, is a functor. To conclude, it suffices to verify that the objectwise identities ιG¯(C)=G(C)\overline{\iota^{*}G}(C)=G(C) and ιF¯(C)=F(C)\iota^{*}\overline{F}(C)=F(C) form a natural transformation and a monoidal natural transformation, respectively.

Unpacking the definitions, one finds that the value of ιG¯\overline{\iota^{*}G} on the equivalence class represented by C1DC2C_{1}\otimes D\to C_{2} is the value of GG on the equivalence class of the composite of C1D𝟙C1DC2C_{1}\otimes D\otimes\mathbb{1}\cong C_{1}\otimes D\to C_{2}, viewed as a complementary morphism with source C2DC_{2}\otimes D, with C1D=C1DC_{1}\otimes D=C_{1}\otimes D, viewed as a complementary morphism with source C1C_{1}. This composite is simply C1D𝟙C1DC2C_{1}\otimes D\otimes\mathbb{1}\cong C_{1}\otimes D\to C_{2}, viewed as a complementary morphism with source C1C_{1}, which is equivalent to our original complementary morphism via the unitor D𝟙DD\otimes\mathbb{1}\cong D. It follows that ιG¯=G\overline{\iota^{*}G}=G.

Similarly, one finds that the value of ιF¯\iota^{*}\overline{F} on a morphism C1C2C_{1}\to C_{2} is the composite in the top row of the diagram

F(C1)\textstyle{F(C_{1})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}\scriptstyle{\sim}F(C1)F(𝟙)\textstyle{F(C_{1})\sqcup F(\mathbb{1})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}μ\scriptstyle{\mu}F(C1𝟙)\textstyle{F(C_{1}\otimes\mathbb{1})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}\scriptstyle{\sim}F(C1)\textstyle{F(C_{1})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}F(C2)\textstyle{F(C_{2})}F(C1)𝟙\textstyle{F(C_{1})\sqcup\mathbb{1}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}F(C1)η\scriptstyle{F(C_{1})\sqcup\eta}\scriptstyle{\sim}

Since the diagram commutes by our assumption on FF, this composite is simply the value of FF on our original morphism. It follows that ιF¯=F\iota^{*}\overline{F}=F as bare functors, so it remains to verify that the two lax structures coincide. Since the unit in 𝒟\mathcal{D} is initial, the second diagram in the definition of a monoidal natural transformation commutes automatically. As for the first, it is an easy exercise to check that the lax structure morphism for ιF¯\iota^{*}\overline{F} produced by Lemma 4.5, as a morphism F(C1)F(C2)F(C1C2)F(C_{1})\sqcup F(C_{2})\to F(C_{1}\otimes C_{2}) in 𝒟\mathcal{D}, has the same components as μ\mu; we remark only that the argument uses the compatibility of μ\mu with the respective monoidal symmetries. The claim then follows from the universal property of the coproduct in 𝒟\mathcal{D}. ∎

Remark 4.6.

As our proof shows, the (rather curious) situation is that the universal property of Theorem 4.2 fails to hold for Quillen’s category not because one cannot define the desired lax monoidal structure maps, but rather because they do not form a natural transformation unless 𝒞\mathcal{C} is a groupoid. The coarser equivalence relation of Pr(𝒞)\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C}) is precisely what is needed to repair this defect.

Example 4.7.

We return to Example 2.7. By definition, the data of a functor from Δ1\Delta^{1} is that of an arrow f:XYf:X\to Y in the target, and our previous analysis shows that the data of an extension of this functor to Quillen’s construction is that of a retraction gg of ff. Assuming the target category to have finite coproducts, suppose that we are instead given the data of a lax monoidal structure on the functor in question. The composite arrow

g:YXYXg:Y\to X\sqcup Y\to X

is again a left inverse to ff, as is readily seen from the commutative diagram

XY\textstyle{X\sqcup Y\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}fY\scriptstyle{f\sqcup Y}YY\textstyle{Y\sqcup Y\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}Y\textstyle{\varnothing\sqcup Y\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}!Y\scriptstyle{!\sqcup Y}X\textstyle{X\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}f\scriptstyle{f}Y.\textstyle{Y.\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}\scriptstyle{\cong}

According to Example 2.7, the category Pr(Δ1)\mathrm{Pr}(\Delta^{1}) is the walking isomorphism, so we should expect that gg is also a right inverse; indeed, this fact follows easily from the commutative diagram

X\textstyle{\varnothing\sqcup X\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}!X\scriptstyle{!\sqcup X}XX\textstyle{X\sqcup X\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}Xf\scriptstyle{X\sqcup f}XY\textstyle{X\sqcup Y\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}X\textstyle{X\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}\scriptstyle{\cong}X.\textstyle{X.}

4.2. Day convolution

In this section, we consider two natural tensor product operations defined on functors between symmetric monoidal categories, the left and right Day convolution tensor products. With mild assumptions on the two categories, it is well known that left convolution determines a symmetric monoidal structure on the functor category. A game of opposites then gives conditions under which right convolution determines a symmetric monoidal structure. Although these conditions are significantly more restrictive, they are nevertheless applicable in our setting of interest.

Definition 4.8.

Let F,G:𝒞𝒟F,G:\mathcal{C}\to\mathcal{D} be functors. The left (resp. right) Day convolution tensor product of FF and GG is the left (resp. right) Kan extension FGF\otimes G in the diagram

𝒞×𝒞\textstyle{\mathcal{C}\times\mathcal{C}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}𝒞\scriptstyle{\otimes_{\mathcal{C}}}F×G\scriptstyle{F\times G}𝒟×𝒟\textstyle{\mathcal{D}\times\mathcal{D}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}𝒟\scriptstyle{\otimes_{\mathcal{D}}}𝒟\textstyle{\mathcal{D}}𝒞\textstyle{\mathcal{C}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}FG\scriptstyle{F\otimes G}

It should be emphasized that either convolution may fail to exist for some or all pairs of functors with fixed source and target. When the left convolution does exist, it is given explicitly by the formula

(FG)(C)=colim((𝒞C)𝒞×𝒞F×G𝒟×𝒟𝒟𝒟),(F\otimes G)(C)=\operatorname*{\mathrm{colim}}\left((\otimes_{\mathcal{C}}\downarrow C)\to\mathcal{C}\times\mathcal{C}\xrightarrow{F\times G}\mathcal{D}\times\mathcal{D}\xrightarrow{\otimes_{\mathcal{D}}}\mathcal{D}\right),

and similarly for right convolution. Mere existence, however, does not guarantee that convolution extends to a monoidal structure.

Theorem 4.9.

If 𝒟\mathcal{D} admits, and 𝒟\otimes_{\mathcal{D}} distributes over, colimits indexed by (𝒞C)(\otimes_{\mathcal{C}}\downarrow C) for every object C𝒞C\in\mathcal{C}, then left Day convolution extends to a canonical symmetric monoidal structure on Fun(𝒞,𝒟)\mathrm{Fun}(\mathcal{C},\mathcal{D}). In this case, there is a canonical isomorphism of categories

Funlax(𝒞,𝒟)AlgCom(Fun(𝒞,𝒟)).\mathrm{Fun}^{\mathrm{lax}}(\mathcal{C},\mathcal{D})\cong\mathrm{Alg}_{\mathrm{Com}}(\mathrm{Fun}(\mathcal{C},\mathcal{D})).

Although this result is essentially standard, it is typically stated with the unnecessarily strong assumption that 𝒟\otimes_{\mathcal{D}} distributes over all colimits. In the left handed setting, this assumption is almost always satisfied; it is in dualizing to the right handed setting in Corollary 4.12 that we require the weaker assumption. For these reasons, we have opted to include an outline of the proof—the reader may consult [8, 17, 27], for example, for further details.

Proof of Theorem 4.9.

The existence assumption grants that FGF\otimes G is defined for every FF and GG. A unit is supplied by the functor 𝟙Day\mathbb{1}_{\mathrm{Day}} given by the left Kan extension of the inclusion of 𝟙𝒟\mathbb{1}_{\mathcal{D}} along the inclusion of 𝟙𝒞\mathbb{1}_{\mathcal{C}}. Indeed, we claim that the left Kan extensions indicated by the dashed arrows are as claimed in the following diagrams:

𝒞\textstyle{\mathcal{C}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}(𝟙𝒟,F)\scriptstyle{(\mathbb{1}_{\mathcal{D}},F)}(𝟙𝒞,id)\scriptstyle{(\mathbb{1}_{\mathcal{C}},\mathrm{id})}𝒟×𝒟\textstyle{\mathcal{D}\times\mathcal{D}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}𝒟\scriptstyle{\otimes_{\mathcal{D}}}𝒟\textstyle{\mathcal{D}}𝒞\textstyle{\mathcal{C}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}F\scriptstyle{F}𝒟\textstyle{\mathcal{D}}𝒞×𝒞\textstyle{\mathcal{C}\times\mathcal{C}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}𝟙Day×F\scriptstyle{\mathbb{1}_{\mathrm{Day}}\times F}𝒞\scriptstyle{\otimes_{\mathcal{C}}}𝒞\textstyle{\mathcal{C}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}𝟙DayF\scriptstyle{\mathbb{1}_{\mathrm{Day}}\otimes F}𝒞\textstyle{\mathcal{C}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}F\scriptstyle{F}

For the righthand diagram, there is nothing to show, and the identification of the innermost Kan extension in the lefthand diagram is immediate from the definitions. Invoking our assumption on distributivity of 𝒟\otimes_{\mathcal{D}}, it follows that the outer left Kan extension is as indicated. We obtain a left unitor by observing that the left unitors of 𝒞\mathcal{C} and 𝒟\mathcal{D} give an isomorphism between the two diagrams, and similarly for a right unitor. The same considerations suffice to identify the left Kan extensions in the following diagram:

𝒞×𝒞×𝒞\textstyle{\mathcal{C}\times\mathcal{C}\times\mathcal{C}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}𝒞×id\scriptstyle{\otimes_{\mathcal{C}}\times\mathrm{id}}F1×F2×F3\scriptstyle{F_{1}\times F_{2}\times F_{3}}𝒟×𝒟×𝒟\textstyle{\mathcal{D}\times\mathcal{D}\times\mathcal{D}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}𝒟×id\scriptstyle{\otimes_{\mathcal{D}}\times\mathrm{id}}𝒟×𝒟\textstyle{\mathcal{D}\times\mathcal{D}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}𝒟\scriptstyle{\otimes_{\mathcal{D}}}𝒟\textstyle{\mathcal{D}}𝒞×𝒞\textstyle{\mathcal{C}\times\mathcal{C}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}𝒞\scriptstyle{\otimes_{\mathcal{C}}}F1F2×F3\scriptstyle{\quad F_{1}\otimes F_{2}\times F_{3}}𝒞\textstyle{\mathcal{C}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}(F1F2)F3\scriptstyle{\quad(F_{1}\otimes F_{2})\otimes F_{3}}

We obtain an associator after observing that the associators of 𝒞\mathcal{C} and 𝒟\mathcal{D} furnish an isomorphism between this diagram and the corresponding diagram for F1(F2F3)F_{1}\otimes(F_{2}\otimes F_{3}). The same approach furnishes a symmetry. The coherence axioms for Fun(𝒞,𝒟)\mathrm{Fun}(\mathcal{C},\mathcal{D}) follow directly from the coherence axioms for 𝒞\mathcal{C} and 𝒟\mathcal{D}, since each structure morphism in the former was built from the corresponding structure morphisms in the latter two.

Toward the final claim, we observe that, by the universal property of the colimit, a monoid structure on F:𝒞𝒟F:\mathcal{C}\to\mathcal{D} provides a compatible collection of maps F(C1)F(C2)F(C)F(C_{1})\otimes F(C_{2})\to F(C), one for each arrow C1C2CC_{1}\otimes C_{2}\to C. By specializing to the case C1C2=CC_{1}\otimes C_{2}=C, such a collection furnishes a collection of candidate components F(C1)F(C2)F(C1C2)F(C_{1})\otimes F(C_{2})\to F(C_{1}\otimes C_{2}) of a lax structure map. Conversely, a lax structure furnishes a candidate monoid structure map via the composites

F(C1)F(C2)F(C1C2)F(C).F(C_{1})\otimes F(C_{2})\to F(C_{1}\otimes C_{2})\to F(C).

Similar remarks apply to units, and it remains to verify that the associativity, symmetry, and unitality constraints of the two structures coincide, a task we leave to the reader. ∎

Before continuing we record a useful consequence of the proof.

Corollary 4.10.

If 𝒟\mathcal{D} admits, and 𝒟\otimes_{\mathcal{D}} distributes over, colimits indexed by (𝒞C)(\otimes_{\mathcal{C}}\downarrow C) for every object C𝒞C\in\mathcal{C}, then the left Day convolution tensor product i=1nFi\bigotimes_{i=1}^{n}F_{i} is canonically isomorphic to the left Kan extension in the diagram

𝒞n\textstyle{\mathcal{C}^{n}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}𝒞(n)\scriptstyle{\otimes_{\mathcal{C}}^{(n)}}(Fi)i=1n\scriptstyle{(F_{i})_{i=1}^{n}}𝒟n\textstyle{\mathcal{D}^{n}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}𝒟(n)\scriptstyle{\otimes_{\mathcal{D}}^{(n)}}𝒟\textstyle{\mathcal{D}}𝒞\textstyle{\mathcal{C}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}i=1nFi\scriptstyle{\otimes_{i=1}^{n}F_{i}}

The existence of the right convolution monoidal structure will rely on a technical condition on the structure of overcategories in 𝒞\mathcal{C}, which we refer to as sparsity. We record several other related technical conditions for later use. In the following definition, we view finite sets as discrete categories.

Definition 4.11.

Let CC be an object in the symmetric monoidal category 𝒞\mathcal{C}.

  1. (1)

    We say that CC is nn-separable if (𝒞(n)C)(\otimes_{\mathcal{C}}^{(n)}\downarrow C) receives a final functor from a finite set.

  2. (2)

    We say that CC is freely nn-separable if (𝒞(n)C)(\otimes_{\mathcal{C}}^{(n)}\downarrow C) receives a Σn\Sigma_{n}-equivariant final functor from a finite free Σn\Sigma_{n}-set.

  3. (3)

    We say that 𝒞\mathcal{C} is sparse if every object of 𝒞\mathcal{C} is 22-separable.

Corollary 4.12.

If 𝒞\mathcal{C} is a sparse symmetric monoidal category and 𝒟\mathcal{D} an additive tensor category, then right Day convolution extends to a canonical symmetric monoidal structure on Fun(𝒞op,𝒟)\mathrm{Fun}(\mathcal{C}^{\mathrm{op}},\mathcal{D}). In this case, there is a canonical isomorphism of categories

Funoplax(𝒞op,𝒟)CoalgCom(Fun(𝒞op,𝒟)).\mathrm{Fun}^{\mathrm{oplax}}(\mathcal{C}^{\mathrm{op}},\mathcal{D})\cong\mathrm{Coalg}_{\mathrm{Com}}(\mathrm{Fun}(\mathcal{C}^{\mathrm{op}},\mathcal{D})).
Proof.

In light of the isomorphism Fun(𝒞op,𝒟)Fun(𝒞,𝒟op)op\mathrm{Fun}(\mathcal{C}^{\mathrm{op}},\mathcal{D})\cong\mathrm{Fun}(\mathcal{C},\mathcal{D}^{\mathrm{op}})^{\mathrm{op}}, together with the fact that the formation of the opposite category interchanges limits and colimits, it suffices to show that 𝒞\mathcal{C} and 𝒟op\mathcal{D}^{\mathrm{op}} satisfy the hypotheses of Theorem 4.9. By sparsity, a colimit indexed by (𝒞C)(\otimes_{\mathcal{C}}\downarrow C) is simply a finite coproduct in 𝒟op\mathcal{D}^{\mathrm{op}}. The proof is complete upon observing that 𝒟op\mathcal{D}^{\mathrm{op}} is also an additive tensor category, since distributivity over finite coproducts is equivalent to distributivity over finite products by additivity. ∎

Remark 4.13.

The right convolution tensor product seems less well known than its sinistral cousin, perhaps due to the apparent restrictiveness of sparsity. We direct the reader to [24] for a prior instance of its use; one assumes that there are other antecedents, but none are known to the author.

4.3. Examples

In this section, we specialize the general theory of the preceding section to the examples of interest.

Given a collision structure SS on JJ and a function f:IJf:I\to J, we write fSf^{*}S for the largest collision structure on II for which ff is a map of collision structures, i.e.,

fS={PΠI:fPS}.f^{*}S=\{P\in\Pi_{I}:f_{*}P\in S\}.

It is easy to check that fSf^{*}S, so defined, is a collision structure; note, however, that it may be empty. In the case of the inclusion of a subset I0II_{0}\subseteq I, we write S|I0S|_{I_{0}}.

Example 4.14.

If S=SΓS=S_{\Gamma} is the collision structure associated to a graph Γ\Gamma with vertex set II according to Example 3.5, then SΓ|I0S_{\Gamma}|_{I_{0}} is the collision structure associated to the full subgraph spanned by I0I_{0}.

Example 4.15.

If S=SKS=S_{K} is the collision structure associated to a simplicial complex KK with vertex set II according to Example 3.6, then SK|I0S_{K}|_{I_{0}} is the collision structure associated to the full subcomplex spanned by I0I_{0}.

Write Surj(I,n)\mathrm{Surj}(I,n) for the set of surjections of II onto the set {1,,n}\{1,\ldots,n\}; in other words, Surj(I,n)\mathrm{Surj}(I,n) is the set of ordered partitions of II with nn blocks.

Lemma 4.16.

Let SS be a collision structure on II. For every n0n\geq 0, there is a canonical inclusion

Surj(I,n)(𝒞𝒮(n)S),\mathrm{Surj}(I,n)\subseteq(\sqcup_{\mathcal{CSB}}^{(n)}\downarrow S),

which is final if II is non-empty.

Proof.

We define the inclusion by sending pSurj(I,n)p\in\mathrm{Surj}(I,n) to the map j=1nS|p1(j)S\bigsqcup_{j=1}^{n}S|_{p^{-1}(j)}\to S of collision structures given by the canonical bijection j=1np1(j)I\bigsqcup_{j=1}^{n}p^{-1}(j)\cong I. Given collision structures SjS_{j} on the finite sets IjI_{j} and a bijective map f:j=1nSjSf:\bigsqcup_{j=1}^{n}S_{j}\to S of collision structures, define pf:I{1,,n}p_{f}:I\to\{1,\ldots,n\} by defining pf(i)p_{f}(i) to be the index jj such that if(Ij)i\in f(I_{j}); note that there is precisely one such index by bijectivity. Then pf1(j)=f(Sj)p_{f}^{-1}(j)=f(S_{j}), and we have the commutative diagram:

j=1nIj\textstyle{\displaystyle\bigsqcup_{j=1}^{n}I_{j}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}f\scriptstyle{f}j=1nf|Ij\scriptstyle{\bigsqcup_{j=1}^{n}f|_{I_{j}}}j=1npf1(j)\textstyle{\displaystyle\bigsqcup_{j=1}^{n}p_{f}^{-1}(j)\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}\scriptstyle{\cong}I\textstyle{I}

Finality follows upon noting that the components of the dashed arrow are uniquely determined by commutativity, each component is a map of collision structures, and no such dashed arrow exists for any ppfp\neq p_{f}. ∎

Corollary 4.17.

If SS is a collision structure on II, then SS is nn-separable as an object of 𝒞𝒮\mathcal{CSB} for every n0n\geq 0, freely if II is non-empty. In particular, 𝒞𝒮\mathcal{CSB} is sparse.

Proof.

Since Σn\Sigma_{n} acts freely on Surj(I,n)\mathrm{Surj}(I,n), Lemma 4.16 directly implies that any collision structure on a non-empty finite set is freely nn-separable for every n0n\geq 0. For the edge case, we note that (𝒞𝒮(n))(\sqcup_{\mathcal{CSB}}^{(n)}\downarrow\varnothing) is a singleton for every n0n\geq 0. ∎

Corollary 4.18.

A graph, a simplicial complex, or a finite set is nn-separable as an object of 𝒢\mathcal{GB}, 𝒮𝒞\mathcal{SCB}, or \mathcal{FB}, respectively, for every n0n\geq 0, freely if non-empty. In particular, all three categories are sparse.

Proof.

First, the inclusion of Surj(I,n)\mathrm{Surj}(I,n) of Lemma 4.16 factors through (𝒢(n)Γ)(\sqcup_{\mathcal{GB}}^{(n)}\downarrow\Gamma), (𝒮𝒞(n)K)(\sqcup_{\mathcal{SCB}}^{(n)}\downarrow K), or ((n)I)(\sqcup_{\mathcal{FB}}^{(n)}\downarrow I), respectively. For the first two, this claim follows from Examples 4.14 and 4.15, and for the third it is obvious. Since these three subcategories are full, each inclusion is also final. ∎

Combining these corollaries with Corollary 4.12, we see that it is sensible to contemplate right Day convolution in this context. Corollary 4.10 and Lemma 4.16 yield the following formula for this tensor product.

Corollary 4.19.

Let 𝒟\mathcal{D} be an additive tensor category. Given functors Fj:𝒞𝒮op𝒟F_{j}:\mathcal{CSB}^{\mathrm{op}}\to\mathcal{D} for 1jn1\leq j\leq n and a collision structure SS on II, there is a canonical natural isomorphism

(j=1nF)(S)I=j=1nIjj=1nF(S|Ij).\left(\bigotimes_{j=1}^{n}F\right)(S)\cong\bigoplus_{I=\bigsqcup_{j=1}^{n}I_{j}}\bigotimes_{j=1}^{n}F(S|_{I_{j}}).

Examining the proof of Corollary 4.18, we see that the same formula holds for 𝒢\mathcal{GB} and 𝒮𝒞\mathcal{SCB} (and \mathcal{FB}, of course). By Examples 4.14 and 4.15, this formula may be interpreted geometrically in terms of full subgraphs and full subcomplexes, respectively.

5. Twisted Koszul duality

The purpose of this section is to explain how the theory of Koszul duality between Lie algebras and cocommutative coalgebras extends to the twisted setting—see Theorem 5.15. Classically, this theory is developed under two key assumptions: first, that the ground ring is a field of characteristic zero; second, that the graded objects in question are sufficiently connected [12, 33]. These assumptions serve to guarantee the good behavior of divided powers—their homotopy invariance and nilpotence, respectively. In our setting, the same good behavior is guaranteed instead by the presence of a weighting with certain natural properties—see Section 5.1. Otherwise, the arguments are essentially identical, and we will at times allow ourselves a certain brevity.

We work throughout over a fixed ground field 𝔽\mathbb{F}, a limitation easily overcome by judicious assumptions of flatness.

5.1. Weights

In this section, we introduce a piece of extra structure that will serve as a substitute for connectivity and divisibility. In the next definition, we refer to Definition 4.11.

Definition 5.1.

Let 𝒞\mathcal{C} be a monoidal category.

  1. (1)

    A weighting of 𝒞\mathcal{C} is a lax monoidal functor w:𝒞0w:\mathcal{C}\to\mathbb{Z}_{\geq 0}. The value w(C)w(C) is the weight of CC. The pair (𝒞,w)(\mathcal{C},w) is a weighted monoidal category

  2. (2)

    A combinatorial monoidal category is a weighted monoidal category such that C𝒞C\in\mathcal{C} is freely nn-separable for every n0n\geq 0 whenever w(C)>0w(C)>0.

Concretely, a weighting amounts to the assignment of a non-negative integer w(C)w(C) to each C𝒞C\in\mathcal{C} such that the following inequalities hold for every C1,C2𝒞C_{1},C_{2}\in\mathcal{C}:

  1. (1)

    w(C1)w(C2)w(C_{1})\leq w(C_{2}) whenever Hom𝒞(C1,C2)\mathrm{Hom}_{\mathcal{C}}(C_{1},C_{2})\neq\varnothing

  2. (2)

    w(C1)+w(C2)w(C1C2)w(C_{1})+w(C_{2})\leq w(C_{1}\otimes C_{2}).

Example 5.2.

Recording the cardinality of a finite set determines a weighting of \mathcal{FB}, whence of 𝒞𝒮\mathcal{CSB}, 𝒢\mathcal{GB}, and 𝒮𝒞\mathcal{SCB}. By the results of Section 4.3, these weighted monoidal categories are combinatorial.

Definition 5.3.

Let 𝒞\mathcal{C} be a weighted monoidal category and 𝒟\mathcal{D} an additive tensor category. We say that a functor F:𝒞𝒟F:\mathcal{C}\to\mathcal{D} is concentrated in weight k\geq k if F(C)=0F(C)=0 whenever w(C)<kw(C)<k. If FF is concentrated in weight 1\geq 1, then we say that FF is reduced.

This definition is justified by the following simple result.

Lemma 5.4.

If 𝒟\mathcal{D} is an additive tensor category, then 𝒟\mathcal{D} admits a zero object 0, and 0D00\otimes D\cong 0 for every D𝒟D\in\mathcal{D}.

Proof.

Additivity guarantees the existence of the biproduct indexed by the empty set, which is to say a zero object. Second, since the tensor product of 𝒟\mathcal{D} distributes over finite coproducts, we have

0Dcolim(!𝒟)Dcolim(×𝒟!×id𝒟×𝒟𝒟)colim(!𝒟)0.0\otimes D\cong\operatorname*{\mathrm{colim}}\left(\varnothing\xrightarrow{!}\mathcal{D}\right)\otimes D\cong\operatorname*{\mathrm{colim}}\left(\varnothing\times\mathcal{D}\xrightarrow{!\times\mathrm{id}}\mathcal{D}\times\mathcal{D}\xrightarrow{\otimes}\mathcal{D}\right)\cong\operatorname*{\mathrm{colim}}\left(\varnothing\xrightarrow{!}\mathcal{D}\right)\cong 0.

The comparison to connectivity made above is justified by the following result.

Lemma 5.5.

Let 𝒞\mathcal{C} be a sparse weighted symmetric monoidal category. If Fi:𝒞op𝒟F_{i}:\mathcal{C}^{\mathrm{op}}\to\mathcal{D} is concentrated in weight ki\geq k_{i} for i{1,2}i\in\{1,2\}, then F1F2F_{1}\otimes F_{2} is concentrated in weight k1+k2\geq k_{1}+k_{2}.

Proof.

Let C𝒞C\in\mathcal{C} be an object with w(C)<k1+k2w(C)<k_{1}+k_{2}. From our assumption of sparsity and the definition of right Day convolution, there is a collection of arrows C1C2CC_{1}\otimes C_{2}\to C such that

(FG)(C)\displaystyle(F\otimes G)(C) C1C2CF1(C1)F2(C2)=0,\displaystyle\cong\bigoplus_{C_{1}\otimes C_{2}\to C}F_{1}(C_{1})\otimes F_{2}(C_{2})=0,

so it suffices to show that each summand vanishes. We have the inequality

k1+k2>w(C)w(C1C2)w(C1)+w(C2).k_{1}+k_{2}>w(C)\geq w(C_{1}\otimes C_{2})\geq w(C_{1})+w(C_{2}).

Since weights are non-negative, it follows that w(C1)<k1w(C_{1})<k_{1} or w(C2)<k2w(C_{2})<k_{2}, whence F1(C1)=0F_{1}(C_{1})=0 or F2(C2)=0F_{2}(C_{2})=0.∎

The comparison to divisibility made above is justified by the following result.

Lemma 5.6.

Let 𝒞\mathcal{C} be a combinatorial symmetric monoidal category and τ:F1F2\tau:F_{1}\to F_{2} a natural transformation between reduced functors from 𝒞op\mathcal{C}^{\mathrm{op}} to the category of chain complexes in an Abelian tensor category. If τ\tau is a quasi-isomorphism in weight <n<n, then Γk(τ)\Gamma^{k}(\tau) is a quasi-isomorphism in weight <n+k1<n+k-1 for every k>0k>0. In particular, if k>1k>1, then Γk(τ)\Gamma^{k}(\tau) is a quasi-isomorphism in weight n\leq n.

Proof.

Fix C𝒞C\in\mathcal{C} with w(C)<n+k1w(C)<n+k-1. If w(C)=0w(C)=0, then Tk(Fi)(C)=0T^{k}(F_{i})(C)=0 by Lemma 5.5, and there is nothing to show, so assume otherwise. Then CC is freely nn-separable by our assumption on 𝒞\mathcal{C}, so Corollary 4.10 grants the existence of a finite, Σk\Sigma_{k}-free set {fr:C1,rCk,rC}\{f_{r}:C_{1,r}\otimes\cdots\otimes C_{k,r}\to C\} of morphisms such that

Tk(Fi)(C)rj=1kFi(Cj,r)T^{k}(F_{i})(C)\cong\bigoplus_{r}\bigotimes_{j=1}^{k}F_{i}(C_{j,r})

compatibly with Tk(τ)T^{k}(\tau). Since the FiF_{i} are reduced, we may assume without loss of generality that w(Cj,r)>0w(C_{j,r})>0 for every jj and rr. It then follows from the inequality

n+k1>w(C)j=1kw(Cj,r)n+k-1>w(C)\geq\sum_{j=1}^{k}w(C_{j,r})

that w(Cj,r)<nw(C_{j,r})<n for every jj and rr. By assumption, τCj,r\tau_{C_{j,r}} is a quasi-isomorphism, so Tk(Fi)(C)T^{k}(F_{i})(C) is a quasi-isomorphism. By freeness, this quasi-isomorphism descends to a quasi-isomorphism on Σk\Sigma_{k}-invariants, completing the proof. ∎

Remark 5.7.

In a previous version of this paper, Lemma 5.6 was stated with the weaker bound only. We thank the referee for pointing out that the proof establishes the improved bound.

5.2. Twisted (co)algebraic structures

We come now to the main definitions.

Definition 5.8.

Let 𝒞\mathcal{C} be a sparse symmetric monoidal category. A 𝒞\mathcal{C}-twisted Lie algebra (over 𝔽\mathbb{F}) is a Lie algebra in Fun(𝒞op,𝒞h𝔽)\mathrm{Fun}(\mathcal{C}^{\mathrm{op}},\mathcal{C}\mathrm{h}_{\mathbb{F}}), regarded as symmetric monoidal under right Day convolution.

Similarly, one has the notion of a 𝒞\mathcal{C}-twisted cocommutative coalgebra, and so on. In the case 𝒞=\mathcal{C}=\mathcal{FB}, one recovers the classical notion of a twisted (co)algebraic structure.

Remark 5.9.

As the reader may know, the term “Lie algebra” has several inequivalent definitions. Ultimately, we will specialize to a setting in which all such definitions coincide, so the reader is welcome to imagine that her favorite definition is also ours.

Given a 𝒞\mathcal{C}-twisted cocommutative coalgebra KK, we write K¯\overline{K} for the kernel of the counit K𝟙K\to\mathbb{1}.

Lemma 5.10.

Let LL be a 𝒞\mathcal{C}-twisted Lie algebra and KK a 𝒞\mathcal{C}-twisted cocommutative coalgebra.

  1. (1)

    The unique degree 1-1 coderivation CE\partial_{\mathrm{CE}} of Γ(L[1])\Gamma(L[1]) extending the composite

    Γ(L[1])[1]Γ2(L[1])[1][,][1]L[1]\Gamma(L[1])[-1]\to\Gamma^{2}(L[1])[-1]\xrightarrow{[-,-][1]}L[1]

    squares to zero.

  2. (2)

    The unique degree 1-1 derivation Q\partial_{\mathrm{Q}} of Lie(K¯[1])\mathrm{Lie}(\overline{K}[-1]) extending the composite

    K¯[1]Δ[1]Lie2(K¯[1])[1]Lie(K¯[1])[1]\overline{K}[-1]\xrightarrow{\Delta[-1]}\mathrm{Lie}^{2}(\overline{K}[-1])[1]\subseteq\mathrm{Lie}(\overline{K}[-1])[1]

    squares to zero.

Proof.

We give only a brief outline, the proof being entirely parallel to the corresponding portions of [12, IV.22(b),(e)]. For the first claim, since the square of a coderivation of odd degree is again a coderivation, and since Γ(L[1])\Gamma(L[1]) is cofree (as a conilpotent cocommutative coalgebra), it suffices to verify that the composite

Γ3(L[1])[2]Γ2(L[1])[1]L[1]\Gamma^{3}(L[1])[-2]\to\Gamma^{2}(L[1])[-1]\to L[1]

vanishes, which is equivalent to the Jacobi identity. The proof of the second claim is essentially the same save that we appeal instead to coassociativity. ∎

This result permits the following fundamental definition.

Definition 5.11.

Let LL be a 𝒞\mathcal{C}-twisted Lie algebra and KK a 𝒞\mathcal{C}-twisted cocommutative coalgebra.

  1. (1)

    The Chevalley–Eilenberg complex of LL is the 𝒞\mathcal{C}-twisted graded cocommutative coalgebra

    CE(L)=(Γ(L[1]),CE+L).\mathrm{CE}(L)=(\Gamma(L[1]),\partial_{\mathrm{CE}}+\partial_{L}).

    Its homology is called the Lie algebra homology of LL and denoted HLie(L)H_{*}^{\mathrm{Lie}}(L).

  2. (2)

    The Quillen complex of KK is the 𝒞\mathcal{C}-twisted graded Lie algebra

    Q(K)=(Lie(K¯[1]),Q+K).\mathrm{Q}(K)=(\mathrm{Lie}(\overline{K}[-1]),\partial_{\mathrm{Q}}+\partial_{K}).
Remark 5.12.

Some readers may be surprised at the appearance of divided powers rather than symmetric powers in the Chevalley–Eilenberg complex. The two coincide in characteristic zero, and more generally in any setting in which the norm map is an isomorphism on tensor powers (as it will be below).

These two complexes are closely interrelated.

Lemma 5.13.

Let LL be a 𝒞\mathcal{C}-twisted Lie algebra and KK a 𝒞\mathcal{C}-twisted cocommutative coalgebra.

  1. (1)

    The map η:KCE(Q(K))\eta:K\to\mathrm{CE}(\mathrm{Q}(K)) of 𝒞\mathcal{C}-twisted coalgebras induced by the inclusion ι:K¯K¯[1][1]Q(K)[1]\iota:\overline{K}\cong\overline{K}[-1][1]\subseteq\mathrm{Q}(K)[1] is a chain map.

  2. (2)

    The map ϵ:Q(CE(L))L\epsilon:\mathrm{Q}(\mathrm{CE}(L))\to L of 𝒞\mathcal{C}-twisted Lie algebras induced by the projection π:CE(L)[1]L[1][1]L\pi:\mathrm{CE}(L)[-1]\to L[1][-1]\cong L is a chain map.

Proof.

Again, we give only a brief outline, as the details are parallel to the relevant portions of the proof of [12, Thm. 22.9]. Writing δ1\delta_{1} and δ2\delta_{2}, respectively, for the clockwise and counterclockwise composites in the diagram

K¯\textstyle{\overline{K}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}K\scriptstyle{\partial_{K}}η\scriptstyle{\eta}CE(Q(K))\textstyle{\mathrm{CE}(\mathrm{Q}(K))\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}CE+Q(K)\scriptstyle{\partial_{\mathrm{CE}}+\partial_{\mathrm{Q}(K)}}K¯\textstyle{\overline{K}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}η\scriptstyle{\eta}CE(Q(K)),\textstyle{\mathrm{CE}(\mathrm{Q}(K)),}

the first claim is the equality δ1=δ2\delta_{1}=\delta_{2}. Since η\eta is a map of coalgebras, the δi\delta_{i} are coderivations; therefore, since CE(Q(K))\mathrm{CE}(\mathrm{Q}(K)) is cofree, it suffices to check that the composite

K¯δiCE(Q(K))𝜋Q(K)[1]\overline{K}\xrightarrow{\delta_{i}}\mathrm{CE}(\mathrm{Q}(K))\xrightarrow{\pi}\mathrm{Q}(K)[1]

is independent of ii, which is essentially a tautology. The proof of the second claim is similar. ∎

5.3. Duality

In order to state the main result, we require one further definition.

Definition 5.14.

Let 𝒞\mathcal{C} be a sparse weighted symmetric monoidal category. We say that a 𝒞\mathcal{C}-twisted Lie algebra is reduced if its underlying functor is so. We say that a 𝒞\mathcal{C}-twisted cocommutative coalgebra KK is reduced if K¯\overline{K} is so.

The goal of this section is to prove the following analogue of [12, Thm. 22.9].

Theorem 5.15.

If 𝒞\mathcal{C} is combinatorial, then the maps η\eta and ϵ\epsilon are quasi-isomorphisms on reduced objects.

The main ingredients are the following two lemmas.

Lemma 5.16.

If 𝒞\mathcal{C} is combinatorial, then the Chevalley–Eilenberg complex preserves and reflects quasi-isomorphisms between reduced 𝒞\mathcal{C}-twisted Lie algebras.

Proof.

Let φ:L1L2\varphi:L_{1}\to L_{2} be a map of 𝒞\mathcal{C}-twisted Lie algebras. Assuming that φ\varphi is a quasi-isomorphism, Lemma 5.6 grants that Γk(φ[1])\Gamma^{k}(\varphi[1]) is also a quasi-isomorphism for every k0k\geq 0. Filtering the Chevalley–Eilenberg complex by tensor degree, we conclude that φ\varphi induces a quasi-isomorphism at the level of associated graded complexes. By induction and the five lemma, it follows that CE(φ)\mathrm{CE}(\varphi) is a quasi-isomorphism after restriction to any filtration stage; therefore, since direct limits preserve quasi-isomorphisms, CE(φ)\mathrm{CE}(\varphi) itself is a quasi-isomorphism.

For reflection, we adapt the argument of [14, 4.1.9]. Assuming that CE(φ)\mathrm{CE}(\varphi) is a quasi-isomorphism, let C𝒞C\in\mathcal{C} be of minimal weight such that φC\varphi_{C} is not a quasi-isomorphism. Since the LiL_{i} are reduced, we have n:=w(C)>0n:=w(C)>0. Setting Ri:=coker(Li[1]CE(Li))R_{i}:=\operatorname*{\mathrm{coker}}(L_{i}[1]\to\mathrm{CE}(L_{i})), we have the following commutative diagram of chain complexes with exact rows:

0\textstyle{0\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}L1(C)[1]\textstyle{L_{1}(C)[1]\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}φC[1]\scriptstyle{\varphi_{C}[1]}CE(L1)(C)\textstyle{\mathrm{CE}(L_{1})(C)\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}CE(φ)C\scriptstyle{\mathrm{CE}(\varphi)_{C}}R1(C)\textstyle{R_{1}(C)\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}0\textstyle{0}0\textstyle{0\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}L2(C)[1]\textstyle{L_{2}(C)[1]\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}CE(L2)(C)\textstyle{\mathrm{CE}(L_{2})(C)\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}R2(C)\textstyle{R_{2}(C)\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}0.\textstyle{0.}

It suffices to show that the righthand vertical arrow is a quasi-isomorphism; indeed, since the middle arrow is a quasi-isomorphism by assumption, the five lemma then implies that the lefthand arrow is a quasi-isomorphism, a contradiction. To this end, we filter RiR_{i} by tensor degree, as above, and observe that the associated graded pieces are of the form Γk(Li[1])\Gamma^{k}(L_{i}[1]) for k>1k>1. By minimality, φ\varphi is a quasi-isomorphism in weight <n<n, so Lemma 5.6 implies that Γk(Li[1])\Gamma^{k}(L_{i}[1]) is a quasi-isomorphism in weight n\leq n for k>1k>1. In particular, the righthand vertical arrow above induces a quasi-isomorphism at the level of associated graded complexes, and the same argument as before completes the proof. ∎

Lemma 5.17.

The projection ρ:CE(Lie(V))V[1]𝟙\rho:\mathrm{CE}(\mathrm{Lie}(V))\to V[1]\oplus\mathbb{1} is a quasi-isomorphism.

Proof.

Since adjunctions compose, the universal enveloping algebra of Lie(V)\mathrm{Lie}(V) is the tensor algebra T(V)T(V); therefore, the homology of the Chevalley–Eilenberg complex is canonically isomorphic to TorT(V)(𝟙,𝟙)\mathrm{Tor}_{*}^{T(V)}(\mathbb{1},\mathbb{1}), which may be computed from the two-step complex T(V)VT(V)T(V)\otimes V\to T(V). The claim follows immediately. ∎

With these results in hand, we complete the proof.

Proof of Theorem 5.15.

Filtering Q(K)\mathrm{Q}(K) by bracket length, the associated graded Lie algebra is Lie(K¯[1])\mathrm{Lie}(\overline{K}[-1]), and the induced filtration on CE(Q(K))\mathrm{CE}(\mathrm{Q}(K)) has associated graded object CE(Lie(K[1]))\mathrm{CE}(\mathrm{Lie}(K[-1])). The composite

K¯gr(η)CE(Lie(K¯[1]))𝜌K¯\overline{K}\xrightarrow{\mathrm{gr}(\eta)}\mathrm{CE}(\mathrm{Lie}(\overline{K}[-1]))\xrightarrow{\rho}\overline{K}

is the identity, and ρ\rho is a quasi-isomorphism by Lemma 5.17, so gr(η)\mathrm{gr}(\eta) is also a quasi-isomorphism. It follows as before that η\eta is a quasi-isomorphism. It is easy to check that CE(ϵ)η=id\mathrm{CE}(\epsilon)\circ\eta=\mathrm{id}, so it follows that CE(ϵ)\mathrm{CE}(\epsilon) is a quasi-isomorphism, and Lemma 5.16 implies that ϵ\epsilon is also a quasi-isomorphism. ∎

Remark 5.18.

In classical operadic Koszul duality [26], the cobar construction (playing the role of the Quillen complex) fails to preserve quasi-isomorphisms in general, so one obtains instead an equivalence between standard homotopy theory on the algebra side and a nonstandard homotopy theory on the coalgebra side. From this point of view, the main point of this section is that Q\mathrm{Q} does preserve quasi-isomorphisms in our setting, which is the essential content of the reflection clause of Lemma 5.16.

6. Projection spaces

We arrive at last at our primary object of study. After cataloguing examples of projection spaces of interest, we define the functor of rational primitives and prove Theorems 1.2 and 1.3 as stated in the introduction.

6.1. Examples

We recall that, according to Definition 1.1, a projection space (over 𝒞\mathcal{C}) is a topological presheaf on Pr(𝒞)\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C}). We begin with the most basic example.

Example 6.1.

Viewing a finite set as a discrete topological space defines a functor 𝒯op\mathcal{FI}\to\mathcal{T}\mathrm{op}. By restriction along this functor, any presheaf of spaces on 𝒯op\mathcal{T}\mathrm{op} determines a projection space over \mathcal{FB} (recall Proposition 2.8); in particular, this construction applies to the representable presheaf Map(,X)\mathrm{Map}(-,X) for any topological space XX. Under the identification Map(I,X)XI\mathrm{Map}(I,X)\cong X^{I}, one checks that the structure map associated to the injection f:IJf:I\to J is the projection πf:XJXI\pi_{f}:X^{J}\to X^{I}, whose iith component is the projection onto the factor of XJX^{J} indexed by f(i)f(i).

Although this example is rather uninteresting, it gives rise to the main motivating example.

Example 6.2.

Given a finite set, the configuration space of II-indexed points in XX is defined as the subspace ConfI(X)XI\mathrm{Conf}_{I}(X)\subseteq X^{I} of injective functions IXI\to X. Since the restriction of an injection along an injection is again an injection, the dashed filler exists in the diagram

ConfJ(X)\textstyle{\mathrm{Conf}_{J}(X)\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}XJ\textstyle{X^{J}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}πf\scriptstyle{\pi_{f}}ConfI(X)\textstyle{\mathrm{Conf}_{I}(X)\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}XI,\textstyle{X^{I},}

so the collection of all such configuration spaces inherits the structure of a projection space over \mathcal{FB}.

The next two examples generalize the previous two in the presence of an action by a group GG.

Example 6.3.

Applying the considerations of Example 6.1 to the inclusion G𝒯opG\mathcal{FI}_{G}\to\mathcal{T}\mathrm{op}_{G} and the functor MapG(,X)\mathrm{Map}_{G}(-,X) represented by the GG-space XX, we obtain a projection space over G\mathcal{FB}_{G} (recall Corollary 2.10). Concretely, the value of this projection space on the finite free GG-set II is XI0X^{I_{0}}, where we have written IG×I0I\cong G\times I_{0} non-canonically. The structure maps combine the action of GG with the projections of Example 6.1.

Example 6.4.

Given a finite free GG-set II, the orbit configuration space of II-indexed points in XX is defined as the subspace ConfIG(X)MapG(I,X)\mathrm{Conf}_{I}^{G}(X)\subseteq\mathrm{Map}_{G}(I,X) of injective equivariant functions. Equivalently, writing IG×I0I\cong G\times I_{0} (non-canonically), the orbit configuration space is the subspace of XI0X^{I_{0}} consisting of tuples with pairwise disjoint orbits, i.e., it is the pullback

ConfIG(X)\textstyle{\mathrm{Conf}_{I}^{G}(X)\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}XI0\textstyle{X^{I_{0}}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}ConfI0(XG)\textstyle{\mathrm{Conf}_{I_{0}}(X_{G})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}(XG)I0.\textstyle{(X_{G})^{I_{0}}.}

Since equivariant injections are closed under composition, the first description endows the collection of orbit configuration spaces with the structure of a projection space over G\mathcal{FB}_{G}.

There is also a linear analogue of these examples. We fix a topological field 𝔽\mathbb{F}, the cases of \mathbb{R} and \mathbb{C} being of greatest interest.

Example 6.5.

By restricting along the inclusion of 𝒱𝔽\mathcal{VI}_{\mathbb{F}} into the category of topological vector spaces, a presheaf of spaces on the latter determines a projection space over 𝒱𝔽\mathcal{VB}_{\mathbb{F}} (recall Corollary 2.10); in particular this construction applies to the representable presheaf Hom𝔽(,W)\mathrm{Hom}_{\mathbb{F}}(-,W) for any topological vector space WW. Since the restriction of an injection along an injection is again an injection, the dashed filler exists in the diagram

Vn(W)\textstyle{V_{n}(W)\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}Hom𝔽(𝔽n,W)\textstyle{\mathrm{Hom}_{\mathbb{F}}(\mathbb{F}^{n},W)\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}φ\scriptstyle{\varphi^{\vee}}Vm(W)\textstyle{V_{m}(W)\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}Hom𝔽(𝔽m,W),\textstyle{\mathrm{Hom}_{\mathbb{F}}(\mathbb{F}^{m},W),}

where Vn(W)V_{n}(W) denotes the space of linear injections of 𝔽n\mathbb{F}^{n} into WW, which is simply the usual non-compact Stiefel manifold of nn-frames in the real or complex case.

Remark 6.6.

One imagines that our framework expands easily to encompass algebrogeometric examples such as flag varieties in positive characteristic.

Given a partition PP of II, we write ΔP={(xi)iI:i1Pi2xi1=xi2}\Delta_{P}=\{(x_{i})_{i\in I}:i_{1}\sim_{P}i_{2}\implies x_{i_{1}}=x_{i_{2}}\}. Given a collision structure SS on II, we set ΔS=PSΔP\Delta_{S}=\bigcup_{P\in S}\Delta_{P} and define the generalized configuration space [32] associated to SS as

ConfS(X)=XIΔS.\mathrm{Conf}_{S}(X)=X^{I}\setminus\Delta_{S}.

Notice that, if PPP\leq P^{\prime}, then ΔPΔP\Delta_{P^{\prime}}\subseteq\Delta_{P}, so ΔS=PS0ΔP\Delta_{S}=\bigcup_{P\in S_{0}}\Delta_{P} for any generating set S0SS_{0}\subseteq S.

Lemma 6.7.

Let SS and TT be collision structures on II and JJ, respectively, and f:IJf:I\to J an injective map of collision structures. The dashed filler exists in the diagram

ConfT(X)\textstyle{\mathrm{Conf}_{T}(X)\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}XJ\textstyle{X^{J}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}πf\scriptstyle{\pi_{f}}ConfS(X)\textstyle{\mathrm{Conf}_{S}(X)\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}XI.\textstyle{X^{I}.}
Proof.

By our assumption on ff, we have the containment ΔfSΔT\Delta_{f_{*}S}\subseteq\Delta_{T}. On the other hand, we calculate that

πf1(ΔS)\displaystyle\pi_{f}^{-1}(\Delta_{S}) =PSπf1(ΔP)\displaystyle=\bigcup_{P\in S}\pi_{f}^{-1}(\Delta_{P})
=PS{(xj)jJ:i1Pi2xf(i1)=xf(i2)}\displaystyle=\bigcup_{P\in S}\{(x_{j})_{j\in J}:i_{1}\sim_{P}i_{2}\implies x_{f(i_{1})}=x_{f(i_{2})}\}
=PS{(xj)jJ:f(i1)Pf(i2)xf(i1)=xf(i2)}\displaystyle=\bigcup_{P\in S}\{(x_{j})_{j\in J}:f(i_{1})\sim_{P}f(i_{2})\implies x_{f(i_{1})}=x_{f(i_{2})}\}
=PS{(xj)jJ:j1fPj2xj1=xj2}\displaystyle=\bigcup_{P\in S}\{(x_{j})_{j\in J}:j_{1}\sim_{f_{*}P}j_{2}\implies x_{j_{1}}=x_{j_{2}}\}
=PSΔfP\displaystyle=\bigcup_{P\in S}\Delta_{f_{*}P}
=ΔfS,\displaystyle=\Delta_{f_{*}S},

where the last equality uses that {fP:PS}\{f_{*}P:P\in S\} is a generating set for fSf_{*}S by definition. Thus, we have the containment ConfT(X)XJπf1(ΔS)=πf1(ConfS(X))\mathrm{Conf}_{T}(X)\subseteq X^{J}\setminus\pi_{f}^{-1}(\Delta_{S})=\pi_{f}^{-1}(\mathrm{Conf}_{S}(X)), as desired. ∎

Example 6.8.

Pulling the projection space IXII\mapsto X^{I} of Example 6.1 back along the forgetful functor from collision structures to finite sets, we obtain a projection space over 𝒞𝒮\mathcal{CSB} with the same values. Invoking Lemma 6.7, we obtain a projection space over 𝒞𝒮\mathcal{CSB} extending the assignment SConfS(X)S\mapsto\mathrm{Conf}_{S}(X) on objects.

Remark 6.9.

There is an obvious common generalization of Examples 6.4 and 6.8, which one would likely dub a generalized orbit configuration space. The ensemble of such also forms a projection space, where one would likely dub the relevant combinatorial object a GG-collision structure.

Example 6.10.

Restricting the projection space of Example 6.8 to 𝒢\mathcal{GI}, we obtain a projection space over 𝒢\mathcal{GB} extending the assignment ΓConfSΓ(X)\Gamma\mapsto\mathrm{Conf}_{S_{\Gamma}}(X) on objects.

Example 6.11.

Restricting the projection space of Example 6.8 to 𝒮𝒞\mathcal{SCI}, we obtain a projection space over 𝒮𝒞\mathcal{SCB} extending the assignment KConfSK(X)K\mapsto\mathrm{Conf}_{S_{K}}(X) on objects.

As the reader will easily verify, all of the examples of projection spaces given in this section are reduced.

6.2. Proofs of the main results

In the following definition, the reader may take the functor AA_{*} to be any symmetric replacement for the oplax monoidal functor rational singular chains. A specific example of such a replacement is given below in Appendix A.

Definition 6.12.

Let 𝒞\mathcal{C} be a sparse symmetric monoidal category and XX a projection space over 𝒞\mathcal{C}. The 𝒞\mathcal{C}-twisted Lie algebra of (derived) rational primitives of XX is the value on XX of the composite functor

L:Fun(Pr(𝒞)op,𝒯op)\textstyle{L:\mathrm{Fun}(\mathrm{Pr}(\mathcal{C})^{\mathrm{op}},\mathcal{T}\mathrm{op})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}(4.3)\scriptstyle{(\ref{cor:translation equivalence})}Funoplax(𝒞op,𝒯op)\textstyle{\mathrm{Fun}^{\mathrm{oplax}}(\mathcal{C}^{\mathrm{op}},\mathcal{T}\mathrm{op})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}A\scriptstyle{A_{*}}Funoplax(𝒞op,𝒞h)\textstyle{\mathrm{Fun}^{\mathrm{oplax}}(\mathcal{C}^{\mathrm{op}},\mathcal{C}\mathrm{h}_{\mathbb{Q}})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}(4.12)\scriptstyle{(\ref{cor:right convolution})}CoalgCom(Fun(𝒞op,𝒞h))\textstyle{\mathrm{Coalg}_{\mathrm{Com}}(\mathrm{Fun}(\mathcal{C}^{\mathrm{op}},\mathcal{C}\mathrm{h}_{\mathbb{Q}}))\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}Q\scriptstyle{\mathrm{Q}}AlgLie(Fun(𝒞op,𝒞h)).\textstyle{\mathrm{Alg}_{\mathrm{Lie}}(\mathrm{Fun}(\mathcal{C}^{\mathrm{op}},\mathcal{C}\mathrm{h}_{\mathbb{Q}})).}
Proof of Theorem 1.2.

Since the isomorphisms of Corollaries 4.3 and 4.12 do not change the underlying functor, we have

HLie(L(X))\displaystyle H_{*}^{\mathrm{Lie}}(L(X)) =H(CE(Q(A(X))))\displaystyle=H_{*}(\mathrm{CE}(\mathrm{Q}(A_{*}(X))))
H(A(X))\displaystyle\cong H_{*}(A_{*}(X))
H(X;)\displaystyle\cong H_{*}(X;\mathbb{Q})

by Theorem 5.15 and Corollary A.5. ∎

We turn now to stability. The prevailing philosophy that has emerged in the wake of the discovery of representation stability is that stability phenomena are the concrete consequences of finite generation results, representation stability itself being equivalent to finite generation over \mathcal{FI} [6]. Prerequisitely, then, one requires an action.

A feature of the Chevalley–Eilenberg complex is that it is a symmetric monoidal functor, converting products into tensor products. Thus, as explained at greater length in [25], a central Lie subalgebra L0LL_{0}\subseteq L gives rise to an action of Γ(L0[1])\Gamma(L_{0}[1]) on Lie algebra homology, while an Abelian quotient LL1L\to L_{1} gives rise to an action of Sym(L1[1])\mathrm{Sym}(L_{1}[1]) on Lie algebra cohomology. Through Theorem 1.2, these two constructions give rise to a host of actions on the (co)homology of a projection space, each a potential source of stability phenomena.

Remark 6.13.

In the case 𝒞=0\mathcal{C}=\mathbb{Z}_{\geq 0}, as shown in [25], these two types of action are united in the action of a single algebra, called a transit algebra. It is less clear how to describe their interaction in general, especially when 𝒞\mathcal{C} is not a groupoid.

We now show that this potential is often realized in the classical case 𝒞=\mathcal{C}=\mathcal{FB}. A functor from this category (or its opposite) is a symmetric sequence, i.e., a list of objects indexed by the non-negative integers (their weights), together with a Σk\Sigma_{k}-action on the kkth object for each k0k\geq 0. We indicate the weight with a subscript, and we write V(1)V(1) for the symmetric sequence with V(1)1=VV(1)_{1}=V and V(1)k=0V(1)_{k}=0 for k1k\neq 1.

Theorem 6.14.

If XX is a reduced op\mathcal{FI}^{\mathrm{op}}-space, then H(X)H^{*}(X) is canonically a Sym(H0(X1)(1))\mathrm{Sym}(H^{0}(X_{1})(1))-module. This module is finitely generated provided L(X)(X) satisfies the following conditions.

  1. (1)

    Hi(L(X)k)H_{i}(L(X)_{k}) is finite dimensional for every i0i\geq 0 and k0k\geq 0.

  2. (2)

    H1(L(X)k)=0H_{-1}(L(X)_{k})=0 for k>1k>1 and Hi(L(X))=0H_{i}(L(X))=0 for i<1i<-1.

  3. (3)

    Hi(L(X)k)=0H_{i}(L(X)_{k})=0 for ii fixed and kk sufficiently large.

It is well known that representation stability is equivalent to finite generation over the free twisted commutative algebra on a single generator in degree 0 and weight 11, so Theorem 1.3 is a special case of this result. In general, the finite generation of the theorem implies a kind of generalized representation stability [34].

Remark 6.15.

We briefly contextualize the assumptions of the theorem. The third assumption is that L(X)L(X) is eventually highly connected; one should view this assumption, which resembles standard hypotheses in the study of homological stability, as the key assumption. The first assumption is simply that each component space is of finite type, as will be the case in most examples of interest. The second assumption, which may at first appear the strangest, is in fact also quite reasonable; indeed, it is not hard to show that it holds whenever XX is path connected in each weight, or more generally when H0(X)H_{0}(X) is cogenerated cofreely by H0(X1)H_{0}(X_{1}), as is the case for configuration spaces. One could weaken this assumption at the cost of a more involved statement.

Lemma 6.16.

If XX is a reduced op\mathcal{FI}^{\mathrm{op}}-space, then L(X)L(X) admits the Abelian twisted Lie algebra H0(X1)(1)[1]H_{0}(X_{1})(1)[-1] as a canonical quotient.

Proof.

We begin by observing the canonical isomorphism L(X)1A(X1)[1]L(X)_{1}\cong A_{*}(X_{1})[-1] of chain complexes. Extending by zero, we obtain the composite map

L(X)A(X1)(1)[1]H0(X1)(1)[1],L(X)\to A_{*}(X_{1})(1)[-1]\to H_{0}(X_{1})(1)[-1],

where the second composition factor is the projection to the quotient. This map is clearly surjective, and it is a map of Lie algebras; indeed, L(X)L(X) is reduced, and weight is additive under the bracket. ∎

Proof of Theorem 6.14.

The Chevalley–Eilenberg complex is the total complex of a bicomplex, whose differentials reflect the internal differential of the Lie algebra and the Lie bracket, respectively. One of the two spectral sequences associated to the dual of this bicomplex has the form

E1Sym(H(L(X))[1])H(X;)E_{1}\cong\mathrm{Sym}(H^{*}(L(X))[1])\implies H^{*}(X;\mathbb{Q})

(we use our first assumption to guarantee that the dual of the divided power is the symmetric power). This spectral sequence is a spectral sequence of Sym(H0(X1)(1))\mathrm{Sym}(H^{0}(X_{1})(1))-modules by functoriality, since the action arises from a map of Lie algebras. As such a module, the E1E^{1}-page is freely generated by Sym(V)\mathrm{Sym}(V), where

V=H(L(X))[1]H0(L(X1)(1))[1].V=\frac{H^{*}(L(X))[1]}{H^{0}(L(X_{1})(1))[1]}.

By our first assumption, H0(X1)H^{0}(X_{1}) is finite dimensional, so Sym(H0(X1)(1))\mathrm{Sym}(H^{0}(X_{1})(1)) is Noetherian [37]; thus, it suffices to show that Sym(V)\mathrm{Sym}(V) is finite dimensional in fixed degree ii, for which we calculate that

Sym(V)k,i=r0(k1++kr=ki1++ir=iIndj=1rΣkjΣkj=1rVkj,ij)Σr.\mathrm{Sym}(V)_{k,i}=\bigoplus_{r\geq 0}\left(\bigoplus_{k_{1}+\cdots+k_{r}=k}\bigoplus_{i_{1}+\cdots+i_{r}=i}\mathrm{Ind}_{\prod_{j=1}^{r}\Sigma_{k_{j}}}^{\Sigma_{k}}\bigotimes_{j=1}^{r}V_{k_{j},i_{j}}\right)_{\Sigma_{r}}.

For fixed kk, this expression is finite dimensional by reducedness and our first assumption, so it suffices to show that it vanishes for kk sufficiently large. By our third assumption on L(X)L(X), there exists \ell sufficiently large so that Vk,i=0V_{k,\leq i}=0 for kk\geq\ell; therefore, the summand indexed by rr vanishes for krk\geq r\ell. On the other hand, our second assumption on L(X)L(X) implies that Vk,i=0V_{k,i}=0 for i0i\leq 0, so we may take ij>0i_{j}>0 for 1jr1\leq j\leq r in the above expression. It follows that the summands indexed by r>ir>i all vanish. Combining these observations, we conclude that Sym(V)k,i=0\mathrm{Sym}(V)_{k,i}=0 for kik\geq i\ell, as desired. ∎

Remark 6.17.

Let MM be a (for simplicity) orientable manifold of dimension nn. According to the conjecture articulated in Section 1.3(2), the homology of the Lie algebra of rational primitives of the ordinary configuration spaces of MM can be described in weight kk as the vector space H(M)Lie(k)[k(n1)]H^{-*}(M)\otimes\mathrm{Lie}(k)[k(n-1)], where Lie(k)\mathrm{Lie}(k) is the kkth Lie representation. As long as n>1n>1, this Lie algebra satisfies the assumptions of Theorem 6.14, so we recover the primordial example of representation stability. This analysis does not actually depend on the validity of the conjecture, since the Chevalley–Eilenberg complex of this Lie algebra does calculate the correct homology.

Appendix A Sullivan chains

The cup product arises from the Alexander–Whitney map C(X×Y)C(X)C(Y)C_{*}(X\times Y)\to C_{*}(X)\otimes C_{*}(Y), a natural transformation constituting an oplax monoidal structure that is famously not symmetric. Fortunately, the failure of symmetry is governed by highly coherent homotopies, which are strictifiable in characteristic zero for abstract reasons.

The purpose of this appendix is to present an explicit model for this strictification. In brief, we construct a pre-dual of (a completion of) the functor of Sullivan cochains AA^{*}, a reference for which is [12, II.10(c)], where it is denoted APLA_{PL}. It is common to discuss this complex in barycentric coordinates, but the expression in increasing coordinates given in [36] will be more convenient for our purposes.

Write VnV_{n} for the chain complex with basis {x1,,xn,dx1,,dxn}\{x_{1},\ldots,x_{n},dx_{1},\ldots,dx_{n}\}, where |xi|=0|x_{i}|=0. This complex carries a natural simplicial structure via the maps

i(xk)={xkkixk1k>isj(xk)={xkkjxk+1k>j.\partial_{i}(x_{k})=\begin{cases}x_{k}&\quad k\leq i\\ x_{k-1}&\quad k>i\end{cases}\qquad\qquad s_{j}(x_{k})=\begin{cases}x_{k}&\quad k\leq j\\ x_{k+1}&\quad k>j.\end{cases}

The dual VnV_{n}^{\vee} thus carries a natural cosimplicial structure.

Definition A.1.

Fix n0n\geq 0.

  1. (1)

    The complex of Sullivan cochains on the standard nn-simplex Δn\Delta^{n} is the commutative differential graded algebra A(Δn)A^{*}(\Delta^{n}) freely generated by VnV_{n}.

  2. (2)

    The complex of Sullivan chains on the standard nn-simplex Δn\Delta^{n} is the conilpotent cocommutative differential graded coalgebra cofreely cogenerated by VnV_{n}^{\vee}.

  3. (3)

    The complex of completed Sullivan cochains on Δn\Delta^{n} is A^(Δn)=A(Δn),\widehat{A}^{*}(\Delta^{n})=A_{*}(\Delta^{n})^{\vee}, regarded as a commutative differential graded algebra.

Each of these constructions inherits a (co)simplicial structure; indeed, each is obtained by applying a functor pointwise to a (co)simplicial object.

Definition A.2.

Write ι:ΔFun(Δop,Set)\iota:\Delta\to\mathrm{Fun}(\Delta^{\mathrm{op}},\mathrm{Set}) for the Yoneda embedding.

  1. (1)

    The functor of Sullivan cochains is the left Kan extension AA^{*} in the diagram

    Δ\textstyle{\Delta\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}ι\scriptstyle{\iota}A(Δ)\scriptstyle{A^{*}(\Delta^{\bullet})}AlgCom(𝒞h)op\textstyle{\mathrm{Alg}_{\mathrm{Com}}(\mathcal{C}\mathrm{h}_{\mathbb{Q}})^{\mathrm{op}}}Fun(Δop,Set)\textstyle{\mathrm{Fun}(\Delta^{\mathrm{op}},\mathrm{Set})\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}A=ι!A(Δ)\scriptstyle{\quad A^{*}=\iota_{!}A^{*}(\Delta^{\bullet})}

    (resp. completed Sullivan cochains, A^\widehat{A}^{*}).

  2. (2)

    The functor of Sullivan chains is the left Kan extension AA_{*} in the diagram

    Δ\textstyle{\Delta\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}ι\scriptstyle{\iota}A(Δ)\scriptstyle{A_{*}(\Delta^{\bullet})}CoalgCom(𝒞h)\textstyle{\mathrm{Coalg}_{\mathrm{Com}}(\mathcal{C}\mathrm{h}_{\mathbb{Q}})}Fun(Δop,Set).\textstyle{\mathrm{Fun}(\Delta^{\mathrm{op}},\mathrm{Set}).\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}A=ι!A(Δ)\scriptstyle{\quad A_{*}=\iota_{!}A_{*}(\Delta^{\bullet})}

The complex of Sullivan (co)chains on the topological space XX is the value of the corresponding functor on the singular set of XX.

Note the canonical isomorphism A^A\widehat{A}^{*}\cong A_{*}^{\vee}; indeed, dualization is colimit preserving when viewed as a functor from cocommutative differential graded coalgebras to the opposite category of commutative differential graded algebras.

Lemma A.3.

The map AA^A^{*}\to\widehat{A}^{*} induced by the composite V(V)A^(Δ)V_{\bullet}\to(V_{\bullet}^{\vee})^{\vee}\to\widehat{A}^{*}(\Delta^{\bullet}) is a quasi-isomorphism.

Proof.

By [12, Prop. 10.5], it suffices to check that the induced map A(Δn)A^(Δn)A^{*}(\Delta^{n})\to\widehat{A}^{*}(\Delta^{n}) is a quasi-isomorphism for each n0n\geq 0. Since the unique map 0Vn0\to V_{n} is a quasi-isomorphism, and since symmetric powers preserve quasi-isomorphisms over \mathbb{Q}, it follows that the unit of A(Δn)A^{*}(\Delta^{n}) is a quasi-isomorphism. Since the linear dual of a quasi-isomorphism is also a quasi-isomorphism, it follows that the unique map Vn0V_{n}^{\vee}\to 0 is a quasi-isomorphism; therefore, after invoking the same property of symmetric powers a second time, it follows that the counit of A(Δn)A_{*}(\Delta^{n}) is a quasi-isomorphism. By the same property of the linear dual, it now follows that the unit of A^(Δn)\widehat{A}^{*}(\Delta^{n}) is a quasi-isomorphism. Since the map in question is compatible with units, being a map of algebras, the claim follows. ∎

Theorem A.4.

Let KK be a simplicial set and write NN_{*} for the functor of rational normalized chains. There is a natural quasi-isomorphism A(K)N(K)A_{*}(K)\simeq N_{*}(K) of differential graded coalgebras.

Proof.

The proof closely follows that of [12, Thm. 10.9]. At the level of simplices, the respective counits induce the maps

A(Δ)A(Δ)N(Δ)N(Δ)A_{*}(\Delta^{\bullet})\leftarrow A_{*}(\Delta^{\bullet})\otimes N_{*}(\Delta^{\bullet})\to N_{*}(\Delta^{\bullet})

of cosimplicial differential graded coalgebras. Since both are objectwise acyclic, these maps are quasi-isomorphisms. Kan extending, one obtains the zig-zag

A=ι!A(Δ)ι!(A(Δ)N(Δ))ι!N(Δ)N,A_{*}=\iota_{!}A_{*}(\Delta^{\bullet})\leftarrow\iota_{!}\left(A_{*}(\Delta^{\bullet})\otimes N_{*}(\Delta^{\bullet})\right)\to\iota_{!}N_{*}(\Delta^{\bullet})\cong N_{*},

where the rightmost isomorphism is justified by the observations that colimits of coalgebras are computed at the level of chain complexes; that NN_{*} is colimit-preserving; and that the identity functor is the left Kan extension of the Yoneda embedding along itself. One could argue directly that these maps are quasi-isomorphisms by appealing to a cosimplicial version of [12, Prop. 10.5]. Alternatively, consider the following commutative diagram of functors from simplicial sets to commutative differential graded algebras:

A^\textstyle{\widehat{A}^{*}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}ι!((A(Δ)N(Δ)))\textstyle{\iota_{!}\left(\left(A_{*}(\Delta^{\bullet})\otimes N_{*}(\Delta^{\bullet})\right)^{\vee}\right)}N\textstyle{N^{*}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}ι!(A^(Δ)N(Δ))\textstyle{\iota_{!}(\widehat{A}^{*}(\Delta^{\bullet})\otimes N^{*}(\Delta^{\bullet}))\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}A\textstyle{A^{*}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}ι!(A(Δ)N(Δ))\textstyle{\iota_{!}\left(A^{*}(\Delta^{\bullet})\otimes N^{*}(\Delta^{\bullet})\right)\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}N,\textstyle{N^{*},\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}

the top row is the linear dual of the zig-zag of interest, the maps in the bottom row are shown to be quasi-isomorphisms in [12, Thm. 10.9], and the lefthand vertical arrow is a quasi-isomorphism by Lemma A.3; therefore, since formation of the linear dual reflects quasi-isomorphisms, it suffices to show that the vertical maps in the middle column are quasi-isomorphisms. By [12, Prop. 10.5], it suffices to show that the maps

A(Δn)N(Δn)A^(Δn)N(Δn)(A(Δn)N(Δn))A^{*}(\Delta^{n})\otimes N^{*}(\Delta^{n})\to\widehat{A}^{*}(\Delta^{n})\otimes N^{*}(\Delta^{n})\to\left(A_{*}(\Delta^{n})\otimes N_{*}(\Delta^{n})\right)^{\vee}

are quasi-isomorphisms for each n0n\geq 0. The first is the quasi-isomorphism of Lemma A.3 tensored with the identity. The second is the canonical map from the tensor product of the linear duals to the linear dual of the tensor product, which is a quasi-isomorphism on complexes with finite dimensional homology. ∎

Corollary A.5.

Let XX be a topological space. There is a natural quasi-isomorphism

A(X)C(X;)A_{*}(X)\simeq C_{*}(X;\mathbb{Q})

of differential graded coalgebras and of oplax monoidal functors.

Proof.

Restricting the quasi-isomorphism of Theorem A.4 along the singular set functor, we obtain the desired quasi-isomorphism of coalgebras. To complete the proof, we need only recall that the coalgebra structure on singular chains determines the oplax monoidal structure via

C(X×Y)C(X×Y)C(X×Y)C(π1)C(π2)C(X)C(Y).C_{*}(X\times Y)\to C_{*}(X\times Y)\otimes C_{*}(X\times Y)\xrightarrow{C_{*}(\pi_{1})\otimes C_{*}(\pi_{2})}C_{*}(X)\otimes C_{*}(Y).

Remark A.6.

One imagines that our approach in this appendix translates essentially unchanged to the setting of [36], providing a symmetric model for integral singular chains. We have not checked the details.

References

  • [1] M. Aguiar and S. Mahajan. Monoidal Functors, Species and Hopf Algebras. Amer. Math. Soc., 2010.
  • [2] B. An, G. Drummond-Cole, and B. Knudsen. Edge stabilization in the homology of graph braid groups. Geom. Topol., 24(1):421–469, 2020.
  • [3] C. Bibby and N. Gadish. A generating function approach to new representation stability phenomena in orbit configuration spaces. arXiv:1911.02125.
  • [4] L. Brantner, J. Hahn, and B. Knudsen. The Lubin–Tate theory of configuration spaces: I. arXiv:1908.11321.
  • [5] T. Church and J. Ellenberg. Homology of FI-modules. Geom. Topol., 21(4):2373–2418, 2017.
  • [6] T. Church, J. S. Ellenberg, and B. Farb. FI-modules and stability for representations of symmetric groups. Duke Math. J., 164(9):1833–1910, 2015.
  • [7] A. Cooper, V. de Silva, and R. Sazdanovic. On configuration spaces and simplicial complexes. New York J. Math., 25:723–744, 2019.
  • [8] B. Day. On closed categories of functors. In Reports of the Midwest Category Seminar IV, pages 1–38, 1970.
  • [9] G. Drummond-Cole and B. Knudsen. Betti numbers of configuration spaces of surfaces. J. London Math. Society, 96:367–393, 2017.
  • [10] M. Eastwood and S. Huggett. Euler characteristics and chromatic polynomials. Eur. J. Comb., 28(6):1553–1560, 2007.
  • [11] J. Ellenberg, T. Tran, and C. Westerland. Fox–Neuwirth–Fuks cells, quantum shuffle algebras, and Malle’s conjecture for function fields. arXiv:1701.04541.
  • [12] Y. Félix, S. Halperin, and J.-C. Thomas. Rational Homotopy Theory. Springer, 2001.
  • [13] Y. Félix and J.-C. Thomas. Rational Betti numbers of configuration spaces. Topology Appl., 102:139–149, 2000.
  • [14] J. Francis and D. Gaitsgory. Chiral Koszul duality. Selecta Math. (N.S.), 18:27–87, 2012.
  • [15] N. Gadish and L. Hainaut. Configuration spaces on a wedge of spheres and Hochschild–Pirashvili homology. arXiv:2202.12494.
  • [16] E. Getzler. Resolving mixed Hodge modules on configuration spaces. Duke Math. J., 96(1):175–203, 1999.
  • [17] S. Glasman. Day convolution for \infty-categories. Math. Res. Lett., 23(5):1369–1385, 2016.
  • [18] D. Grayson. Higher algebraic K-theory: II (after Daniel Quillen). In Algebraic K-theory, volume 551 of Lecture Notes in Math., 1976.
  • [19] R. Hepworth. On the edge of the stable range. Math. Ann., 377(1):123–181, 2020.
  • [20] Q. Ho. Higher representation stability for ordered configuration spaces and twisted commutative factorization algebras. arXiv:2004.00252.
  • [21] Q. Ho. Homological stability and densities of generalized configuration spaces. Geom. Topol., 25(2):813–912, 2021.
  • [22] N. Idrissi. The Lambrechts–Stanley model of configuration spaces. Invent. Math., 216:1–68, 2019.
  • [23] B. Knudsen. Betti numbers and stability for configuration spaces via factorization homology. Alg. Geom. Topol., 17:3137–3187, 2017.
  • [24] B. Knudsen. Higher enveloping algebras. Geom. Topol., 22:4013–4066, 2018.
  • [25] B. Knudsen, J. Miller, and P. Tosteson. Extremal stability for configuration spaces. Math. Ann., 2022.
  • [26] J.-L. Loday and B. Vallette. Algebraic Operads. Springer, 2012.
  • [27] M. Mandell, J. P. May, S. Schwede, and B. Shipley. Model categories of diagram spectra. Proc. Lond. Math. Soc., 82(2):441–512, 2001.
  • [28] J. P. May. The Geometry of Iterated loop spaces, volume 271 of Lecture Notes in Math. Springer, 1972.
  • [29] D. McDuff. Configuration spaces of positive and negative particles. Topology, 14:91–107, 1975.
  • [30] J. Miller and J. Wilson. Higher order representation stability and ordered configuration spaces of manifolds. Geom. Topol., 23(5), 2016.
  • [31] R. Nagpal, S. Sam, and A. Snowden. Noetherianity of some degree two twisted skew-commutative algebras. Selecta Math. (N.S.), 25, 2019.
  • [32] D. Petersen. Cohomology of generalized configuration spaces. Compos. Math., 156(2):251–298, 2020.
  • [33] D. Quillen. Rational homotopy theory. Ann. Math., 1969.
  • [34] E. Ramos. Generalized representation stability and FId\mathrm{FI}_{d}-modules. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc, 145(11):4647–4660, 2017.
  • [35] O. Randal-Williams and N. Wahl. Homological stability for automorphism groups. Adv. Math., 318:534–626, 2017.
  • [36] B. Richter and S. Sagave. A strictly commutative model for the cochain algebra of a space. Compos. Math., 156(8):1718–1743, 2020.
  • [37] A. Snowden. Syzygies of Segre embeddings and Δ\Delta-modules. Duke Math. J., 162(2):225–277, 2013.
  • [38] B. Totaro. Configuration spaces of algebraic varieties. Topology, 35(4):1057–1067, 1996.