Projection spaces and twisted Lie algebras
Abstract.
A projection space is a collection of spaces interrelated by the combinatorics of projection onto tensor factors in a symmetric monoidal background category. Examples include classical configuration spaces, orbit configuration spaces, the graphical configuration spaces of Eastwood–Huggett, the simplicial configuration spaces of Cooper–de Silva–Sazdanovic, the generalized configuration spaces of Petersen, and Stiefel manifolds. We show that, under natural assumptions on the background category, the homology of a projection space is calculated by the Chevalley–Eilenberg complex of a certain generalized Lie algebra. We identify conditions on this Lie algebra implying representation stability in the classical setting of finite sets and injections.
1. Introduction
Experience has proven the value of studying configuration spaces in families. When organized correctly, these spaces exhibit emergent algebraic structure that imposes strong constraints on their topological invariants. One important means of organization involves the background space in an essential way; one speaks of operads and their algebras and modules [22, 28], or of adding a particle near the boundary of a manifold [29] or onto an edge of a graph [2]. Here, we pursue an orthogonal organizing principle, namely that of the underlying combinatorics.
1.1. Context and motivation
As a motivating example, consider the ordinary configuration space , defined as the space of injections from the finite set into the topological space . The composite of injections being an injection, the collection of all such spaces forms a presheaf on the category of finite sets and injections. In many examples of interest, this combinatorial structure forces the rational (co)homology of configuration spaces to exhibit representation stability [6].
There are now a number of machines devoted to the study of stability phenomena in various contexts [19, 35]. Unfortunately, most of these machines are adapted to the study of automorphism groups, rather than configuration spaces. The goal of this paper is to develop a framework better adapted to examples such as those listed in the following table.
Combinatorics | Configuration space |
---|---|
Sets | Ordinary |
-sets | Orbit |
Graphs | Graphical [10] |
Simplicial complexes | Simplicial [7] |
Collision structures | Generalized [32] |
Vector spaces | Stiefel |
We proceed from the observation that the projection induced by the injection is subsumed by the map that splits an -indexed configuration into a configuration indexed by the image of and one indexed by its complement. The collection of all such splitting maps can be regarded as a kind of cocommutative comultiplication, which, according to the philosophy of Koszul duality, is governed by its Lie algebra of (derived) primitives.
The resulting interpretation of the homology of ordinary configuration spaces as Lie algebra homology has proven quite fruitful [4, 9, 15, 23, 24, 25]. This success motivates us to generalize the relationship, showing that the homology of something sufficiently like a configuration space is governed by something like a Lie algebra.
1.2. Framework and results
Our first step is to generalize the relationship between bijections and injections among finite sets in the relationship between a symmetric monoidal category and its projection category . Roughly, a morphism in is (opposite to) a projection onto a tensor factor in (see Section 2.1 for details). We then make the following definition, which encompasses all of the spaces listed in the table above (see Section 6.1).
Definition 1.1.
A projection space over is a functor . We say that is reduced if its value on the monoidal unit is a singleton.
The bulk of the paper is spent in constructing the following composite functor, which associates to each projection space a -twisted Lie algebra of rational primitives:
Briefly, the first functor witnesses a universal property of the projection category (Corollary 4.3); the second is the functor of Sullivan chains, a suitable rational replacement for singular chains (Corollary A.5); the third relies on a variant of Day convolution (Corollary 4.12); and the fourth is Quillen’s Koszul duality functor [33]. The main result is as follows—see Section 5 for undefined terms.
Theorem 1.2.
Let be a reduced projection space over the combinatorial symmetric monoidal category . There is a canonical isomorphism of -twisted cocommutative coalgebras
As a consequence, the homology of generalized configuration spaces is calculated by the Chevalley–Eilenberg complex of a certain Lie algebra. This general connection to Lie algebras may at first seem surprising. Indeed, for ordinary configuration spaces, it is natural to view the connection as arising by combining the Goresky–MacPherson formula, expressing the homology of a stratified space in terms of poset homology, with the identification of the Lie operad with the homology of the partition posets [32]. In the more general setting, the resulting poset homology has no obvious relation to the Lie operad, yet the connection persists.
As foreshadowed above, we imagine Theorem 1.2 as a source and organizing principle for stability phenomena. As a proof of concept, we show that our framework encompasses representation stability. Specifically, stability is tied to the eventual high connectivity of the Lie algebra of rational primitives.
Theorem 1.3.
Let be a reduced -space taking values in path connected spaces. Suppose that satisfies the following conditions.
-
(1)
is finite dimensional for every and .
-
(2)
for .
-
(3)
for fixed and sufficiently large.
Then is representation stable.
We deduce this theorem from a more general result encompassing projection spaces with path disconnected values—see Theorem 6.14.
1.3. Future directions
Our work leaves a rather large number of natural questions unanswered (but see [20] and [21] for closely related work). The following three extensions at least are likely within easy reach.
-
(1)
Integer coefficients. Our program relies crucially on a strictly symmetric replacement for the oplax monoidal functor of singular chains. In characteristic zero, such a replacement is within easy reach (see Appendix A). With a bit less laziness, one should be able to work integrally, as in [32], after minor modifications of the techniques of [36]—see also Remark A.6.
-
(2)
Classical primitives. Let be a (for simplicity) orientable -manifold. In view of a myriad of (semi-)classical results, it seems a virtual certainty that the Lie algebra associated to the ordinary configuration spaces of is (quasi-isomorphic to) the tensor product of the compactly supported Sullivan cochains of with a free twisted Lie algebra on one generator in degree and weight [13, 16, 23, 32]. It is likely possible to deduce this claim easily from either of the last two references with a little care taken in comparing models.
-
(3)
Orbit primitives. The results of [3] suggest that the same description is valid verbatim for orbit configuration spaces, save that the phrase “free twisted Lie algebra” should be interpreted with respect to the category of equivariant bijections among free -sets.
In more exotic settings, it is less clear what one should expect.
-
(4)
Generalized primitives. What is the Lie algebra associated to generalized configuration spaces? Petersen’s results in [32] suggest an expression in terms of the homology of the order complex associated to a collision structure. One imagines that the Chevalley–Eilenberg complex for this Lie algebra comprises the complexes described by Petersen, in the same way that the various Totaro spectral sequences [38] assemble into the Chevalley–Eilenberg complex of the Lie algebra described above in the case of ordinary configuration spaces [22].
One imagines that Theorem 1.3 is merely the beginning of a robust connection between stability phenomena and the twisted Chevalley–Eilenberg complex.
-
(5)
-homology. We show that sufficient connectivity of implies representation stability. Is there a direct connection between this Lie algebra and -(hyper)homology [5]?
- (6)
-
(7)
Beyond representation stability. What finite generation properties does dictate for projection spaces in more exotic contexts? What homological asymptotics do they imply? Pursuit of this direction almost certainly entails grappling with thorny Noetherianity problems for -twisted commutative algebras, already notoriously difficult (and mostly unsolved) in the classical case [31].
It is likely that our framework and examples can be expanded considerably.
- (8)
-
(9)
Linear collision structures. It is likely that a linear version of the theory developed in Section 3 would permit the expression of the homology of subspace arrangements as twisted Lie algebra homology.
-
(10)
Rational homotopy theory. In the language of [1], the Day convolution and pointwise tensor products endow the category of presheaves of chain complexes with the structure of a -monoidal category, and the singular chains of a projection space carry the structure of a double coalgebra in this category, with the second comultiplication induced by the objectwise diagonal. Does this structure provide a faithful algebraic model for the homotopy theory of rationalized projection spaces [33]?
1.4. Conventions
Chain complexes are bounded below and homologically graded. The -fold homological suspension is denoted . When working with monoidal categories, we suppress the associator whenever possible. We use the symbols and for the tensor product and unit of a generic monoidal category, employing subscripts (rarely) to disambiguate as necessary (e.g., ). An additive tensor category is an additive category equipped with a symmetric monoidal structure whose tensor product distributes over finite coproducts. We write , , , and .
1.5. Acknowledgements
The author thanks Najib Idrissi and Roberto Pagaria for helpful conversations related to this work and the anonymous referee for her feedback. This paper was written for the proceedings of the conference “Compactifications, Configurations, and Cohomology,” held at Northeastern University in October of 2021. The author extends his heartfelt gratitude to the organizers, Peter Crooks and Alex Suciu, for the opportunity to speak, to write, and to be reminded that face-to-face interaction in mathematics is a precious, even indispensable, commodity. This work was supported by NSF grant DMS-1906174.
2. Projection categories
In this section, we introduce the projection category associated to a monoidal category . We then explore a selection of simple examples.
2.1. Definitions
Roughly speaking, we wish for a presheaf on the projection category to carry a structure map for each projection of an object onto a tensor factor. The following definition makes this idea precise.
Definition 2.1.
Let and be objects in the monoidal category .
-
(1)
A complementary morphism from to is the data of an object of together with a morphism .
-
(2)
The composite of the complementary morphisms and is the complementary morphism .
-
(3)
An elementary equivalence from the complementary morphism to the complementary morphism is a map fitting into the commutative diagram
-
(4)
We say that two complementary morphisms are equivalent if they differ by a finite sequence of elementary equivalences.
We emphasize that the arrow in the definition of an elementary equivalence is not required to be an isomorphism—see Remark 2.6 below for more on this point.
Remark 2.2.
The definition of a complementary morphism is biased by mapping order, i.e., whether to consider or . Up to opposites, the two choices produce essentially the same result. The definition is also biaed by tensor order, i.e., whether to consider or . Following this section, we will assume that is symmetric monoidal, so this bias will play no role.
Lemma 2.3.
Composition is associative and unital up to equivalence and well-defined on equivalence classes.
Proof.
We give only an outline, leaving the (easy) details to the reader. For associativity, one uses the associator of to produce an elementary equivalence between the two composites, and the compositional unit is the unitor . Well-definition in one composition factor follows from the commuting diagram
and a similar diagram establishes well-definition in the second factor. ∎
The lemma allows us our main definition.
Definition 2.4.
Let be a monoidal category. The projection category of is the category with the same objects as and arrows the equivalence classes of complementary morphisms under composition.
The projection category is functorial for strong monoidal functors. Briefly, given such a functor , we define on objects, and we declare that send the equivalence class of the complementary morphism to the equivalence class of the composite . It is a simple matter to check that is a well-defined functor.
Remark 2.5.
The functoriality described above is a shadow of a larger structure. Specifically, the projection category is the truncation of an obvious bicategory, and an elaboration of the considerations of Section 4.1 shows that a lax monoidal functor between monoidal categories induces a pseudofunctor at the level of bicategories. We make no use of this extended functoriality.
Remark 2.6.
The projection category is closely related to a construction due to Quillen [18] (see also [35, p. 11]). More precisely, the projection category is obtained from the bicategory described in Remark 2.5 by replacing the morphism categories by their connected components, while Quillen’s construction (in the case of a self-action) is obtained by replacing them with the connected components of their maximal subgroupoids—see Example 2.7 for a simple example illustrating the difference. In particular, one should expect the two to coincide only when is itself a groupoid. The use of the full morphism category is essential to the universal property of Theorem 4.2—see Remark 4.6 and Example 4.7.
Example 2.7.
Let denote the walking arrow, i.e., the category with objects and and a unique non-identity morphism . The usual rules of integer multiplication extend to a unique symmetric monoidal structure on . With this monoidal structure, one finds that there are the exactly five complementary morphisms. Since has no non-identity isomorphisms, these five morphisms are distinct in Quillen’s category. One checks that the resulting category is the walking retract, i.e., the category generated by the arrows and subject only to the relation , where and . In contrast, the commutative diagram
is a simple equivalence demonstrating the relation in . Thus, the projection category is instead the walking isomorphism.
2.2. Groupoid examples
We begin with the primordial motivating example. Although this result is subsumed in Proposition 2.9, we include an independent proof, both for tactility and for later use.
Proposition 2.8.
There is a canonical isomorphism of categories
Proof.
The two categories have the same objects. We define a functor from left to right on arrows by sending the equivalence class of the complementary morphism to the injection . One checks immediately that this prescription is invariant under equivalence and respects identities. As for composition, the complementary morphisms and compose to give , and
as required. To define the functor from right to left, we send the injection to the equivalence class of the complementary morphism . The injection is sent to the equivalence class of , which is the identity of in , and the composite of and is sent to the equivalence class of , which is equivalent to the appropriate composite via the bijection
induced by .
We have shown that both assignments are functors, and the composite functors are the respective identities on objects by construction. On arrows, given , we have
and provides an equivalence between our original complementary morphism and the complementary morphism , which represents its image under the composite functor. We leave it to the reader to check that the other composite is also the identity on arrows. ∎
We now consider a class of example recurrent throughout the study of stability phenomena. In the next result, the assumption that be skeletal is made solely for simplicity of exposition.
Proposition 2.9.
Let be a skeletal symmetric monoidal groupoid. There is a canonical bijection
under which composition is given by the dashed filler in the following commutative diagram:
Proof.
For each object such that , an automorphism of determines a complementary morphism , and every complementary morphism is determined in this way. Thus, we have a canonical surjection
By definition, two automorphisms of differ by an automorphism of the form for if and only if the corresponding complementary morphisms are equivalent. It follows that the above surjection descends to the indicated disjoint union of orbit sets, and that each of the resulting functions is injective. Since is skeletal, complementary morphisms indexed by different choices of are never equivalent, so the function as a whole is injective, implying the first claim. The (essentially immediate) verification of the second claim is left to the reader. ∎
In the following result, denotes the category of equivariant injections among free -sets with finitely many orbits, where is a fixed group, and denotes the category of linear injections among finite dimensional vector spaces over a fixed vector space (resp. , , bijections).
Corollary 2.10.
Let be a group and a field. There are the following canonical isomorphisms of categories:
2.3. The projection category of a deformation
We close this section with an observation on the relationship between the formation of projection categories and subcategories of a certain type.
Definition 2.11.
A subcategory is a deformation of if there is a functor and a natural transformation .
Note that any subcategory containing a deformation is itself a deformation.
Proposition 2.12.
Let be a monoidal category and a full subcategory containing and closed under tensor products. If is a deformation of , then the induced functor is fully faithful with image the subcategory with objects the objects of and morphisms the equivalence classes of complementary morphisms such that lies in .
Proof.
Prerequisitely, we note that is, in fact, a subcategory by closure under tensor products. This same assumption, together with fullness and the assumption that , implies that the tensor product of restricts to a monoidal structure on with the same unit and coherence isomorphisms, so is defined, and the inclusion is strong monoidal, so is defined. We claim that this functor factors through the inclusion of as an isomorphism. The existence, surjectivity on objects, and fullness of the factorization being essentially immediate, the main point is to verify faithfulness. Consider the zig-zag of simple equivalences of the form
with all objects but lying in . By assumption, there is a functor and a natural transformation , from which we derive the enlarged diagram
This diagram supplies the following chain of simple equivalences:
all of which lie in . In the same way, an arbitrary zig-zag of simple equivalences expressing the equivalence in of two complementary morphisms with source and target in may be replaced by a (perhaps longer) zig-zag of simple equivalences in . In other words, complementary morphisms in are equivalent if and only if they are equivalent as complementary morphisms in , which is faithfulness. ∎
3. Collision structures
In this section, we develop a general combinatorial framework encompassing all of our examples. Inspired by [32], we define a collision structure to be a set of partitions of a finite set closed under merging blocks. We define a notion of morphism between collision structures and calculate the projection category associated to the category of collision structures and bijections (Theorem 3.11).
3.1. Definitions
We begin by recalling a few standard ideas regarding partitions.
Definition 3.1.
Let be a set. A partition of is a set of nonempty subsets of , called blocks, such that every element of is contained in exactly one block of . We say that is a refinement of , written , if every block of is a union of blocks of .
The data of a partition of is equivalent to the data of the equivalence relation on given by declaring that two elements are equivalent provided they lie in the same block of . Note that the empty set admits a unique partition, which is itself empty.
Partitions of form a poset under refinement, which has the unique minimum and, if is nonempty, the unique maximum .
Definition 3.2.
A collision structure on the set is an upward closed subset , i.e., such that whenever and .
We think of a collision structure as prescribing which collisions among elements of the underlying set are forbidden. From this point of view, the requirement of upward closure is obvious.
The intersection or union of collision structures on a fixed set is again a collision structure; therefore, it is sensible to speak of the largest and smallest collision structure with a given property, and of the collision structure generated by a set of partitions.
Example 3.3.
The trivial collision structure is initial among collision structures on .
Given a partition of and an injection , we write for the partition of given by the images under of the blocks of , together with the singletons in the complement of the image of . Given a subset , we write for the collision structure generated by the set
Definition 3.4.
Let and be collision structures on and . We say that an injection is a map of collision structures if .
Since we clearly have , maps of collision structures on finite sets form a category . We will also be interested in the wide subcategory of bijective maps of collision structures.
As we will see below in Section 6.1, a collision structure has an associated configuration space, in which collisions among particles are forbidden if the resulting partition lies in . These spaces are precisely the generalized configuration spaces of [32]. We close this section by observing that the category of collision structures subsumes the combinatorics underlying the graphical configuration spaces of [10] and the simplicial configuration spaces of [7]
Example 3.5.
A graph determines a collision structure on its set of vertices by declaring that lies in if and only if some block of contains an edge. An injection between vertex sets is a map of collision structures if and only if it is a graph homomorphism.
Example 3.6.
A simplicial complex determines a collision structure on its set of vertices by declaring that lies in if and only if some block of is not a simplex of (we use that the set of simplices is closed under the formation of subsets). An injection between vertex sets is a map of collision structures if and only if it preserves non-simplices.111Maps of this kind are called “cosimplicial” in [7]. We avoid this terminology for reasons that are likely obvious.
Note that the collision structure associated to a graph according to Example 3.5 coincides with the collision structure associated to its independence complex according to Example 3.6.
From these examples, we obtain the categories and of injections among graphs and simplicial complexes, respectively, both full subcategories of , and similarly for bijections.
3.2. Monoidal structure and projection category
The main result of this section identifies the projection category of the category of collision structures and bijections. In order to formulate such a result, we first require a monoidal structure.
Definition 3.7.
Let and be collision structures on and , respectively. The disjoint union of and is the collision structure generated by , where denotes the inclusion (resp. ).
This definition is arranged so that and are maps of collision structures.
Lemma 3.8.
Disjoint union of collision structures extends to a unique symmetric monoidal structure such that the forgetful functor is strong monoidal.
Proof.
The main point is to verify that the (suppressed) associator of finite sets is an isomorphism of collision structures, but it is not difficult to check, given collision structures on for , that and are both generated by the set . ∎
By functoriality for strong monoidal functors, we obtain an induced functor at the level of projection categories, concerning which we have the following result.
Lemma 3.9.
The induced functor is faithful.
Proof.
For , let and be collision structures on and , respectively. Consider the following diagram of bijections:
It suffices to show, assuming that and are maps of collision structures (and not necessarily so), that and are equivalent as complementary morphisms in . Let denote the collision structure on generated by and . Then is a map of collision structures from to , and the identity is a map of collision structures from to . We claim that is a map of collision structures from to , for which it suffices to verify the following three containments:
The first and third containment are the assumption that is a map of collision structures, and the second follows from the assumption that is so, since by commutativity. We have established the existence of the commutative diagram
of collision structures, which represents a pair of elementary equivalences connecting and . ∎
Example 3.10.
We come now to the main result of this section.
Theorem 3.11.
There is a canonical isomorphism of categories
Proof.
The two categories have the same objects, and we wish to extend this equality to an isomorphism of categories. Forgetting collision structures determines the vertical functors in the diagram
where the bottom functor is the isomorphism of Proposition 2.8. Since the vertical functors are faithful by Lemma 3.9 and by definition, respectively, the dashed functor (extending the identity on objects) is unique if it exists.
By definition, an arrow from to in the source of the putative functor is represented by a bijection such that . We have
so the injection defines a morphism from to in . Thus, the dashed functor exists. To obtain its inverse, it suffices for the same reasons to note, given an injection with , that the bijection lifts uniquely to a complementary morphism in . For existence, we note that the bijection in question is a map of collision structures when carries the empty collision structure. For uniqueness, we note that, for any collision structure on , any permutation of this set defines a morphism of collision structures ; therefore, any lift of to a complementary morphism is equivalent to the lift constructed above. ∎
Corollary 3.12.
There are the following canonical isomorphisms of categories:
Proof.
We aim to use Proposition 2.12, the main point being to verify that and are deformations of . We begin by observing that the assignment of a finite set to its trivial collision structure defines a fully faithful functor , which is a section of the forgetful functor. Identifying with its essential image under this functor, we observe that is a deformation of , since the trivial collision structure is initial. Moreover, we have the containment ; indeed, the trivial collision structure on corresponds to the discrete graph on and to the simplex spanned by . Since a subcategory containing a deformation is itself a deformation, the proof is complete.
∎
4. Monoidal matters
In this section, we consider interactions among various tensor products. First, we prove the structural result that the opposite of the projection category represents oplax symmetric monoidal functors with Cartesian target (Corollary 4.3). Second, we show that, under restrictive but applicable hypotheses, a variant of Day convolution identifies such oplax functors with certain coalgebras (Corollary 4.12). These two results form the bridge from combinatorial structure to algebraic structure underpinning our proof of Theorem 1.2.
4.1. Projection categories and lax structures
The goal of this section is to establish a universal property of the projection category in the symmetric setting. Before articulating this universal property in Theorem 4.2 below, we pause to establish notation regarding a few standard concepts.
Definition 4.1.
Let and be monoidal categories.
-
(1)
A lax (monoidal) structure on a functor is a natural transformation and a morphism such that the following diagrams commute for all .
A lax (monoidal) functor is a functor equipped with a (typically suppressed) lax structure.
-
(2)
Suppose that and are symmetric monoidal. We say that the lax functor is symmetric if the following diagram commutes:
-
(3)
Let and be lax functors. A natural transformation is monoidal if the following diagrams commute:
-
(4)
A (symmetric) oplax structure on is a (symmetric) lax structure on .
It is immediate from the definitions that monoidality and symmetry is closed under composition; therefore, lax symmetric monoidal functors and monoidal natural transformations form a category . Likewise, we have the category of oplax symmetric monoidal functors. The reader should note that we do not reflect the condition of symmetry in the notation, since we will have no cause to consider nonsymmetric (op)lax functors.
Theorem 4.2.
Let be a symmetric monoidal category and a category with finite coproducts. There is a canonical isomorphism of categories
In our application, it will be the dual version of this result that will be of most interest.
Corollary 4.3.
Let be a symmetric monoidal category and a category with finite products. There is a canonical isomorphism of categories
Proof.
By our assumption on , the opposite category has finite coproducts, so Theorem 4.2 supplies the middle of the three isomorphisms of categories:
∎
We begin the proof of the theorem by observing that is the source of a natural functor to its own projection category.
Lemma 4.4.
The assignments and determine a functor .
Proof.
It is immediate that preserves identities. For composition, we appeal to the commutative diagram
The composite in the bottom row represents , while the full clockwise composite represents . Since the leftmost vertical arrow is the identity of tensored with the unitor, commutativity implies that the two complementary morphisms are equivalent, as desired. ∎
The equivalence of Theorem 4.2 will be given by restriction along the functor of Lemma 4.4. The following result will allow us to make sense of this idea.
Lemma 4.5.
Let be category with finite coproducts.
-
(1)
Given a functor , the restriction carries a canonical lax structure, which is symmetric.
-
(2)
Given a natural transformation in , the restriction is monoidal.
Proof.
Since the unit in is initial, we have the unique map . The identity and the symmetry of determine complementary morphisms from and to , respectively. Applying and invoking the universal property of the coproduct in , we obtain a family of maps of the form . The verification that these maps form a natural transformation, although straightforward, reveals a subtle asymmetry, which may at first be surprising; for this reason, we choose to include some details. The verification of the axioms of a symmetric lax structure and a monoidal natural transformation are left to the enthusiastic reader.
By the universal property of the coproduct, naturality in the first variable amounts to the commutativity of the diagrams obtained by applying to the following two diagrams in :
The composites in the first diagram are represented by the respective rows of the following commutative diagram in :
As indicated, the symmetry of supplies an elementary equivalence between the two, establishing the desired commutativity. On other hand, the counterclockwise composite and righthand diagonal arrow in the second diagram are represented by the clockwise composite and bottom arrow, respectively, of the following commutative diagram in :
The lefthand vertical composite gives a simple equivalence between the two, establishing the claim. Naturality in the second variable is similar. ∎
Note that the arrow providing the final simple equivlanece of this proof is in general not an isomorphism—see Remark 4.6 below.
Proof of Theorem 4.2.
Invoking Lemma 4.5, we obtain the (abusively named) functor
which we claim to be an isomorphism. To prove this claim, we construct an inverse isomorphism explicitly. Given a symmetric lax functor , we define the value of on the equivalence class of to be the composite
One checks immediately that this definition is independent of the choice of representative and that , so defined, is a functor. To conclude, it suffices to verify that the objectwise identities and form a natural transformation and a monoidal natural transformation, respectively.
Unpacking the definitions, one finds that the value of on the equivalence class represented by is the value of on the equivalence class of the composite of , viewed as a complementary morphism with source , with , viewed as a complementary morphism with source . This composite is simply , viewed as a complementary morphism with source , which is equivalent to our original complementary morphism via the unitor . It follows that .
Similarly, one finds that the value of on a morphism is the composite in the top row of the diagram
Since the diagram commutes by our assumption on , this composite is simply the value of on our original morphism. It follows that as bare functors, so it remains to verify that the two lax structures coincide. Since the unit in is initial, the second diagram in the definition of a monoidal natural transformation commutes automatically. As for the first, it is an easy exercise to check that the lax structure morphism for produced by Lemma 4.5, as a morphism in , has the same components as ; we remark only that the argument uses the compatibility of with the respective monoidal symmetries. The claim then follows from the universal property of the coproduct in . ∎
Remark 4.6.
As our proof shows, the (rather curious) situation is that the universal property of Theorem 4.2 fails to hold for Quillen’s category not because one cannot define the desired lax monoidal structure maps, but rather because they do not form a natural transformation unless is a groupoid. The coarser equivalence relation of is precisely what is needed to repair this defect.
Example 4.7.
We return to Example 2.7. By definition, the data of a functor from is that of an arrow in the target, and our previous analysis shows that the data of an extension of this functor to Quillen’s construction is that of a retraction of . Assuming the target category to have finite coproducts, suppose that we are instead given the data of a lax monoidal structure on the functor in question. The composite arrow
is again a left inverse to , as is readily seen from the commutative diagram
According to Example 2.7, the category is the walking isomorphism, so we should expect that is also a right inverse; indeed, this fact follows easily from the commutative diagram
4.2. Day convolution
In this section, we consider two natural tensor product operations defined on functors between symmetric monoidal categories, the left and right Day convolution tensor products. With mild assumptions on the two categories, it is well known that left convolution determines a symmetric monoidal structure on the functor category. A game of opposites then gives conditions under which right convolution determines a symmetric monoidal structure. Although these conditions are significantly more restrictive, they are nevertheless applicable in our setting of interest.
Definition 4.8.
Let be functors. The left (resp. right) Day convolution tensor product of and is the left (resp. right) Kan extension in the diagram
It should be emphasized that either convolution may fail to exist for some or all pairs of functors with fixed source and target. When the left convolution does exist, it is given explicitly by the formula
and similarly for right convolution. Mere existence, however, does not guarantee that convolution extends to a monoidal structure.
Theorem 4.9.
If admits, and distributes over, colimits indexed by for every object , then left Day convolution extends to a canonical symmetric monoidal structure on . In this case, there is a canonical isomorphism of categories
Although this result is essentially standard, it is typically stated with the unnecessarily strong assumption that distributes over all colimits. In the left handed setting, this assumption is almost always satisfied; it is in dualizing to the right handed setting in Corollary 4.12 that we require the weaker assumption. For these reasons, we have opted to include an outline of the proof—the reader may consult [8, 17, 27], for example, for further details.
Proof of Theorem 4.9.
The existence assumption grants that is defined for every and . A unit is supplied by the functor given by the left Kan extension of the inclusion of along the inclusion of . Indeed, we claim that the left Kan extensions indicated by the dashed arrows are as claimed in the following diagrams:
For the righthand diagram, there is nothing to show, and the identification of the innermost Kan extension in the lefthand diagram is immediate from the definitions. Invoking our assumption on distributivity of , it follows that the outer left Kan extension is as indicated. We obtain a left unitor by observing that the left unitors of and give an isomorphism between the two diagrams, and similarly for a right unitor. The same considerations suffice to identify the left Kan extensions in the following diagram:
We obtain an associator after observing that the associators of and furnish an isomorphism between this diagram and the corresponding diagram for . The same approach furnishes a symmetry. The coherence axioms for follow directly from the coherence axioms for and , since each structure morphism in the former was built from the corresponding structure morphisms in the latter two.
Toward the final claim, we observe that, by the universal property of the colimit, a monoid structure on provides a compatible collection of maps , one for each arrow . By specializing to the case , such a collection furnishes a collection of candidate components of a lax structure map. Conversely, a lax structure furnishes a candidate monoid structure map via the composites
Similar remarks apply to units, and it remains to verify that the associativity, symmetry, and unitality constraints of the two structures coincide, a task we leave to the reader. ∎
Before continuing we record a useful consequence of the proof.
Corollary 4.10.
If admits, and distributes over, colimits indexed by for every object , then the left Day convolution tensor product is canonically isomorphic to the left Kan extension in the diagram
The existence of the right convolution monoidal structure will rely on a technical condition on the structure of overcategories in , which we refer to as sparsity. We record several other related technical conditions for later use. In the following definition, we view finite sets as discrete categories.
Definition 4.11.
Let be an object in the symmetric monoidal category .
-
(1)
We say that is -separable if receives a final functor from a finite set.
-
(2)
We say that is freely -separable if receives a -equivariant final functor from a finite free -set.
-
(3)
We say that is sparse if every object of is -separable.
Corollary 4.12.
If is a sparse symmetric monoidal category and an additive tensor category, then right Day convolution extends to a canonical symmetric monoidal structure on . In this case, there is a canonical isomorphism of categories
Proof.
In light of the isomorphism , together with the fact that the formation of the opposite category interchanges limits and colimits, it suffices to show that and satisfy the hypotheses of Theorem 4.9. By sparsity, a colimit indexed by is simply a finite coproduct in . The proof is complete upon observing that is also an additive tensor category, since distributivity over finite coproducts is equivalent to distributivity over finite products by additivity. ∎
Remark 4.13.
The right convolution tensor product seems less well known than its sinistral cousin, perhaps due to the apparent restrictiveness of sparsity. We direct the reader to [24] for a prior instance of its use; one assumes that there are other antecedents, but none are known to the author.
4.3. Examples
In this section, we specialize the general theory of the preceding section to the examples of interest.
Given a collision structure on and a function , we write for the largest collision structure on for which is a map of collision structures, i.e.,
It is easy to check that , so defined, is a collision structure; note, however, that it may be empty. In the case of the inclusion of a subset , we write .
Example 4.14.
If is the collision structure associated to a graph with vertex set according to Example 3.5, then is the collision structure associated to the full subgraph spanned by .
Example 4.15.
If is the collision structure associated to a simplicial complex with vertex set according to Example 3.6, then is the collision structure associated to the full subcomplex spanned by .
Write for the set of surjections of onto the set ; in other words, is the set of ordered partitions of with blocks.
Lemma 4.16.
Let be a collision structure on . For every , there is a canonical inclusion
which is final if is non-empty.
Proof.
We define the inclusion by sending to the map of collision structures given by the canonical bijection . Given collision structures on the finite sets and a bijective map of collision structures, define by defining to be the index such that ; note that there is precisely one such index by bijectivity. Then , and we have the commutative diagram:
Finality follows upon noting that the components of the dashed arrow are uniquely determined by commutativity, each component is a map of collision structures, and no such dashed arrow exists for any . ∎
Corollary 4.17.
If is a collision structure on , then is -separable as an object of for every , freely if is non-empty. In particular, is sparse.
Proof.
Since acts freely on , Lemma 4.16 directly implies that any collision structure on a non-empty finite set is freely -separable for every . For the edge case, we note that is a singleton for every . ∎
Corollary 4.18.
A graph, a simplicial complex, or a finite set is -separable as an object of , , or , respectively, for every , freely if non-empty. In particular, all three categories are sparse.
Proof.
Combining these corollaries with Corollary 4.12, we see that it is sensible to contemplate right Day convolution in this context. Corollary 4.10 and Lemma 4.16 yield the following formula for this tensor product.
Corollary 4.19.
Let be an additive tensor category. Given functors for and a collision structure on , there is a canonical natural isomorphism
5. Twisted Koszul duality
The purpose of this section is to explain how the theory of Koszul duality between Lie algebras and cocommutative coalgebras extends to the twisted setting—see Theorem 5.15. Classically, this theory is developed under two key assumptions: first, that the ground ring is a field of characteristic zero; second, that the graded objects in question are sufficiently connected [12, 33]. These assumptions serve to guarantee the good behavior of divided powers—their homotopy invariance and nilpotence, respectively. In our setting, the same good behavior is guaranteed instead by the presence of a weighting with certain natural properties—see Section 5.1. Otherwise, the arguments are essentially identical, and we will at times allow ourselves a certain brevity.
We work throughout over a fixed ground field , a limitation easily overcome by judicious assumptions of flatness.
5.1. Weights
In this section, we introduce a piece of extra structure that will serve as a substitute for connectivity and divisibility. In the next definition, we refer to Definition 4.11.
Definition 5.1.
Let be a monoidal category.
-
(1)
A weighting of is a lax monoidal functor . The value is the weight of . The pair is a weighted monoidal category
-
(2)
A combinatorial monoidal category is a weighted monoidal category such that is freely -separable for every whenever .
Concretely, a weighting amounts to the assignment of a non-negative integer to each such that the following inequalities hold for every :
-
(1)
whenever
-
(2)
.
Example 5.2.
Recording the cardinality of a finite set determines a weighting of , whence of , , and . By the results of Section 4.3, these weighted monoidal categories are combinatorial.
Definition 5.3.
Let be a weighted monoidal category and an additive tensor category. We say that a functor is concentrated in weight if whenever . If is concentrated in weight , then we say that is reduced.
This definition is justified by the following simple result.
Lemma 5.4.
If is an additive tensor category, then admits a zero object , and for every .
Proof.
Additivity guarantees the existence of the biproduct indexed by the empty set, which is to say a zero object. Second, since the tensor product of distributes over finite coproducts, we have
∎
The comparison to connectivity made above is justified by the following result.
Lemma 5.5.
Let be a sparse weighted symmetric monoidal category. If is concentrated in weight for , then is concentrated in weight .
Proof.
Let be an object with . From our assumption of sparsity and the definition of right Day convolution, there is a collection of arrows such that
so it suffices to show that each summand vanishes. We have the inequality
Since weights are non-negative, it follows that or , whence or .∎
The comparison to divisibility made above is justified by the following result.
Lemma 5.6.
Let be a combinatorial symmetric monoidal category and a natural transformation between reduced functors from to the category of chain complexes in an Abelian tensor category. If is a quasi-isomorphism in weight , then is a quasi-isomorphism in weight for every . In particular, if , then is a quasi-isomorphism in weight .
Proof.
Fix with . If , then by Lemma 5.5, and there is nothing to show, so assume otherwise. Then is freely -separable by our assumption on , so Corollary 4.10 grants the existence of a finite, -free set of morphisms such that
compatibly with . Since the are reduced, we may assume without loss of generality that for every and . It then follows from the inequality
that for every and . By assumption, is a quasi-isomorphism, so is a quasi-isomorphism. By freeness, this quasi-isomorphism descends to a quasi-isomorphism on -invariants, completing the proof. ∎
Remark 5.7.
In a previous version of this paper, Lemma 5.6 was stated with the weaker bound only. We thank the referee for pointing out that the proof establishes the improved bound.
5.2. Twisted (co)algebraic structures
We come now to the main definitions.
Definition 5.8.
Let be a sparse symmetric monoidal category. A -twisted Lie algebra (over ) is a Lie algebra in , regarded as symmetric monoidal under right Day convolution.
Similarly, one has the notion of a -twisted cocommutative coalgebra, and so on. In the case , one recovers the classical notion of a twisted (co)algebraic structure.
Remark 5.9.
As the reader may know, the term “Lie algebra” has several inequivalent definitions. Ultimately, we will specialize to a setting in which all such definitions coincide, so the reader is welcome to imagine that her favorite definition is also ours.
Given a -twisted cocommutative coalgebra , we write for the kernel of the counit .
Lemma 5.10.
Let be a -twisted Lie algebra and a -twisted cocommutative coalgebra.
-
(1)
The unique degree coderivation of extending the composite
squares to zero.
-
(2)
The unique degree derivation of extending the composite
squares to zero.
Proof.
We give only a brief outline, the proof being entirely parallel to the corresponding portions of [12, IV.22(b),(e)]. For the first claim, since the square of a coderivation of odd degree is again a coderivation, and since is cofree (as a conilpotent cocommutative coalgebra), it suffices to verify that the composite
vanishes, which is equivalent to the Jacobi identity. The proof of the second claim is essentially the same save that we appeal instead to coassociativity. ∎
This result permits the following fundamental definition.
Definition 5.11.
Let be a -twisted Lie algebra and a -twisted cocommutative coalgebra.
-
(1)
The Chevalley–Eilenberg complex of is the -twisted graded cocommutative coalgebra
Its homology is called the Lie algebra homology of and denoted .
-
(2)
The Quillen complex of is the -twisted graded Lie algebra
Remark 5.12.
Some readers may be surprised at the appearance of divided powers rather than symmetric powers in the Chevalley–Eilenberg complex. The two coincide in characteristic zero, and more generally in any setting in which the norm map is an isomorphism on tensor powers (as it will be below).
These two complexes are closely interrelated.
Lemma 5.13.
Let be a -twisted Lie algebra and a -twisted cocommutative coalgebra.
-
(1)
The map of -twisted coalgebras induced by the inclusion is a chain map.
-
(2)
The map of -twisted Lie algebras induced by the projection is a chain map.
Proof.
Again, we give only a brief outline, as the details are parallel to the relevant portions of the proof of [12, Thm. 22.9]. Writing and , respectively, for the clockwise and counterclockwise composites in the diagram
the first claim is the equality . Since is a map of coalgebras, the are coderivations; therefore, since is cofree, it suffices to check that the composite
is independent of , which is essentially a tautology. The proof of the second claim is similar. ∎
5.3. Duality
In order to state the main result, we require one further definition.
Definition 5.14.
Let be a sparse weighted symmetric monoidal category. We say that a -twisted Lie algebra is reduced if its underlying functor is so. We say that a -twisted cocommutative coalgebra is reduced if is so.
The goal of this section is to prove the following analogue of [12, Thm. 22.9].
Theorem 5.15.
If is combinatorial, then the maps and are quasi-isomorphisms on reduced objects.
The main ingredients are the following two lemmas.
Lemma 5.16.
If is combinatorial, then the Chevalley–Eilenberg complex preserves and reflects quasi-isomorphisms between reduced -twisted Lie algebras.
Proof.
Let be a map of -twisted Lie algebras. Assuming that is a quasi-isomorphism, Lemma 5.6 grants that is also a quasi-isomorphism for every . Filtering the Chevalley–Eilenberg complex by tensor degree, we conclude that induces a quasi-isomorphism at the level of associated graded complexes. By induction and the five lemma, it follows that is a quasi-isomorphism after restriction to any filtration stage; therefore, since direct limits preserve quasi-isomorphisms, itself is a quasi-isomorphism.
For reflection, we adapt the argument of [14, 4.1.9]. Assuming that is a quasi-isomorphism, let be of minimal weight such that is not a quasi-isomorphism. Since the are reduced, we have . Setting , we have the following commutative diagram of chain complexes with exact rows:
It suffices to show that the righthand vertical arrow is a quasi-isomorphism; indeed, since the middle arrow is a quasi-isomorphism by assumption, the five lemma then implies that the lefthand arrow is a quasi-isomorphism, a contradiction. To this end, we filter by tensor degree, as above, and observe that the associated graded pieces are of the form for . By minimality, is a quasi-isomorphism in weight , so Lemma 5.6 implies that is a quasi-isomorphism in weight for . In particular, the righthand vertical arrow above induces a quasi-isomorphism at the level of associated graded complexes, and the same argument as before completes the proof. ∎
Lemma 5.17.
The projection is a quasi-isomorphism.
Proof.
Since adjunctions compose, the universal enveloping algebra of is the tensor algebra ; therefore, the homology of the Chevalley–Eilenberg complex is canonically isomorphic to , which may be computed from the two-step complex . The claim follows immediately. ∎
With these results in hand, we complete the proof.
Proof of Theorem 5.15.
Filtering by bracket length, the associated graded Lie algebra is , and the induced filtration on has associated graded object . The composite
is the identity, and is a quasi-isomorphism by Lemma 5.17, so is also a quasi-isomorphism. It follows as before that is a quasi-isomorphism. It is easy to check that , so it follows that is a quasi-isomorphism, and Lemma 5.16 implies that is also a quasi-isomorphism. ∎
Remark 5.18.
In classical operadic Koszul duality [26], the cobar construction (playing the role of the Quillen complex) fails to preserve quasi-isomorphisms in general, so one obtains instead an equivalence between standard homotopy theory on the algebra side and a nonstandard homotopy theory on the coalgebra side. From this point of view, the main point of this section is that does preserve quasi-isomorphisms in our setting, which is the essential content of the reflection clause of Lemma 5.16.
6. Projection spaces
We arrive at last at our primary object of study. After cataloguing examples of projection spaces of interest, we define the functor of rational primitives and prove Theorems 1.2 and 1.3 as stated in the introduction.
6.1. Examples
We recall that, according to Definition 1.1, a projection space (over ) is a topological presheaf on . We begin with the most basic example.
Example 6.1.
Viewing a finite set as a discrete topological space defines a functor . By restriction along this functor, any presheaf of spaces on determines a projection space over (recall Proposition 2.8); in particular, this construction applies to the representable presheaf for any topological space . Under the identification , one checks that the structure map associated to the injection is the projection , whose th component is the projection onto the factor of indexed by .
Although this example is rather uninteresting, it gives rise to the main motivating example.
Example 6.2.
Given a finite set, the configuration space of -indexed points in is defined as the subspace of injective functions . Since the restriction of an injection along an injection is again an injection, the dashed filler exists in the diagram
so the collection of all such configuration spaces inherits the structure of a projection space over .
The next two examples generalize the previous two in the presence of an action by a group .
Example 6.3.
Applying the considerations of Example 6.1 to the inclusion and the functor represented by the -space , we obtain a projection space over (recall Corollary 2.10). Concretely, the value of this projection space on the finite free -set is , where we have written non-canonically. The structure maps combine the action of with the projections of Example 6.1.
Example 6.4.
Given a finite free -set , the orbit configuration space of -indexed points in is defined as the subspace of injective equivariant functions. Equivalently, writing (non-canonically), the orbit configuration space is the subspace of consisting of tuples with pairwise disjoint orbits, i.e., it is the pullback
Since equivariant injections are closed under composition, the first description endows the collection of orbit configuration spaces with the structure of a projection space over .
There is also a linear analogue of these examples. We fix a topological field , the cases of and being of greatest interest.
Example 6.5.
By restricting along the inclusion of into the category of topological vector spaces, a presheaf of spaces on the latter determines a projection space over (recall Corollary 2.10); in particular this construction applies to the representable presheaf for any topological vector space . Since the restriction of an injection along an injection is again an injection, the dashed filler exists in the diagram
where denotes the space of linear injections of into , which is simply the usual non-compact Stiefel manifold of -frames in the real or complex case.
Remark 6.6.
One imagines that our framework expands easily to encompass algebrogeometric examples such as flag varieties in positive characteristic.
Given a partition of , we write . Given a collision structure on , we set and define the generalized configuration space [32] associated to as
Notice that, if , then , so for any generating set .
Lemma 6.7.
Let and be collision structures on and , respectively, and an injective map of collision structures. The dashed filler exists in the diagram
Proof.
By our assumption on , we have the containment . On the other hand, we calculate that
where the last equality uses that is a generating set for by definition. Thus, we have the containment , as desired. ∎
Example 6.8.
Remark 6.9.
Example 6.10.
Restricting the projection space of Example 6.8 to , we obtain a projection space over extending the assignment on objects.
Example 6.11.
Restricting the projection space of Example 6.8 to , we obtain a projection space over extending the assignment on objects.
As the reader will easily verify, all of the examples of projection spaces given in this section are reduced.
6.2. Proofs of the main results
In the following definition, the reader may take the functor to be any symmetric replacement for the oplax monoidal functor rational singular chains. A specific example of such a replacement is given below in Appendix A.
Definition 6.12.
Let be a sparse symmetric monoidal category and a projection space over . The -twisted Lie algebra of (derived) rational primitives of is the value on of the composite functor
Proof of Theorem 1.2.
We turn now to stability. The prevailing philosophy that has emerged in the wake of the discovery of representation stability is that stability phenomena are the concrete consequences of finite generation results, representation stability itself being equivalent to finite generation over [6]. Prerequisitely, then, one requires an action.
A feature of the Chevalley–Eilenberg complex is that it is a symmetric monoidal functor, converting products into tensor products. Thus, as explained at greater length in [25], a central Lie subalgebra gives rise to an action of on Lie algebra homology, while an Abelian quotient gives rise to an action of on Lie algebra cohomology. Through Theorem 1.2, these two constructions give rise to a host of actions on the (co)homology of a projection space, each a potential source of stability phenomena.
Remark 6.13.
In the case , as shown in [25], these two types of action are united in the action of a single algebra, called a transit algebra. It is less clear how to describe their interaction in general, especially when is not a groupoid.
We now show that this potential is often realized in the classical case . A functor from this category (or its opposite) is a symmetric sequence, i.e., a list of objects indexed by the non-negative integers (their weights), together with a -action on the th object for each . We indicate the weight with a subscript, and we write for the symmetric sequence with and for .
Theorem 6.14.
If is a reduced -space, then is canonically a -module. This module is finitely generated provided L satisfies the following conditions.
-
(1)
is finite dimensional for every and .
-
(2)
for and for .
-
(3)
for fixed and sufficiently large.
It is well known that representation stability is equivalent to finite generation over the free twisted commutative algebra on a single generator in degree and weight , so Theorem 1.3 is a special case of this result. In general, the finite generation of the theorem implies a kind of generalized representation stability [34].
Remark 6.15.
We briefly contextualize the assumptions of the theorem. The third assumption is that is eventually highly connected; one should view this assumption, which resembles standard hypotheses in the study of homological stability, as the key assumption. The first assumption is simply that each component space is of finite type, as will be the case in most examples of interest. The second assumption, which may at first appear the strangest, is in fact also quite reasonable; indeed, it is not hard to show that it holds whenever is path connected in each weight, or more generally when is cogenerated cofreely by , as is the case for configuration spaces. One could weaken this assumption at the cost of a more involved statement.
Lemma 6.16.
If is a reduced -space, then admits the Abelian twisted Lie algebra as a canonical quotient.
Proof.
We begin by observing the canonical isomorphism of chain complexes. Extending by zero, we obtain the composite map
where the second composition factor is the projection to the quotient. This map is clearly surjective, and it is a map of Lie algebras; indeed, is reduced, and weight is additive under the bracket. ∎
Proof of Theorem 6.14.
The Chevalley–Eilenberg complex is the total complex of a bicomplex, whose differentials reflect the internal differential of the Lie algebra and the Lie bracket, respectively. One of the two spectral sequences associated to the dual of this bicomplex has the form
(we use our first assumption to guarantee that the dual of the divided power is the symmetric power). This spectral sequence is a spectral sequence of -modules by functoriality, since the action arises from a map of Lie algebras. As such a module, the -page is freely generated by , where
By our first assumption, is finite dimensional, so is Noetherian [37]; thus, it suffices to show that is finite dimensional in fixed degree , for which we calculate that
For fixed , this expression is finite dimensional by reducedness and our first assumption, so it suffices to show that it vanishes for sufficiently large. By our third assumption on , there exists sufficiently large so that for ; therefore, the summand indexed by vanishes for . On the other hand, our second assumption on implies that for , so we may take for in the above expression. It follows that the summands indexed by all vanish. Combining these observations, we conclude that for , as desired. ∎
Remark 6.17.
Let be a (for simplicity) orientable manifold of dimension . According to the conjecture articulated in Section 1.3(2), the homology of the Lie algebra of rational primitives of the ordinary configuration spaces of can be described in weight as the vector space , where is the th Lie representation. As long as , this Lie algebra satisfies the assumptions of Theorem 6.14, so we recover the primordial example of representation stability. This analysis does not actually depend on the validity of the conjecture, since the Chevalley–Eilenberg complex of this Lie algebra does calculate the correct homology.
Appendix A Sullivan chains
The cup product arises from the Alexander–Whitney map , a natural transformation constituting an oplax monoidal structure that is famously not symmetric. Fortunately, the failure of symmetry is governed by highly coherent homotopies, which are strictifiable in characteristic zero for abstract reasons.
The purpose of this appendix is to present an explicit model for this strictification. In brief, we construct a pre-dual of (a completion of) the functor of Sullivan cochains , a reference for which is [12, II.10(c)], where it is denoted . It is common to discuss this complex in barycentric coordinates, but the expression in increasing coordinates given in [36] will be more convenient for our purposes.
Write for the chain complex with basis , where . This complex carries a natural simplicial structure via the maps
The dual thus carries a natural cosimplicial structure.
Definition A.1.
Fix .
-
(1)
The complex of Sullivan cochains on the standard -simplex is the commutative differential graded algebra freely generated by .
-
(2)
The complex of Sullivan chains on the standard -simplex is the conilpotent cocommutative differential graded coalgebra cofreely cogenerated by .
-
(3)
The complex of completed Sullivan cochains on is regarded as a commutative differential graded algebra.
Each of these constructions inherits a (co)simplicial structure; indeed, each is obtained by applying a functor pointwise to a (co)simplicial object.
Definition A.2.
Write for the Yoneda embedding.
-
(1)
The functor of Sullivan cochains is the left Kan extension in the diagram
(resp. completed Sullivan cochains, ).
-
(2)
The functor of Sullivan chains is the left Kan extension in the diagram
The complex of Sullivan (co)chains on the topological space is the value of the corresponding functor on the singular set of .
Note the canonical isomorphism ; indeed, dualization is colimit preserving when viewed as a functor from cocommutative differential graded coalgebras to the opposite category of commutative differential graded algebras.
Lemma A.3.
The map induced by the composite is a quasi-isomorphism.
Proof.
By [12, Prop. 10.5], it suffices to check that the induced map is a quasi-isomorphism for each . Since the unique map is a quasi-isomorphism, and since symmetric powers preserve quasi-isomorphisms over , it follows that the unit of is a quasi-isomorphism. Since the linear dual of a quasi-isomorphism is also a quasi-isomorphism, it follows that the unique map is a quasi-isomorphism; therefore, after invoking the same property of symmetric powers a second time, it follows that the counit of is a quasi-isomorphism. By the same property of the linear dual, it now follows that the unit of is a quasi-isomorphism. Since the map in question is compatible with units, being a map of algebras, the claim follows. ∎
Theorem A.4.
Let be a simplicial set and write for the functor of rational normalized chains. There is a natural quasi-isomorphism of differential graded coalgebras.
Proof.
The proof closely follows that of [12, Thm. 10.9]. At the level of simplices, the respective counits induce the maps
of cosimplicial differential graded coalgebras. Since both are objectwise acyclic, these maps are quasi-isomorphisms. Kan extending, one obtains the zig-zag
where the rightmost isomorphism is justified by the observations that colimits of coalgebras are computed at the level of chain complexes; that is colimit-preserving; and that the identity functor is the left Kan extension of the Yoneda embedding along itself. One could argue directly that these maps are quasi-isomorphisms by appealing to a cosimplicial version of [12, Prop. 10.5]. Alternatively, consider the following commutative diagram of functors from simplicial sets to commutative differential graded algebras:
the top row is the linear dual of the zig-zag of interest, the maps in the bottom row are shown to be quasi-isomorphisms in [12, Thm. 10.9], and the lefthand vertical arrow is a quasi-isomorphism by Lemma A.3; therefore, since formation of the linear dual reflects quasi-isomorphisms, it suffices to show that the vertical maps in the middle column are quasi-isomorphisms. By [12, Prop. 10.5], it suffices to show that the maps
are quasi-isomorphisms for each . The first is the quasi-isomorphism of Lemma A.3 tensored with the identity. The second is the canonical map from the tensor product of the linear duals to the linear dual of the tensor product, which is a quasi-isomorphism on complexes with finite dimensional homology. ∎
Corollary A.5.
Let be a topological space. There is a natural quasi-isomorphism
of differential graded coalgebras and of oplax monoidal functors.
Proof.
Restricting the quasi-isomorphism of Theorem A.4 along the singular set functor, we obtain the desired quasi-isomorphism of coalgebras. To complete the proof, we need only recall that the coalgebra structure on singular chains determines the oplax monoidal structure via
∎
Remark A.6.
One imagines that our approach in this appendix translates essentially unchanged to the setting of [36], providing a symmetric model for integral singular chains. We have not checked the details.
References
- [1] M. Aguiar and S. Mahajan. Monoidal Functors, Species and Hopf Algebras. Amer. Math. Soc., 2010.
- [2] B. An, G. Drummond-Cole, and B. Knudsen. Edge stabilization in the homology of graph braid groups. Geom. Topol., 24(1):421–469, 2020.
- [3] C. Bibby and N. Gadish. A generating function approach to new representation stability phenomena in orbit configuration spaces. arXiv:1911.02125.
- [4] L. Brantner, J. Hahn, and B. Knudsen. The Lubin–Tate theory of configuration spaces: I. arXiv:1908.11321.
- [5] T. Church and J. Ellenberg. Homology of FI-modules. Geom. Topol., 21(4):2373–2418, 2017.
- [6] T. Church, J. S. Ellenberg, and B. Farb. FI-modules and stability for representations of symmetric groups. Duke Math. J., 164(9):1833–1910, 2015.
- [7] A. Cooper, V. de Silva, and R. Sazdanovic. On configuration spaces and simplicial complexes. New York J. Math., 25:723–744, 2019.
- [8] B. Day. On closed categories of functors. In Reports of the Midwest Category Seminar IV, pages 1–38, 1970.
- [9] G. Drummond-Cole and B. Knudsen. Betti numbers of configuration spaces of surfaces. J. London Math. Society, 96:367–393, 2017.
- [10] M. Eastwood and S. Huggett. Euler characteristics and chromatic polynomials. Eur. J. Comb., 28(6):1553–1560, 2007.
- [11] J. Ellenberg, T. Tran, and C. Westerland. Fox–Neuwirth–Fuks cells, quantum shuffle algebras, and Malle’s conjecture for function fields. arXiv:1701.04541.
- [12] Y. Félix, S. Halperin, and J.-C. Thomas. Rational Homotopy Theory. Springer, 2001.
- [13] Y. Félix and J.-C. Thomas. Rational Betti numbers of configuration spaces. Topology Appl., 102:139–149, 2000.
- [14] J. Francis and D. Gaitsgory. Chiral Koszul duality. Selecta Math. (N.S.), 18:27–87, 2012.
- [15] N. Gadish and L. Hainaut. Configuration spaces on a wedge of spheres and Hochschild–Pirashvili homology. arXiv:2202.12494.
- [16] E. Getzler. Resolving mixed Hodge modules on configuration spaces. Duke Math. J., 96(1):175–203, 1999.
- [17] S. Glasman. Day convolution for -categories. Math. Res. Lett., 23(5):1369–1385, 2016.
- [18] D. Grayson. Higher algebraic K-theory: II (after Daniel Quillen). In Algebraic K-theory, volume 551 of Lecture Notes in Math., 1976.
- [19] R. Hepworth. On the edge of the stable range. Math. Ann., 377(1):123–181, 2020.
- [20] Q. Ho. Higher representation stability for ordered configuration spaces and twisted commutative factorization algebras. arXiv:2004.00252.
- [21] Q. Ho. Homological stability and densities of generalized configuration spaces. Geom. Topol., 25(2):813–912, 2021.
- [22] N. Idrissi. The Lambrechts–Stanley model of configuration spaces. Invent. Math., 216:1–68, 2019.
- [23] B. Knudsen. Betti numbers and stability for configuration spaces via factorization homology. Alg. Geom. Topol., 17:3137–3187, 2017.
- [24] B. Knudsen. Higher enveloping algebras. Geom. Topol., 22:4013–4066, 2018.
- [25] B. Knudsen, J. Miller, and P. Tosteson. Extremal stability for configuration spaces. Math. Ann., 2022.
- [26] J.-L. Loday and B. Vallette. Algebraic Operads. Springer, 2012.
- [27] M. Mandell, J. P. May, S. Schwede, and B. Shipley. Model categories of diagram spectra. Proc. Lond. Math. Soc., 82(2):441–512, 2001.
- [28] J. P. May. The Geometry of Iterated loop spaces, volume 271 of Lecture Notes in Math. Springer, 1972.
- [29] D. McDuff. Configuration spaces of positive and negative particles. Topology, 14:91–107, 1975.
- [30] J. Miller and J. Wilson. Higher order representation stability and ordered configuration spaces of manifolds. Geom. Topol., 23(5), 2016.
- [31] R. Nagpal, S. Sam, and A. Snowden. Noetherianity of some degree two twisted skew-commutative algebras. Selecta Math. (N.S.), 25, 2019.
- [32] D. Petersen. Cohomology of generalized configuration spaces. Compos. Math., 156(2):251–298, 2020.
- [33] D. Quillen. Rational homotopy theory. Ann. Math., 1969.
- [34] E. Ramos. Generalized representation stability and -modules. Proc. Amer. Math. Soc, 145(11):4647–4660, 2017.
- [35] O. Randal-Williams and N. Wahl. Homological stability for automorphism groups. Adv. Math., 318:534–626, 2017.
- [36] B. Richter and S. Sagave. A strictly commutative model for the cochain algebra of a space. Compos. Math., 156(8):1718–1743, 2020.
- [37] A. Snowden. Syzygies of Segre embeddings and -modules. Duke Math. J., 162(2):225–277, 2013.
- [38] B. Totaro. Configuration spaces of algebraic varieties. Topology, 35(4):1057–1067, 1996.