This paper was converted on www.awesomepapers.org from LaTeX by an anonymous user.
Want to know more? Visit the Converter page.

Probabilistic consequence relations

Paul Égré IRL Crossing, CNRS. [email protected]    David Ripley Monash University. [email protected]
Abstract

This paper investigates logical consequence defined in terms of probability distributions, for a classical propositional language using a standard notion of probability. We examine three distinct probabilistic consequence notions, which we call material consequence, preservation consequence, and symmetric consequence. While material consequence is fully classical for any threshold, preservation consequence and symmetric consequence are subclassical, with only symmetric consequence gradually approaching classical logic at the limit threshold equal to 1. Our results extend earlier results obtained by J. Paris in a Set-Fmla setting to the Set-Set setting, and consider open thresholds beside closed ones. In the Set-Set setting, in particular, they reveal that probability 1 preservation does not yield classical logic, but supervaluationism, and conversely positive probability preservation yields subvaluationism.

1 Introduction

Logical validity for an argument is defined differently depending on whether one thinks of deductive or inductive arguments. In the deductive case, the standard definition of logical consequence is in terms of truth preservation (see Tarski, 1936; Ladd-Franklin and Peirce, 1902). In the inductive case, it is in terms of probability preservation (Skyrms, 1966; Ladd-Franklin and Peirce, 1902). Truth and probability are distinct notions, and one should not expect the preservation of the one to coincide with the preservation of the other, except in limit cases.

When arguments have a set of premises and a single conclusion (what we, following Humberstone, 2011, call the Set-Fmla framework), classical logic is such a limit case. In this framework, classical validity can be semantically characterized either in terms of preserving truth or in terms of preserving certainty (probability 1) (Hailperin, 1984; Adams, 1998; Paris, 2004). When the premises are not certain, however, then we get well-known departures from classical logic. The most famous example is given by lottery cases (Kyburg, 1997): the probability of AA (“ticket 1 will lose”) and the probability of BB (“ticket 2 will lose”) can both exceed a threshold less than 1 (say 23\frac{2}{3} in a 3-ticket lottery), but the probability of ABA\wedge B can fall below that threshold (to as low as 13\frac{1}{3}).

Cases in which premises are believed with less than certainty are extremely common in everyday reasoning, and they raise a natural question: what logics govern the preservation of high (but possibly not 1) probability? This question has received attention from various scholars, notably from Ernest Adams, Kevin Knight, and Jeff Paris (see Adams, 1996; Knight, 2003; Paris, 2004). Paris, in particular, produces a sound and complete axiomatization for logics defined in terms of probability preservation at or above a rational number between 0 and 1.

In this paper we are interested in a generalization of this question along two main directions. The first direction concerns the format of arguments. For Paris, and similarly for Adams and Knight, arguments are given in a multiple-premises single-conclusion setting (Set-Fmla). We are interested in the multiple-premises multiple-conclusions case (Set-Set) as well. One motivation for that is that this generalization casts a novel light on the characterization of some non-classical logics that coincide with classical logic in the Set-Fmla case, but that differ from it in the Set-Set case, namely supervaluationist logic on the one hand (Fine, 1975), and subvaluationist logic on the other (Jaśkowski, 1969; Varzi, 1994; Hyde, 1997).

The second direction has to do with a variation on the notion of probability preservation, using a more general template entertained by Knight and Paris, allowing probabilistic thresholds to vary depending on premises and conclusions (see Paris, 2004; Knight, 2003). Consider a lottery case again: although the probability of a conjunction is typically less than the probability of either conjunct, there are well-known lower and upper bounds on the probability that a conjunction can take, namely the Fréchet-Hoeffding bounds (Fréchet, 1935), whereby max(0,p(A)+p(B)1)p(AB)min(p(A),p(B))\max(0,p(A)+p(B)-1)\leq p(A\wedge B)\leq\min(p(A),p(B)). Thus, when the probability of AA and that of BB are both at least 23\frac{2}{3}, the probability of the conjunction cannot be less than 13\frac{1}{3}. This observation is also central in the study of probabilistic coherence (see Knight, 2002; Biazzo et al., 2005), since it puts constraints on the attitude of rational belief that an agent ought to have in uncertain cases.

We use it to define a notion of validity which we call “symmetric validity”. The notion basically requires that when premises are believed above some threshold α\alpha, then not all conclusions can be disbelieved with probability less than 1α1-\alpha. Unlike preservation logics, symmetric logics give us more texture regarding the relation between thresholds and logical operations. Unlike preservation logics, moreover, the resulting logics display interesting substructural, non-Tarskian features. Such logics have a closely related counterpart in the area of fuzzy logic (see Cobreros et al., 2024), but they display fundamentally different properties.

Two main caveats need to be made before we proceed. The first is that, unlike in particular Adams, (1996), in this paper we will not deal with the incorporation of a special conditional connective in the language to express the notion of conditional probability. The language will be perfectly classical; the only conditional we consider is the classical material conditional. The second caveat is that the notion of probability we will be using is entirely classical too, unlike in recent work concerned with the incorporation of probability to non-classical logics (see Klein et al., 2021; Égré et al., 2024).

The material of this paper is organized as follows. First, in Section 2 we introduce the kinds of probabilistic models we use to define logical consequence. In Section 3 we then start with a notion of consequence that allows us to build an exact probabilistic match with classical consequence in the Set-Set setting, and which we call material consequence. The next three sections deal with the study of preservation consequence: Section 4 opens up with the special case of the extreme thresholds 1{1} and (0,1](0,1] to give a probabilistic characterization of super- and sub-valuationism. Section 5 then looks at the general case. Section 6 establishes how many different preservation properties there are and discusses their structural properties. Section 7 deals with symmetric consequence. Finally, Section 8 concludes on the way in which the three approaches relate to each other and to classical logic.

2 Probabilistic models

2.1 Language and models

Throughout this paper we work with a propositional language \mathcal{L} with a countable infinity of atomic sentences p,q,r,p,q,r,\ldots, a unary connective ¬\neg for negation and a binary connective \lor for disjunction. We also make use of connectives ,,,\land,\bot,\top,\mathrel{\supset}; these are officially understood as defined from ¬,\neg,\vee as usual.

Definition 1.

An argument Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is a pair of finite sets Γ,Δ\Gamma,\Delta of sentences from \mathcal{L}.

To evaluate arguments, we need models, and we use what we call probabilistic models.

Definition 2.

A probabilistic model is a quadruple 𝔐=W,𝒜,,p\mathfrak{M}=\langle W,\mathcal{A},\llbracket\;\rrbracket,\textsc{p}\rangle, where:

  • WW is a nonempty set of worlds;

  • 𝒜\mathcal{A} is an algebra on WW, which is to say:

    • 𝒜(W)\mathcal{A}\subseteq\wp(W),

    • 𝒜\emptyset\in\mathcal{A},

    • for any A𝒜A\in\mathcal{A}, we have WA𝒜W\setminus A\in\mathcal{A}, and

    • for any A,B𝒜A,B\in\mathcal{A}, we have AB𝒜A\cup B\in\mathcal{A};

  • \llbracket\;\rrbracket is a classical denotation function, a function 𝒜\mathcal{L}\to\mathcal{A} such that:

    • ¬ϕ=Wϕ\llbracket\neg\phi\rrbracket=W\setminus\llbracket\phi\rrbracket

    • ϕψ=ϕψ\llbracket\phi\lor\psi\rrbracket=\llbracket\phi\rrbracket\cup\llbracket\psi\rrbracket; and

  • p is a probability function, a function 𝒜\interval01\mathcal{A}\to\interval{0}{1} such that:

    • p()=0\textsc{p}(\emptyset)=0,

    • p(WA)=1p(A)\textsc{p}(W\setminus A)=1-\textsc{p}(A), and

    • if A,B𝒜A,B\in\mathcal{A} and AB=A\cap B=\emptyset, then p(AB)=p(A)+p(B)\textsc{p}(A\cup B)=\textsc{p}(A)+\textsc{p}(B).

Some notational shorthand involving these models will prove useful:

First, given such a model, we often treat p also as a function [0,1]\mathcal{L}\to[0,1], writing just ‘p(ϕ)\textsc{p}(\phi)’ to mean p(ϕ)\textsc{p}(\llbracket\phi\rrbracket). In effect, we treat ‘p’ as ambiguous between p itself and p\textsc{p}\circ\llbracket\;\rrbracket, trusting in context and in your indulgence. Second, given such a model, we also say that ‘ww makes ϕ\phi true’, or that ‘ϕ\phi is true at ww’, when wϕw\in\llbracket\phi\rrbracket. Third, we will sometimes write ‘𝔐p\mathfrak{M}_{\textsc{p}}’ to indicate some W,𝒜,,p\langle W,\mathcal{A},\llbracket\;\rrbracket,\textsc{p}\rangle, where we will have no need of further reference to W,𝒜,W,\mathcal{A}, or \llbracket\;\rrbracket.

Note that in the case where WW is finite and where {w}𝒜\{w\}\in\mathcal{A} for every wWw\in W, then to fully specify p it suffices to give p{w}\textsc{p}{\{w\}} for each wWw\in W, such that these probabilities of singletons sum to 1. In this case we must have 𝒜=(W)\mathcal{A}=\wp(W), and the probabilities of all other elements of 𝒜\mathcal{A} are determined by finite additivity.111The difference between finite additivity and countable additivity doesn’t matter for our purposes in this paper. Finite additivity is enough for all our proofs to go through, so we don’t require more; but in fact all the particular models we specify are finite, and so their finite additivity suffices for them to be countably additive as well. Requiring countable additivity instead, then, wouldn’t have any effect on what follows here.

These models, with their modal structure, are handy for a number of the manipulations to follow, and they connect nicely to the structures used for example in Moss, (2018). Much of the literature on probabilistic logic, however, uses less complex structures, just probability distributions:

Definition 3.

A probability distribution is a function [0,1]\mathcal{L}\to[0,1] such that:

  • p()=0\textsc{p}(\bot)=0,

  • p(¬ϕ)=1p(ϕ)\textsc{p}(\neg\phi)=1-\textsc{p}(\phi), and

  • if ϕ,ψCL\phi,\psi\vdash_{CL}\bot then p(ϕψ)=p(ϕ)+p(ψ)\textsc{p}(\phi\lor\psi)=\textsc{p}(\phi)+\textsc{p}(\psi), where CL\vdash_{CL} is classical consequence.

It is quick to see that, given any probabilistic model W,𝒜,,p\langle W,\mathcal{A},\llbracket\;\rrbracket,\textsc{p}\rangle, indeed p\textsc{p}\circ\llbracket\;\rrbracket (which, again, we often write just as ‘p’) is always a probability distribution. We can also go in the other direction, filling in any probability distribution to an entire probabilistic model. However, it is more convenient for our purposes to show the following related fact: that we can take any probability distribution together with any finite Γ\Gamma\subseteq\mathcal{L}, and create a finite probabilistic model that agrees with p in its assignments of probabilities to every sentence in Γ\Gamma.

Fact 4.

Given any finite set Γ\Gamma of sentences, let At(Γ)At(\Gamma) be the (necessarily finite) set of atomic sentences occurring in Γ\Gamma. Then for any probability distribution p, there is a probabilistic model 𝔐pΓ=WpΓ,𝒜pΓ,pΓ,ppΓ)\mathfrak{M}^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}}=\langle W^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}},\mathcal{A}^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}},\llbracket\;\rrbracket^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}},\textsc{p}^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}})\rangle such that:

  • WpΓ=(At(Γ))W^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}}=\wp(At(\Gamma));

  • 𝒜pΓ=(WpΓ)\mathcal{A}^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}}=\wp(W^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}});

  • for every atom pAt(Γ)p\in At(\Gamma), ppΓ={wWpΓ|pw}\llbracket p\rrbracket^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}}=\{w\in W^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}}\;|\;p\in w\}; and

  • for every sentence γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma, ppΓ(γ)=p(γ)\textsc{p}^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}}(\gamma)=\textsc{p}(\gamma).

Proof.

There is no decision to be made for WpΓW^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}} and 𝒜pΓ\mathcal{A}^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}}; these are specified in the claim. So we just need to specify pΓ\llbracket\;\rrbracket^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}} and ppΓ\textsc{p}^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}} in a way that meets the claims. We know ppΓ\llbracket p\rrbracket^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}} for all pAt(Γ)p\in At(\Gamma); for any qAt(Γ)q\not\in At(\Gamma), let qpΓ=\llbracket q\rrbracket^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}}=\emptyset.222This is just for concreteness; really it doesn’t matter what qpΓ\llbracket q\rrbracket^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}} is when qAt(Γ)q\not\in At(\Gamma).

If At(Γ)={p1,,pn}At(\Gamma)=\{p_{1},\ldots,p_{n}\}, let a state description be any sentence of the form ±p1±pn\pm p_{1}\land\ldots\land\pm p_{n}, where ±pi\pm p_{i} is either pip_{i} or ¬pi\neg p_{i}. We have a bijection from state descriptions to worlds in WpΓW^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}} given by pΓ\llbracket\;\rrbracket^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}}; let its inverse be SS. (For example, if n=4n=4, then S({p1,p3})=p1¬p2p3¬p4S(\{p_{1},p_{3}\})=p_{1}\land\neg p_{2}\land p_{3}\land\neg p_{4}.)

To specify ppΓ\textsc{p}^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}} in full, it suffices to specify it on singletons. For each wWpΓw\in W^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}}, let ppΓ({w})=p(S(w))\textsc{p}^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}}(\{w\})=\textsc{p}(S(w)). Now, since S(w)pΓ={w}\llbracket S(w)\rrbracket^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}}=\{w\}, this gives us that for every ww, we have ppΓ(S(w))=p(S(w))\textsc{p}^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}}(S(w))=\textsc{p}(S(w)). Moreover, every state description is S(w)S(w) for some wWpΓw\in W^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}}, so for every state description ss we have ppΓ(s)=p(s)\textsc{p}^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}}(s)=\textsc{p}(s). Since any two distinct state descriptions are classically inconsistent with each other, this in turn ensures that for any disjunction δ\delta of state descriptions, ppΓ(δ)=p(δ)\textsc{p}^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}}(\delta)=\textsc{p}(\delta). But every γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma is classically equivalent to some disjunction of state descriptions, so for all such γ\gamma we have ppΓ(γ)=p(γ)\textsc{p}^{\Gamma}_{\textsc{p}}(\gamma)=\textsc{p}(\gamma), as needed.333Taking \bot to be the disjunction of the empty set of state descriptions. Similarly, the case where At(Γ)=At(\Gamma)=\emptyset is perhaps not very interesting, but it is included in this reasoning, taking the conjunction of 0 conjuncts (the only state description in such a case) to be \top.

2.2 Classical, super- and subvaluationist validity

With these models in hand, we proceed to define a few familiar non-probabilistic notions of validity. (These three notions make no use of the final coordinate in these models, but we stick to full probabilistic models for the sake of uniformity.) Our first concept of validity is classical validity, which we define in terms of truth preservation:

Definition 5.

We say that Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is classically valid, written ΓCLΔ\Gamma\models_{CL}\Delta, iff for every probabilistic model 𝔐p=W,𝒜,,p\mathfrak{M}_{\textsc{p}}=\langle W,\mathcal{A},\llbracket\;\rrbracket,\textsc{p}\rangle and every world wWw\in W, if ww makes every γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma true, then ww makes some δΔ\delta\in\Delta true. Equivalently, Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is classically valid iff for every model 𝔐p\mathfrak{M}_{\textsc{p}}, ΓΔ=W\llbracket\bigwedge\Gamma\mathrel{\supset}\bigvee\Delta\rrbracket=W.

We also consider two germane notions of logical consequence: supervaluationist validity is preservation of super-truth (truth at every world), and subvaluationist validity is preservation of sub-truth (truth at some world).

Definition 6.

We say that Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is supervaluationistically valid, written ΓSVΔ\Gamma\models_{SV}\Delta, iff for every probabilistic model 𝔐p=W,𝒜,,p\mathfrak{M}_{\textsc{p}}=\langle W,\mathcal{A},\llbracket\;\rrbracket,\textsc{p}\rangle, if every γ\gamma is true at every world of WW, then some δ\delta is true at every world of WW. Equivalently, Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is supervaluationistically valid iff, if γ=W\llbracket\gamma\rrbracket=W for every γG\gamma\in G, then δ=W\llbracket\delta\rrbracket=W for some δG\delta\in G.

Definition 7.

We say that Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is subvaluationistically valid, written ΓsVΔ\Gamma\models_{sV}\Delta, iff for every probabilistic model 𝔐p=W,𝒜,,p\mathfrak{M}_{\textsc{p}}=\langle W,\mathcal{A},\llbracket\;\rrbracket,\textsc{p}\rangle, if every γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma is true at some world ww, then some δΔ\delta\in\Delta is true at some world; Equivalently, Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is subvaluationistically valid iff, if γ\llbracket\gamma\rrbracket\neq\emptyset for every γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma, then δ\llbracket\delta\rrbracket\neq\emptyset for some δΔ\delta\in\Delta.

While supervaluationist validity and subvaluationist validity coincide with classical validity in the Set-Fmla case and the Fmla-Set case, respectively, they differ in the Set-Set framework (see Hyde, 1997; Ripley, 2013). In particular, p¬p⊧̸SVp,¬pp\vee\neg p\not\models_{SV}p,\neg p, and p,¬p⊧̸sVp¬pp,\neg p\not\models_{sV}p\wedge\neg p, that is we lose abjunction and adjunction, respectively, in those frameworks.

2.3 Probabilistic consequence: The general recipe

We defined classical validity, supervaluationist validity, and subvaluationist validity in terms of truth preservation, but we shall see that each has an equivalent characterization in terms of probability preservation, which is what drives the introduction of probabilistic models in the first place.

Our notions of consequence over these probabilistic models all follow a general recipe. First, we take for granted some set α\interval01\alpha\subseteq\interval{0}{1} that is to count as the ‘good’ probabilities: sentences with probabilities in α\alpha are those with a probability high enough. We remain neutral throughout as to what such probabilities are high enough for; we hope our results here can be useful to a range of possible interpretations and applications.

We make three assumptions about our set α\alpha of ‘good’ probabilities: it contains 1, it does not contain 0, and it is an upset, in the sense that for any x,y\interval01x,y\in\interval{0}{1} with xyx\leq y, if xαx\in\alpha then yαy\in\alpha. We refer to all such sets simply as upsets, taking for granted the conditions about 1 and 0. To fix ideas and notation, note that every upset α\alpha has an infimum infα\inf\alpha, which we call α\alpha’s threshold, and that for any 0<x<10<x<1, there are exactly two upsets with threshold xx: namely, \interval[softopenfences,openleft]x1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{x}{1} and \intervalx1\interval{x}{1}.444Since all upsets exclude 0, there is only an open upset with threshold 0; and since all upsets include 1, there is only a closed upset with threshold 1. We call upsets \interval[softopenfences,openleft]x1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{x}{1} open and upsets \intervalx1\interval{x}{1} closed. This gives a convenient way to specify any upset: simply by giving its threshold and saying whether it is open or closed.

Let a counterexample notion be a three-place relation between upsets, probabilistic models, and arguments. Given a counterexample notion and an upset α\alpha, we always determine a consequence relation following the same recipe: count an argument as valid iff there is no probabilistic model that bears the counterexample notion relation to α\alpha and that argument.

3 Material consequence

The bulk of the paper considers two main counterexample notions in the probabilistic setting, which we will call preservation consequence and symmetric consequence. As a warm-up and an aid to later discussion, in this brief section we first explore a distinct option, which we call material consequence.

Definition 8.

Given an upset α\alpha, a probabilistic model 𝔐p\mathfrak{M}_{\textsc{p}} is an α\alpha material counterexample to an argument Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta iff p(ΓΔ)α\textsc{p}(\bigwedge\Gamma\mathrel{\supset}\bigvee\Delta)\not\in\alpha. Thus, the argument Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is α\alpha-materially valid iff every 𝔐p\mathfrak{M}_{\textsc{p}} is such that p(ΓΔ)α\textsc{p}(\bigwedge\Gamma\mathrel{\supset}\bigvee\Delta)\in\alpha.

That is, to see whether a probabilistic model is a material counterexample to an argument, we first roll the entire argument up into a single sentence, and then check the probability of that sentence on the model. If the probability is not high enough (is not in the specified upset), then we have a counterexample; if the probability is high enough (is in the upset), then we do not have a counterexample. The arguments that are α\alpha-materially valid, then, are those whose associated sentences always have probabilities in α\alpha. This, we think, is a reasonable enough notion. We know how to assign probabilities to sentences, and there is a natural way of associating a sentence to each argument; material consequence results from putting these two ideas together.

One upshot of this idea, though, is that the dependence on an upset α\alpha is an illusion:

Fact 9.

For any upset α\alpha, the argument Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is α\alpha-materially valid iff it is classically valid.

Proof.

From the definition of material validity, Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is α\alpha-materially valid iff for all probability models 𝔐p\mathfrak{M}_{\textsc{p}}, we have p(ΓΔ)α\textsc{p}(\bigwedge\Gamma\mathrel{\supset}\bigvee\Delta)\in\alpha. And it’s well-known that Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is classically valid iff ΓΔ\bigwedge\Gamma\mathrel{\supset}\bigvee\Delta is a classical tautology. So it’s enough to show that for any upset α\alpha and any sentence ϕ\phi, there is a probability model 𝔐p\mathfrak{M}_{\textsc{p}} with p(ϕ)α\textsc{p}(\phi)\not\in\alpha iff ϕ\phi is not a classical tautology.

All classical tautologies ϕ\phi have probability 1 on every probability model since ϕ=W\llbracket\phi\rrbracket=W, so the left-to-right direction is immediate by contraposition. For the right-to-left direction, note that for any ϕ\phi that is not a classical tautology, there is a probability model 𝔐p\mathfrak{M}_{\textsc{p}} such that ϕW\llbracket\phi\rrbracket\neq W. Let p\textsc{p}^{\prime} be a probability function based on the same model such that p(ϕ)=0\textsc{p}^{\prime}(\llbracket\phi\rrbracket)=0 and p(W\ϕ)=1\textsc{p}^{\prime}(W\backslash\llbracket\phi\rrbracket)=1; such a probability function exists, as it suffices that it concentrates all the mass on a single world in W\ϕW\backslash\llbracket\phi\rrbracket. By Fact 4, there is a model 𝔐pϕ\mathfrak{M}_{\textsc{p}^{\prime}}^{\phi} in which ppϕ(ϕ)=p(ϕ)=0\textsc{p}^{\prime\phi}_{\textsc{p}^{\prime}}(\phi)=\textsc{p}^{\prime}(\phi)=0.

Material validity, then, always perfectly matches classical validity, regardless of which upset we choose. This fact is interesting in its own right, and it also helps circumscribe the applications where material validity might be of some interest: those where reasoning under uncertainty should nonetheless hold exactly to classical standards.

In the rest of the paper, however, we explore other options besides this. We are particularly interested in approaches to reasoning under uncertainty that capture a different kind of insight: the idea that classicality should emerge at the limit, when things are certain (that is, at the upset {1}\{1\}); but that some nonclassical features can be appropriate when more uncertainty is in the air (that is, for looser upsets).

4 Preservation consequence: the {1}\{1\} and (0,1](0,1] cases

In this section we introduce the probabilistic counterexample notion that is arguably the most natural, namely preservation. We start with some examples and then characterize the two extremes of preservation consequence, which turn out to match super- and sub-valuationist validity.

4.1 Definition

Definition 10.

A probabilistic model 𝔐p\mathfrak{M}_{\textsc{p}} is an α\alpha-preservation counterexample to an argument Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta iff p[Γ]α\textsc{p}[\Gamma]\subseteq\alpha and p[Δ]\interval01α\textsc{p}[\Delta]\subseteq\interval{0}{1}\setminus\alpha. Thus, the argument Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is α\alpha-preservation valid iff every 𝔐p\mathfrak{M}_{\textsc{p}} is such that if p[Γ]α\textsc{p}[\Gamma]\subseteq\alpha, then there is some δΔ\delta\in\Delta with p(δ)α\textsc{p}(\delta)\in\alpha.

This is just like usual designated-values approaches to defining consequence, here using probabilities in α\alpha as our designated values. An α\alpha-preservation counterexample to an argument is one that takes all the premises of the argument, and none of its conclusions, to designated values. An argument is α\alpha-preservation valid, then, where there is no way to do this, when any probabilistic model that gives all premises probabilities in α\alpha must also give some conclusion a probability in α\alpha.

For example, consider the upset \interval[softopenfences,openleft].71\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{.7}{1} and the probabilities associated with a single roll of a fair 6-sided die. Let pp be the proposition that the die comes up >1>1, let qq be the proposition that the die comes up <6<6, and let p come from a probabilistic model that assigns appropriate probabilities to this situation. Then p(p)=p(q)=56>.7\textsc{p}(p)=\textsc{p}(q)=\frac{5}{6}>.7, while p(pq)=46<.7\textsc{p}(p\land q)=\frac{4}{6}<.7. So the argument p,q\Yrightpqp,q\,\Yright\,p\land q is not \interval[softopenfences,openleft].71\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{.7}{1}-preservation valid; there is a \interval[softopenfences,openleft].71\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{.7}{1}-preservation counterexample. (As we will see, the argument p,q\Yrightpqp,q\,\Yright\,p\land q is α\alpha-preservation valid only for one choice of α\alpha, namely, {1}\{1\}.)

On the other hand, consider the upset \interval.41\interval{.4}{1} and the argument p¬q,q¬p,¬(pq)\Yrightp\land\neg q,q\land\neg p,\neg(p\lor q)\,\Yright\,\bot. Note that any \interval.41\interval{.4}{1}-preservation counterexample to this argument would have to assign a probability .4\geq.4 to each of p¬qp\land\neg q, q¬pq\land\neg p, and ¬(pq)\neg(p\lor q). Since these three sentences are pairwise incompatible, this isn’t possible, since the sum of those values would have to exceed 1. So there can be no \interval.41\interval{.4}{1}-preservation counterexample to this argument, and the argument is \interval.41\interval{.4}{1}-preservation valid. On the other hand, there are probabilistic models that assign a probability of 13\frac{1}{3} to each of these sentences, so the same argument is not \interval.31\interval{.3}{1}-preservation valid.

4.2 Super and subvaluationism

Given our setup, there are two extreme upsets: the smallest upset {1}\{1\} and the largest upset \interval[softopenfences,openleft]01\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1}.555Recall that we require that every upset includes 11 and excludes 0. We leave consideration of the situation involving {}\{\} and \interval01\interval{0}{1} as exercises for the interested reader. In this section, we show that the preservation consequence relations associated with these extreme upsets are familiar from non-probabilistic work.

Fact 11.

An argument Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is {1}\{1\}-preservation valid iff it is supervaluationistically valid.

Proof.

Left to right: suppose that there is a supervaluational counterexample to Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta. This is a probabilistic model W,𝒜,,p\langle W,\mathcal{A},\llbracket\;\rrbracket,\textsc{p}\rangle such that for every γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma we have γ=W\llbracket\gamma\rrbracket=W and for each δΔ\delta\in\Delta we have δW\llbracket\delta\rrbracket\neq W. We’re going to use this to generate a new probabilistic model W,𝒜,,p\langle W,\mathcal{A},\llbracket\;\rrbracket,\textsc{p}^{\prime}\rangle.

Since Δ\Delta is finite, let nn be the number of its members; and for every δiΔ\delta_{i}\in\Delta, choose some world wiδiw_{i}\not\in\llbracket\delta_{i}\rrbracket. Now let p\textsc{p}^{\prime} be the probability distribution that assigns probability 1n\frac{1}{n} to each such wiw_{i} and probability 0 to all other worlds.

To see that W,𝒜,,p\langle W,\mathcal{A},\llbracket\;\rrbracket,\textsc{p}\rangle is a {1}\{1\}-preservation counterexample to Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta, note first that γ=W\llbracket\gamma\rrbracket=W for each γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma, so p(γ)=1\textsc{p}(\gamma)=1 for each of these as well. And also note that since wiδiw_{i}\not\in\llbracket\delta_{i}\rrbracket for each δiΔ\delta_{i}\in\Delta, each such δi\delta_{i} can have probability at most n1n\frac{n-1}{n}, which is less than 1. So we have our counterexample.

Right to left: suppose that there is a {1}\{1\}-preservation counterexample to Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta. This is a probabilistic model W,𝒜,,p\langle W,\mathcal{A},\llbracket\;\rrbracket,\textsc{p}\rangle such that p(γ)=1\textsc{p}(\gamma)=1 for every γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma and p(δ)1\textsc{p}(\delta)\neq 1 for every δΔ\delta\in\Delta. We’re going to use this to generate a new probabilistic model W,𝒜,,p\langle W^{\prime},\mathcal{A}^{\prime},\llbracket\;\rrbracket^{\prime},\textsc{p}^{\prime}\rangle.

For W,𝒜,W^{\prime},\mathcal{A}^{\prime},\llbracket\;\rrbracket^{\prime}, the idea is essentially just to throw out any worlds outside Γ\llbracket\bigwedge{\Gamma}\rrbracket. That is, let W=ΓW^{\prime}=\llbracket\bigwedge\Gamma\rrbracket, let 𝒜={AΓ|A𝒜}\mathcal{A}^{\prime}=\{A\cap\llbracket\bigwedge\Gamma\rrbracket\;|\;A\in\mathcal{A}\}, and let A=AΓ\llbracket A\rrbracket^{\prime}=\llbracket A\rrbracket\cap\llbracket\bigwedge\Gamma\rrbracket. This idea extends to p\textsc{p}^{\prime} too. Any A𝒜A^{\prime}\in\mathcal{A}^{\prime} is AΓA\cap\llbracket\bigwedge\Gamma\rrbracket for some A𝒜A\in\mathcal{A}, and so A𝒜A^{\prime}\in\mathcal{A} as well; we simply let p(A)=p(A)\textsc{p}^{\prime}(A^{\prime})=\textsc{p}(A^{\prime}). We know p\textsc{p}^{\prime} is a probability distribution, since p(W)=1\textsc{p}^{\prime}(W^{\prime})=1 by hypothesis, and p()=0\textsc{p}^{\prime}(\emptyset)=0, and finite additivity results from the fact that the AA^{\prime} are elements of 𝒜\mathcal{A}. This then gives us that p(ϕ)=p(ϕ)\textsc{p}^{\prime}(\phi)=\textsc{p}(\phi) for any sentence ϕ\phi.

To see that W,𝒜,,p\langle W^{\prime},\mathcal{A}^{\prime},\llbracket\;\rrbracket^{\prime},\textsc{p}^{\prime}\rangle is a supervaluational counterexample to Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta, note first that γ=W\llbracket\gamma\rrbracket=W^{\prime} for each γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma. Then, note that, since p(δ)1\textsc{p}(\delta)\neq 1 for every δΔ\delta\in\Delta, we also have p(δ)1\textsc{p}^{\prime}(\delta)\neq 1 for all such δ\delta. Since p(W)=1\textsc{p}^{\prime}(W^{\prime})=1, for each such δ\delta there must be some wWw\in W^{\prime} with wδw\not\in\llbracket\delta\rrbracket^{\prime}. So we have our counterexample. ∎

The situation with the other extreme upset is, as you might expect, the mirror image:

Fact 12.

An argument Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is \interval[softopenfences,openleft]01\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1}-preservation valid iff it is subvaluationistically valid.

Proof.

As Fact 11, mutatis mutandis. ∎

Note that any Set-Set consequence relation determines a particular Set-Fmla consequence relation, but that many different Set-Set consequence relations can determine the same Set-Fmla consequence relation. For example, the classical and supervaluational Set-Set consequence relations are distinct, but they share their Set-Fmla fragment. Because of this, working in a Set-Set framework allows us to see differences that are invisible through a Set-Fmla lens.

Along these lines, Fact 11 reveals more complexity behind the claim, made for example in Adams, (1998, p. 26), that preservation of probability 1 and classical entailment coincide. This claim, as made there, is true, since the context fixes that what’s meant is the Set-Fmla fragments of these relations. But Fact 11 goes farther, showing that {1}\{1\}-preservation consequence is not fully classical, when the extra texture visible in a Set-Set framework is considered. Moreover, this extra texture reveals {1}\{1\}-preservation consequence to be supervaluational consequence.

As the Fmla-Set framework is less commonly studied, we don’t know of anyone who has claimed that \interval[softopenfences,openleft]01\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1}-preservation consequence is classical. We can see, though, that there would be a kind of justice to such a claim: it is indeed classical in the Fmla-Set framework, just not in the full Set-Set framework we work with in this paper.

The characterization of super- and sub-valuationism in terms of probability preservation sheds a specific light on a property often stressed of both frameworks (for example in Williamson, 1994), which is that super-truth and sub-truth fail to be truth-functional. That is, in the same way the probability of a disjunction cannot be determined just from the probabilities of its disjuncts, the super-truth or otherwise of a disjunction cannot be determined just from whether its disjuncts are super-true or not. (For more detailed discussion of truth-functionality, see Chemla and Égré, 2019 or Humberstone, 2011, §3.1.) So while truth-preservation and α\alpha-probability-preservation may appear to coincide in the Set-Fmla case when α=1\alpha=1, the Set-Set case reveals that the notions behave fundamentally differently, even in that extreme case.666The reader may also wonder about the connection between α\alpha-preservation consequence and the analog in the case of Łukasiewicz’s fuzzy propositional logics in which the set of truth values is [0,1][0,1] and validity is defined as the preservation of the degree α\alpha from premises to conclusions, restricting the connectives to negation, conjunction, and disjunction (see Hájek, 1998 and Bergmann, 2008 for more information on these logics). Assuming v(¬A)=1v(A)v(\neg A)=1-v(A), v(AB)=min(v(A),v(B))v(A\wedge B)=min(v(A),v(B)), and v(AB)=max(v(A),v(B))v(A\vee B)=max(v(A),v(B)), qq fails to entail p¬pp\vee\neg p in Łukasiewicz’s logic when α=1\alpha=1, unlike supervaluationism. And for thresholds α\alpha below 1, the resulting Łukasiewicz logics will preserve adjunction, unlike the corresponding probabilistic α\alpha-preservation consequence relations. So probabilistic α\alpha-preservation logics and their fuzzy counterparts differ across the board in the Set-Fmla  case.

We pause to note some results about supervaluational and subvaluational consequence shown in Kremer and Kremer, (2003, pp. 237–238):

  • if Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is supervaluationistically valid, then either Δ\Delta is empty or there is some δΔ\delta\in\Delta where Γ\Yrightδ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\delta is supervaluationistically valid; and

  • if Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is subvaluationistically valid, then either Γ\Gamma is empty or there is some γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma where γ\YrightΔ\gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is subvaluationistically valid.

So we can immediately conclude the same of {1}\{1\}-preservation and \interval[softopenfences,openleft]01\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1}-preservation, respectively. Indeed, we will now work our way up to some results—named Corollaries 22 and 23 below—that in some sense extend these results to intermediate choices of upset.777Unfortunately, we didn’t find a way to adapt Kremer and Kremer, (2003)’s elegant proofs of these above claims to our more general setting, so we’ve had to take a different, less elegant, approach.

5 Preservation consequence: general case

There is some interesting texture to explore in the preservation consequence relations, outside the two extreme upsets {1}\{1\} and \interval[softopenfences,openleft]01\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1} that turn out to determine familiar consequence relations. We open our discussion of this texture by developing some ideas and background, on the way to showing, in Section 5.3, three sufficient conditions for α\alpha-preservation invalidity. These sufficient conditions give us a grip on α\alpha-preservation consequence for upsets besides these extremes.

5.1 α\alpha-satisfiability, α\alpha-tautology, and dual upsets

For any upset α\alpha, we have the following notions:

Definition 13.

A set Γ\Gamma is α\alpha-satisfiable iff there is some probabilistic model W,𝒜,,p\langle W,\mathcal{A},\llbracket\;\rrbracket,\textsc{p}\rangle such that p(γ)α\textsc{p}(\gamma)\in\alpha for each γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma. A set Δ\Delta is α\alpha-tautologous iff for every probabilistic model W,𝒜,,p\langle W,\mathcal{A},\llbracket\;\rrbracket,\textsc{p}\rangle, there is some δΔ\delta\in\Delta such that p(δ)α\textsc{p}(\delta)\in\alpha.

Note that α\alpha-unsatisfiability and α\alpha-tautology connect to special cases of α\alpha-preservation validity: Γ\Gamma is α\alpha-unsatisfiable iff Γ\Yright\Gamma\,\Yright\,\emptyset is α\alpha-preservation valid; and Δ\Delta is α\alpha-tautologous iff \YrightΔ\emptyset\,\Yright\,\Delta is α\alpha-preservation valid.

Definition 14.

The mirror image α¯\overline{\alpha} of α\alpha is {x\interval01| 1xα}\{x\in\interval{0}{1}\;|\;1-x\in\alpha\}; and the dual α\alpha^{\star} of α\alpha is \interval01α¯\interval{0}{1}\setminus\overline{\alpha}.

It is immediate that α\alpha^{\star} is an upset, and that α=α\alpha^{\star\star}=\alpha. It’s also quick to see that no upset α\alpha can be self-dual, as α\alpha^{\star} contains .5.5 iff α\alpha does not. These notions are interrelated as follows:

Fact 15.

For any upset α\alpha and argument Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta, the argument Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is α\alpha-preservation valid iff ¬Δ\Yright¬Γ\neg\Delta\,\Yright\,\neg\Gamma is α\alpha^{\star}-preservation valid.

As a special case of this, α\alpha and set Δ\Delta of sentences, Δ\Delta is α\alpha-tautologous iff ¬Δ\neg\Delta is α\alpha^{\star}-unsatisfiable.

Proof.

Spelling out definitions, recalling that p(¬δ)=1p(δ)\textsc{p}(\neg\delta)=1-\textsc{p}(\delta) for any probability distribution p and sentence δ\delta. ∎

Fact 15 will be useful in what follows particularly when we focus on Set-Fmla and Fmla-Set fragments of α\alpha-preservation consequence relations, as it allows us to turn results about one of these fragments into results about the other, just for the dual upset.

In this paper, we do not explore α\alpha-satisfiability and α\alpha-tautology in any depth. By Fact 15, it would be enough to focus on just one of these, but we do not develop any detailed picture of either one.888For a valuable and in-depth discussion of α\alpha-satisfiability, see Knight, (2002)—noting that Knight speaks of ‘η\eta-consistency’ to mean what we would call ‘\intervalη1\interval{\eta}{1}-satisfiability’. (That paper does not consider open upsets.) We will be drawing on results from this paper as we go. Instead, we use these notions to describe and explore our real target: α\alpha-preservation.

5.2 Background from Adams and Levine, (1975)

The results in this subsection are taken from Adams and Levine, (1975), although we restate them here in the forms we’ll need them in. We also prove them here, as they are not explicitly proved in Adams and Levine, (1975).

Definition 16.

Given a classically-valid Set-Fmla argument Γ\Yrightϕ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\phi, say that a set ΓΓ\Gamma^{\prime}\subseteq\Gamma is minimally sufficient iff Γ\Yrightϕ\Gamma^{\prime}\,\Yright\,\phi is classically valid and there is no proper subset Γ′′Γ\Gamma^{\prime\prime}\subsetneq\Gamma^{\prime} such that Γ′′\Yrightϕ\Gamma^{\prime\prime}\,\Yright\,\phi is classically valid.

For any classically-valid Set-Fmla argument Γ\Yrightϕ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\phi whose minimally sufficient sets are Γ1,,Γn\Gamma^{\prime}_{1},\ldots,\Gamma^{\prime}_{n}, let msϕΓ\text{ms}^{\Gamma}_{\phi} be the sentence 1in(Γi)\bigvee_{1\leq i\leq n}(\bigwedge\Gamma^{\prime}_{i}).

Fact 17.

For any classically-valid Set-Fmla argument Γ\Yrightϕ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\phi and any ΣΓ\Sigma\subseteq\Gamma, the set Σ{¬ϕ}\Sigma\cup\{\neg\phi\} is classically consistent iff the set Σ{¬msϕΓ}\Sigma\cup\{\neg\text{ms}^{\Gamma}_{\phi}\} is classically consistent.

Proof.

Recall that msϕΓ\text{ms}^{\Gamma}_{\phi} is a disjunction each of whose disjuncts classically entails ϕ\phi; so msϕΓ\Yrightϕ\text{ms}^{\Gamma}_{\phi}\,\Yright\,\phi is classically valid. But if Σ{¬msϕΓ}\Sigma\cup\{\neg\text{ms}^{\Gamma}_{\phi}\} is inconsistent then Σ\YrightmsϕΓ\Sigma\,\Yright\,\text{ms}^{\Gamma}_{\phi} is classically valid; so by transitivity of classical validity Σ\Yrightϕ\Sigma\,\Yright\,\phi would have to be classically valid, and thus Σ{¬ϕ}\Sigma\cup\{\neg\phi\} classically inconsistent.

For the other direction, suppose that Σ{¬ϕ}\Sigma\cup\{\neg\phi\} is classically inconsistent; then Σ\Yrightϕ\Sigma\,\Yright\,\phi is classically valid. Then, since ΣΓ\Sigma\subseteq\Gamma, there must be some minimally sufficient Γ\Gamma^{\prime} such that ΓΣ\Gamma^{\prime}\subseteq\Sigma, and so Σ\YrightΓ\Sigma\,\Yright\,\bigwedge\Gamma^{\prime} is classically valid. But then Σ\YrightmsϕΓ\Sigma\,\Yright\,\text{ms}^{\Gamma}_{\phi} is classically valid as well, and so Σ{¬msϕΓ}\Sigma\cup\{\neg\text{ms}^{\Gamma}_{\phi}\} is classically inconsistent. ∎

Fact 18 (see Adams and Levine, 1975, p. 434).

Suppose the Set-Fmla argument Γ\Yrightϕ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\phi is classically valid, and that all its minimally sufficient sets are classically inconsistent. Then for any probabilistic model 𝔐p\mathfrak{M}_{\textsc{p}}, there is a probabilistic model 𝔐p\mathfrak{M}_{\textsc{p}^{\prime}} such that:

  • for all γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma, we have p(γ)=p(γ)\textsc{p}^{\prime}(\gamma)=\textsc{p}(\gamma), and

  • p(ϕ)=0\textsc{p}^{\prime}(\phi)=0.

Proof.

Let 𝔐p\mathfrak{M}_{\textsc{p}} be given. We move first to 𝔐=𝔐pΓ{ϕ}\mathfrak{M}^{\star}=\mathfrak{M}^{\Gamma\cup\{\phi\}}_{\textsc{p}}, as given by Fact 4. That is, 𝔐=W,𝒜,,p\mathfrak{M}^{\star}=\langle W^{\star},\mathcal{A}^{\star},\llbracket\;\rrbracket^{\star},\textsc{p}^{\star}\rangle, where:

  • W=(At(Γ{ϕ}))W^{\star}=\wp(At(\Gamma\cup\{\phi\}));

  • 𝒜=(W)\mathcal{A}^{\star}=\wp(W^{\star});

  • for all pAt(Γ{ϕ})p\in At(\Gamma\cup\{\phi\}), we have p={wW|pW}\llbracket p\rrbracket^{\star}=\{w\in W^{\star}\;|\;p\in W\}; and

  • for all γΓ{ϕ}\gamma\in\Gamma\cup\{\phi\}, we have p(γ)=p(γ)\textsc{p}^{\star}(\gamma)=\textsc{p}(\gamma).

Now, we arrive at the desired 𝔐p\mathfrak{M}_{\textsc{p}^{\prime}} by modifying just the last coordinate of 𝔐\mathfrak{M}^{\star}. That is, 𝔐p=W,𝒜,,p\mathfrak{M}_{\textsc{p}^{\prime}}=\langle W^{\star},\mathcal{A}^{\star},\llbracket\;\rrbracket^{\star},\textsc{p}^{\prime}\rangle, and it remains just to specify p\textsc{p}^{\prime} and to show the claimed results about it.

First, note that since all of Γ\Yrightϕ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\phi’s minimally sufficient sets are inconsistent, so too is their disjunction, which is to say that msϕΓ\text{ms}^{\Gamma}_{\phi} is inconsistent. As such, we know that msϕΓ=\llbracket\text{ms}^{\Gamma}_{\phi}\rrbracket^{\star}=\emptyset.

Consider, then, any wϕw\in\llbracket\phi\rrbracket^{\star}. Let Σw={γ|γΓ and wγ}{¬γ|γΓ and wγ}\Sigma_{w}=\{\gamma\;|\;\gamma\in\Gamma\text{ and }w\in\llbracket\gamma\rrbracket^{\star}\}\cup\{\neg\gamma\;|\;\gamma\in\Gamma\text{ and }w\not\in\llbracket\gamma\rrbracket^{\star}\}. The set Σw{¬msϕΓ}\Sigma_{w}\cup\{\neg\text{ms}^{\Gamma}_{\phi}\} is classically consistent, since all its members are true at ww, and so by Fact 17 the set Σw{¬ϕ}\Sigma_{w}\cup\{\neg\phi\} is also classically consistent. Since At(Σw{¬ϕ})At(Γ{ϕ})At(\Sigma_{w}\cup\{\neg\phi\})\subseteq At(\Gamma\cup\{\phi\}), as we’ve defined WW^{\star} and \llbracket\;\rrbracket^{\star} this is enough to conclude that there is some wWw^{\dagger}\in W^{\star} such that for every σΣw{¬ϕ}\sigma\in\Sigma_{w}\cup\{\neg\phi\}, we have wσw^{\dagger}\in\llbracket\sigma\rrbracket^{\star}. And for any wϕw\not\in\llbracket\phi\rrbracket^{\star}, let w=ww^{\dagger}=w. This gives us, for each wWw\in W^{\star}, some corresponding ww^{\dagger} where: 1) wϕw^{\dagger}\not\in\llbracket\phi\rrbracket^{\star}, and 2) for every γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma, we have wγw\in\llbracket\gamma\rrbracket^{\star} iff wγw^{\dagger}\in\llbracket\gamma\rrbracket^{\star}.

Now, for any wWw\in W^{\star}, let w{}^{\dagger}w be its -preimage, the set {x|x=w}\{x\;|\;x^{\dagger}=w\}. Note that whenever wϕw\in\llbracket\phi\rrbracket^{\prime}, then the set w{}^{\dagger}w is empty. Using this, we define p\textsc{p}^{\prime} by defining it on singletons as p({w})=xwp(x)\textsc{p}^{\prime}(\{w\})=\sum_{x\in^{\dagger}w}\textsc{p}^{\star}(x).

In effect, we are moving from p\textsc{p}^{\star} to p\textsc{p}^{\prime} by taking the weight of probability at each world ww and shifting it to ww^{\dagger}. Any worlds wϕw\not\in\llbracket\phi\rrbracket^{\star} retain all the probability they begin with under this operation, since for all such worlds w=ww^{\dagger}=w. Such worlds might, however, end up with more total probability, since such a ww might still be xx^{\dagger} for some xwx\neq w. And any worlds wϕw\in\llbracket\phi\rrbracket^{\star} end up with 0 probability, since for all such worlds there is no xx with x=wx^{\dagger}=w.

Clearly, then, we have p(ϕ)=0\textsc{p}^{\prime}(\phi)=0, as desired. It remains to show that p(γ)=p(γ)\textsc{p}^{\prime}(\gamma)=\textsc{p}^{\star}(\gamma) for all γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma. Take any such γ\gamma, then, with γ={w1,,wn}\llbracket\gamma\rrbracket^{\star}=\{w_{1},\ldots,w_{n}\}. We know p(γ)=p({w1})++p({wn})\textsc{p}^{\star}(\gamma)=\textsc{p}^{\star}(\{w_{1}\})+\ldots+\textsc{p}^{\star}(\{w_{n}\}), and that p(γ)=p({w1})++p({wn})\textsc{p}^{\prime}(\gamma)=\textsc{p}^{\prime}(\{w_{1}\})+\ldots+\textsc{p}^{\prime}(\{w_{n}\}). But for any of these wiw_{i}, the world wiw_{i}^{\dagger} must be one of these wjw_{j}, since we know that wiγw_{i}\in\llbracket\gamma\rrbracket^{\star} iff wiγw_{i}^{\dagger}\in\llbracket\gamma\rrbracket^{\star}. And similarly, for any wWw\in W^{\star} that is not among the wiw_{i}s, ww^{\dagger} is also not among them, for the same reason. So while we might shift some probability from addend to addend, we do not shift any probability away from or into the whole collection, and so the two sums must be the same. Thus, we have what we’re after. ∎

5.3 Sufficient conditions for preservation invalidity

Here, we use the foregoing to compile some results about conditions that are sufficient to show a given argument to be α\alpha-preservation invalid. First, we prove that all α\alpha-preservation consequence relations are subclassical:

Fact 19.

For any upset α\alpha, if Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is classically invalid, then it is α\alpha-preservation invalid.

Proof.

Take a one-world probabilistic model 𝔐={w},{w},,p\mathfrak{M}=\langle\{w\},\wp{\{w\}},\llbracket\;\rrbracket,\textsc{p}\rangle where \llbracket\;\rrbracket is a classical valuation that provides a counterexample to Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta. In this model, p(γ)=1\textsc{p}(\gamma)=1 for every γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma and p(δ)=0\textsc{p}(\delta)=0 for every δΔ\delta\in\Delta, so this is an α\alpha-preservation counterexample to Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta, regardless of α\alpha. ∎

Before moving to our next result, we pause to cite a theorem due to Adams, as we draw on this result in what follows:

Theorem 20 (Adams,, 1998, Thm. 14, p. 39).

Take a classically valid Set-Fmla argument Γ\Yrightδ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\delta, where Γ={γ1,,γn}\Gamma=\{\gamma_{1},\ldots,\gamma_{n}\}. If Γ\Gamma is classically consistent, and if Γ\Yrightδ\Gamma^{\prime}\,\Yright\,\delta is classically invalid for every ΓΓ\Gamma^{\prime}\subsetneq\Gamma, then for any sequence x1,,xnx_{1},\ldots,x_{n} of numbers from \interval01\interval{0}{1} such that 1inxi1\sum_{1\leq i\leq n}x_{i}\leq 1, there is a probability function p such that p(ϕ)=11inxi\textsc{p}(\phi)=1-\sum_{1\leq i\leq n}x_{i}, and such that p(γi)=1xi\textsc{p}(\gamma_{i})=1-x_{i} for each 1in1\leq i\leq n.

Proof.

See the cited work. ∎

Fact 21.

If α{1}\alpha\neq\{1\}, if Γ\Gamma is α\alpha-satisfiable, δ\delta is not a classical tautology, and there is no γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma such that γ\Yrightδ\gamma\,\Yright\,\delta is classically valid, then Γ\Yrightδ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\delta is not α\alpha-preservation valid.

Proof.

Consider all ΓΓ\Gamma^{\prime}\subseteq\Gamma such that Γ\Yrightδ\Gamma^{\prime}\,\Yright\,\delta is classically valid. Either some such Γ\Gamma^{\prime} is classically consistent, or all such Γ\Gamma^{\prime} are classically inconsistent.

  • If there is some such Γ\Gamma^{\prime} that is classically consistent, take some Γ′′Γ\Gamma^{\prime\prime}\subseteq\Gamma^{\prime} such that Γ′′\Yrightδ\Gamma^{\prime\prime}\,\Yright\,\delta is classically valid and there is no Γ′′′Γ′′\Gamma^{\prime\prime\prime}\subsetneq\Gamma^{\prime\prime} with Γ′′′\Yrightδ\Gamma^{\prime\prime\prime}\,\Yright\,\delta classically valid. Since Γ\Gamma^{\prime} is classically consistent, Γ′′\Gamma^{\prime\prime} must be as well.

    This meets the assumptions of Theorem 20, so we apply that result. Where |Γ′′|=n|\Gamma^{\prime\prime}|=n, all that remains is to choose an appropriate sequence x1,,xmx_{1},\ldots,x_{m} with sum at most 1 to arrive at our desired α\alpha-preservation counterexample. First, choose some yαy\not\in\alpha such that y+12α\frac{y+1}{2}\in\alpha.999This is always possible. If α=\interval[softopenfences,openleft]01\alpha=\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1}, then let yy be 0; otherwise, let xx be the threshold of α\alpha, and choose some positive ε\varepsilon such that ε<min(x,1x)\varepsilon<\min(x,1-x) and let y=xεy=x-\varepsilon. Then since ε\varepsilon is positive we have y<xy<x, and so yαy\not\in\alpha. To see that y+12α\frac{y+1}{2}\in\alpha, note that y+12=xε+12=x+xε+12\frac{y+1}{2}=\frac{x-\varepsilon+1}{2}=x+\frac{-x-\varepsilon+1}{2}. This must be >x>x since ε<1x\varepsilon<1-x, so it’s in y+12α\frac{y+1}{2}\in\alpha.

    By assumption, there is no Γ\Gamma^{\prime} with |Γ|<2|\Gamma^{\prime}|<2 such that Γ\Yrightδ\Gamma^{\prime}\,\Yright\,\delta is classically valid, so |Γ′′|2|\Gamma^{\prime\prime}|\geq 2. Our desired sequence then has x1=x2=1y+12x_{1}=x_{2}=1-\frac{y+1}{2}, and xi=0x_{i}=0 for i>2i>2, if there are any.

    The cited theorem then assures us that there is a probability distribution p such that p(γ)α\textsc{p}(\gamma)\in\alpha for each γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma, since for each such γ\gamma, either p(γ)=y+12\textsc{p}(\gamma)=\frac{y+1}{2} or p(γ)=1\textsc{p}(\gamma)=1, and such that p(δ)=1(2(y+1))=y\textsc{p}(\delta)=1-(2-(y+1))=y. By our choice of yy, then, any probabilistic model with p as its final coordinate is an α\alpha-preservation counterexample to Γ\Yrightδ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\delta, as desired.

  • If all such Γ\Gamma^{\prime} are classically inconsistent, we note that Γ\Gamma is α\alpha-satisfiable by assumption, so there is a p such that p(γ)α\textsc{p}(\gamma)\in\alpha for every γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma. We then apply Fact 18 to conclude that there is some p\textsc{p}^{\prime} that is an α\alpha-preservation counterexample to Γ\Yrightδ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\delta, as desired.

Fact 21 drastically narrows down the ways a Set-Fmla argument Γ\Yrightϕ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\phi can come to be α\alpha-preservation valid for α\alpha other than {1}\{1\}—only if Γ\Gamma itself is not α\alpha-satisfiable, or δ\delta is a classical tautology, or there is some single γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma such that γ\Yrightδ\gamma\,\Yright\,\delta is classically valid. There is no other way. For example, it follows immediately from Fact 21 that p,q\Yrightpqp,q\,\Yright\,p\land q is α\alpha-preservation invalid for all α{1}\alpha\neq\{1\}.101010Recall from Section 4.2 that when α={1}\alpha=\{1\} then α\alpha-preservation consequence is exactly supervaluational, and this in turn is classical for Set-Fmla arguments, so this argument is α\alpha-preservation valid in that special case. After all, the set {p,q}\{p,q\} is α\alpha-satisfiable for any α\alpha, but pqp\land q is not a classical tautology and neither p\Yrightpqp\,\Yright\,p\land q nor q\Yrightpqq\,\Yright\,p\land q is classically valid.

Essentially, what Fact 21 tells us, for Set-Fmla arguments in these preservation consequence relations, is this. Premises can interact with each other (to reach α\alpha-unsatisfiability), and any single premise can interact with the conclusion (to reach classical validity), and the conclusion alone might suffice (when it is a classical tautology), but: we can never have a case where validity is secured by premises interacting with each other and the conclusion. There is a slipperiness to each α\alpha-preservation consequence, at least in its Set-Fmla fragment.

This can be extended directly to the full Set-Set framework, however:

Corollary 22.

If α{1}\alpha\neq\{1\}, if Γ\Gamma is α\alpha-satisfiable, Δ\bigvee\Delta is not a classical tautology, and if there is no γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma such that γ\YrightΔ\gamma\,\Yright\,\bigvee\Delta is classically valid, then Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is not α\alpha-preservation valid.

Proof.

From these assumptions, Fact 21 gives us that Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\bigvee\Delta is not α\alpha-preservation valid. But any counterexample to Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\bigvee\Delta must at the same time be a counterexample to Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta. ∎

Fact 21 and Corollary 22 are asymmetric in their assumptions, focusing on multiplicity among the premises of an argument, and either assuming a single conclusion or else lumping all conclusions together with \bigvee. As might be expected, these results can be dualized:

Corollary 23.

If α\interval[softopenfences,openleft]01\alpha\neq\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1}, if Δ\Delta is not α\alpha-tautologous, Γ\bigwedge\Gamma is classically satisfiable, and if there is no δΔ\delta\in\Delta such that Γ\Yrightδ\bigwedge\Gamma\,\Yright\,\delta is classically valid, then Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is not α\alpha-preservation valid.

Proof.

Suppose the antecedent. Then by Fact 15 we have that ¬Δ\neg\Delta is α\alpha^{\star}-satisfiable. Moreover, since classical logic is self-dual (in the sense that Σ\YrightΘ\Sigma\,\Yright\,\Theta is classically valid iff ¬Θ\Yright¬Σ\neg\Theta\,\Yright\,\neg\Sigma is), we know that there is no Γ¬Δ\Gamma^{\prime}\subseteq\neg\Delta such that |Γ|<2|\Gamma^{\prime}|<2 and Γ\Yright¬Γ\Gamma^{\prime}\,\Yright\,\neg\bigwedge\Gamma is classically valid. By a De Morgan equivalence, that ensures that there is no such Γ\Gamma^{\prime} with Γ\Yright¬Γ\Gamma^{\prime}\,\Yright\,\bigvee\neg\Gamma classically valid. Thus, by Fact 21, we can conclude that ¬Δ\Yright¬Γ\neg\Delta\,\Yright\,\neg\Gamma is not α\alpha^{\star}-preservation valid, and so by Fact 15 we have that Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is not α\alpha-preservation valid, as desired. ∎

We pause for a moment to give a couple of examples and take stock. Fact 19, Corollary 22 and Corollary 23 together establish that a wide range of arguments are α\alpha-preservation invalid.

For example, consider the argument p,qr\Yrightpq,rp,q\lor r\,\Yright\,p\land q,r. This is classically valid, so Fact 19 does not apply. However, neither p\Yright(pq)rp\,\Yright\,(p\land q)\lor r nor qr\Yright(pq)rq\lor r\,\Yright\,(p\land q)\lor r is classically valid, and (pq)r(p\land q)\lor r is not a classical tautology. Thus, by Corollary 22, if α{1}\alpha\neq\{1\} and {p,qr}\{p,q\lor r\} is α\alpha-satisfiable, the argument is α\alpha-preservation invalid. But {p,qr}\{p,q\lor r\} is α\alpha-satisfiable for any upset α\alpha. So this argument is α\alpha-preservation invalid for all α{1}\alpha\neq\{1\}. (Moreover, since the argument is also supervaluationistically invalid, by Fact 11 it is also {1}\{1\}-preservation invalid.)

On the other hand, consider the argument p,q\Yrightpq,p¬qp,q\,\Yright\,p\land q,p\land\neg q. This is classically valid, so Fact 19 does not apply. Moreover, p\Yright(pq)(p¬q)p\,\Yright\,(p\land q)\vee(p\land\neg q) is classically valid, so Corollary 22 does not apply. And pq\Yrightpqp\land q\,\Yright\,p\land q is classically valid, so Corollary 23 does not apply. The argument is both supervaluationistically and subvaluationistically valid, so α\alpha-preservation valid for the extreme cases of α={1}\alpha=\{1\} and α=\interval[softopenfences,openleft]01\alpha=\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1}. But what about non-extreme choices of α\alpha? Our foregoing results do not apply to this case.

Nonetheless, the argument is still α\alpha invalid for all such. To see this, choose some x,yαx,y\not\in\alpha such that x+yαx+y\in\alpha, with the constraint that x+2y1x+2y\leq 1. (Note that this is not possible for the extreme thresholds \interval[softopenfences,openleft]01\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1} and {1}\{1\}, but is possible for all other thresholds.) Then consider the model {a,b,c,d},({a,b,c,d}),,p\langle\{a,b,c,d\},\wp(\{a,b,c,d\}),\llbracket\;\rrbracket,\textsc{p}\rangle where:

  • p={a,b}\llbracket p\rrbracket=\{a,b\} and q={a,c}\llbracket q\rrbracket=\{a,c\}; and

  • p({a})=x\textsc{p}(\{a\})=x and p({b})=p({c})=y\textsc{p}(\{b\})=\textsc{p}(\{c\})=y and p({d})=1(x+2y)\textsc{p}(\{d\})=1-(x+2y)

Now note that p(p)=p(q)=x+y\textsc{p}(p)=\textsc{p}(q)=x+y, but that p(pq)=x\textsc{p}(p\land q)=x and p(p¬q)=y\textsc{p}(p\land\neg q)=y; so we have an α\alpha-preservation counterexample to this argument.

Our sufficient conditions for α\alpha-preservation invalidity, then, are genuinely only sufficient: there remain α\alpha-preservation invalid arguments that fall outside the purview of Fact 19, Corollary 22, Corollary 23. We conjecture a stronger claim:

Conjecture 24.

If \interval[softopenfences,openleft]01α{1}\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1}\neq\alpha\neq\{1\}, if Γ\Gamma is α\alpha-satisfiable and Δ\Delta is not α\alpha-tautologous, and if there are no γΓ,δΔ\gamma\in\Gamma,\delta\in\Delta such that γ\Yrightδ\gamma\,\Yright\,\delta is classically valid, then Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is not α\alpha-preservation valid.

If Conjecture 24 is true, it is also comprehensive: every α\alpha-preservation invalid argument would satisfy its assumptions (since failing any one of the assumptions is immediately sufficient for α\alpha-preservation validity). We know of no α\alpha-preservation valid argument that provides a counterexample to Conjecture 24, but we also have not been able to prove the conjecture. For now, then, we leave things where they stand: with some broad sufficient conditions for invalidity in place.

6 Properties of Preservation Consequence

We can now state some general properties of α\alpha-consequence relations: we start with an overview of relations between α\alpha-preservation relations for different α\alpha, then establish how many distinct consequence relations there are, and conclude with a note on operational and structural features of those relations.

6.1 Containment relations

With these results established, we are in a place to note some other interesting features of α\alpha-preservation validity. The first is a slight strengthening of a result of Paris, (2004). The strengthening is just that we consider both closed and open upsets, while that paper considers (in effect) only closed. Our proof of this result, however, is quite different, since we can appeal to the foregoing.

Fact 25.

If βα\beta\subseteq\alpha, then if Γ\Yrightϕ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\phi is α\alpha-preservation valid, it is β\beta-preservation valid.

Proof.

Suppose βα\beta\subseteq\alpha and Γ\Yrightϕ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\phi is α\alpha-preservation valid. Then by Fact 21, either ϕ\phi is a classical tautology, or there is some γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma such that γ\Yrightϕ\gamma\,\Yright\,\phi is classically valid, or Γ\Gamma is α\alpha-inconsistent. If any of these holds, however, then Γ\Yrightϕ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\phi is β\beta-preservation valid as well. (For the third disjunct: if Γ\Gamma is α\alpha-inconsistent, then it must be β\beta-inconsistent, and so Γ\Yrightϕ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\phi is β\beta-preservation valid.) ∎

That is, as we narrow the upsets we consider, we strengthen the Set-Fmla fragment of the preservation consequence that results. As you might expect, the situation is the reverse for Fmla-Set arguments: the Fmla-Set fragment of these preservation consequence relations gets stronger as the upset widens.

Fact 26.

If αβ\alpha\subseteq\beta, then if ϕ\YrightΔ\phi\,\Yright\,\Delta is α\alpha-preservation valid, it is β\beta-preservation valid.

Proof.

Suppose αβ\alpha\subseteq\beta and ϕ\YrightΔ\phi\,\Yright\,\Delta is α\alpha-preservation valid. Then by Corollary 23, either ϕ\phi is a classical contradiction, or there is some δΔ\delta\in\Delta such that ϕ\Yrightδ\phi\,\Yright\,\delta is classically valid, or Δ\Delta is α\alpha-tautologous. If any of these holds, however, then ϕ\YrightΔ\phi\,\Yright\,\Delta is β\beta-preservation valid as well. ∎

Facts 25 and 26 together give us an interesting overview of these preservation consequences: in their Set-Fmla fragment, they get stronger as the upset narrows, but in their Fmla-Set fragment, they get stronger as the upset widens instead. As we saw in Section 4.2, the limits are the familiar relations of supervaluational (at {1}\{1\}) and subvaluational (at \interval[softopenfences,openleft]01\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1}) consequence. This also means that every preservation consequence relation agrees with every other on Fmla-Fmla arguments, regardless of which upset is chosen, since Fmla-Fmla arguments are both Set-Fmla and Fmla-Set(and so every preservation consequence relation is classical on Fmla-Fmla arguments).

Fact 25 also allows us to connect our results here to a fascinating result of Knight, (2003), connecting the Set-Fmla fragment of subvaluationistic logic to a related framework. Note that by Fact 25 and Fact 12, we know that the intersection of all the α\alpha-preservation consequence relations has as its Set-Fmla fragment the Set-Fmla fragment of subvaluationistic logic. Knight, (2003) shows, in effect, that the intersection of a much wider class of Set-Fmla probabilistic consequence relations also matches subvaluationistic logic.

As for the more general Set-Set situation, these neat ordering facts do not obtain. For example, consider again the extremes of {1}\{1\}-preservation and \interval[softopenfences,openleft]01\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1}-preservation. As mentioned before, p,q\Yrightpqp,q\,\Yright\,p\land q is valid in supervaluationist logic but not subvaluationist logic, while pq\Yrightp,qp\lor q\,\Yright\,p,q is valid in subvaluationist logic but not supervaluationist logic.

6.2 Counting preservation relations

The purpose of this section is to show that there are continuum many distinct α\alpha-preservation consequence relations, and to consider the relationship between the closed and open upsets at any particular threshold.

First, we show that we can get our hands on enough sentences with the right logical properties for our purposes:

Fact 27.

For every natural number mm, there is a set of mm sentences such that each of them is classically consistent and any pair of them is classically inconsistent.

Proof.

Take nn atomic sentences, where nn is such that 2nm2^{n}\geq m; let these be {p1,,pn}\{p_{1},\ldots,p_{n}\}. There are 2n2^{n} sentences of the form ±p1±pn\pm p_{1}\land\ldots\ldots\pm p_{n}, where +pi+p_{i} is pip_{i} and p1-p_{1} is ¬pi\neg p_{i}, and these are pairwise inconsistent, since any two differ on at least one pip_{i}. They are also all individually consistent. So take any mm of them. ∎

With that in hand, we move to a lemma that allows us to draw a divide between the closed and open upsets at any rational number:

Lemma 28.

For every rational number nm(0,1)\frac{n}{m}\in(0,1), there is a set Γ\Gamma that is \intervalnm1\interval{\frac{n}{m}}{1}-satisfiable and not \interval[softopenfences,openleft]nm1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{\frac{n}{m}}{1}-satisfiable.111111Many thanks to Peter Fritz for helping to find this proof.

Proof.

By Fact 27, there is a set of mm sentences that are individually consistent and pairwise inconsistent; let these be ϕ1,,ϕm\phi_{1},\ldots,\phi_{m}. Our target Γ\Gamma is {ϕi1ϕin| 1i1<<inm}\{\phi_{i_{1}}\lor\ldots\lor\phi_{i_{n}}\;|\;1\leq i_{1}<\ldots<i_{n}\leq m\}.

First, to see that Γ\Gamma is \intervalnm1\interval{\frac{n}{m}}{1}-satisfiable. Consider the model W,𝒜,,p\langle W,\mathcal{A},\llbracket\;\rrbracket,\textsc{p}\rangle, where W={w1,,wm}W=\{w_{1},\ldots,w_{m}\}; where 𝒜=(W)\mathcal{A}=\wp(W); where \llbracket\;\rrbracket is such that ϕi={wi}\llbracket\phi_{i}\rrbracket=\{w_{i}\}, which is possible since each ϕi\phi_{i} is consistent and none classically entails any other; and where p({wi})=1m\textsc{p}(\{w_{i}\})=\frac{1}{m}. In this model, p(γ)=nm\textsc{p}(\gamma)=\frac{n}{m} for each γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma.

Now, to see that Γ\Gamma is not \interval[softopenfences,openleft]nm1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{\frac{n}{m}}{1}-satisfiable. Suppose otherwise; then we have a probability distribution p such that p(γ)>nm\textsc{p}(\gamma)>\frac{n}{m} for each γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma. Note that since each γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma is an nn-ary disjunction of pairwise incompatible ϕi\phi_{i}s, and since each choice of nn ϕi\phi_{i}s is disjoined in some such γ\gamma, the probabilities of the sentences in Γ\Gamma are exactly the nn-ary sums whose addends are drawn (without replacement) from the p(ϕi)\textsc{p}(\phi_{i})s.

Since by supposition all such nn-ary sums are >nm>\frac{n}{m}, there can be at most n1n-1 of the ϕi\phi_{i}s such that p(ϕi)1m\textsc{p}(\phi_{i})\leq\frac{1}{m}. So there are at least mn+1m-n+1 of the ϕi\phi_{i} that are such that p(ϕi)>1m\textsc{p}(\phi_{i})>\frac{1}{m}; choose mnm-n of these. For concreteness, but without loss of generality, we suppose that these are ϕ1,,ϕmn\phi_{1},\ldots,\phi_{m-n}.

Now, p(ϕ1)++p(ϕmn)>mnm\textsc{p}(\phi_{1})+\ldots+\textsc{p}(\phi_{m-n})>\frac{m-n}{m}, and so p(ϕmn+1)++p(ϕm)<nm\textsc{p}(\phi_{m-n+1})+\ldots+\textsc{p}(\phi_{m})<\frac{n}{m}, since the sum of these two sums cannot be greater than 11. But the latter sum is an nn-ary sum whose addends are drawn without replacement from the p(ϕi)\textsc{p}(\phi_{i}). By assumption all such sums are >nm>\frac{n}{m}, so we have a contradiction. ∎

We also note a result of Knight, (2002) about α\alpha-satisfiability; we use both this and Lemma 28 both here and later in Section 7:

Theorem 29 (Knight,, 2002, Thm. 4.14, p. 86).

For any finite set Γ\Gamma of sentences, there is some maximum xx such that Γ\Gamma is \intervalx1\interval{x}{1}-satisfiable, and such maximum xx is rational.

Proof.

See the cited work. ∎

This then gives a quick corollary, which is the form we’ll use it in:

Corollary 30.

For any x(0,1)x\in(0,1), if there is a finite set Γ\Gamma such that Γ\Gamma is \intervalx1\interval{x}{1}-satisfiable and \interval[softopenfences,openleft]x1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{x}{1}-unsatisfiable, then xx is rational.

Proof.

Immediate from Theorem 29. ∎

This is now enough for us to summarize the situation surrounding any \intervalx1\interval{x}{1}- and \interval[softopenfences,openleft]x1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{x}{1}-preservation consequence. For purposes of this discussion, we treat these consequence relations simply as sets of valid arguments; we call them distinct when they are distinct as sets and incomparable when neither set is a subset of the other.

Theorem 31.

For any x(0,1)x\in(0,1), if the consequence relations of \intervalx1\interval{x}{1}-preservation and \interval[softopenfences,openleft]x1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{x}{1}-preservation are distinct, then xx is rational; and if xx is rational, then the consequence relations of \intervalx1\interval{x}{1}-preservation and \interval[softopenfences,openleft]x1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{x}{1}-preservation are incomparable.

Proof.

First, suppose the consequence relations are distinct, to show that xx is rational. Since \intervalx1\interval{x}{1}-preservation consequence and \interval[softopenfences,openleft]x1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{x}{1}-preservation consequence differ, there must be some argument Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta that is either \interval[softopenfences,openleft]x1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{x}{1}-preservation valid and \intervalx1\interval{x}{1}-preservation invalid, or \intervalx1\interval{x}{1}-preservation valid and \interval[softopenfences,openleft]x1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{x}{1}-preservation invalid,

Suppose the first disjunct. Then by Corollary 22, it must be that Γ\Gamma is \intervalx1\interval{x}{1}-satisfiable but not \interval[softopenfences,openleft]x1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{x}{1}-satisfiable. So, by Corollary 30, xx is rational.

On the other hand, suppose the second disjunct. Then by Corollary 23, it must be that Δ\Delta is \intervalx1\interval{x}{1}-tautologous but not \interval[softopenfences,openleft]x1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{x}{1}-tautologous. By Fact 15, then, ¬Δ\neg\Delta is \interval1x1\interval{1-x}{1}-satisfiable but not \interval[softopenfences,openleft]1x1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{1-x}{1}-satisfiable. By Corollary 30, then, 1x1-x is rational; and then so is xx itself.

Next, we show that when xx is rational the relations are incomparable. Lemma 28 assures us that when xx is rational there is a set Γ\Gamma that is \intervalx1\interval{x}{1}-satisfiable but not \interval[softopenfences,openleft]x1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{x}{1}-satisfiable. But then Γ\Yright\Gamma\,\Yright\,\emptyset is an argument that is \interval[softopenfences,openleft]x1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{x}{1}-preservation valid and not \intervalx1\interval{x}{1}-preservation valid.

Also, since xx is rational so is 1x1-x, and there is thus a set Δ\Delta that is \interval1x1\interval{1-x}{1}-satisfiable but not \interval[softopenfences,openleft]1x1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{1-x}{1} satisfiable, again by Lemma 28. But then by Fact 15 we have that ¬Δ\neg\Delta is \intervalx1\interval{x}{1}-tautologous and not \interval[softopenfences,openleft]x1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{x}{1}-tautologous, which is to say that \Yright¬Δ\emptyset\,\Yright\,\neg\Delta is \intervalx1\interval{x}{1}-preservation valid and \interval[softopenfences,openleft]x1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{x}{1}-preservation invalid. ∎

We can also now count the distinct α\alpha-preservation consequence relations:

Theorem 32.

For any distinct x,y\interval[softopenfences,openleft]01x,y\in\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1}, if xx is the threshold of α\alpha and yy is the threshold of β\beta, then α\alpha-preservation consequence and β\beta-preservation consequence are incomparable.

Proof.

Without loss of generality, let x<yx<y; we first show there is a set that is \intervalx1\interval{x}{1}-satisfiable but not \intervaly1\interval{y}{1}-satisfiable. To see this, take some rational zz such that x<z<yx<z<y, and use Lemma 28 to arrive at some Γ\Gamma that is \intervalz1\interval{z}{1}-satisfiable but not \interval[softopenfences,openleft]z1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{z}{1}-satisfiable. Since Γ\Gamma is \intervalz1\interval{z}{1}-satisfiable and x<zx<z, it is also \interval[softopenfences,openleft]x1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{x}{1}-satisfiable, and so α\alpha-satisfiable. And since Γ\Gamma is not \interval[softopenfences,openleft]z1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{z}{1}-satisfiable and z<yz<y, it is also not \intervaly1\interval{y}{1}-satisfiable, and so not β\beta-satisfiable. Now, consider the argument Γ\Yright\Gamma\,\Yright\,\emptyset; this is β\beta-preservation valid and α\alpha-preservation invalid.

For the other direction of incomparability, note that since x<yx<y we also have 1y<1x1-y<1-x; so we can take some rational ww such that 1y<w<1x1-y<w<1-x, and use Lemma 28 to arrive at some Δ\Delta that is \intervalw1\interval{w}{1}-satisfiable but \interval[softopenfences,openleft]w1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{w}{1}-unsatisfiable. This ensures that Δ\Delta is \interval[softopenfences,openleft]1y1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{1-y}{1}-satisfiable and \interval1x1\interval{1-x}{1}-unsatisfiable, which by Fact 15 gives us that ¬Δ\neg\Delta is \interval[softopenfences,openleft]x1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{x}{1}-tautologous but not \intervaly1\interval{y}{1}-tautologous. This ensures that ¬Δ\neg\Delta is α\alpha-tautologous and not β\beta-tautologous, and so \Yright¬Δ\emptyset\,\Yright\,\neg\Delta is α\alpha-preservation valid and not β\beta-preservation valid. ∎

Corollary 33.

There are uncountably many distinct preservation consequence relations, and any distinct preservation consequence relations are incomparable.

Proof.

The uncountability is from Theorem 32 and the fact that \interval[softopenfences,openleft]01\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1} is uncountable.

For the second half, take any upsets α,β\alpha,\beta. If α\alpha and β\beta have the same threshold, then Theorem 31 ensures that if α\alpha-preservation consequence and β\beta-preservation consequence are distinct they are incomparable. On the other hand, if α\alpha and β\beta have distinct thresholds, then Theorem 32 ensures that α\alpha-preservation consequence and β\beta-preservation consequence are certainly incomparable. ∎

The results of this section give us an interesting picture. In some sense the fact that Knight, (2002), Paris, (2004), and others consider only closed upsets makes a very small difference—one that matters at every rational threshold, but nowhere else. On the other hand, the fact that Paris, (2004) considers only the Set-Fmla framework makes a very big difference: Fact 25 gives a linear order to the Set-Fmla fragments of these consequence relations, while Corollary 33 shows that in the full Set-Set framework this very much does not obtain.

6.3 Structural and operational features

How different and how similar are preservation consequence relations from classical consequence, when considering structural and operational properties?

First of all, and for comparison with what comes next, we note that, simply because our α\alpha-preservation consequence relations are all defined by preservation of some status, all of them have the Tarskian properties of reflexivity, monotonicity, and transitivity, in the following senses, by Shoesmith and Smiley, (1978, Thm. 2.1):

  • ϕ\Yrightϕ\phi\,\Yright\,\phi is valid;

  • if Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is valid, then Γ,Γ\YrightΔ,Δ\Gamma^{\prime},\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta,\Delta^{\prime} is valid; and

  • if Γ\YrightΔ,ϕ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta,\phi and ϕ,Γ\YrightΔ\phi,\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta are valid, then Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is valid.121212Shoesmith and Smiley, (1978) claims a different transitivity property here, one that is properly stronger than ours in general, but is equivalent in our present setting where only finite arguments are considered. See Shoesmith and Smiley, (1978, §2.1) and Humberstone, (2011, §1.16) for helpful discussion of this difference; or for further discussion of various properties that travel under the name ‘transitivity’, and proofs of relations between these properties, see Ripley, (2017); Chen and Wen, (2024).

Regarding operational properties, we note (also for comparison with other consequence relations to be discussed presently) the situation around nn-ary conjunction introduction. Let p1,,pnp_{1},\ldots,p_{n} be the first nn atomic sentences, and let CInCI_{n} be the argument p1,,pn\Yrightpip_{1},\ldots,p_{n}\,\Yright\,\bigwedge p_{i}. Since this is a Set-Fmla classically valid argument, it is supervaluationistically valid, and so {1}\{1\}-preservation valid. Moreover, CI0CI_{0} and CI1CI_{1} are α\alpha-preservation valid for any α\alpha. However, for any α{1}\alpha\neq\{1\} and any n2n\geq 2, the argument CInCI_{n} is α\alpha-preservation invalid. This follows immediately from Fact 21, but we note it here for later comparison.

Next, we recall that subvaluationistic logic is what is sometimes called weakly paraconsistent (see Hyde, 1997): while ϕ¬ϕ\Yrightψ\phi\land\neg\phi\,\Yright\,\psi is subvaluationistically valid for any sentences ϕ,ψ\phi,\psi, there are nonetheless choices of ϕ,ψ\phi,\psi where ϕ,¬ϕ\Yrightψ\phi,\neg\phi\,\Yright\,\psi is invalid. For example, p,¬p\Yrightqp,\neg p\,\Yright\,q is subvaluationistically invalid. Upsets α\alpha that do not include .5.5 do not determine preservation consequence relations that are paraconsistent in any sense. Conversely, supervaluational logic has been called weakly paracomplete (see Hyde, 2008, p. 76, crediting Arruda): while ψ\Yrightϕ¬ϕ\psi\,\Yright\,\phi\vee\neg\phi is supervaluationistically valid, ψ\Yrightϕ,¬ϕ\psi\,\Yright\,\phi,\neg\phi is not.

For later reference, we note that it is not just the extremes; indeed every preservation consequence relation has exactly one of these properties:

Fact 34.

For any α\alpha, if .5α.5\not\in\alpha, then α\alpha-preservation consequence is weakly paracomplete but not weakly paraconsistent; and if .5α.5\in\alpha, then α\alpha-preservation consequence is weakly paraconsistent but not weakly paracomplete.

Proof.

Immediate, once it’s noted that there is a model that assigns probability .5.5 to both pp and ¬p\neg p, and that there is no model that assigns a probability strictly greater than .5.5 to both pp and ¬p\neg p. ∎

This also allows us to see that no α\alpha-preservation consequence relation is self-dual. In Section 5.1, we noted that no upset can be self-dual, since any upset α\alpha includes .5.5 iff its dual α\alpha^{\star} does not. However, that left open whether there could be two dual upsets which, while necessarily distinct as sets, still manage to determine the same preservation consequence relation. We can now see that this is never the case, since for any upset α\alpha, exactly one of α\alpha-preservation consequence and α\alpha^{\star}-preservation consequence must be weakly paraconsistent, and so they cannot be the same.

7 Symmetric consequence

We find it natural to think that classical logic should in some sense be a limit case of probabilistic reasoning, applying perfectly in cases of perfect certainty, and gradually approached as levels of certainty increase. However, as we’ve seen, neither material consequence nor preservation consequence seems to be able to support this natural thought. Material consequence is fully classical regardless of what upset we choose, and so regardless of the level of certainty in play; classical consequence gets to apply perfectly in cases of perfect certainty, but it applies perfectly in all other cases as well! It is not in any illuminating sense approached as certainty increases.

On the other hand, preservation consequence does at least provide us with some distinct consequence relations for different upsets α\alpha, as described in Theorem 31 and Corollary 33. However, it also fails to support our natural thought, in two ways. First, at the limit of perfect certainty—the upset {1}\{1\}—preservation consequence is not classical but supervaluational.

But even if we were to artificially restrict our attention to the Set-Fmla fragment, where this difference is not visible, Fact 21 tells us that again, we do not approach this limit as our upset narrows in any useful or informative way. To see this, take any classically-valid Set-Fmla argument whose premises are classically consistent, whose conclusion is not classically tautologous, and where no single premise classically entails the conclusion. For example, take modus ponens pq,p\Yrightqp\mathrel{\supset}q,p\,\Yright\,q, or conjunction introduction p,q\Yrightpqp,q\,\Yright\,p\land q, or really almost any example that actually gets used in argumentation. All such arguments, because Set-Fmla and classically valid, are {1}\{1\}-preservation valid. But by Fact 21, none of them is α\alpha-preservation valid for any other choice of α\alpha. These arguments all languish in invalidity as our choice of α\alpha narrows until the very last instant, at {1}\{1\}, where they all simultaneously leap to validity. This is not the gradual approach envisioned in our natural thought.

In this section, then, we introduce a third counterexample notion, determining what we call symmetric consequence. Unlike material and preservation consequence, symmetric consequence does support our natural thought, as we will show.

7.1 Definition

To define symmetric consequence, we use the idea of the mirror image of an upset. Recall from Section 5.1 that for any upset α\alpha, its mirror image α¯\overline{\alpha} is {x| 1xα}\{x\;|\;1-x\in\alpha\}. This reflects α\alpha around the midpoint .5.5. Since α\alpha is an upset, this means that α¯\overline{\alpha} must contain 0, must not contain 1, and must be closed downwards.

With this notion in hand, we are ready to define symmetric counterexamples:

Definition 35.

A probabilistic model 𝔐p\mathfrak{M}_{\textsc{p}} is an α\alpha-symmetric counterexample to an argument Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta iff p[Γ]α\textsc{p}[\Gamma]\subseteq\alpha and p[Δ]α¯\textsc{p}[\Delta]\subseteq\overline{\alpha}. Thus, the argument Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is α\alpha-symmetric valid iff every 𝔐p\mathfrak{M}_{\textsc{p}} is such that if p[Γ]α\textsc{p}[\Gamma]\subseteq\alpha, then there is some δΔ\delta\in\Delta with p(δ)α¯\textsc{p}(\delta)\not\in\overline{\alpha}.

In the same way that an upset α\alpha indicates probabilities that are high enough, we take its mirror image α¯\overline{\alpha} to indicate probabilities that are too low. By using the mirror image in this way, we assume that tight standards for what counts as high enough come linked with tight standards for what counts as too low, and similarly for loose standards.131313It is, of course, possible to consider a freer notion that would allow these standards to be set independently of each other. Sticking to probability distributions, this freer notion is closely related to ideas in Knight, (2003); Paris et al., (2009). To see a similar idea in the case of fuzzy logic see Cobreros et al., (2024). For more general reflections on such independence between premises and conclusions, see Humberstone, (1988); Blasio et al., (2017); Chemla et al., (2017); French and Ripley, (2019); Chemla and Égré, (2019). Here, though, we keep things simple and do not move to such freer settings.

For example, consider again (as in Section 4) the upset α=\interval[softopenfences,openleft].71\alpha=\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{.7}{1} and a single roll of a 6-sided die, where pp says that the die comes up strictly greater than 11 and qq says that the die comes up strictly less than 66. To give an α\alpha-symmetric counterexample to the argument p,q\Yrightpqp,q\,\Yright\,p\land q, we would need some probability distribution p such that p(p)>.7\textsc{p}(p)>.7 and p(q)>.7\textsc{p}(q)>.7 and p(pq)<.3\textsc{p}(p\land q)<.3. But this can never happen, whether or not the die is fair; by the Fréchet-Hoeffding bounds (which are a special case of Adams, 1998, Thm. 13, p. 38), for any probability distribution p where p(p)>.7\textsc{p}(p)>.7 and p(q)>.7\textsc{p}(q)>.7, we have p(pq)>.4\textsc{p}(p\land q)>.4. So the argument p,q\Yrightpqp,q\,\Yright\,p\land q is \interval[softopenfences,openleft].71\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{.7}{1}-symmetric valid.

As we saw above, however, this same argument is not \interval[softopenfences,openleft].71\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{.7}{1}-preservation valid. Intuitively, in this argument probabilities can slip from high enough to not high enough as we go from premises to conclusion, but they cannot slip from high enough to too low.

7.1.1 Negation and monotonicity

We begin our consideration of α\alpha-symmetric consequence by quickly noting some features it has that will smooth the reasoning to follow.

First, in Section 6.3, we noted that no α\alpha-preservation consequence relation is self-dual, in the sense that it validates any Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta iff it validates ¬Δ\Yright¬Γ\neg\Delta\,\Yright\,\neg\Gamma. The situation is very different for our symmetric consequence relations:

Fact 36.

For any upset α\alpha: the argument ϕ,Γ\YrightΔ\phi,\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is α\alpha-symmetrically valid iff Γ\YrightΔ,¬ϕ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta,\neg\phi is; and the argument Γ\YrightΔ,ϕ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta,\phi is α\alpha-symmetrically valid iff ¬ϕ,Γ\YrightΔ\neg\phi,\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is.

Proof.

Immediate from Definitions 14 and 35, recalling that p(¬ϕ)=1p(ϕ)\textsc{p}(\neg\phi)=1-\textsc{p}(\phi) for any probability distribution p. ∎

Fact 36 more than suffices to show that every α\alpha-symmetric consequence relation is self-dual, regardless of the choice of α\alpha.

Second (and relatedly), negation gives us a direct bridge between α\alpha-symmetric validity and α\alpha-unsatisfiability:

Fact 37.

An argument Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is α\alpha-symmetric valid iff Γ¬Δ\Gamma\cup\neg\Delta is α\alpha-unsatisfiable.

Proof.

Immediate from Definitions 13, 14 and 35, as in the proof of Fact 36. ∎

In what follows, we will appeal to Fact 37 without further comment, treating questions of α\alpha-symmetric validity and of α\alpha-unsatisfiability interchangeably.

Third, we turn to the question of the monotonicity of α\alpha-symmetric consequence. (We leave consideration of the other Tarskian properties for Section 7.4, since we will not need them before then.)

Fact 38.

For any upset α\alpha, the α\alpha-symmetric consequence relation is monotonic.

Proof.

Suppose that Γ,Γ\YrightΔ,Δ\Gamma^{\prime},\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta,\Delta^{\prime} is α\alpha-symmetric invalid; then it has a counterexample. But any counterexample to this argument is also a counterexample to Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta. ∎

7.2 Classicality in the limit

Here, we show that α\alpha-symmetric consequence fits well with our natural thought above. That is, as we move from wider upsets to narrower, the resulting symmetric consequence relations steadily approach classical consequence until, at the narrowest upset {1}\{1\}, they reach it exactly.

Fact 39.

If αβ\alpha\subseteq\beta and Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is β\beta-symmetric valid, then it is α\alpha-symmetric valid.

Proof.

We show the contrapositive; suppose that we have an α\alpha-symmetric counterexample to Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta. Since αβ\alpha\subseteq\beta, we know that α¯β¯\overline{\alpha}\subseteq\overline{\beta}, and so this very counterexample is itself a β\beta-symmetric counterexample as well. ∎

Compare Fact 39 to Facts 25 and 26. For preservation consequence, narrowing our upset can have complex results: it can move Set-Fmla arguments from invalid to valid, and can move Fmla-Set arguments in the other direction, from valid to invalid; and can affect other arguments in either direction.141414Consider, for example, the argument p,q,¬(pq)\Yrightr,¬rp,q,\neg(p\land q)\,\Yright\,r,\neg r. This is α\alpha-preservation valid because of its conclusion set if .5α.5\in\alpha, and it is α\alpha-preservation valid because of its premise set if 23α\frac{2}{3}\not\in\alpha. However, for any α\alpha where .5α.5\not\in\alpha and 23α\frac{2}{3}\in\alpha, this argument is α\alpha-preservation invalid, as we can build a model that assigns probability 23\frac{2}{3} to each premise and .5.5 to each conclusion. So as we consider the full range of upsets, narrowing from \interval[softopenfences,openleft]01\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1} to {1}\{1\}, this argument goes from valid to invalid and then back to valid. For symmetric consequence, on the other hand, narrowing our upset can only move an argument from invalid to valid, full stop.

This drastically simplifies the situation, by giving us a linear order on α\alpha-symmetric consequence relations, with \interval[softopenfences,openleft]01\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1}-symmetric consequence as the weakest and {1}\{1\}-symmetric consequence as the strongest. We turn now to describing these two consequence relations.

Fact 40.

An argument Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is {1}\{1\}-symmetric valid iff it is classically valid.

Proof.

First, suppose that we have a classical counterexample to Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta. Then consider the model {w},({w}),,p\langle\{w\},\wp(\{w\}),\llbracket\;\rrbracket,\textsc{p}\rangle, where \llbracket\;\rrbracket is set up to make the world ww that classical counterexample. This gives us p(γ)=1\textsc{p}(\gamma)=1 for each γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma and p(δ)=0\textsc{p}(\delta)=0 for each δΔ\delta\in\Delta, so we have our {1}\{1\}-symmetric counterexample.

For the other direction, suppose we have a {1}\{1\}-symmetric counterexample to Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta. This is some W,𝒜,,p\langle W,\mathcal{A},\llbracket\;\rrbracket,\textsc{p}\rangle where p(γ)=1\textsc{p}(\gamma)=1 for each γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma and p(δ)=0\textsc{p}(\delta)=0 for each δΔ\delta\in\Delta. Since Γ\Gamma and Δ\Delta are finite, this means that p(Γ)=1\textsc{p}(\bigwedge\Gamma)=1 and p(Δ)=0\textsc{p}(\bigvee\Delta)=0 as well. Since p(Γ)>p(Δ)\textsc{p}(\bigwedge\Gamma)>\textsc{p}(\bigvee\Delta), we must have ΓΔ\llbracket\bigwedge\Gamma\rrbracket\not\subseteq\llbracket\bigvee\Delta\rrbracket, so there must be some wWw\in W where wΓw\in\llbracket\bigwedge\Gamma\rrbracket and wΔw\not\in\llbracket\bigvee\Delta\rrbracket; this ww is our classical counterexample. ∎

As for \interval[softopenfences,openleft]01\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1}-symmetric validity, it turns out to be relatively simple, obtaining exactly when some premise is classically contradictory or some conclusion is classically tautologous:

Fact 41.

The argument Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is \interval[softopenfences,openleft]01\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1}-symmetric valid iff either: there is some γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma such that γ\gamma is classically contradictory; or there is some δΔ\delta\in\Delta such that δ\delta is a classical tautology.

Proof.

Since p(γ)=0\textsc{p}(\gamma)=0 for all probability distributions p and classically unsatisfiable γ\gamma, and similarly p(δ)=1\textsc{p}(\delta)=1 for all probability distributions p and classically tautologous δ\delta, the right-to-left direction is secured.

For the left-to-right direction, note that a \interval[softopenfences,openleft]01\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1}-symmetric counterexample to Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is any model that assigns non-0 probability to everything in Γ\Gamma and non-1 probability to everything in Δ\Delta. Now, we proceed contrapositively.

Take some Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta with no classically unsatisfiable γΓ\gamma\in\Gamma and no classically tautologous δΔ\delta\in\Delta. If ΓΔ=\Gamma\cup\Delta=\emptyset, then any model is a \interval[softopenfences,openleft]01\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1}-symmetric counterexample to Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta, so we have invalidity; assume, then, that ΓΔ\Gamma\cup\Delta is nonempty. Let Γ={γ1,,γm}\Gamma=\{\gamma_{1},\ldots,\gamma_{m}\} and Δ={δ1,,δn}\Delta=\{\delta_{1},\ldots,\delta_{n}\}; we know m+n1m+n\geq 1.

Now, take a model W,𝒜,,p\langle W,\mathcal{A},\llbracket\;\rrbracket,\textsc{p}\rangle such that:

  • W={w1,,wm,wm+1,,wm+n}W=\{w_{1},\ldots,w_{m},w_{m+1},\ldots,w_{m+n}\};

  • 𝒜=(W)\mathcal{A}=\wp(W);

  • \llbracket\;\rrbracket is such that:

    • for all 1im1\leq i\leq m, we have wiγiw_{i}\in\llbracket\gamma_{i}\rrbracket; and

    • for all 1jn1\leq j\leq n, we have wm+jδjw_{m+j}\not\in\llbracket\delta_{j}\rrbracket; and

  • for all 1km+n1\leq k\leq m+n, we have p({wk})=1m+n\textsc{p}(\{w_{k}\})=\frac{1}{m+n}.

Such a model exists; the constraints on \llbracket\;\rrbracket are jointly achievable because each constrains a different world, and we know that each γi\gamma_{i} is classically satisfiable and each δj\delta_{j} classically nontautologous. In this model, we have p(γi)1m+n>0\textsc{p}(\gamma_{i})\geq\frac{1}{m+n}>0 for each γiΓ\gamma_{i}\in\Gamma, and p(δj)11m+n<1\textsc{p}(\delta_{j})\leq 1-\frac{1}{m+n}<1 for each δjΔ\delta_{j}\in\Delta, so the model is a \interval[softopenfences,openleft]01\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1}-symmetric counterexample to Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta. ∎

Our picture of α\alpha-symmetric consequence is filling in bit by bit: at the narrowest upset {1}\{1\}, we indeed reach exactly Set-Set classical logic, but at the widest upset \interval[softopenfences,openleft]01\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1}, we have something different. Symmetric consequence is thus unlike both preservation consequence (which never gives classical logic) and material consequence (which never gives anything else).

We can draw on some of our earlier reasoning around α\alpha-satisfiability (from Section 6.2) to learn about what happens along the way, and in particular which distinct upsets determine distinct symmetric consequence relations.

Fact 42.

For any x(0,1)x\in(0,1), the \intervalx1\interval{x}{1}-symmetric and \interval[softopenfences,openleft]x1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{x}{1}-symmetric consequence relations are distinct iff xx is rational.

Proof.

Directly from Corollary 30 and Lemma 28. ∎

Fact 43.

For any distinct x,y\interval[softopenfences,openleft]01x,y\in\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1}, the \intervalx1\interval{x}{1}-symmetric and \intervaly1\interval{y}{1}-symmetric consequence relations are distinct, and so there are uncountably many distinct symmetric consequence relations.

Proof.

As in Theorem 32. Without loss of generality, let x<yx<y. Take some rational zz such that xz<yx\leq z<y, and use Lemma 28 to arrive at some Γ\Gamma that is \intervalz1\interval{z}{1}-satisfiable but not \interval[softopenfences,openleft]z1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{z}{1}-satisfiable. ∎

There is more to say, however, about α\alpha-symmetric consequence for closed upsets α\alpha:

Fact 44.

If Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is \intervalx1\interval{x}{1}-symmetric valid, then there is some α\intervalx1\alpha\supsetneq\interval{x}{1} such that Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is α\alpha-symmetric valid.

Proof.

Take any \intervalx1\interval{x}{1}-symmetric valid argument Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta. By theorem 29, there is some maximum z\interval01z\in\interval{0}{1} such that Γ¬Δ\Gamma\cup\neg\Delta is \intervalz1\interval{z}{1}-consistent. Then z<xz<x, since if zxz\geq x the argument Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta would not be \intervalx1\interval{x}{1}-symmetric valid; so choose some yy such that z<y<xz<y<x and let α=\intervaly1\alpha=\interval{y}{1}, noting that α\intervalx1\alpha\supsetneq\interval{x}{1}. By zz’s maximality, we know that Σ\Sigma is α\alpha-inconsistent; but then Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is α\alpha-symmetric valid. ∎

If we imagine starting a process at the widest upset \interval[softopenfences,openleft]01\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1} and gradually narrowing all the way to the other extreme {1}\{1\}, we now have a clear picture of the result. While arguments certainly move from invalid to valid as we narrow our upset, this doesn’t happen just anywhere. First, Fact 42 ensures us that this never happens in the move from \intervalx1\interval{x}{1} to \interval[softopenfences,openleft]x1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{x}{1} where xx is irrational. And Fact 44 ensures that this never happens as we move to a closed upset at all, regardless of whether its threshold is rational or irrational—any argument validated by the symmetric consequence at a closed upset was already validated by some properly wider upset. The only time a new argument can become valid, then, is in the shift from \intervalx1\interval{x}{1} to \interval[softopenfences,openleft]x1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{x}{1} when xx is rational—and Fact 42 ensures that this indeed happens for every rational xx.

Moreover, this process indeed reaches classical logic right at {1}\{1\}, just as our natural picture requires. (By Fact 43, it cannot reach classical logic any earlier.) We can see that the way this happens is very different from the way that preservation consequence reaches supervaluational logic at {1}\{1\}. As we saw above, there is a very large class of arguments, including most classically valid Set-Fmla arguments of any interest, that are {1}\{1\}-preservation valid but α\alpha-preservation invalid for all other α\alpha. Preservation consequence has a massive leap exactly at {1}\{1\} in its Set-Fmla fragment, and a corresponding massive leap exactly at \interval[softopenfences,openleft]01\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1} in its Fmla-Set fragment. Symmetric consequence, by contrast, has no sudden leap at {1}\{1\}; by Fact 44 it adds no valid arguments that were not already counted as valid on some wider upset, and this holds even for the full Set-Set framework.

7.3 Argument size

So far, this has all left open any questions about which arguments become valid when as the upset for symmetric consequence narrows. But in fact we can describe this process more precisely, pinpointing for at least some arguments exactly where in this process they move from invalid to valid, and giving for every argument an upper bound.

To do this, we’ll use the notion of the size of an argument and another result from Knight, (2002):

Definition 45.

The size of the argument Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is |Γ¬Δ||\Gamma\cup\neg\Delta|.151515In fact, the results to follow would also hold if size counted members of Γ¬Δ\Gamma\cup\neg\Delta only up to classical equivalence; and this notion might be better-behaved in some ways. But we kept it simple. An argument Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma^{\prime}\,\Yright\,\Delta^{\prime} is a subargument of the argument Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta iff ΓΓ\Gamma^{\prime}\subseteq\Gamma and ΔΔ\Delta^{\prime}\subseteq\Delta, and a proper subargument iff it is a subargument and they are distinct.

Fact 46 (Knight, 2002, Thm. 3.5, p. 80).

If Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is classically valid, but no proper subargument of it is classically valid, then where nn is its size, it is \intervaln1n1\interval{\frac{n-1}{n}}{1}-symmetric invalid and \interval[softopenfences,openleft]n1n1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{\frac{n-1}{n}}{1}-symmetric valid.

This immediately settles the situation for very many arguments. For example, recall from Section 6.3 the nn-ary conjunction introduction arguments, where CInCI_{n} is p1,,pn\Yrightpip_{1},\ldots,p_{n}\,\Yright\,\bigwedge p_{i}. Note that these all meet the conditions of Fact 46, and that CInCI_{n} has size n+1n+1. So for any nn, the argument CInCI_{n} is \intervalnn+11\interval{\frac{n}{n+1}}{1}-invalid and \interval[softopenfences,openleft]nn+11\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{\frac{n}{n+1}}{1}-valid. As α\alpha narrows, we can α\alpha-symmetric validly conjoin larger and larger collections of conjuncts.

Or let MPnMP_{n} be the argument p1,p1p2,,pn1pn\Yrightpnp_{1},p_{1}\mathrel{\supset}p_{2},\ldots,p_{n-1}\mathrel{\supset}p_{n}\,\Yright\,p_{n}. Again, all of these meet the conditions of Fact 46, and MPnMP_{n} has size n+1n+1. So for any α\alpha, MPnMP_{n} is α\alpha-symmetric valid iff CInCI_{n} is—again, as α\alpha narrows, we can α\alpha-symmetric validly detach longer and longer chains of material conditionals.

Fact 46 gives us the exact place where certain arguments move from invalid to valid as we narrow our upset, but it only covers arguments with no classically-valid proper subarguments. We can use it, however, to get an upper bound that applies to all arguments:161616Knight, (2002) also gives interesting and useful results for cases where Γ¬Δ\Gamma\cup\neg\Delta is inconsistent but not minimally so, achieving tighter upper bounds than this; but there are complexities involved that we prefer to avoid here.

Fact 47.

If Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is classically valid and has size nn, then it is \interval[softopenfences,openleft]n1n1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{\frac{n-1}{n}}{1}-symmetric valid.

Proof.

If Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is classically valid, then it contains some subargument Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma^{\prime}\,\Yright\,\Delta^{\prime} that is minimally classically valid; let this subargument have size mm. By Fact 46, this subargument is \interval[softopenfences,openleft]m1m1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{\frac{m-1}{m}}{1}-symmetric valid; and so by Fact 38 Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is as well. But since Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma^{\prime}\,\Yright\,\Delta^{\prime} is a subargument of Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta, we know that mnm\leq n, and so \interval[softopenfences,openleft]n1n1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]m1m1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{\frac{n-1}{n}}{1}\subseteq\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{\frac{m-1}{m}}{1}. By Fact 39, then, we have our result. ∎

This fleshes out our natural thought, giving us more detail about when various classically-valid arguments settle into α\alpha-symmetric validity. It also lets us determine, for any classically valid argument, some degree of probability that is not perfect certainty but still high enough to ensure that the argument’s premises can’t all have probability that high while all its conclusions have symmetrically low probabilities.

7.4 Tarskian properties, weak paraconsistency, weak paracompleteness

We now turn to questions of the Tarskian-ness (or otherwise) of symmetric consequence relations, and also consider their weak paraconsistency and weak paracompleteness.

We have already seen in Fact 38 that all α\alpha-symmetric consequence relations are monotonic. But since symmetric consequence is not defined by preserving any single status across all models, it is worth asking about reflexivity and transitivity as well.171717There is more on this topic in Humberstone, (1988); French and Ripley, (2019).

Fact 48.

α\alpha-symmetric consequence is reflexive iff .5α.5\not\in\alpha.

Proof.

If .5α.5\in\alpha, then also .5α¯.5\in\overline{\alpha}. In this case, take a two-world model {u,v},({u,v}),,p\langle\{u,v\},\wp(\{u,v\}),\llbracket\;\rrbracket,\textsc{p}\rangle such that p={u}\llbracket p\rrbracket=\{u\} and p({u})=p({v})=.5\textsc{p}(\{u\})=\textsc{p}(\{v\})=.5; this is an α\alpha-symmetric counterexample to p\Yrightpp\,\Yright\,p.

On the other hand, suppose we have any α\alpha-symmetric counterexample W,𝒜,,p\langle W,\mathcal{A},\llbracket\;\rrbracket,\textsc{p}\rangle to p\Yrightpp\,\Yright\,p. Then we must have p(p)αα¯\textsc{p}(p)\in\alpha\cap\overline{\alpha}; but if αα¯\alpha\cap\overline{\alpha} is nonempty then .5α.5\in\alpha. ∎

Fact 49.

α\alpha-symmetric consequence is transitive iff .5α.5\in\alpha or α={1}\alpha=\{1\}.

Proof.

By Fact 40 (and the fact that classical consequence is transitive), we know that {1}\{1\}-symmetric consequence is transitive. So let α{1}\alpha\neq\{1\}.

First, we show that if .5α.5\in\alpha then α\alpha-symmetric consequence is transitive. To that end, we show the contrapositive: that if Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is α\alpha-symmetric invalid, then at least one of the arguments Γ\YrightΔ,ϕ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta,\phi or ϕ,Γ\YrightΔ\phi,\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is α\alpha-symmetric invalid as well. To see this, let .5α.5\in\alpha, and take an α\alpha-symmetric counterexample W,𝒜,,p\langle W,\mathcal{A},\llbracket\;\rrbracket,\textsc{p}\rangle to Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta. If p(ϕ).5\textsc{p}(\phi)\geq.5, then this is also an α\alpha-symmetric counterexample to ϕ,Γ\YrightΔ\phi,\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta; and if p(ϕ).5\textsc{p}(\phi)\leq.5, then this is also an α\alpha-symmetric counterexample to Γ\YrightΔ,ϕ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta,\phi. So one or the other of those arguments indeed must be α\alpha-symmetric invalid.

Now, we show that if .5α{1}.5\not\in\alpha\neq\{1\}, then α\alpha-symmetric consequence is not transitive. Return to our arguments CInCI_{n} discussed above. By our assumptions on α\alpha, we know from Fact 46 that CI2CI_{2} is α\alpha-symmetric valid and that there is some kk such that CIkCI_{k} is not α\alpha-symmetric valid. But it is quick to see that any monotonic and transitive consequence relation where CI2CI_{2} is valid must validate CInCI_{n} for all nn. Since we know from Fact 38 that α\alpha-symmetric consequence is monotonic, it must not be transitive. ∎

Facts 48, 38 and 49 together show that, among α\alpha-symmetric consequence relations, only one is fully Tarskian: the limit case of {1}\{1\}-symmetric consequence, which is classical consequence. For all other choices of α\alpha, either .5α.5\in\alpha and we have a nonreflexive (but transitive) consequence relation, or .5α.5\not\in\alpha and we have a nontransitive (but reflexive) relation.

We also have some easy facts about weak paraconsistency and weak paracompleteness, that again connect to the key question whether .5α.5\in\alpha:

Fact 50.

For any α\alpha, the following are equivalent:

  • α\alpha-symmetric consequence is weakly paraconsistent;

  • α\alpha-symmetric consequence is weakly paracomplete;

  • α\alpha-symmetric consequence is nonreflexive.

Proof.

Weak paraconsistency implies weak paracompleteness: let ϕ,¬ϕ\YrightΔ\phi,\neg\phi\,\Yright\,\Delta be α\alpha-symmetric invalid. Then by self-duality, ¬Δ\Yright¬ϕ,¬¬ϕ\neg\Delta\,\Yright\,\neg\phi,\neg\neg\phi is invalid; this shows weak paracompleteness.

Weak paracompleteness implies nonreflexivity: let Γ\Yrightϕ,¬ϕ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\phi,\neg\phi be α\alpha-symmetric invalid. Then by Fact 36 Γ,ϕ\Yrightϕ\Gamma,\phi\,\Yright\,\phi is α\alpha-symmetric invalid, and so by Fact 38 ϕ\Yrightϕ\phi\,\Yright\,\phi must be α\alpha-symmetric invalid.

Nonreflexivity implies weak paraconsistency: let ϕ\Yrightϕ\phi\,\Yright\,\phi be α\alpha-symmetric invalid. Then by Fact 36 ϕ,¬ϕ\Yright\phi,\neg\phi\,\Yright\,\emptyset is α\alpha-symmetric invalid. Since ϕ¬ϕ\phi\land\neg\phi can never take probability other than 0, any counterexample to ϕ,¬ϕ\Yright\phi,\neg\phi\,\Yright\,\emptyset is also a counterexample to ϕ,¬ϕ\Yrightϕ¬ϕ\phi,\neg\phi\,\Yright\,\phi\land\neg\phi. ∎

7.5 Relations to preservation consequence

We close our discussion of symmetric consequence relations by pointing out some relations of relative strength that connect symmetric and preservation consequence relations. Recall that from Fact 39 we know that if αα\alpha\subseteq\alpha^{\star} then α\alpha-symmetric consequence is at least as strong as α\alpha^{\star}-symmetric consequence, and if αα\alpha^{\star}\subseteq\alpha then α\alpha^{\star}-symmetric consequence is at least as strong as α\alpha-symmetric consequence. In fact, we can show that either way, α\alpha-preservation consequence always lies somewhere properly in between:

Fact 51.

For any α\alpha, the consequence relation of α\alpha-preservation is intermediate in strength between α\alpha-symmetric consequence and α\alpha^{\star}-symmetric consequence.

Proof.

Without loss of generality, suppose that αα\alpha\subseteq\alpha^{\star},181818If instead αα\alpha^{\star}\subseteq\alpha, then let β=α\beta=\alpha^{\star} and apply the result to β\beta. and so by Fact 39 if any argument Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is α\alpha^{\star}-symmetric valid it must also be α\alpha-symmetric valid.

We show first that if any Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is α\alpha^{\star}-symmetric valid then it is α\alpha-preservation valid. Suppose that 𝔐=W,𝒜,,p\mathfrak{M}=\langle W,\mathcal{A},\llbracket\;\rrbracket,\textsc{p}\rangle is an α\alpha-preservation counterexample to Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta; then p[Γ]α\textsc{p}[\Gamma]\subseteq\alpha and p[Δ]\interval01α\textsc{p}[\Delta]\subseteq\interval{0}{1}\setminus\alpha. Since αα\alpha\subseteq\alpha^{\star}, we have that p[Γ]α\textsc{p}[\Gamma]\subseteq\alpha^{\star}, and \interval01α=α¯\interval{0}{1}\setminus\alpha=\overline{\alpha^{\star}}, so 𝔐\mathfrak{M} is in fact a α\alpha^{\star}-symmetric counterexample to Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta as well.

Next we show that if any Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta is α\alpha-preservation valid then it is α\alpha-symmetric valid. Suppose that 𝔐=W,𝒜,,p\mathfrak{M}=\langle W,\mathcal{A},\llbracket\;\rrbracket,\textsc{p}\rangle is an α\alpha-symmetric counterexample to Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta; then p[Γ]α\textsc{p}[\Gamma]\subseteq\alpha and p[Δ]α¯=\interval01α\textsc{p}[\Delta]\subseteq\overline{\alpha}=\interval{0}{1}\setminus\alpha^{\star}. But since αα\alpha\subseteq\alpha^{\star}, we know that \interval01α\interval01α\interval{0}{1}\setminus\alpha^{\star}\subseteq\interval{0}{1}\setminus\alpha, so p[Δ]\interval01α\textsc{p}[\Delta]\subseteq\interval{0}{1}\setminus\alpha, and 𝔐\mathfrak{M} is in fact an α\alpha-preservation counterexample to Γ\YrightΔ\Gamma\,\Yright\,\Delta as well. ∎

Moreover, we can also show that preservation consequence and symmetric consequence never quite meet:

Fact 52.

For any upsets α,β\alpha,\beta, we have that α\alpha-symmetric consequence is distinct from β\beta-preservation consequence.

Proof.

By Fact 50, α\alpha-symmetric consequence is either: both weakly paracomplete and weakly paraconsistent, or neither weakly paracomplete nor weakly paraconsistent. By Fact 34, β\beta-preservation consequence is either: weakly paracomplete and not weakly paraconsistent, or weakly paraconsistent and not weakly paracomplete. So they cannot be the same. ∎

8 Conclusion

In this paper we have explored three notions of probabilistic consequence, which we called material consequence, preservation consequence, and symmetric consequence. Preservation consequence is the most central of these three, since material consequence and symmetric consequence can be both be reduced to it. Indeed, to say that Γ\Gamma α\alpha materially entails Δ\Delta is to say that ΓΔ\bigwedge\Gamma\mathrel{\supset}\bigvee\Delta is α\alpha-preservation valid. And to say that Γ\Gamma α\alpha-symmetrically entails Δ\Delta is to say that Γ¬Δ\Gamma\cup\neg\Delta α\alpha-entails a contradiction.

All three relations of consequence coincide with classical logic in specific cases, but while material consequence coincides with classical logic for any α\alpha, symmetric consequence coincides with classical logic only in the case of α={1}\alpha=\{1\}; preservation consequence too coincides with classical logic for α={1}\alpha=\{1\}, but only in the Set-Fmla setting. In the Set-Set setting, as we have seen, certainty preservation yields supervaluationism rather than classical logic. Figure 1 gives a representation of the containment relations between these logics. In this figure, a logic is included in another when it is lower and connected by a solid edge; thick lines indicate continuum many logics, either contained one in another in the case of solid thick lines or all incomparable in the case of dotted thick lines.

Our exploration in this paper leaves us with some open questions. In particular, we have yet to prove or to disprove Conjecture 24 above, and stating that nontrivial Set-Set cases of α\alpha-entailment supervene on classical entailment between a specific premise and a specific conclusion. On a more philosophical level, we have yet to examine how these various consequence relations can help us handle specific arguments, such as the lottery paradox, the preface paradox, and the sorites paradox — invoked in particular by Adams, (1998) and Knight, (2002), and which also motivated the fuzzy counterpart of symmetric consequence relations found in Smith, (2008); Cobreros et al., (2024). We leave this investigation, as well as the issue of which consequence relation or relations to favor and to build upon, for further work.

S\interval[softopenfences,openleft]01\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1}α\alpha^{\star}α\alpha^{\prime\star}β\beta^{\star}γ\gamma^{\star}γ\gammaβ\betaα\alpha^{\prime}α\alphaS{1}\{1\}P\interval[softopenfences,openleft]01\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1}α\alpha^{\star}\mkern-10.0muα\alpha^{\prime\star}\mkern-15.0muβ\beta^{\star}\mkern-10.0muγ\gamma^{\star}\mkern-10.0muγ\gammaβ\betaα\alpha^{\prime}\mkern-10.0muα\alphaP{1}\{1\}

Symmetric consequence relations pictured on the vertical axis; preservation on the horizontal. Solid lines indicate containment; dotted lines indicate incomparability. Thick lines indicate continuum many consequence relations. γ\gamma is the upset \interval[softopenfences,openleft].51\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{.5}{1}. Zooming in at any rational z>.5z>.5 reveals the indicated structure where α\alpha is \interval[softopenfences,openleft]z1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{z}{1} and α\alpha^{\prime} is \intervalz1\interval{z}{1}; zooming in at any irrational x>.5x>.5 reveals the indicated structure where β\beta is both \interval[softopenfences,openleft]x1\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{x}{1} and \intervalx1\interval{x}{1}.

P\interval[softopenfences,openleft]01\interval[softopenfences,openleft]{0}{1} is also subvaluational, P{1}\{1\} supervaluational, and S{1}\{1\} is classical logic as well as every material consequence relation.

Figure 1: Containments among consequence relations

Acknowledgments

We thank two anonymous referees for their helpful comments, as well as several audiences, in particular at the Melbourne Logic Workshop held at Monash University in 2023, at the University of Queensland, and at the workshop Conditionals 2024 held in Barcelona. We also thank several colleagues for helpful exchanges and discussions on topics connected to this paper, including Guillermo Badia, Quentin Blomet, Alba Cuenca, Pablo Cobreros, Tommaso Flaminio, Peter Fritz, Lluis Godo, Gabriele Kern-Isberner, Serafina Lapenta, Lorenzo Rossi, Hans Rott, Giuseppe Sanfilippo, Jan Sprenger, and Benjamin Spector. This research received support from PLEXUS (Grant Agreement no 101086295), a Marie Sklodowska-Curie action funded by the EU under the Horizon Europe Research and Innovation Programme. We also thank the ANR programs PROBASEM (ANR-19-CE28-0004) and FRONTCOG (17-EURE-0017). DR thanks the ARC project “Substructural logics for limited resources”. PE thanks Institut Jean-Nicod (CNRS, ENS-PSL, EHESS), and Monash University for hosting him during the writing of this paper.

References

  • Adams, (1996) Adams, E. (1996). Four probability-preserving properties of inferences. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 25:1–24.
  • Adams, (1998) Adams, E. W. (1998). A Primer of Probability Logic. CSLI Publications, Stanford, California.
  • Adams and Levine, (1975) Adams, E. W. and Levine, H. P. (1975). On the uncertainties transmitted from premises to conclusions in deductive inferences. Synthese, 30(3/4):429–460.
  • Bergmann, (2008) Bergmann, M. (2008). An introduction to many-valued and fuzzy logic: semantics, algebras, and derivation systems. Cambridge University Press.
  • Biazzo et al., (2005) Biazzo, V., Gilio, A., Lukasiewicz, T., and Sanfilippo, G. (2005). Probabilistic logic under coherence: Complexity and algorithms. Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence, 45:35–81.
  • Blasio et al., (2017) Blasio, C., Marcos, J., and Wansing, H. (2017). An inferentially many-valued two-dimensional notion of entailment. Bulletin of the Section of Logic, 46(3/4):233–262.
  • Chemla and Égré, (2019) Chemla, E. and Égré, P. (2019). Suszko’s problem: Mixed consequence and compositionality. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 12(4):736–767.
  • Chemla et al., (2017) Chemla, E., Égré, P., and Spector, B. (2017). Characterizing logical consequence in many-valued logic. Journal of Logic and Computation, 27(7):2193–2226.
  • Chen and Wen, (2024) Chen, L. and Wen, X. (2024). On the transitivity of logical consequence without assuming monotonicity. Logica Universalis.
  • Cobreros et al., (2024) Cobreros, P., Égré, P., Ripley, D., and van Rooij, R. (2024). Tolerance and degrees of truth. In Petrolo, M. and Venturi, G., editors, Paradoxes between Truth and Proof, pages 209–235. Springer.
  • Égré et al., (2024) Égré, P., Rossi, L., and Sprenger, J. (2024). Certain and uncertain inference with indicative conditionals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy. Forthcoming.
  • Fine, (1975) Fine, K. (1975). Vagueness, truth, and logic. Synthese, 30:265–300.
  • Fréchet, (1935) Fréchet, M. (1935). Généralisation du théorème des probabilités totales. Fundamenta mathematicae, 25(1):379–387.
  • French and Ripley, (2019) French, R. and Ripley, D. (2019). Valuations: bi, tri, and tetra. Studia Logica. An International Journal for Symbolic Logic, 107(6):1313–1346.
  • Hailperin, (1984) Hailperin, T. (1984). Probability logic. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 25(3):198–212.
  • Hájek, (1998) Hájek, P. (1998). Metamathematics of fuzzy logic. Springer.
  • Humberstone, (1988) Humberstone, L. (1988). Heterogeneous logic. Erkenntnis. An International Journal of Scientific Philosophy, 29(3):395–435.
  • Humberstone, (2011) Humberstone, L. (2011). The connectives. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.
  • Hyde, (1997) Hyde, D. (1997). From heaps and gaps to heaps of gluts. Mind, 106(424):641–660.
  • Hyde, (2008) Hyde, D. (2008). Vagueness, logic and ontology. Ashgate, Aldershot.
  • Jaśkowski, (1969) Jaśkowski, S. (1969). Propositional calculus for contradictory deductive systems. Studia Logica: An International Journal for Symbolic Logic, 24:143–160. Communicated at the Meeting of March 19, 1948.
  • Klein et al., (2021) Klein, D., Majer, O., and Rafiee Rad, S. (2021). Probabilities with gaps and gluts. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 50(5):1107–1141.
  • Knight, (2002) Knight, K. (2002). Measuring inconsistency. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 31(1):77–98.
  • Knight, (2003) Knight, K. (2003). Probabilistic entailment and a non-probabilistic logic. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 11(3):353–365.
  • Kremer and Kremer, (2003) Kremer, P. and Kremer, M. (2003). Some supervaluation-based consequence relations. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 32(3):225–244.
  • Kyburg, (1997) Kyburg, H. E. (1997). The rule of adjunction and reasonable inference. The Journal of Philosophy, 94(3):109–125.
  • Ladd-Franklin and Peirce, (1902) Ladd-Franklin, C. and Peirce, C. S. (1902). Validity. In Baldwin, J., editor, Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology, pages 748–749.
  • Moss, (2018) Moss, S. (2018). Probabilistic knowledge. Oxford University Press.
  • Paris, (2004) Paris, J. (2004). Deriving information from inconsistent knowledge bases. Logic Journal of IGPL, 12(5):345–353.
  • Paris et al., (2009) Paris, J., Muino, D. P., and Rosefield, M. (2009). Inconsistency as qualified truth: a probability logic approach. International Journal of Approximate Reasoning, 50(8):1151–1163.
  • Ripley, (2013) Ripley, D. (2013). Sorting out the sorites. In Tanaka, K., Berto, F., and Mares, E., editors, Paraconsistency: Logic and Applications, pages 329–3. Springer.
  • Ripley, (2017) Ripley, D. (2017). On the ‘transitivity’ of consequence relations. Journal of Logic and Computation, 28(2):433–450.
  • Shoesmith and Smiley, (1978) Shoesmith, D. J. and Smiley, T. J. (1978). Multiple-conclusion logic. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
  • Skyrms, (1966) Skyrms, B. (1966). Choice and Chance: an Introduction to Inductive Logic. Dickenson Publishing Co., Inc.; Belmont, California. Fourth edition, Wadsworth/Thomson, 2000.
  • Smith, (2008) Smith, N. J. J. (2008). Vagueness and Degrees of Truth. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
  • Tarski, (1936) Tarski, A. (1936). The concept of logical consequence. In Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics, pages 409–420. Hackett publishing company.
  • Varzi, (1994) Varzi, A. (1994). Universal Semantics. PhD thesis, University of Toronto.
  • Williamson, (1994) Williamson, T. (1994). Vagueness. Blackwell.