Presented at
Physics Beyond Relativity 2019 conference
Prague, Czech Republic, October 20, 2019
(invited presentation)
Logical Analysis of Relativity Theory
1 Prelude
1.1 Newton v.s. Galileo: Reclining Tower Experiment
Through analysing Kepler’s massive data on the observed motion of planets, Newton reached the conclusion that our planets are orbiting around the Sun and the cause of such circular motion is the gravitational pull (centripetal force) exerted by the Sun on the planets. Upon this discovery, Newton developed the first theory of dynamics in human history. This should be understood as the first major example of how empiricism contributed to building a most important theory of physics.
Interestingly, this success also gives a stern warning to the popularized thesis that this process is one-way only. Indeed, as we will show in what follows, that Newton’s dynamics refutes Galileo’s famous reclining tower experiment.
Since the famous reclining tower experiment of Galileo, students of physics have been told that contrary to the ancient claim of Aristotle, the speed of a falling light object and that of a heavy object were the same when dropped from the same height.
In what follows, we will see that, according to Newtonian mechanics, Aristotle was correct, namely that the heavier the mass the faster it falls.
Assume and are two masses with . Let be the distance from the centre of the Earth to both and . Let be the mass of the Earth. The gravitational force between the Earth and is So,
where is the absolute acceleration of due to the gravitational pull by . The absolute acceleration for in the absolute space is . Therefore the relative acceleration between and is The time required for and to reach is not the same unless . If , we have
This means “The heavier the mass the faster it falls.”
This is a clear example of how inaccurate experiment could readily lead us to the wrong conclusion. Physics community believed in this wrong prediction by Galileo for four centuries until we brought up this problem just a few years ago.
Remark 1
Indeed, in a more advanced stage of quantum mechanics, Kuhn pointed out that there is no such thing as the so-called experimental verification or even refutation. This is because the prediction in quantum mechanics is intrinsically probabilistic and the probability theory states that the relative frequency converges only at the limit. Indeed, one cannot experimentally prove that in tossing a coin the probability of obtaining heads is 0.5.
1.2 Newton’s absolutism v.s. Galileo’s relativism: God v.s. human
Galileo assumed that each observer in this universe has his/her own reference frame in which physical phenomena take place. He further assumed that the observer is stationary in his/her own reference frame and that some objects are stationary in his/her frame while others are in motion in his/her frame. This means that the entire frame of another observer moving in his frame is moving inside his frame.
All of this makes the observed phenomena appear different in different reference frames. To resolve this problem, Galileo assumed that every reference frame has its own independent status and that reference frames are connected to each other through the so-called Principle of Relativity which asserts that all valid laws of physics must be shared by all reference frames.
Newton objected to this view of Galileo and presented a strikingly different view of relativism (relative motion). Within the absolute theory of dynamics as discussed above, Newton defined “relative motion” as the difference between two absolute motions in the absolute frame of the universe. So, unlike Galileo’s view, relative motions are to be observed only by an observer standing on the shoulder of God from outside of the physical universe. For Galileo, the relative motions are to be observed by the moving observer.
Without this absolute perspective, Galileo’s relativity theory suffered from a fundamental obscurity. It has always been a controversial issue in relativity theory as to whether if A observes B moving with speed , B should observe that A is moving with speed . Some relativists agree and some disagree. After all, assuming this is violating the most important assumption of “symmetry” which is essential to relativism. Why a difference in the sign? To begin with, this issue raises a fundamental question on the validity of Galilean relativity theory and its extension, Einsteinian relativity theory. This certainly gives rise to a most fundamental question of what do we mean by “observation”. As an “empiricism”, relativism has a duty to make this point clear.
In the fast developing phase of the theoretical physics this fundamental difference between these views of the two giants have been overlooked. A major purpose of this monograph is to make the relation between them articulate so as to clear the existing confusion.
Galileo had not articulated laws of physics as axioms. He experimentally proved that regardless of the magnitude of “masses”, two masses take the same time to reach the ground when released from the same height. Naturally, he had no theory to precisely prove this experimental fact. So, it was impossible for his contemporaries to evaluate the validity (or the effectiveness) of the principle of relativity. A century later, Newton’s dynamics presented legitimate laws of physics and it was discovered that when we consider two Galilean reference frames that are in acceleration with respect to each other the principle of relativity fails. The standard argument goes as follows: Assume a train is in acceleration on a track. On the embankment, there is a tree. An observer on the embankment will observe that the train is under force. Another observer on the embankment will observe that the tree is under acceleration. So, Post-Newtonian era Galilean relativists resolved this problem by rejecting reference frames under acceleration. In this way they abandoned most of Newton’s dynamics. From this point on, researchers stopped paying much attention to this problem until it resurfaced in the late 19th century when the Michelson-Morley experiment threw physics into a serious crisis from which Einstein’s special theory of relativity emerged.
What is not clear is whether this argument involves the applicability of the Newtonian laws of physics to Galilean relativity theory. Newton assumed these laws only for the absolute frame. This problem can be more clearly explicated as follows: Assume we allow moving reference frames inside Newton’s absolute frame. Assume and are attracting each other with the gravitational force. If we consider a reference frame for that moves inside the absolute frame of Newton, we end up with violating the third law of Newton’s as is not moving in this frame. So, there is no hope for expecting Newton’s law of physics to be shared by all reference frames.
The Newtonian interpretation above is based upon the observation from the outside of the universe. Galileo was observing it from the frame of himself and the reclining tower, which is the frame of . This will give us an entirely different conclusion. According to Galileo, does not move and so the acceleration between and is Similarly, the acceleration between and is So both and will reach the ground within the same time interval. This result is false as the reasoning behind it ignored the action-reaction law in between and . In classical dynamics we accept the assumption of point mass.
This deep philosophical problem will resurface in the modern setting when Einsteinian relativists present the light bend observation as the empirical verification of the claim of the general theory of relativity.
1.3 Classical Electromagnetism
The theory of electromagnetism was started by Coulomb as an action at a distance theory of electromagnetic forces. The first systematic theorization was done by Gauss and Weber. As Faraday’s work, such as Faraday induction, made the theory more complex than Newton’s gravitational theory, Heaviside and Hertz moved towards a theory that was based upon electromagnetic force field diverting from the action at a distance theory. Having been influenced by Heaviside and Hertz, Maxwell reluctantly formalized the electromagnetic theory as a field theory. However, together with Lorentz, Maxwell was trying to deploy an action-reaction-based interpretation of the field-based theory to compensate for some fundamental deficiencies of the electromagnetic field theory. This is known as “electromagnetic aether theory”. Maxwell’s electromagnetic field equations are
Here is the current vector that transcends electromagnetic force field and is the charge density of the current.
The first major impact of the introduction of the force field concept into the formulation of the electromagnetic theory was the apparent increase of the mass of a charge in the field in terms of acceleration. This problem already appeared in the fluid dynamics of Stokes.
(1) J. J. Thomson discovered that “energy of electromagnetic field” gives raise to an additional mass to charged bodies and called it electromagnetic mass (renormalized mass).
(2) Using the “momentum of electromagnetic fields”, Poincaré showed that these fields contribute an additional mass to a charged body.
(3) J.J. Thomson further observed that electromagnetic mass (renormalized mass) increases as the velocity of the mass increases.
(4) Summing up the above, Lorentz concluded that the ratio of the electron’s mass in the moving frame and that of the ether frame is parallel to the direction of motion (longitudinal), and perpendicular to the direction of motion (transverse) where and is a constant. Setting Lorentz calculated the expressions for the electromagnetic masses in these directions as
This means that well before Einstein’s relativity theory, Thomson and Lorentz concluded that the “speed of a charged mass” could not exceed .
Indeed, what is astounding here is that this work on renormalized mass put electromagnetic theory in direct conflict with classical dynamics. In the latter, mass will not be affected by its speed. The direct link between speed and mass immediately violates the second law of Newton where force is determined only by acceleration as mass is invariant. This manifests itself further as the violation of the second law of Newton as in the so-called Lorentz force we have
All of this implies that the issue of “electromagnetic mass” is still alive and to be investigated. The most urgent problem is that Lorentz force makes the electromagnetic field theory inconsistent as it also uses Newton’s second law.
Regarding Poincarè’s electromagnetic mass, what is outstanding is that he obtained it from the electromagnetic momentum instead of the electromagnetic energy. J. J. Thomson obtained it from electromagnetic energy. We know that energy is a modal concept and not a physical reality.
1.4 Michelson-Morley experiment
As proponents of Newton’s dynamics, Michelson and Morley felt urged to find out the absolute speed of our planet in the absolute space. Their idea was that when we measure the speed of light in all directions possible, then in the direction of the motion of our planet the speed of light will be maximum. To their astonishment they found out that the measured speed of light is the same in all directions. They subsequently concluded that the speed of light is constant regardless of the speed of the emitter of light, in symbols . Regarding this apparent contradiction, there are at least two major issues to be discussed before coming up with hasty conclusions.
(1) Experiment in general is not as simple a matter as we tend to think. Indeed, the great mathematician/philosopher Russell already warned us that experimental verification is viciously circular as to design an experiment, we use a theory whose validity is to be verified by the experiment. In the same sense, he pointed out that experimental refutation of a theory is also viciously circular. To design an experiment to refute a theory requires the use of the theory to be refuted. This gives rise to the questioning on the most fundamental role of experiments in physics, which, unlike engineering, is a theory. Logical coherence is a most important issue of physics.
(2) It is not quite clear what Michelson and Morley really did. Were they measuring the speed of light in the absolute frame or in the frame of the apparatus? All we can say at this stage is that, as Newton implied, the absolute speed of anything cannot be empirically known unless we stand on the shoulder of God. Was this not what made Michelson and Morley want to measure our absolute speed in the universe?
All of these are rather philosophical and conceptual questions. One of the major deficiencies of the current practice of physics is the failure to consider these conceptually important questions. The Michelson-Morley experiment is one of the main examples of this deficiency. Despite its overvalued importance, the more we think the more we get lost.
1.5 Fitzgerald contraction and electromagnetic Lorentz transformation
The first group of physicists who took the result of the Michelson-Morley experiment very seriously were researchers in the electromagnetic field theory, which was expected as the theory of light was a part of the EM field theory of Maxwell. Fitzgerald prematurely concluded that a moving body shrinks in the direction of the motion. Theoretically, there is no such thing as physical bodies as Newton reduced all of them to point masses in order to make the mathematics work to form a theory of dynamics. This is to say that a body is not the subject of theoretical study in dynamics. (In modern day term what Fitzgerald called body is a massively complex system of particles, each of which obeys the laws of quantum mechanics.) It was Lorentz who embraced this idea of Fitzgerald and developed it into the concept of what we now call Lorentz transformation. For Lorentz, who was not a relativist, this transformation however was limited only to between the absolute electromagnetic field and a frame moving inside it.
2 Special theory of relativity: kinematics
2.1 Special theory of relativity: kinematics
Einstein thought that Lorentz transformation, which was limited just to the absolute electromagnetic field frame and a moving frame, can be generalized to any two reference frames, thus removing the concept of the absolute frame. As discussed above, after Newton’s dynamics, relativists removed accelerating reference frames to avoid violating the principle of relativity, the action-reaction law in particular. Einstein was not an exception. Now the Galilean relativity theory is limited only to inertial reference frames.
2.2 Time dilation and length contraction
To this Galilean relativity theory of inertial frames, Einstein added the axiom of the Constancy of the Speed of Light (CSL) reflecting the Michelson-Morley experiment. The CSL says that in all inertial frames the speed of light is constant . So, if light in a frame F is observed by an observer A in an inertial frame F and by another observer A’ in an inertial frame F’, both A and A’ will observe that the same light moves with speed .
Remark 2
One of the major issues regarding this claim is that we do not know what light is and therefore we don’t know either what we mean by “measuring” the speed of light. This is a near fatal problem with the philosophy of empiricism, which was questioned by Newton. The concept of measurement is not a definable concept and, as Russell said, such a concept may well be viciously circular.
Notwithstanding, based upon the axiom of CSL, Einstein went on to obtain time dilation (TD) and length contraction (LC) through a thought experiment. Now, the simplest way to explicate Einstein’s argument for TD and LC is to present a thought experiment that exposes the fundamental inconsistency of the theory of inertial reference frames with the CSL axiom. We call this thought experiment “the (power pole)-(power line) paradox.
It goes like this. Assume a train runs on a track. When the tip of the power pole of the train touches the power line at point P a spark occurs at P. An observer located in the train straight down the point P will observe that the light comes straight down to him/her from the point P, which is the tip of the power pole. Also the observer will see that the same light comes to him/her diagonally from the point P, which also is a stationary point of the power line. This is a contradiction. and it is consistent with Aristotle’s warning that a point on a line may not be a part of the line. the same is held by contemporary topologists but in a more modern way, namely that real numbers (even rational numbers on the real line) are defined through a limit. Therefore there is no finite access to any real number on a real line. If we cannot access it, how can we move it? If we cannot move even a single point in our 3D space, how can we move the entire 3D space inside another 3D space? In short, topology says that a point does not exist on a topological space.
So what about the issue of TD and LC? The simplest way to refute these two claims is such that topology refutes the possibility of moving 3D space inside another space. So, the setting of the thought experiment for proving TD and LC is invalid. It is no wonder that these two concepts caused all kinds of contradictions.
We tend to take mathematics we use in physics lightly just as a language. This is a perfect example of the price we pay for our ignorance and arrogance. Mathematical results at the level of topology, etc., are obtained with utmost care and precision. So often, unless we pay due attention and effort to understand, we take the results wrongly and end up with this kind of devastating mistakes.
2.3 Relativistic Lorentz transformation
Without knowing of the falsity of TD and LC, Einstein showed that from TD and LC alone, without relating to electromagnetic field theory, we can obtain Lorentz transformation. From time dilation
and length contraction
Lorentz transformation is obtained as
The proof goes as follows: By applying the effect of length contraction on Galilean transformation we obtain Length contraction in the opposite direction is
Solving these two equations for , we have
A common argument for proving TD from LT
goes as follows: Set , then we have
A more careful logical analysis shows that what this really showed was that transformed time depends upon the location of the clock! It did not prove that LT implies TD. To the contrary, it refuted this claim. To be precise, it showed that when observed at , time dilates with the gamma factor. TD states that, observed from anywhere on the -axis, time dilates with the gamma factor. This is an interesting instance of the same formula meaning entirely different things depending upon the context it was obtained in. This is possible because there is more going on in physics that is visible on the surface of mathematical symbols.
This puts us in a delicate situation where we have to question the equivalence between Minkowski’s special theory of relativity, which does not use TD and LC, and Einstein’s special theory of relativity, which uses them. This further makes us wonder about the validity of the currently held belief that the general theory of relativity is a generalization of Einstein’s special theory of relativity. The general theory of relativity includes not Einstein’s special theory of relativity but Minkowski’s special theory (tangentially).
2.4 Lorentz transformation v.s. principle of relativity
The Lorentz transformation plays yet other questionable roles. We can shown that this transformation fails to respect Newton’s law of gravitation, Coulombs’ law, Newton’s second law and wave equations. For example, despite the claimed advantage of conserving wave equations, Lorentz transformation astoundingly fails to conserve the more fundamental second law and the law of gravitation. Considering the way Lorentz transformation was obtained, it is not surprising that these two major laws of mechanics are not Lorentz invariant. This means that Lorentz transformation is not a relativistic transformation as it violates the principle of relativity.
2.5 Is wave equation invariant under the Lorentz transformation?
We can further show that the claimed invariance of wave equations under Lorentz transformation is false. To make the argument more articulate, let us discuss the issue under a general setting.
Similarly
Similarly
This is valid only under the condition The second equality comes from the fact that is the wave speed. The first equation implies that the frame speed is which is not possible in the special theory of relativity. This means that Einstein’s claim that the electromagnetic wave equation is invariant under the Lorentz transformation is invalid. It is a well understood fact that there is no reference frame for light at the pain of contradiction. If then the gamma factor becomes undefined and there is no Lorentz transformation for such a frame.
All of this was well expected logically. Lorentz transformation is defined in terms of the constant , which is the speed of electromagnetic waves in vacuum. So, there is no convincing reason why this transformation will conserve wave equations, which are not electromagnetic wave equations of Maxwell.
2.6 Inconsistency of the special theory of relativity
2.6.1 The power pole - power line paradox
Assume a train runs and when the tip of the power pole of the train touches the power line at point A, spark occurs at this point. An observer in the train located straight down the tip of the power pole will observe that the light comes straight down from the tip of the power pole. However as the point A is also a stationary point of the power line, he will observe that the light comes diagonally down from the stationary point A. This is a contradiction.
This contradiction tells us that we cannot move one reference frame, which is a 3D space, inside the other. Aristotle knew this 3,000 years ago and said that a point on a line will not be a part of the line. Modern topologists will say that a point on a real line is accessible only through infinite limit process and so we have no finite access to any point on a real line. All of this means that we cannot move a point in a space. Then how is it possible to move an entire 3D space inside another. This paradox tells us that even the Galilean theory of relativity is inconsistent.
2.6.2 Deductive paradox
The general theory of relativity (GTR) deduces Einstein added the CSL axiom to GTR to form the special theory of relativity (STR) kinematics. The outcome of this is that the STR kinematics proves both CSL and its negation. This is a deductive inconsistency. The problem here is that by adding a new axiom to an old theory, one cannot block any theorem deducible from the old theory. It is called the monotonicity of deduction and is a most basic law of formal reasoning.
2.6.3 Speed paradox
Assume A observes that B is moving with constant speed relative to A (and to each other), where and are length and time observed classically by A. Then B will observe that A is moving with speed where
Then we have The problem here is that [speed] is determined by the [length] and [time] as
So, [speed] cannot alter [length] and [time] as in length contraction and time dilation. This is to say that STR kinematics violates a most fundamental law of dimensional analysis.
This can be argued in a more ontological way as follows: Assume an object O in another frame moves inside our frame a distance in time . Let A and B be the positions of O at time and in out frame, respectively. According to the perspective of O, A and B are moving points. So, O will observe that the distance between A and B is less than . Also O will observe that the time interval , which took A to be in front of it and B to be in front of it, is more than . So, O will observe that the speed of our frame is , which is not . This failure means that according to the relativity theory an observer observes the speed of a reference frame as and as such that
2.6.4 Dingle’s paradox
Herbert Dingle knew STR kinematics extremely well. He was one of the top researchers of STR before he became a top critic of this theory. He knew well that one cannot consider acceleration in this theory because of the principle of relativity. He thus considered two clocks that are already synchronized and moving towards each other with constant speed. He pointed out that due to the time dilation each clock will see the other moving slower.
Main stream relativists responded arguing that when one twin moves out and comes back, then it is this twin who went through time dilation and not the other twin. So, there is no paradox, according to this argument. However, we are discussing time dilation that is to occur in STR kinematics. So, the element of acceleration is out of the issue. It might be that STR dynamics may support this argument. But certainly such theory, if any, should bring back the same problem for the symmetric acceleration case. If both twins accelerate symmetrically and come back to see each other, we have the same problem. This means that the claimed generalization of STR kinematics to STR dynamics also has a serious inconsistency problem.
2.7 Michelson-Morley experiment revisited I
There are two criticisms of the way how this historic experiment was treated in theoretical physics. This experiment was interpreted under the assumption that light is an electromagnetic wave, in accordance with Hertz’s proposal. Even to this day though, we are not sure what light is. We were told to accept the view of Hertz without a substantial proof thereof.
Moreover, electromagnetic waves are not physical reality as the concept of electromagnetic field is not a physical reality. This concept is what logicians and philosophers call “modality”, “counter factual modality” to be precise. The spatial distribution of electromagnetic force per a unit charge is not reality. Such distribution should appear in reality only when we place unit charge everywhere in the space. But, if we place a unit charge at every point in the electromagnetic field, the source which created such a field will be affected and the electromagnetic field will not be maintained. Moreover, the placed unit charges will react with each other making it impossible to sustain such a configuration. Putting it more mathematically, there is not enough charges to fill all points in a space. Pure mathematics will put this as follows: There are uncountably many points in a geometric space and there are only countably many charges in the universe. This implies that the concept of electromagnetic field has nothing to do with reality. To be precise, the so-called electromagnetic wave is an “action at a distance transmission” of the change in electromagnetism at the source to a charge placed at a certain location in the space. There is no wave. This is precisely why without wave medium the so-called electromagnetic waves “travel” with speed . So, there is no need for the “aether”. There is no physical realism that supports the counter-factual modality. All of this calls to question the treatment of light as an electromagnetic wave by the Michelson-Morley experiment.
3 Special theory of relativity: dynamics
3.1 Einstein’s ambition and its fallout
Galilean theory of relativity did not consider reference frames that are under acceleration relative to each other. This was because acceleration, through the second law, violates the principle of relativity. This only restriction imposed by kinematics on relativity theory was too limiting for Einstein. Considering that way before this setback, already at the most basic level of Galilean theory of relativity the concept of relativity is insurrectionist, Einstein should have abandoned the idea of relativity. It is unfortunately not what happened.
3.1.1 Relativistic collision, relativistic mass, relativistic momentum and relativistic energy
Einstein’s first motive towards STR dynamics was to consider the relativistic collision problem. To make sure that the conservation of momentum holds for relativistic collision, Einstein defined relativistic mass as follows:
where is the rest mass and is the speed of the mass in relation to the observer. From this he obtained the famous relativistic energy formula as follows: The relativistic second law is
where is the relativistic momentum. Then
From this he calculated that
The mistake made here is that Einstein forgot that up to here is constant. For mathematical sanity, in collision problems, we do not consider accelerated bodies. The moment of impact is excluded from consideration. So, what we should have here is
rather. This mistake impacted heavily the relativistic energy-momentum relation
However, from the point of view of dimensional analysis, this is not surprising at all. There is no reason to think that the dimension of energy and that of momentum are related. Indeed, energy is not even a physical dimension. It is a modality rather as it is the “potential” to do [work]. So, [work] is a physical dimension but energy is not. Therefore the energy-momentum relation of Einstein is false conceptually as well.
Remark 3
Indeed, there is a complaint from the discipline of wave mechanics regarding Einstein’s energy-momentum relation. In wave mechanics of continuum medium, there is nothing moving in the direction of the motion of the wave. The only thing that is moving in this direction is the local vibration of the medium. This means that there is no momentum in waves.
3.1.2 Impact on quantum field theory
All of this implies the end of the entire 20th century theoretical physics. Einstein correctly said that when his relativistic energy equation fails, the entire 20th century theoretical physics fails.
Indeed, upon this energy equation are based both the duality of the photon and the electromagnetic wave
as well as the de Broglie relation, paving way to what is called quantum mechanics. Also, as we will discuss later, Gordon-Klein’s theory of relativising quantum mechanics by replacing and with quantum operators E and p in the energy-momentum relation is invalid. The entire quantum field theory also collapses. The same convention used by Dirac in his quantum electrodynamics also is invalid for the same reason.
3.1.3 More contradictions coming from
The quantum mechanics, which was built upon the special theory of relativity, quantized light as electromagnetic wave and presented what we now call “photon” as the particle dual of light wave. To avoid the famous relativistic formula
diverging for the photon with , Einstein assumed that for the photon the rest mass This lead to which Einstein thought can be any number as the linear equation has any number as its solution. This is wrong because does not involve the division by while involves division by , which is an impossible operation. This rather expectedly leads to the following contradiction:
We can derive yet another contradiction:
Without knowing this problem, photons are now introduced as a legitimate particle dual to light wave with rest mass and speed . What is truly paradoxical is that a particle that never rests now has a rest mass . This is what philosophers and logicians call a category error.
3.2 Michelson-Morley experiment revisited II
3.2.1 Light-as-photon interpretation of Michelson-Morley experiment
With the photon becoming a particle dual to the light wave, we have yet another interpretation of Michelson-Morley experiment. “Assume photons are particles.” Then it must be the case that when we emit a photon to the vacuum from an emitter moving with speed , the speed of the photon must be in the vacuum. So, the emitted photon moves towards the reflecting mirror with speed . But as the mirror itself moves with the speed in the same direction, the effect of cancels. When the photon is reflected at the mirror, it comes out with speed . But as the receiver of this photon is moving towards the photon with speed , this cancels again. This means that this experiment will not detect the . In conclusion, but the experiment set as it is cannot detect this .
3.2.2 Quantum mechanical interpretation of Michelson-Morley experiment
Experimental physics sometimes asserts that in order to understand the Michelson-Morley experiment, one must consider the quantum mechanical process of light reflecting at the mirror surface. If reflection of light at the surface of a mirror is the consequence of energized (by the incident light) electrons inside the mirror surface recoiling, then it should take some time for the reflected light to come out of the surface of the mirror. Considering the Compton effect, it may not be the case that the reflected light is not of the same frequency as the incident light. It is not clear how seriously these questions were taken in theoretical physics.
Recently, Wheeler carried out an experiment using an apparatus very similar to the Michelson-Morley apparatus which however used a half-silvered mirror instead. The experiment showed an unexpected behaviour of this apparatus which current quantum mechanics cannot explain. The problem with the so-called “splitter” (half-silvered mirror) is that it had an explanation only for a pure wave theory of light, but it has no explanation using the light quanta. Better said: if photons are deviated with probability 50 %, there is no interference. But on the other side, if they are really split in two directions, this contradicts the Planck-Einstein hypothesis, as far as the two pieces of a photon are entangled and are evidently waiting for the two halves to build a photon together. So in a certain way, the interference does not indicate anymore some delay of a half-ray relatively to the other, as planned by Michelson-Morley. This makes us wonder if Michelson-Morley’s interpretation was correct.
According to the model used by Michelson-Morley, in the second splitter (or by twice passing the same splitter) one should have had again a 50 - 50 distribution, and not a 100 - 0 distribution, as observed by Wheeler. Without intending it, Wheeler shows with his experiment that the Michelson-Morley apparatus contains aspects that nobody has thought about. So one cannot claim to have experimental proof of the constancy of the speed of light using something that nobody understands.
This problem exhibits exactly the same pattern as the Michelson-Morley experiment, which was conducted under the assumption that light was a wave. The irony is that, using Michelson-Morley experiment, through the special theory of relativity the “wave-particle duality” was introduced first and then the “particle theory of light” offered entirely different picture. This way, in the end, the empiricism proved that the wave-particle duality hypothesis is invalid at the pain of contradiction.
3.3 From Einstein, through Dirac to material science: the particle-wave duality in full swing
The ultimate product of this highly questionable wave-particle duality manifested itself most dramatically in the quantum electrodynamics (QED) of Dirac. Quantum electrodynamics seems to be the ultimate end-product of Einstein’s special theory of relativity, which is inconsistent. Here is a summary of the complications we have regarding this issue.
-
1.
The reflection of light on the mirror is a complex problem of statistical particle physics and only material science can bring us closer to the truth. The problem we have here is that we have not such material science. Also the material science which digs into this kind of problems must come from a satisfactory quantum mechanics, which we have not, as our quantum mechanics is based upon the special theory of relativity, which came from the Michelson-Morley experiment. To make the matter even worse, now Wheeler’s result seems to support the concern that Michelson-Morley’s experiment could have been interpreted wrongly.
-
2.
Even if the Michelson-Morley experiment is limited to electromagnetic waves only, these waves are not physical reality. They are counter-factual modality. Moreover, when we operate upon the assumption of wave-particle duality, the uncertainty principle creeps in and this makes the constancy of the speed of light claim “statistical”. When a most fundamental assumption of our theory is of statistical nature, we do have some serious concern. True, the original CSL argument is not statistical. It was based upon abstract (not physical) wave theory of counter-factual modal waves. But the recent argument by Wheeler again is statistical.
Early quantum mechanics in principle avoided getting into this kind of problems when the problem of particles enclosed by walls etc. was considered. Walls are represented not as a complex material, but as potential barriers, which is nothing but a mathematical entity. Here, one is trying to study the reflection of light at the mirror. Quantum mechanics cannot really handle the reflection of light on a mirror as we do not understand what mirrors are sufficiently enough to discuss these issues. To understand it requires perfect quantum mechanics, which we have not.
We use macro materials, which are microscopically incredibly complex, to do our experiments. It is not a problem when we do macro-level physics. But when we deal with micro-level physics, we have no solution. Our experimental instruments belong to the macro-level physics. The cosmology shares the same problem. We can never conduct experiment or measurement at this incredibly large scale level. It is not promising to do physics of the cosmos through looking at billions of stars light years away from us. The only tool we have available here is the relativistic Doppler effect and we do not even know what light is.
What is striking is that regardless of the status of quantum mechanics, Wheeler’s experiment shows that while passing the second splitter, the light “knows” which part it came out from the first splitter. In the second splitter we get the Hadamard-Walsh gate, which is an “operator” in quantum computing. This is sufficient for engineering. But it is unfortunate that our theory will not make us understand all of this.
Philosophically, what we are facing is a crisis where the most basic laws of physics are no longer macroscopic laws. To make it macroscopic we went through a statistical argument, which makes us wonder what laws of physics are.
Moreover, all of these problems by which we become overwhelmed make us wonder what do we really mean by experimental observation, which is the essence of empiricism. To make experiments at the micro-level, we need a functional theory of the micro-level physics. But such a theory must come from an acceptable micro-level experiment. We are going around a big circle. As we said above, cosmology is facing the same difficulty at the other end of the spectrum. In the case of micro-level physics, we have a distinguished difficulty of uncertainty issue which makes the theory probabilistic. All of these issues have to be dealt with even after we manage to free quantum physics from the inconsistency of relativity theory. A long way to go lies ahead of us.
So, it is no longer just an isolated problem of theoretical physics. The dynamic linkage between theory and empiricism has to be re-examined and new working link must be established.
4 Minkowski’s relativity theory
It appears to be the case that Minkowski’s 4D spacetime relativity theory was a serious effort to make the inconsistency problems in Einstein’s special theory of relativity disappear mathematically.
For Einstein, the Lorentz transformations are transformations from one inertial 3D frame that is moving inside another 3D frame with relative speed and the associated transformation of time. This immediately lead to the flooding of contradictions, which we discussed in the foregoing. Most of such paradoxes originate from the “power line-power pole paradox” which is deeply embedded in the theory of Galilean inertial reference frames upon which Einstein’s STR was built. As a logical triviality, inconsistency problems will not disappear by adding one extra axiom of CSL.
The reason behind Minkowski’s apparent success is that his theory appeared to have little to do with the troubled part of Einstein’s STR, which is based upon mutually moving 3D reference frames. From this troubled assumption Einstein proved TD and LC, which naturally lead to a mountain of paradoxes. Lorentz and Einstein in their own setting deduced LT from TD and LC. Unfortunately, motion takes place inside a geometric space and so we cannot move reference frames, which are essential for defining such motion. This issue was already philosophically addressed by Aristotle. He pointed out that a point in a geometric space is not a part of the space. Modern topology explicated this warning of Aristotle by proclaiming that there is no point in a geometric space. it said rightly that a point in a geometric space can be “accessed” only through limit. If we cannot reach it by finite means, how can we “move” it? This kind of conceptual issues are quite well attended to in pure mathematics as mathematics has experienced the horror of contradictions at deep levels. Also, the lack of empiricism made mathematicians focus on these conceptual problems.
Here is a possible interpretation of Minkowski’s work as a mathematical physicist. He used only one 4D spacetime as a reference frame (plus time) and from his single reference frame, he “not formally but conceptually” derived two reference frames, say F1 and F2. First, he placed F1 as the “mother frame” and defined a Lorentz transformation from it to itself where in the gamma factor is the mutual speed between F1 and F2. In this way he thought he “simulated” F1 and F2 with just F and the Lorentz transformation from F to itself. Unfortunately, his formalism by itself did not explicitly support this interpretation. This is a possible but rather obscure interpretation of his formalism.
Minkowskian relativity theory with Minkowski distance dominated the entire theoretical physics for nearly a century as the deepest theoretical foundation of physics that apparently evaded the contradiction associated with Einstein’s special theory of relativity. When under the help from Hilbert, Einstein accepted Minkowskian spacetime as a local tangential spacetime at each location in the Riemannian spacetime theory of the general theory of relativity, the “consistency” of STR and GTR was “established” and relativity theory became the ultimate truth in theoretical physics.
What is interesting here however is that this Minkowskian 4D spacetime approach can be adopted to formulate the issue of Fitzgerald contraction (LC) by considering the unique 4D spacetime as the universe and the Lorentz transformation as a representation of a specific observer frame and representing the speed of the observer frame inside the universal frame. So, Minkowski’s theory integrates the issue of relativity in the setting of electromagnetic field theory. However, all we could do for this new formulation of Einsteinian STR was to hope that the equivalence of Lorentz transformation and (TD,LC) will hold. It did not happen, as we have shown in the foregoing.
After all, all of this is a pointless discussion as (TD, LC) pair deduce “physical paradoxes”. Deducing (TD, LC) from Lorentz transformation simply removes the apparent capacity of Minkowski’s theory to be a consistent alternative to Einstein’s relativity theory. Moreover, even if Lorentz transformation did not deduce (TD, LC) and saved itself from inconsistency, we would have ended up with the question of the relevance of such a theory in theoretical physics. Under the standard interpretation of inertial reference frames, as we have discussed, LC implies TD.
As Einstein’s original SRT is plagued by the inconsistency, the uncertainty of the status of Lorentz transformation in Minkowski’s theory seems to be the only hope left. The apparent discrepancy between Lorentz transformation and (TD, LC) is still giving us some hope.
The problem here is that we do not know what Lorentz transformation means physically if is not the relative speed of two reference frames and Minkowski did not define Lorentz transformation using two reference frames. Nevertheless, there is an understandable reason why he did not use two 4D spacetime frames. If we use two then there is not much point in using 4D spacetime. Einstein’s theory is easier to handle. In Einstein’s theory, 3D space and time are independent and separate. So, technically it is easy to consider a 3D space move inside another space and vice versa. The only problem with this is that this leads to the geometric paradox which killed Einstein’s STR. But there is yet another question here. It is mathematically impossible to discuss the motion of 3D space inside the 4D spacetime. All we can do is to express motions in the 3D space as geodesics inside the 4D spacetime. But is this not all we need?
We have a mountain of nontechnical, extremely challenging and deep problems on the border of physics, mathematics and philosophy. And literally, nothing has been done.
One of the most important contributions of Minkowski was the metric on his 4D spacetime. This came from the mathematical argument that his metric such that
is invariant under the Lorentz transformation. It was understandable that Minkowski had to look for such a metric as Lorentz transformation changes the metric on [time] and that on [length] relative to the [speed] . Luckily he found one. It is neither a space metric nor a time metric as Lorentz transformation operates upon 4D spacetime. Hence, there are some issues:
-
1.
This metric does not form a topological metric space over the 4D spacetime and this is totally expected as Minkowski adopted the irregularity inherent in relativity theory that [speed] = [length]/[time] redefines [time] and [length], which leads to contradiction. That Lorentz transformation conserves this metric is yet another indication of the highly questionable status of this transformation.
-
2.
This metric could be negative, which makes no sense at all. There is no such thing as a distance that is negative. Regardless of the direction of an arrow, the length of the arrow is always positive. However, it may be due to the fact that an inconsistent theory can produce any result. This is why such a theory is useless.
-
3.
Minkowski’s metric is appreciated as it defined light cone interpretation. Light cone is formed inside absolute space time. After the introduction of the light cone, thus, there was a tendency to stop using relativity theory and just stick to the absolute frame, a very distorted absolute frame.
It is an open question what this metric means mathematically and philosophically. It means that maybe Minkowski relativity theory is consistent but with the cost that it has no relevance to anything including physics at all. After all, Lorentz transformation came from TD + LC, which is inconsistent. There are more questions than answers.
Given that the Minkowski equation
is invariant under the Lorentz transformation, is it so also under the TD and LC? The answer is a “no”. A proof goes as follows:
Therefore
This reconfirms that Einstein’s STR and Minkowski’s STR are two different theories. There is no such thing as Minkowski distance in Einstein’s STR. There is no light cone either. This is a good news in a sense as the inconsistency of Einstein’s STR will not be deleterious to Minkowski’d STR. However, as we have stressed many times, nobody knows what Minkowski’s STR is and what it is for. There is no ontology associated with it. Furthermore we now have to cleanly detach Minkowski’s STR from Einstein’s STR. It is a lot of work, especially because most of popular results in STR came from Einstein’s version. This is however expected, because it is not clear what Minkowski was talking about.
5 General theory of relativity
Einstein resolved the problem of the limitation of STR kinematics by violating the principle of relativity, as in the development of the STR dynamics leading the entire theoretical physics to the fallacy of Next, he ventured into a new theory in which accelerating frames can be treated as inertial frames with gravitational field induced by acceleration.
5.1 Principle of equivalence
Einstein assumed that if an accelerating reference frame can be reduced to an inertial frame in which acceleration induces “gravitational field”, then it is possible to treat accelerating frames as inertial frames within the theory of relativity, which rejects reference frames under acceleration for a legitimate reason. He called this the principle of equivalence. To that end he proceed as follows:
Assume a spaceship is in inertial motion in our reference frame. Moreover, a force accelerates this spaceship with a rate A body in the spaceship experiences a force , which is due to the acceleration of the spaceship that makes the body move with an acceleration of rate in the frame of the spaceship. Putting aside what the force is, this means Then from our perspective, in the spaceship experiences the acceleration with rate So, will experience Therefore,
This means that, from our perspective, the acceleration on the spaceship induces an “additional” force on which Einstein called “inertial force” upon the mass and the equation (IF) yields the force experiences in the accelerating spaceship. This Einstein called the second law in the accelerating frame of the spaceship. According to him, upon the modification of to , the second law is conserved under the choice of accelerating reference frames.
There are several issues to be considered with respect to that.
-
1.
Putting aside the invalidity of the special theory of relativity (as we discussed in the foregoing), some issues have been overlooked here. Namely, according to the special theory of relativity, even addition of speeds is not classical addition. One has to use the so-called relativistic addition of speeds So, how can the addition of accelerations be the same as classical addition, hoping that in the words of Einstein, acceleration is still the time derivative of speed. This confusion is closely related to the issue of the disjointedness between the acceleration and relativistic reference frames. For that reason the special theory of relativity does not consider acceleration, as we have been told.
-
2.
As an important example, this inertial force is also closely related to the issue of “fictitious force” on a mass inside an orbiting object. Fictitious force is a “force in fiction”, not reality. The reason why we have a problem with the fictitious force for an orbiting spaceship is because orbiting spaceships are under centripetal acceleration. Therefore, it is not an inertial frame. It is wrong to claim that just because inside the orbiting spaceship a fictitious force called centrifugal force is “created?”, the orbiting spaceship becomes an inertial reference frame.
-
3.
This fictitious force is the creation of the relativistic interpretation of the second law of Newton. This law can be interpreted in two ways. First, when force is applied to a mass , it accelerates the mass with the rate Second, when is accelerating with a rate , a “fictitious force” appears. Ontologically the second interpretation is invalid. It is always the case that a force applied to a mass causes an acceleration of the mass. It becomes clear when we consider the case of an accelerating train. Assume a stationary train accelerates. Then, a passenger in the train will feel that he/she is pushed back (against the direction of the train’s acceleration). This is simply because the observer tries to stay where he/she is in the train due to the first law of Newton. If the observer can see the outside, which is not moving, he/she will see that it is not him/her but the train that is moving under the force.
-
4.
Now it is clear that the problem of inertial force (fictitious force) is caused by the faulty relativistic interpretation of the second law of Newton. This is to say that the second law is not “relativistic”, further confirming that the relativism as per Galileo and Einstein is untenable. With this, we have that the relativism violates not only the third law of Newton but also the second law.
-
5.
It also is important to note that the fictitious force violates the third law of Newton.
5.2 Violating the point mass assumption
An even more fundamental issue here is considering the spaceship (or train). In the theory of dynamics, as Newton made it clear, theoretically there is no such thing as a spaceship. All physical bodies must be point masses, and rightly so. For this reason, there is no such thing as a mass inside a spaceship. In dynamics, there is no such thing as a spaceship to begin with, for very good mathematical reasons, as incisively explained by Newton.
Remark 4
Here it is important to notice that there are two kinds of the violation of point mass assumption in post-Newtonian physics. First, mass taken as a solid with volume. This situation can be dealt with ease by reducing the mass to a point mass, as we are used to. Second, a mass with an inside space such as a spaceship or a train. This case is a lot more complicated as it may allow another mass in the inside space. When we collapse the outer mass, what happens to the inside mass?
Moreover, a body attached firmly to the wall of a spaceship will not experience any special force. This is because when we consider the dynamics of the spaceship it is just a point mass and there is no “inside” of it to which this extra mass is to be attached. Even if we reluctantly allow spaceships, according to the law of inertia without force exerted, a mass will continue constant speed motion in a frame. So, what force is supposed to be exerted upon this body “inside” the spaceship”? Does this firmly attached mass move inside the spaceship?
The usual response is that we experience such force even if we are firmly attached to the inside wall.
However, our body is not just a solid. Our body is beyond the category of physical objects. Our body has incredibly complex internal system for perception. This is why we feel such a pressure.
The most fundamental reason why Newton correctly reduced all moving masses to point masses is simple. It is purely mathematical and conceptual. Newton correctly observed that the best we can do is to consider a physical body as a point object with size of a geometric point. Without this assumption, how can one define motion mathematically? With this assumption Newton found a solid mathematical representation of motion in a space as a function from time to space. With this he obtained the legitimate concept of speed as the first order derivative of the motion function and the legitimate concept of acceleration as the first order derivative of the speed function. Without all of this basics, we have no theory of motion upon which to build dynamics. Mathematics is an essential part of physics and not just a language for physics.
Moreover, for dynamics, we have yet another important reason to reduce a mass to a point mass. It is because force is a vector, a pointed entity. So, the only entity to which we can exert a force is a point object (mass).
5.3 Acceleration-induced gravitational field
There are some more issues to be discussed regarding the “gravitational field” that Einstein introduced to a space under acceleration. As discussed in the foregoing, the concept of any force field, in general, violates the action-reaction law, which in turn violates the principle of relativity. Moreover, the gravitational field that Einstein introduced to an accelerating space is a force field which has no source for the gravitational forces spreading all over the space. This is yet another violation of the third law in a different sense. The “uniform gravitational field” near the surface of our planet is a gravitational field in “approximation”.
More importantly, the “force field”, whatever it may be, that Einstein introduced to frames under acceleration is not gravitational at all. Gravitational fields are to be the modal representation of the effect of gravitational force created by Newton’s law of gravity. So, it is not a uniform field. A possible argument to counter that would be that near the surface of the Earth the gravitational field is “almost” uniform. This is however not acceptable in precise science such as theoretical physics. Almost uniform is not uniform. The Universe is not approximate.
It appears that the idea of associating “acceleration” with “gravitational force” comes from the old concept of “aether” by Descartes. Descartes wrongly considered a spaceship that contains an object which is under acceleration and identified the fictitious (inertial) force with gravitational force. As the name “fictitious force” clearly indicates, such a force is just an imaginary force that in fact does not exist. It is not that the acceleration exerts such a force but as the object in the accelerating frame is not a part of the frame (spaceship) it appears that everything in the spaceship moves with acceleration relative to the object. Hence, it is not a real force. It is a fictitious force.
5.4 Red shift and energy issue
Einstein assumed a laboratory that is free falling under the gravitational force. Assume we emit a light beam upward from the floor to the ceiling. Due to the acceleration, by the time the light reaches the ceiling, the ceiling is moving faster than the source on the floor was when the light beam left it. In other words, the receiver at the ceiling is approaching the source (where it was when the light left). Therefore the observer in the lab will notice the blue shift due to the Doppler effect. This will make this observer notice the downward acceleration. This contradicts the equivalence principle which states that a free falling body will not notice its free falling. So, Einstein postulated that there must be a red shift due to the light moving upwards against the gravitational force to offset this blue shift. Unfortunately, it is not the observer in the lab who sees that the ceiling is moving towards the floor. It is an observer outside of the falling lab who will see that the ceiling is falling towards where the floor used to be. So, the observer inside the lab will not observe the blue shift. This is how Einstein obtained the red shift effect.
The situation is rather complex and we have to consider many elements involved in this apparently simple thought experiment. This is an instance of the confusion coming from the ambiguity that a rest point in a frame F1 is also a moving point in a reference frame F2 that is moving relative to F1. The problem which haunted the special theory of relativity, which we presented as the “power pole-power line paradox” in the context of time dilation and length contraction, came back to haunt the general theory of relativity, in the context of accelerating frames this time. As inertial frames and accelerating frames are both moving frames, the same problem affects both of them. So the equivalence principle which is to reduce an accelerating frame to an “inertial frame” with induced gravitational field has no capability to avoid this fatal contradiction.
Moreover, the connection between relativistic dynamics and the general theory of relativity is not clear at all. Are they equivalent? Both of them are supposed to be the relativity theory of dynamics dealing with more than relativistic kinematics, which is known as the special theory of relativity. We know the former is inconsistent as it violates the limitation to non-accelerating frames, which is badly needed to avoid the contradiction against the third law of dynamics, an absolutely essential assumption for any dynamics.
Putting aside the problem associated with the inconsistency of the relativistic dynamics, there are some more lessons to be learned from using inconsistent theories such as the special theory of relativity, relativistic dynamics and the general theory of relativity. Neither the special theory of relativity nor relativistic dynamics can handle energy. What about the general theory of relativity, which is based upon the equivalence principle? Unfortunately the answer is negative as well. As we have discussed at the beginning of this section, the special theory of relativity claims that the addition of speeds should not be but This contradicts the second law of dynamics.
All of this clearly suggests that Newton’s dynamics is a theory of dynamics in the absolute frame only. Relativity is introduced not in the way Galileo and Einstein did in their relativity theory. Relative motions are defined as the difference of two absolute motions. All attempts to relativize Newton’s dynamics thus far have failed rather expectedly.
5.5 Centre of masses in general relativity theory
As discussed above, when we represent a constant speed motion in the 3D Euclidean space as its graph, it becomes a straight line in the 4D space-time. If the motion is an accelerating one, then the graph becomes a curved line in the 4D space-time. Einstein represented gravitational force field, which will cause accelerating motions, as the 4D space-time manifold so that all motions caused by the gravitational field will appear as straight lines (geodesics) in the manifold. Applying this idea to gravitational fields created by a system of masses, Einstein obtained the so-called gravitational field theory. In this theory the spatial distribution of masses determines the 4D space-time manifold representing all possible “motions”.
According to the classical dynamics, when we have a system of masses in a space, the mutual gravitational pull makes them converge to a single point called the centre of gravity. It is unclear how this process of convergence is dealt with in the gravitational field theory of Einstein. This question relates to the capacity of this theory to express dynamic processes.
5.6 Light bend
Einstein studied the rest mass photon under constant acceleration. He considered a photon moving with speed in the -direction while it is in a frame that is under acceleration in the -direction. So, we have
If is the angle made by a tangent of the light ray to the -axis, we have
and we can assume that is very small. So we have
But the GTR predicts otherwise, i.e.
Note that Eddington proved experimentally that the GTR’s prediction is correct.
It is clear that all of this uses nothing but the kinematic concept of acceleration and in kinematics there is no concept of mass. Putting aside the issue of inconsistency coming from the assumption of the mass point mass as discussed in section 3.1.3, the concept of photon belongs to dynamics. The photon is a point mass of mass . Having no mass and having mass are entirely different categories. The problem with considering a point object whose mass is is that the second law fails for the mass point object. So, it makes no sense to say that the light (trajectory of photon) bends due to the gravitational force of the Sun. Thus, Einstein’s argument here diverted this difficulty by replacing the “gravitational force upon mass photon” with the “reference frame of photon accelerated by the Sun’s gravitation”. It is truly astounding that this even worse confusion has never been detected till now. The reference frame of this photon cannot be accelerated unless there is some mass stationary in it. The second law was never meant to be applied to mass zero objects.
So, the only apparently appropriate thing to say here is that the claim that light bends due to the acceleration of the reference frame caused by the gravitation force is also false. In the end, we do not know what is really happening here. If the curved 4D spacetime GTR predicts the equation (3), then clearly something that went wrong in the development of 4D spacetime GTR. Unfortunately, Einstein’s rest mass particle that moves with speed was brought into physics with serious consequences.
5.7 “Induced gravitational field” revisited
As discussed in the foregoing, the concept of any force field in general violates the action-reaction law, and in turn violates the principle of relativity. Moreover, the gravitational field that Einstein introduced to an accelerating space is a force field that has no “external source” creating the “gravitational forces per unit mass” spreading all over the space. This is yet another violation of the third law in a different sense. The “uniform gravitational field” near the surface of our planet is a gravitational field in “approximation”. It is “not” a gravitational field. So, it is wrong to call Einstein’s “induced” force field a gravitational force field.
To simplify this already confusing situation, let us put it this way. In classical post-Newtonian dynamics, a field of gravitational force applied to each location on a unit mass placed there was considered. This concept itself fundamentally violates the action-reaction law and so must be abandoned. The situation here with Einstein’s gravitational field created by the empty reference frame under acceleration makes things even more problematic. The former ignored the source mass that created the force field. Here such a source mass to be ignored does not exist at all.
We must stop identifying entirely different things in approximation as it was done in quantum field theory.
Moreover, the force field that Einstein introduced to the frame of the spaceship is not gravitational at all. Gravitational fields are to be the field representation of the effect of gravitational force created by Newton’s law of gravity. So, it is not a uniform field.
It was Minkowski’s 4D spacetime theory of relativity which taught Einstein that the motion line (geodesic) in the 4D spacetime bends in the presence of acceleration. Combining this with the second law of dynamics, which connects acceleration and force through mass, and the law of gravity, Einstein concluded that through gravitational force masses distributed in the 4D spacetime bend the 4D spacetime. Now the 4D space itself is curved and the motion line is a straight line (geodesic) in this curved 4D spacetime. So, there is no need for TD, LC and Lorentz transformation. But then what about Einstein’s claim that Minkowski spacetime is a local tangential space-time in the curved spacetime?
6 General theory of relativity (II)
6.1 General coordinate system
Judging from the argument to claim the equivalence principle, it appears that Einstein was considering only local situations, such as a spaceship, as an accelerating frame. In this local setting it appears possible to treat all accelerating frames as inertial frames. Without knowing that the equivalence principle is false, which we explain above, Einstein made a move to represent all accelerating reference frames as “local inertial frames” in which acceleration is replaced by the induced gravitational field. This ill-fated idea lead Einstein to consider the general coordinate system upon which all accelerating frames are treated as local inertial frames with induced gravitational field. Hence, Einstein moved on to develop the concept of general absolute reference frames to which we will turn in what follows.
Einstein assumed that the whole cosmos is occupied by a fluid whose molecules are “clocks” of any variety. This fluid can flow in any manner except that it will be assumed that there is no turbulence, so that neighbouring molecules always have almost equal “speed” and the velocity of the flow is a continuous function.
Remark 5
This means that Einstein assumes a universal time and a universal space upon which clocks move.
Each clock is allocated three coordinates in such a manner that:
-
1.
No two clocks will have the same coordinates, and
-
2.
Neighbouring clocks have neighbouring coordinates. Therefore, coordinates are also continuous with respect to spatial displacement.
-
3.
It is understood that the coordinate of each clock remains the same through time. As time elapses at each clock, its readings are assumed to increase but the rate of increase is not necessarily uniform as compared with a local standard clock. No attempt is made to synchronize distant clocks. Neighbouring clocks are assumed to be “sufficiently synchronized” so that the clock readings are continuous with respect to spatial displacement.
-
4.
The reading of a clock will be denoted by
It is unfortunate that this paradigm is not possible for the following reasons:
-
a)
No clock has any specific coordinate as it is not a point object.
-
b)
In the continuum, there is no such thing as a point next to another point. So, the concept of a “neighbouring point” to a point is invalid. There is no such thing as a rational number next to a given rational number. This is because in between any two rational numbers, we can always find a rational number. This property is called the density of the set of rational numbers.
-
c)
As pointed out in b), there is no such thing as the coordinate of a clock in this setting. Clocks are made by continuumly many points. They are by themselves very complex physical structures. In a) Einstein assumes the fluid of clocks and yet in c) he says that the coordinate of each clock remains the same.
More generally, the following further questions remain to be answered.
-
(1)
Upon what time and space the mechanics of such molecule clocks is defined? Each clock is a physical system and so it is operating in a spacetime that is not the same as the spacetime defined by the clock. This is to say that the spacetime does not define the inside dynamics of the clock at . Moreover, where is the clock which governs the spacetime in which this clock operates? According to the general theory of relativity, the time of this spacetime and that of the spacetime in which this clock operates are not the same and how much they are synchronized depends upon the location of the clock that defines the spacetime that defines the clock. This problem is related to a more general problem associated with the instrumentalist view of time as clocks. This view falls into the following vicious circle: The clock, which is supposed to define time, must operate as a dynamical system upon some time and space. Then how this time and space are supposed to be defined?
-
(2)
It is a common understanding among researchers in “dynamical system theory” that time has a special status and is different from all other coordinates of the system. This is in agreement with the idea of Newton in his classical dynamics. Newton said that time, unlike other coordinates, has a natural flow that “moves” forward only. This makes it impossible to consider time as reading of clocks. Time is an entity that transcends empiricism and operationalism.
Once we violate the most fundamental assumption on time, anything can happen and relativity apparently made it happen.
-
(3)
Clocks are physical entities. There are at most countably many clocks in this universe. No mater how closely we put clocks together, we cannot form a continuum of clocks. No matter how one puts countably infinite particles together, one will not create a mathematical continuum. This is mathematically the same problem as the problem of photons, which are supposed to exist for each frequency: as the frequency has a continuous spectrum, there must exist uncountably infinite particles called photons. Countably infinite points will never form real continuum. We need continuumly many points to form mathematical continuum.
-
(4)
What does it mean to be sufficiently synchronized? The concept of synchronization presupposes external absolute time which contradicts the concept of relativism. Here, we have to check time of each clock at precisely the same moment in absolute time.
6.2 Minkowskian local frame
Suppose that at a point P in a “gravitational field”, which is sea of infinitely many clocks, a freely falling non-rotational (relative to distant stars) local inertial frame is “constructed”. We further assume that the axioms of the special theory of relativity are valid within this frame as it is supposed to be an inertial reference frame. So, we can set up a Cartesian coordinate system at this point P. Furthermore, we can distribute clocks over the frame, all of them synchronized to the clock at .
As we assumed that the universe is a sea of clocks that are not overall synchronized, this implies that such a coordinate system is not universal. It is a local coordinate system around .
Using this frame and clocks, events that occur in the vicinity of P over a suitably restricted time period, can be allocated space-time coordinates .
It is not quite clear why the time period must be restricted.
Now suppose that in this local inertial frame a pair of neighboring events have space-time coordinates and Then, if such that
is Lorentz invariant, then it also is called the Minkowski distance. This serves as the correct metric on the 4D Minkowskian spacetime.
Remark 6
As we will discuss later, Lorentz transformation is irrelevant to theoretical physics as the claim by Lorentz that this transformation maps wave equations to wave equations is false and so Einstein’s claim that all equational axioms of Maxwell are Lorentz invariant is false too. So, Minkowski distance also is irrelevant to physics. Mathematical relevance of such transformation is highly questionable either.
There are some mathematical problems regarding this metric on the “local” 4D spacetime. (1): It is not a topological metric that is used in topology. This is to say that Minkowski 4D space time is not a metric space. (2): The Minkowski distance between two events that happen at the same time is zero regardless of the 3D geometric distance between these two events. (3): Here, Einstein is assuming that in this “freely falling” local inertial frame, in which a gravitational field is induced by the equivalence principle, all clocks are synchronized. The local inertial frame must be accompanied by a gravitational field. So, all of these clocks are under gravitational acceleration. How is it possible then that all of these clocks are synchronized? Einstein also claims that all clocks under acceleration slow down. Do they slow down uniformly? As the acceleration is inertial “locally”, and time dilation is relative to the inertial speed, this slowdown is not uniform at all.
After all, as we have shown in the foregoing, the Minkowski distance has no relevance to theoretical physics. It is mathematically irrelevant too as it is not a topological metric. This clearly shows where relativity theory should be placed in science. It is neither physics nor mathematics. It appears that it belongs to its own category.
The local inertial frame is suitable only for the description of very limited situations. For a larger scale (temporal, as well as spatial) issues, it is necessary to use one of the general reference frames. If are space-time coordinates relative to such a general frame, transformations of the form must exist relating to [the local inertial frame] such that
Then, if are subjected to increments , the corresponding increments in will be given by
etc. and substitution in equation of proper time interval
will result in an expression that is quadratic in the increments , i.e. whose terms will either involve squares of the or the product of two different . Thus
where the coefficients will be the functions of .
Now, a continuum in which the interval between neighbouring points is given by a quadratic form like is called a “Riemannian space” and the quadratic form like is called its metric. Thus, the space-time continuum is a four-dimensional Riemannian space whose interval is everywhere identified with the proper time interval between neighbouring events in a local inertial frame.
Here are some issues to be discussed:
-
1.
What is important for physics is not that we use 4D spacetime manifold of Riemann. What has been questioned here is the relevance of such a mathematical structure to physics. This structure is obtained by substitution
etc. in the equation of proper time interval
As we have shown, this whole mathematical argument makes little physical sense. A most serious flaw in all of this is that the theory of general relativity was obtained from the special theory of relativity which is both mathematically and ontologically inconsistent. So, the general theory is false too. As discussed above, the special theory of relativity yields the relativistic addition of speed which contradicts the addition of acceleration of a mass which is governed by the second law of Newton. The equivalence principle, which is the most fundamental assumption of the general theory of relativity, is based upon the second law of dynamics. Einstein explains the curved space in the general theory of relativity using a rotating disc; the radius of the disk does not contract as the motion of the disk is not along this direction. It comes under the influence of the length contraction around the perimeter of the disk as the motion is in the direction of the tangential speed of the point on the perimeter of the disk. There are two errors in this argument. Firstly, the tangential speed of a circular motion is not inertial, it is under acceleration and so, the length contraction should not apply. Secondly, length contraction is false.
-
2.
More fundamentally, Einstein was clearly not aware of the difference between a countably infinite and a continuum. Cantor’s diagonal argument clearly shows that there are more points in the geometric continuum than the discrete collection of points. The Lebesgue integral of the Weierstrass function over shows that the geometric continuum has unimaginably more points than the “space” of countably many points has. For example, on the real number line almost all points are irrational numbers. So, one cannot cover the entire global space with clocks as there are only finitely many clocks. This makes the most fundamental assumptions of Einstein’s general theory of relativity untenable. There is no such thing as the “global spacetime” prescribed by Einstein. define neither differentiation nor integration.
-
3.
Also, Einstein’s description of the clocks used to define the global spacetime is off. To begin with, it must be required that the neighbouring clocks are of infinitesimal distance and the time difference between each pair of neighbouring clocks must be infinitesimally small. Otherwise we cannot use calculus to calculate on such a structure. Physically, it is impossible to make enough clocks to do this and place them in the way expected, as we stated above. As an infinitesimal means a number that comes in between and any positive number, this method is ontologically untenable. Clearly Einstein was unaware of what infinitesimals were as this concept was articulated only later in 1960’s by Abraham Robinson. Even in pure mathematics, the work of Robinson is understood only by a small number of mathematical logicians. The general theory of relativity was developed before the development of Robinson’s infinitesimal calculus and so it is understandable that the Hilbert school of mathematics and physics did not have the concept of infinitesimals. By the time Robinson’s work came out, the separation between pure mathematics and theoretical physics became material and communication between these two communities became almost non-existent.
-
4.
In short, contrary to what Einstein proposed, the universe cannot be a sea of clocks.
In addition to this topological problem the general theory of relativity suffers, there is an even more fundamental issue of logical deficiency in the idea of the general reference frame which is the sea of clocks. Clocks are physical entities and it requires physics to make them. One cannot use clocks to define clocks at the pain of vicious circle. So, there is no such thing as metaphysical clocks though time is certainly a metaphysical entity, as Newton thought. It was relativity theory, the special and the general, which tried to use empirical clocks that lead the world of physics to the current confusion about time.
Logically speaking, modern physics started with the wrong idea of what is time. Contrary to the special theory of relativity, time cannot be defined in terms of speed as speed is defined in terms of time. And as we have discussed here, the universe is not a sea of clocks contrary to the general theory of relativity. From the combination of these wrong assumptions, it is expected that we ended up with questioning what time is.
Our understanding of time as in relativity theory is completely wrong.
We have shown that the general theory of relativity came from the special theory of relativity, which is false. Therefore, the general theory of relativity is also false. Any theory which contains an inconsistent theory is inconsistent.
6.3 Geodesics
When we express a linear function of one variable on a 2D space, then the function’s graph becomes a straight line. The coefficient of the first order variable is the slope of the line. This idea was extensively exploited by train companies to visualize train operation on a 2D space where one coordinate is the time coordinate and the other coordinate is the location coordinate expressed at the distance from the origin station. It is called “operational diagram”, which pure mathematicians came to treat as a 4D spacetime. In the 4D space time all constant speed 3D motions should be just straight lines and the slope of the line is the constant speed 3D motion.
So, in 4D spacetime geometry of 3D motions, the “Euclidean geometric distance” between two points and in the 4D spacetime is:
The slope of the line segment is given as
In general theory of relativity, this changes: the distance, as par Minkowski, between and is
It can be shown that this distance is smaller than any other “Euclidean distance” along any curve connecting and in the 4D space. It goes as follows. Clearly,
But for any path between and ,
where is the Euclidean length of
From this, relativity theory concludes that the 4D spacetime with Minkowski metric is not a Euclidean space but a Riemannian space that is curved. There are some unclear issues to be addressed here.
-
1.
In Euclidean geometry, we define the distance between two points P and Q using the Pythagorean formula and we show that the length of any path connecting the two points P and Q is longer or equal to the distance between them. We have not seen how to define the length of a curved path between P and Q in Minkowski 4D spacetime.
-
2.
Putting this purely mathematical issue aside, the only reasoning for admitting , the Minkowski distance between and , is because this distance is invariant under Lorentz transformation. There are two questions to be answered here however. (1) Why Lorentz transformation is the issue in the general theory of relativity? This transformation belongs to the special theory of relativity. (2) This transformation is said to be essential for the special theory of relativity as it is said to preserve all wave equations and axioms of Maxwell’s electromagnetic field theory. (3) We have shown that this claim is false in our paper “Reference Frame Transformations and Quantization”.
Nonetheless ,Einstein continued to develop his theory as follows: Under the equivalence principle,
From this, Einstein concludes that the free fall in the gravitational field is a geodesics [in the 4D spacetime]. This is called the “geodesic principle”. Under this principle we obtain equations of motion for bodies falling freely in a gravitational field.
Using Riemannian geometry for the “general metric”
we can show the following “general equation of a geodesic”
For the metric
these equations reduce to
This is equivalent to
where are constants.
Remark 7
According to the general theory of geodesics, light coming from a distant star passing near our sun has a geodesic (4D) which bends near the Sun due to the gravity of the Sun. As it is a 4D bending, we cannot graphically express this bending. But when we omit the time bending, the light path bends in our 3D space. This is what we see in science museum exhibitions everywhere. Then we have a problem to think about. This 3D bending is a phenomenon that takes place in our 3D Euclidean space. This can be observed only from the outside of our 3D space. As we are inside the 3D space, in theory, we will be unable to observe this bending of light path. This was precisely what George Gamow warned us about. Gamow basically said that unless we are in the position of Newton out of the universe observing, we will not observe this bending. This valid question was never answered scientifically. The late Prof. Marmet presented a classical explanation of this observation using no bending space but bending light in unbent space interpretation. It was ignored. This means that we still do not know if space really bends as Einstein predicted due to the gravitation of Earth.
6.4 Einstein’s equation of gravitation
The discussion above shows that determines the motion (geodesic) in general relativity theory. Given the energy-momentum tensor which describes the distribution of mass, energy and momentum of the system, Einstein’s equations of gravitation yield corresponding enabling one to calculate the geodesics of the system. It was Schwarzschild who first obtained an exact solution of Einstein’s equations for a spherically symmetric field. He used the solutions to calculate the motion of a planet in the field of its sun.
Putting aside the problems of the general theory of relativity as discussed above, this result of Einstein and Schwarzschild poses some issues to consider. The question is what this momentum-energy tensor is about. There are several issues to be cleared.
-
1.
The momentum-energy relation is a problem. The former is a predicative concept but the latter, as the potential to do work, is a modal concept, and so, connecting them in the same category is not the right thing to do.
-
2.
Logically speaking waves in wave mechanics have no momentum. This is because momentum is the product of a mass and its speed. In wave mechanics, no mass moves in the direction of the wave. What is moving towards the direction of the wave is the local vibration of the medium. So, waves have no momentum. When it comes to energy, as the work needed to accelerate from to is not necessarily the concept of kinetic energy is false. The work needed for this acceleration depends upon how we accelerate from to
-
3.
So, the energy-momentum relation does not represent the state of a physical system properly. Then how can the energy-momentum tensor describe the physical system properly?
-
4.
Is the energy-momentum relation as energy-momentum tensor used here classical or relativistic? If it is relativistic, the entire argument by Einstein becomes viciously circular. If not, then how does it relate to the claim that the classical physics is invalid. This is a contradiction, is it not? Classically we have some tension between momentum and energy. Moreover, the relativistic energy-momentum relation is also false. It is because is false as we discussed earlier in this paper. This equation came from the false assumption that the in the gamma factor in is time dependent, which is not allowed in relativity theory. Considering that the concept of energy is not a physical reality but a modality and understanding that, as philosophy asserts, the modality and reality are of different category, it is astounding that the momentum-energy tensor plays the most fundamental role in general relativity theory. Mathematics is not just a language for physics. It is the only way to understand physical nature around us. It is the most articulate way of thinking correctly.
-
5.
What is the most fundamental issue here is that the practice of bootstrapping classical mechanics to relativistic mechanics is not a legitimate thing to do.
References
References
- [1] F. Bacon. Novum Organum. 1620.
- [2] J. Bennett. Locke, Berkeley, Hume: Central Themes. Oxford University Press, 1971.
- [3] P. G. Bergmann. Introduction to the Theory of Relativity. Prentice Hall, 1942.
- [4] G. Berkeley. A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge (Part I). 1710.
- [5] L. De Broglie. Recherches sur la théorie des quanta (on the theory of quanta). Ann. de Physique, 10, 1925.
- [6] H. Dingle. Science at the Crossroads. Martin Brian and O’Keeffee, 1972.
- [7] A. Einstein. Zur elektrodynamik bewegter körper. Annalen der Physik, 332:10, 1905.
- [8] W. Engelhardt. Phase and frequency shift in a michelson interferometer. Physics Essays, 27, 2014.
- [9] W. Heisenberg. The Physical Principles of the Quantum Theory (Translators Eckart C, Hoyt F C). Dover, 1930.
- [10] A. Kanda and P. Apostoli. Inconsistency of some formal theories. In presented at the Meeting of Exact Philosophers at University of British Columbia, 2007.
- [11] A. Kanda and P. Apostoli. Logicism v.s empiricism. In International Seminar on the structure in Cosmology and Theoretical physics, Finish Physics Foundation Society and Finish Society for Natural Philosophy, Helsinki, 2010.
- [12] A. Kanda, R. Wong, and M. Prunescu. Reference frame transformations and quantization. In invited talk at Physics Beyond Relativity Conference, Praha, Czech Republic, 2019.
- [13] T. S. Kuhn. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. The University of Chicago Press, 1962.
- [14] D. F. Lawden. Elements of Relativity Theory. Wiley, 1985.
- [15] H. A. Lorentz. Electromagnetic phenomena in a system moving with any velocity smaller than that of light. In Proceedings of the Royal Netherlands Academy of Arts and Sciences, 1904.
- [16] James C. Maxwell. A dynamical theory of the electromagnetic field. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, 155:459–512, 1865.
- [17] N. Miller and S. C. Ashby. Principles of Modern Physics. Holden Day, 1970.
- [18] H. Minkowski. Das relativitätsprinzip. Annalen der Physik, 352:927–938, 1907.
- [19] A. Robinson. Non-standard analysis. Princeton Landmarks in Mathematics. Princeton University Press, 1966.
- [20] E. Schrödinger. An undulatory theory of the mechanics of atoms and molecules. Physical Review, 28:1049–1070, 1926.
- [21] R. T. Sells and R. L. Weidner. Elementary Modern Physics. Allyn and Bacon, 1973.
- [22] T. Suntola. Dynamic Universe. Physics Foundations Society, 2011.