PCF Theory and The Tukey Spectrum
Abstract.
In this paper, we investigate the relationship between the Tukey order and PCF theory, as applied to sets of regular cardinals. We show that it is consistent that for all sets of regular cardinals that the Tukey spectrum of , denoted , is equal to the set of possible cofinalities of , denoted ; this is to be read in light of the fact that holds for all . We also prove results about when regular limit cardinals must be in the Tukey spectrum or must be out of the Tukey spectrum of some , and we show the relevance of these for forcings which might separate from . Finally, we show that the strong part of the Tukey spectrum can be used in place of PCF-theoretic scales to lift the existence of Jónsson algebras from below a singular to hold at its successor. We close with a list of questions.
Key words and phrases:
PCF Theory, Tukey order, cofinality, weakly compact cardinals, Mahlo cardinals2020 Mathematics Subject Classification:
Primary 03E04, 03E051. Introduction
The Tukey order has become a very useful tool for comparing directed, partially ordered sets. The order is sufficiently coarse that is allows us to compare many different partial orders, yet it is fine enough to preserve a number of order-theoretic properties of interest (such as calibre properties; see Proposition 2.4 below). The Tukey order works by comparing partial orders in terms of what happens “eventually”, or more precisely, in terms of what happens cofinally.
The Tukey order arose in the study of Moore-Smith convergence in topology ([21] and [35]), with [2] and [5] following shortly after. Schmidt ([25]) and Isbell ([15] and [16]) later studied cofinal types among the class of directed posets. Later, Todorčević ([32]) showed that it is consistent that there are only five cofinal types of directed sets of size . Todorčević also showed that under the , there are -many such cofinal types, and in [34] he extended this result to all transitive relations on .
Since then, there has been a tremendous amount of research on the Tukey order in a variety of circumstances. Some results concern definable directed sets ([31], [30]). Others concern cofinal types of ultrafilters ([20], [6], [7], [8], [24], [23], [18]). Additional research concerns the Tukey order on various sets in topological spaces ([12], [13], [11]). Yet another batch of results studies the number of cofinal types of partial orders of various sizes below ([19], [26]). See also [10] and [22].
Cofinal structure has been studied by set theorists coming from a different angle. Especially important for us is Shelah’s theory of possible cofinalities, or PCF theory for short. The main objects of study in PCF theory are reduced products of sets of regular cardinals, modulo an ideal. Shelah has developed the theory in a series of papers which culminated in the book [29]. PCF theory has had dramatic implications for our understanding of cardinal arithmetic (see [1]), as well as plenty of applications both inside and outside of set theory, such as [17]. See [28] for a discussion of further applications.
These two ways of studying cofinal structure are related (and we will discuss this more later): given a set of regular cardinals, we consider the Tukey spectrum of , which consists of all regular cardinals which are Tukey below (i.e., with the pointwise domination ordering). We denote this by . It follows quickly from the definitions (which we give later) that for any set of regular cardinals, . In this paper, we are concerned with the following general question:
Question 1.1.
Does prove that for any set of regular cardinals, ?
To our knowledge, the only result, so far, which addresses this question is due to Gartside and Mamatelashvili ([11]) who have a proof showing that if is any progressive set of regular cardinals, then (“progressive” is a common assumption when doing PCF theory). However, there is a gap in their proof. We address this gap later, observing that their argument rather shows that if is progressive, then .111Since consists, by definition, of regular cardinals, if is progressive and , then has a regular limit point. Additional assumptions on then guarantee equality. However, the status of Question 1.1 when is not progressive is far from clear.
In this work, we prove various results related to Question 1.1. After a review of the basics of the Tukey order and PCF theory in Section 2, we turn in Section 3 to the question of how much bigger can be than . We review the theorem from [11] and address the gap in their proof. Then we turn to showing that Question 1.1 has a consistent positive answer. We also discuss circumstances under which, for all , is no worse than . In Section 4 we address the role that small large cardinals (Mahlo and weakly compact) have in excluding a regular limit from (where ) or for ensuring that . The upshot of these results is that they may reduce the options for showing that Question 1.1 has a consistent negative answer which is witnessed by a forcing separating and (if such exists). In the last main section, Section 5, we show that a subset of the Tukey spectrum (what we call the “strong part” of the Tukey spectrum) is sufficiently strong to be able to “lift” the existence of Jónsson algebras; this generalizes Shelah’s celebrated result [27] that scales in PCF theory can lift the existence of Jónsson algebras.
Acknowledgements We would like to thank Will Brian, James Cummings, Todd Eisworth, and Paul Gartside for many helpful conversations about the Tukey order and PCF theory and for suggesting ways of extending this line of research.
2. A quick overview of Tukey and PCF
In this section we review the basics of the Tukey order and PCF theory which are relevant for this paper.
Remark 2.1.
Throughout the paper, all posets are assumed to be directed.
First we recall the definition of the Tukey order (see [12] for a detailed development of these ideas).
Definition 2.2.
A poset is said to be a Tukey quotient of if there exists a function which preserves cofinal sets. We denote this by .
is equivalent to the existence of a map which preserves unbounded sets.
Definition 2.3.
Suppose that are cardinals. We say that a poset has calibre if for all -sized there is a -sized so that every -sized is bounded in .
We say simply that has calibre if has calibre .
Note that the definition of having calibre simplifies to the following: every -sized has a -sized subset which is bounded in .
The following item connects the ideas of and calibre.
Proposition 2.4.
Suppose that is regular, that has calibre , and that . Then has calibre too.
The next item is particularly relevant for us.
Proposition 2.5.
For a regular cardinal , a poset fails to have calibre iff .
Now we define the Tukey spectrum of a poset.
Definition 2.6.
The Tukey spectrum of a poset is denoted by and defined to be .
When is a set of regular cardinals, we let abbreviate .
Remark 2.7.
consists of all regular so that does not have calibre .
It is helpful to get a better handle on what means in the specific case that is a set of regular cardinals. Indeed, iff there exists a set of -many functions in so that every is unbounded in , i.e., with the pointwise domination ordering. That is to say, there is at least one coordinate so that
is unbounded in the regular cardinal . We give a name to these coordinates in the next definition.
Definition 2.8.
Suppose that is a set of regular cardinals . A cardinal is called an unbounded coordinate of if is unbounded in .
We let denote the set of unbounded coordinates of .
We address the question of how many coordinates are in in Section 5.
The following lemma is a standard part of Tukey-ology.
Lemma 2.9.
. Hence if and are sets of regular cardinals, .
This captures all of the basics of the Tukey order that we need. We now review some of the central results in PCF theory, beginning with the central definition (see [1] for a clear and detailed exposition of these and related ideas).
Definition 2.10.
Let be a set of regular cardinals.
The following are routine facts about the pcf function.
Fact 2.11.
Suppose that and are sets of regular cardinals.
-
(1)
(by using principal ultrafilters).
-
(2)
If , then (since any ultrafilter on can be extended to one on ).
-
(3)
(since any ultrafilter on contains either or ).
The next lemma follows almost immediately from the definitions:
Lemma 2.12.
For any set of regular cardinals, .
A very useful assumption when doing PCF theory is the following:
Definition 2.13.
A set of regular cardinals is progressive if .
We next define certain ideals which are naturally associated to the cardinals in . being progressive plays an important role in the development of the ideas that follow.
Definition 2.14.
Let be a set of regular cardinals and a cardinal (singular or regular). Define the ideal to consist of all so that for any ultrafilter on with , .
If the set is clear from context, we write instead of . A crucial fact about the ideal is the following:
Proposition 2.15.
Suppose that is progressive. Then for any cardinal , is -directed (that is, any set of fewer than -many functions in has an upper bound mod ).
A major theorem in PCF theory is the existence of generators, which we define now.
Definition 2.16.
Let be a set of regular cardinals and . A generator for is a set in so that generates . In other words, given , iff .
Thus a generating set is a maximal set in , modulo ; they are unique modulo . The following is often proven using universal cofinal sequences:
Proposition 2.17.
Suppose that is progressive. Then for any , there is a generator for .
Generators give an instance of compactness:
Proposition 2.18.
Suppose that is progressive and . Let be a sequence of generators. Then there exists a finite decreasing sequence of elements of with so that
Another application of generators and related ideas is the following fact:
Proposition 2.19.
Suppose that is progressive. Then has a maximum element, and moreover,
The last collection of background facts to review concerns weak compactness.
Definition 2.20.
Let be an inaccessible cardinal. We say that a transitive set is an -model if , has size , is closed under -sequences, and .
Now we recall the following characterization of weak compactness (see [14]):
Fact 2.21.
An inaccessible cardinal is weakly compact if and only if for any -model , there exist a -model and an elementary embedding with .
In the context of the previous fact, note that gives rise to an -normal ultrafilter on (recall that an -ultrafilter is -normal if for any and any regressive with , is constant on a set in ). Moreover, since is closed under -sequences (by definition of a -model), this ultrafilter is -closed in (but of course it only measures subsets of in ).
3. How bad can Spec be?
In this section, we study various conditions which guarantee that either (a) is no worse than together with (regular) limit points of or (b) is no worse than together with regular limit points of . These results, when coupled with anti large cardinal hypotheses, give a consistent positive answer to Question 1.1.
We begin by looking at the theorem from [11] which we mentioned in the introduction. Addressing a small gap in their argument, what their proof shows is that for any progressive , can at worst add regular limits of . Additional assumptions on then give the equality of and . We first have some notation.
Notation 3.1.
Given functions in some product of regular cardinals, we let be the function defined by
Theorem 3.2.
(Almost entirely [11]) Suppose that is a progressive set of regular cardinals. Then .222The original statement of their theorem applies to which are finite unions of progressive sets and uses what we are calling Lemma 2.9 to reduce to the case of a single progressive set.
In particular, if is closed under regular limits, or if has no regular limits (for example, if is itself progressive), then .
Proof.
We begin with some set-up. Since is progressive, we may apply Proposition 2.17 to fix a sequence of generators for . For each , is progressive, being a subset of the progressive set . Thus , using for the first equality and applying Proposition 2.19 for the second equality. Therefore, for each , we may choose a sequence of functions in so that is cofinal in .
Fix a cardinal , suppose that is not a limit point of , and we will show that . Because is not a limit point of , we know that ; this will permit us to apply a pigeonhole argument at a crucial step later in the proof.
Since , let enumerate a set of -many functions in so that every -sized subset of is unbounded in . To show that , it suffices to show that . Since is bounded in (because this reduced product is -directed, by Proposition 2.15), it in turn suffices to show that is unbounded in .
We work by contradiction and suppose that is bounded in . Our goal is to define a set of fewer than -many functions in so that every is pointwise below some . Supposing we can define such an , we obtain a contradiction as follows: since is regular, there is a single which is pointwise above -many elements of , and this contradicts the fact that witnesses that .
We begin the construction of as follows. Since is bounded in , let be a bound. For each , each sequence in , and each sequence with for all , we let be the function ; see Notation 3.1. We let be the set of such . Since by assumption is bounded below , we see that consists of fewer than -many functions.
Now we verify that has the desired property. Recalling that enumerates , fix some . Since , we know that
is in . Thus , and so by Proposition 2.18, we may find a sequence in so that . Then, for each , pick so that
(i.e., this holds pointwise on ). Then we see that
Indeed, if , then . On the other hand, if , there is some so that , and hence . Since the function is in , this completes the main part of the proof.
For the “in particular” part of the theorem, observe that if is progressive, then there are no regular limit in . Otherwise, , contradicting that is progressive. ∎
In the rest of this section, we work to isolate a condition (Theorem 3.5) which is consistent with and which implies that for all . In fact, it implies the stronger result that for all . We have some preliminary lemmas. The first of these illustrates a “dropping” phenomenon in the Tukey spectrum; we will use this lemma as part of a later inductive argument.
Lemma 3.3.
Suppose that is a set of regular cardinals. Let . Then .
Proof.
Set ; note that we are making no assumption about whether or not . Since , let be a set of -many functions in so that for all , is unbounded in . Let
and
Note that since , is a non-empty set of regular cardinals. Also, note that is bounded in , since consists of at most -many functions, and we can take a sup of -many elements on each coordinate in .
We next argue that has size and that every -sized subset is unbounded in ; this will show the desired result. First suppose for a contradiction that has size . Then there is a single so that for -many , . Let be this set of . But then is bounded in the entire product , using the observation from the previous paragraph to bound the elements of on coordinates in above . A nearly identical argument shows that must satisfy that every -sized subset is unbounded in . ∎
The next lemma will also be used in the proof of Theorem 3.5:
Lemma 3.4.
Suppose that is a regular limit cardinal. Let be a non-stationary set of regular cardinals which is unbounded in , and let be an ultrafilter on which extends the tail filter on . Then .
Proof.
To begin, let be the increasing enumeration of , and let enumerate a club with . By relabeling if necessary, we take .
Suppose for a contradiction that ; then the cofinality must equal exactly since extends the tail filter on . Let be a sequence of functions in which is increasing and cofinal modulo . We obtain our contradiction by showing that is bounded in , modulo the tail filter on , and hence modulo .
Given (corresponding to ), let so that (such an exists since is club and ). The following observation, though simple, is crucial: for each , : indeed, since the enumeration of is increasing. But and , so . Therefore is also strictly above , and so
is below . We let be above this sup. is then a member of .
We finish the proof by showing that bounds each of the on a tail. To this end, fix , and let so that . We claim that for all , . Fix , and let so that . Then
where the last inequality follows since . ∎
Theorem 3.5.
Let be a model of in which for all limit cardinals and in which there are no Mahlo cardinals. Then satisfies that for any set of regular cardinals, .
Consequently, if for all singular and if there are no regular limit cardinals, then for all , .
Proof.
Fix such a (for example, work in up to the first which is Mahlo in , if such a exists, and otherwise work in all of ). Let be a set of regular cardinals, and we will prove the result by induction on the order type of .
We first dispense with the case when exists. Let . Then, applying Lemma 2.9 and Fact 2.11, as well as our inductive assumption, we get
Now we suppose that does not have a max. Let , and fix . We have a few cases on .
First suppose that . Then by Lemma 3.3, . Since the order type of is less than the order type of , we apply the induction hypothesis to conclude that
Now suppose that . If (and in particular, is a regular limit cardinal), then because is unbounded in , .
The final case is that (here may be either regular or singular). Since is a limit cardinal, our cardinal arithmetic assumption implies that has size . Hence no cardinal greater than is in or in .
To finish the proof in this final case, we will argue that . Towards this end, let be an ultrafilter on which extends the tail filter on . Then . If is singular, then the regular cardinal is greater than . On the other hand, if is regular, then is not a Mahlo cardinal by assumption. This in turn, with the help of Lemma 3.4, implies that . Thus in either case on , . This cofinality must be exactly , however, since has size .
For the “consequently” part of the theorem, recall that consists, by definition, of regular cardinals. Thus if there are no regular limit cardinals, contains no regular cardinals, and this implies that . By Lemma 2.12, we conclude that . ∎
Thus Question 1.1 has a consistent positive answer.
4. Small Large Cardinals and the Tukey Spectrum
In this section, we prove some results showing the relationship between certain small large cardinals (Mahlo and weakly compact) and the Tukey spectrum. The first of this gives a sufficient condition for including a regular limit cardinal in the Tukey spectrum. After this, we prove Theorem 4.2 which gives a sufficient condition for excluding a cardinal from . After the proof of Theorem 4.2, we comment on applications.
Proposition 4.1.
Suppose that is a Mahlo cardinal and that is any stationary set of regular cardinals. Then .
Proof.
We show that functions which are constant on a tail witness the result. For each , let be the function in which takes value on all with , and which takes value on all with . We claim that the sequence enumerates a set which witnesses that .
Towards this end, let , and we will show that is unbounded in . Since is stationary, we may find some . Then for all , . Since is a limit point of , we have that is cofinal in . This completes the proof. ∎
The next result shows that we can use weak compactness to exclude a regular limit from , for certain .
Theorem 4.2.
Suppose that is weakly compact and that is a non-stationary set of regular cardinals which is unbounded in . Then .
Therefore, if is weakly compact and is an unbounded set of regular cardinals, iff is stationary.
Proof.
Let be a club with . Enumerate in increasing order as , where we assume . Also, enumerate in increasing order as . As in the proof of Lemma 3.4, we have that for each , .
Next, let be an enumeration of a set of -many functions in , and we will show that does not witness that . Fix a -model (see Definition 2.20) which contains , , and as elements. By the weak compactness of , let be an -normal ultrafilter on .
Our strategy is to use to successively freeze out longer and longer initial segments of many functions on the sequence . We will then bound their tails using the non-stationarity of .
For each , the product
is a member of , and hence a subset of . Since is strongly inaccessible, this product has size . Applying the fact that is a -complete ultrafilter on , we may find a function in so that
Next, define an increasing sequence below so that for all ,
This also uses the completeness of to see that for each , is in and has size .
As a result of this freezing out, we have the following: for a fixed , and all , . Hence, for all ,
Now consider an and . Let
i.e., all values of all of the on the column . By applying the argument in the previous paragraph, we conclude that in fact equals
Now fix an arbitrary . Since is a club and , there is an so that . We claim that has size less than . If is finite, then is finite, and hence has size smaller than (which is, after all, an infinite cardinal). On the other hand, if is infinite, then
Consequently, for each , is bounded in , as is regular. But by definition of , this means that for all , is bounded in . Thus enumerates a set of -many functions from which is bounded in . Since was arbitrary, this shows that .
For the final statement of the theorem, note that if is non-stationary, then since is Mahlo, Proposition 4.1 shows that . ∎
Note that the converse of the above theorem may fail, since a regular limit cardinal which is not weakly compact may also fail to be in :
Corollary 4.3.
Suppose that is weakly compact and that is a non-stationary set of regular cardinals unbounded in . Let , the poset to add -many Cohen subsets of . Then forces that .
Proof.
Let be a sequence of -names for elements of . We will find an in so that forces that is bounded.
Indeed, using the c.c.c. of , for each , we may find a function so that . Namely, let be above the sup of the countably-many so that is forced to be the value of by some condition in .
By the Theorem 4.2, let so that is bounded in the product , say with as a bound. Then forces that for each , is pointwise below . ∎
We conclude this section with a discussion of a promising suggestion of James Cummings about separating and . Given that always holds, we’d like to create a forcing extension in which, for some , there is a cardinal .
The strategy is to start with a cardinal which is at least Mahlo. Then let and attempt to force the existence of a set of -many functions in which witnesses that . This strategy appears promising due to the next observation.
Lemma 4.4.
Suppose that is strongly inaccessible and that is a nonstationary set of regular cardinals unbounded in . Then .
Proof.
If is an ultrafilter on that concentrates on a bounded subset of , then the strong inaccessibility of implies that . On the other hand, if extends the tail filter on , then by Lemma 3.4, . ∎
While the above strategy is natural, problems remain. First, natural Easton-style forcings to add a witness to seem either to fail to add such a witness, or seem to change the Mahlo into a weakly, non-strongly inaccessible cardinal, i.e., they increase the continuum function below to take values at or above . Thus the crucial assumption of Lemma 4.4 fails. Or phrased differently, ultrafilters which concentrate on bounded subsets may give rise to reduced products with very high cofinality.
Moreover, Theorem 4.2 provides another obstacle: if a forcing places inside for some which is non-stationary and unbounded in , then one of two things needs to happen. Either starts off as non-weakly compact (and this assumption plays a role in the argument) or must ensure that loses its weak compactness.
5. The Strong Part of the Tukey Spectrum
In this section we introduce the idea of the strong part of the Tukey spectrum, and then we will show how this idea can be used in place of scales to lift the property of not being a Jónsson cardinal. Recall the notation from Definition 2.8.
First we make a simple observation about having infinitely-many unbounded coordinates.
Lemma 5.1.
Let be a set of regular cardinals without a max, and let with . Let be any witness that . Then for all , is infinite.
Proof.
Suppose otherwise, with as a counterexample. Then since is finite and has a max below , has size below . Let so that the function is constant, say with value . Then we can bound all of in the entire product using on the coordinates in . ∎
Of course, can very well be finite, or even a singleton, for instance, if is a member of .
We want to isolate cases in which there are plenty of unbounded coordinates. This leads to the next definition.
Definition 5.2.
Suppose that is a set of regular cardinals. The strong part of the Tukey spectrum of , denoted , consists of all regular satisfying the following: there is a set of size , so that for every , is unbounded in .
Thus iff there is a witness to with the additional property that every -sized subset has unboundedly-many unbounded coordinates.
Observe that if is a set of regular cardinals without a max, then . Indeed, if and has size , then we can bound on all coordinates in .
Under cardinal arithmetic assumptions, it is easy to see that every is in :
Lemma 5.3.
Suppose that is a set of regular cardinals with no max and that is a strong limit cardinal (regular or singular). Then .
Proof.
Fix at least as large as . It suffices to show that if is any witness that , then is unbounded. Fix . Then the product has size below . Thus there is so that the function taking to is constant on . Since witnesses that , we must have that is non-empty. Let be the least element of , and note that , since we froze out the values of the functions in on . ∎
We’d now like to connect the strong part of the Tukey spectrum with PCF theory. First we recall a few more definitions from PCF theory, beginning with the following standard version of the notion of a scale:
Definition 5.4.
Let be a singular cardinal, an increasing sequence of regular cardinals which is cofinal in , and an ideal on . Let be a sequence of functions in . The tuple is called a scale of length modulo if is increasing and cofinal in modulo .
If is just the ideal of bounded subsets of , then we simply say that is a scale of length for .
We now connect scales with the strong part of the Tukey spectrum:
Lemma 5.5.
Suppose that is a scale of length , where is a regular cardinal. Then is in , where .
Proof.
This follows since we are working modulo the ideal of bounded subsets of . Indeed, let , and we will show that witnesses the result. Note that if , then is also a scale. But then must be unbounded in , as otherwise we contradict that is cofinal in modulo the bounded ideal. ∎
Now we examine one way in which can play a traditional PCF-theoretic role. We begin with some background: a remarkable phenomenon in PCF theory is that scales of length (where is singular) can be used to “lift” a property which holds at the to hold at . For example, Shelah proved that the failure of being a Jónsson cardinal lifts in this way; we will discuss this in more detail in a moment. Other examples include Theorem 3.5 of [4] and a theorem of Todorcevic about lifting the failure of certain square bracket partition relations ([33]).
Here we include a very short review of the notion of a Jónsson cardinal, referring the reader to [9] for more details.
Definition 5.6.
-
(1)
An algebra is a structure so that each is a finitary function mapping to .
-
(2)
A Jónsson algebra is an algebra without a proper subalgebra of the same cardinality.
-
(3)
A cardinal is said to be a Jónsson cardinal if there does not exist a Jónsson algebra of cardinality .
Jónsson cardinals can be characterized in terms of a coloring relation.
Fact 5.7.
is a Jónsson cardinal iff for any , there exists an so that the range of is a proper subset of .
We use to denote the coloring property from the previous fact. We can also characterize this in terms of elementary submodels. The next item is almost exactly Lemma 5.6 from [9]; we have added a parameter to the statement, which does not change the proof. In the statement of the lemma, denotes a wellorder of .
Lemma 5.8.
The following two statements are equivalent:
-
(1)
is a Jónsson cardinal.
-
(2)
For every sufficiently large regular , every cardinal so that , and every parameter , there is an so that
-
(a)
;
-
(b)
;
-
(c)
; and
-
(d)
.
-
(a)
Shelah ([27]) has proven the following remarkable theorem:
Theorem 5.9.
(Shelah) Suppose that is singular and that is a scale (modulo the ideal of bounded sets) of length . Additionally, suppose that each carries a Jónsson algebra (i.e., is not a Jónsson cardinal). Then carries a Jónsson algebra.
Here we show that it suffices to assume that is in the strong part of the Tukey spectrum of , provided the order type of is not too high.
Theorem 5.10.
Suppose that is a set of regular cardinals with so that every carries a Jónsson algebra, and suppose that . Then carries a Jónsson algebra.
Proof.
We will show that carries a Jónsson algebra by showing that (2) of Lemma 5.8 is false.
Fix a large enough regular cardinal . Letting , , and play the respective roles of , , and in (the negation of) Lemma 5.8(2), fix an arbitrary so that , , and . We will show that . Observe that , since contains a bijection from onto , and since .
Applying the elementarity of , we may find a set of functions witnessing with . Using , we will show that there are unboundedly-many so that . The upshot of this is that for each such , since is not a Jónsson cardinal, . Since there are unboundedly-many such , we conclude that . And finally, since , we can conclude that .
To show the existence of unboundedly-many such , let . Since , we know that . Since , the set is unbounded in .
Now let . Then for all , , since and are each members of . Since is unbounded in (by definition of being an unbounded coordinate) and a subset of , we conclude that has size . This completes the proof. ∎
We close this section by providing a bound on the strong part of the Tukey spectrum. First note that it follows almost immediately from the definitions that
Now let denote the ideal of bounded sets on . Note that does have a cofinality, but it needn’t have a true cofinality (i.e., a linearly-ordered, cofinal subset).
Proposition 5.11.
Let be a set of regular cardinals, and let . Then either or for some proper initial segment of .
In particular (see Definition 5.2), if is in , then .
Proof.
Let , and let enumerate a set of functions which is cofinal (but not necessarily increasing) in . Suppose that . Let enumerate a set of -many functions witnessing that . Since is regular and , fix and so that for all , . Now freeze out the tail: let and so that for all and all ,
Thus is bounded on every coordinate in . Since , is unbounded in . From this, one can argue that has size and witnesses that .
For the “in particular” part of the proposition, note that if , then the previous argument shows that there is an so that is bounded in . ∎
6. Questions
Here we record a few questions which we find interesting. The first question restates Question 1.1, the main one driving this line of research:
Question 6.1.
Does prove that for all sets of regular cardinals, ?
Question 6.2.
Does prove that for all progressive sets of regular cardinals, ?
One can also ask about the relationship between and , as in the next two questions:
Question 6.3.
Does prove that ?
Question 6.4.
Does prove that if is a set of regular cardinals without a max, then ?
The following question should be read in light of Theorem 3.5:
Question 6.5.
Does prove that for all sets of regular cardinals,
Question 6.6.
Is a weakly compact necessary to get a model in which is a regular limit, is unbounded and non-stationary, and ?
Theorem 5.10 showed that the strong part of the Tukey spectrum can be used in place of PCF-theoretic scales to lift the property of not being a Jónsson cardinal. Where else, if at all, can be used in this way? In particular, we ask whether the strong part of the Tukey spectrum is enough to generalize a classic result of Todorcevic ([33]; see the treatments in [3] and [9]).
Question 6.7.
Suppose that is a set of regular cardinals cofinal in a singular so that every fails to satisfy . Suppose that . Does this imply that fails to satisfy ?
References
- [1] U. Abraham and M. Magidor. Cardinal arithmetic. In M. Foreman and A. Kanamori, editors, Handbook of Set Theory, pages 1149–1227. Springer Netherlands, 2010.
- [2] G. Birkhoff. Moore-Smith convergence in general topology. Annals of Mathematics (2), 38(1):39–56, 1937.
- [3] M. Burke and M. Magidor. Shelah’s PCF theory and its applications. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 50:207–254, 1990.
- [4] J. Cummings, M. Foreman, and M. Magidor. Canonical structure in the universe of set theory I. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 129(1-3):211–243, 2004.
- [5] M. Day. Oriented systems. Duke Mathematics Journal, 11:201–229, 1944.
- [6] N. Dobrinen and S. Todorčević. Tukey types of ultrafilters. Illinois Journal of Mathematics, 55(3):907–951, 2011.
- [7] N. Dobrinen and S. Todorčević. A new class of Ramsey-classification theorems and their application in the Tukey theory of ultrafilters, part 1. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 366(3):1659–1684, 2014.
- [8] N. Dobrinen and S. Todorčević. A new class of Ramsey-classification theorems and their application in the Tukey theory of ultrafilters, part 2. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 367(7):4627–4659, 2015.
- [9] T. Eisworth. Successors of singular cardinals. In M. Foreman and A. Kanamori, editors, Handbook of Set Theory, pages 1229–1350. Springer Netherlands, 2010.
- [10] D.H. Fremlin. The partially ordered sets of measure theory and Tukey’s ordering. Note Mat., 11:177–214. Dedicated to the memory of Professor Gottfried K öthe, 1991.
- [11] P.M. Gartside and A. Mamatelashvili. Tukey order, calibres and the rationals. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 172, 2016.
- [12] P.M. Gartside and A. Mamatelashvili. The Tukey order on compact subsets of separable metric spaces. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 81:181–200, 2016.
- [13] P.M. Gartside and A. Mamatelashvili. The Tukey order and subsets of . Order, 35, 2018.
- [14] K. Hauser. Indescribable cardinals and elementary embeddings. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 56(2):439–457, 1991.
- [15] J.R. Isbell. The category of cofinal types. II. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 116:394–416, 1965.
- [16] J.R. Isbell. Seven cofinal types. Journal of London Mathematical Society, 4:394–416, 1972.
- [17] M. Kojman and S. Shelah. A Dowker space in : an application of pcf theory to topology. Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, 126(8):2459–2465, 1998.
- [18] B. Kuzeljevic and D. Raghavan. A long chain of p-points. Journal of Mathematical Logic, 18(1):185000, 38, 2018.
- [19] B. Kuzeljevic and S. Todorčević. Cofinal types on , 2021. https://arxiv.org/abs/2108.03701.
- [20] D. Milovich. Tukey classes of ultrafilters on . In Spring Topology and Dynamics Conference, volume 32, pages 351–362. 2008.
- [21] E.H. Moore and H.L. Smith. A general theory of limits. American Journal of Mathematics, 44:102–121, 1922.
- [22] J.T. Moore and S. Solecki. A ideal of compact sets strictly above the nowhere dense ideal in the Tukey order. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 156:270–273, 2008.
- [23] D. Raghavan and S. Shelah. On embedding certain partial orders into the -points under RK and Tukey reducibility. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 369(6):4433–4455, 2017.
- [24] D. Raghavan and S. Todorčević. Cofinal types of ultrafilters. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 163(3):185–199, 2012.
- [25] J. Schmidt. Kofinalität. Z. Math. Logik Grundlagen Math, 1:271–303, 1955.
- [26] R. Shalev. Cofinal types below , 2022. https://arxiv.org/abs/2205.00023.
- [27] S. Shelah. Jonsson algebras in successor cardinals. Israel Journal of Mathematics, 30(1-2):57–64, 1978.
- [28] S. Shelah. Cardinal arithmetic for skeptics. Bulletin of the AMS, 26(2):197–210, 1992.
- [29] S. Shelah. Cardinal Arithmetic, volume 29. The Clarendon Press, Oxford University Press, New York, 1994.
- [30] S. Solecki and S. Todorčević. Cofinal types of topological directed orders. Annales de l’Institut Fourier, 54(6):1877–1911 (2005), 2004.
- [31] S. Solecki and S. Todorčević. Avoiding families and Tukey functions on the nowhere-dense ideal. Journal of the Institute of Mathematics of Jussieu, 10(2):405–435, 2011.
- [32] S. Todorčević. Directed sets and cofinal types. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 290(2):711–723, 1985.
- [33] S. Todorčević. Partitioning pairs of countable ordinals. Acta Mathematica, 159(3-4):261–294, 1987.
- [34] S. Todorčević. A classification of transitive relations on . Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society (3), 73(3):501–533, 1996.
- [35] J.W. Tukey. Convergence and uniformity in topology, volume 2 of Annals of Mathematics Studies. Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1940.