Partitions of vertices and facets in trees and stacked simplicial complexes
Abstract.
For stacked simplicial complexes, (special subclasses of such are: trees, triangulations of polygons, stacked polytopes with their triangulations), we give an explicit bijection between partitions of facets (for trees: edges), and partitions of vertices into independent sets. More generally we give bijections between facet partitions whose parts have minimal distance and vertex partitions whose parts have minimal distance .
Key words and phrases:
tree, partition, independent vertices, stacked simplicial complex, natural numbers, Stirling numbers, bijection2020 Mathematics Subject Classification:
Primary: 05C05 05C69, 05E45; Secondary: 05C701. Introduction
If is a graph with vertices and edges , a set of vertices is independent if no two vertices in are on the same edge. Between any two vertices there is a well-defined distance, and the vertices are independent if their distance is . Distance may also be defined between edges in a graph.
Assume the graph is a tree and consider partitions of vertices in a tree
into non-empty parts. We can also partition edges
into non-empty parts.
0. We give a bijection between:
-
i)
Partitions of vertices into non-empty parts, each part consisting of independent vertices, and
-
ii)
partitions of edges into non-empty parts (and no further requirements).
Example 1.1.
Any tree has a unique partition of the vertices into two independent sets (two colors modulo ). This corresponds to the partition of the edges into one part (one color).
Moreover the above generalizes in two directions.
1. Define a set of vertices to be -scattered if the distance between any two vertices is . Similarly we have the notion of a set of edges being -scattered. We show, Theorem 3.6, for a tree and for there is a bijection between:
-
i)
Partitions of vertices into non-empty parts, each part being -scattered, and
-
ii)
Partitions of edges into non-empty parts, each part being -scattered
2. Stacked simplicial complexes is a generalization of trees to higher dimensions. Stacked polytopes [8] with the triangulation coming from a stacking of simplices, induce a well-known subclass of stacked simplicial complexes. The main feature of stacked simplicial complexes for us is that between any two facets (maximal faces) there is a unique path. Similarly between any pair of vertices there is a unique path of facets. We show:
Theorem 3.6 Let be a stacked simplicial complex of dimension and . There is a bijection between:
-
i)
Partitions of vertices of into non-empty parts, each part being -scattered,
-
ii)
Partitions of facets of into non-empty parts, each part being -scattered
The results on trees appear quite non-trivial even for the simplest of graphs, the line graph. By considering larger and large line graphs, we get in the limit results for partitions of natural numbers.
Theorem 4.1 There is a bijection between partitions of the natural numbers into non-empty parts, each part being -scattered, and partitions of into non-empty parts, each part being -scattered.
As a consequence we get for instance:
Corollary 4.3 There is a bijection between partitions of into two parts (each part automatically -scattered) and partitions of into parts , each part being -scattered.
(A trivial special case by repeated use of Theorem 4.1, starting from and successively increasing : There is a unique partition of into parts, each being -scattered. These parts are of course the congruence classes modulo .)
Let us explain in more detail the bijection, first for trees, and secondly in an example of triangulations of polygons. Such triangulations are stacked simplicial complexes of dimension two.
Given a tree and a partition of the vertices , make a partition of the edges as follows: If and are vertices consider the unique path in linking and . Let , respectively , be the edge incident to , respectively , on this path. If (i) and are in the same part of and (ii) no other vertex on this path is in the part , then put and into the same part of , and write . The partition of edges is the equivalence relation generated by .
Conversely given a partition of the edges , make a partition of the vertices as follows: Let and be distinct vertices, and consider again the path from to . Let the edges be as above. If (i) the edges and are distinct (equivalently the vertices are independent), (ii) and are in the same part , and (iii) no other edge on this path is in the part , then put and in the same part of , and write . The partition of vertices is the equivalence relation generated by .
Example 1.2.
In Figure 1 we partition the edges into two parts, colored red and black. The vertices are then partitioned into three parts, each consisting of independent vertices. The partition of the vertex set of the first tree is
and that of the second tree is
Example 1.3.
Consider now a triangulation of the heptagon, which is a stacked simplicial complex. We partition the facets into two parts: three blue and two red, Figure 2. This corresponds, in a similar way as for trees, to a partition of the vertices, now into four parts of independent vertices: two yellow vertices , three red , one blue , and one green . In fact the facet parts here are -scattered and so each of the vertex parts will even be -scattered.
Note that the colors have no real significance here, they are just added for pedagogical and visualisation purposes. In particular there is no connection between colors of facets and colors of vertices.
Our results here came out of work in [7] by M.Orlich and the author on triangulations of polygons and more generally on stacked simplicial complexes.
Results related to the present article are to be found in enumerative combinatorics. A first result in this direction is W.Yang [14] considering trees on vertices, showing that partitions into independent sets of vertices are counted by Bell numbers . He also considers generalized -trees and show that partitions into independent sets of vertices of such a tree with vertices is counted by the Bell number . A generalized -tree is the same as the edges (or -skeleton) of a stacked simplicial complex of dimension .
B.Duncan and R.Peele [4] consider enumerative aspects of partitions of vertices of graphs into independent sets. For trees they show that partitions of a tree with vertices into independent parts are in bijection with partitions of an -set into parts. They give, mostly illustrated by a large example, a bijection which is essentially the same as we give. But we gain here the conceptual advantage of expressing this in terms of edges of the tree. Their statement involves choosing an arbitrary vertex , a root, and then relating independent vertex partitions of to partitions of . Their less conceptual form may also be the reason they do not have the extension to -scattered parts. [9] and [11] considers enumerative aspects of graphical Bell numbers further, and the latter also generalized -trees.
W.Chen, E.Deng, and R.Du [2] consider ordered sets and use the terminology -regular for -scattered. They show that partitions of an ordered -set into parts which are -regular are in bijection with partitions of an -set into parts which are -regular. This corresponds to the case of line graphs, and for this case the bijection they give is essentially the same as ours. We discuss this in Section 4. They also show that we have bijections in this case when considering non-crossing partitions. Related enumerative results are found in [13] and [3]. The book [12] is a comprehensive account of partitions of ordered sets.
Remark 1.4.
The results of this paper dropped out of investigations in [7], concerning Stanley-Reisner rings of stacked simplicial complexes. Among such simplicial complexes there are certain separated models, and from these models we obtain every stacked simplicial complex by partitioning the vertices into independent classes and then collapsing each class into a single vertex. This is done such that the essential algebraic and homological properties of the associated rings are preserved.
The algebra involved here should generalize to much larger classes of simplicial complexes. Polarizing Artin monomial ideals gives separated models, and in [1] we describe all such for polarizations of any power of a graded maximal ideal in a polynomial ring. The case of stacked simplicial complex is the case of the second power. Polarizing Artin monomial ideals in general still goes much further than [1]. The results in the present article therefore likely have vast generalizations, see Subsection 8.2 of [6]. This should involve partitions of vertices, but it is a challenge what other ingredients and statements should be involved.
Let us also mention that the main result of [6] is a fundamental theorem of combinatorial geometry of monomial ideals. Namely that any polarization of an Artin monomial ideal, via the Stanley-Reisner correspondence, is a simplicial complex whose topological realization is a ball.
We describe the organization of this article. Section 2 gives the notion of stacked simplicial complex of dimension . It characterizes these, Proposition 2.9, as the simplicial complexes for which there is a unique path between any pair of facets, and the number of vertices is more then that number of facets. Section 3 describes the correspondence between partitions of vertices and partitions of facets, and shows our main Theorem 3.6. In the last Section 4 we specialize these results to bijections between partitions of natural numbers, the parts having lower bound requirements on minimal distance.
Acknowledgements. I thank M.Orlich for making Figure 1.
2. Stacked simplicial complexes
We recall the notion of stacked simplicial complex. Its main feature from our perspective, is that it generalizes the property of trees, that for every two faces, there is a unique path between them.
2.1. Paths
Let be a finite set. A simplicial complex on is a family of subsets of closed under taking subsets of each element of the family. So for an element and , then also . The elements of are vertices, the elemens of are faces, and the maximal elements of for the inclusion relation are facets. A simplicial complex has a natural geometric realization. A face with vertices is then realized as a simplex of dimension .
Given any family of subsets of , the simplicial complex generated by is the family of all subsets of such that for some .
Definition 2.1.
A pure simplicial complex (i.e., where all the facets have the same dimension) is stacked if there is an ordering of its facets such that if is the simplicial complex generated by , then for the facet is attached to along a single codimension one face of . So we may write where is a codimension one face of and is not a vertex of . The vertex is the free vertex of , in this stacking order.
Remark 2.2.
This is a special case of shellable simplicial complexes, see [10, Subsection 8.2]. It is not the same as the notion of simplicial complex being a tree as in [5], even if the tree is pure. Rather the notion of stacked simplicial complex is more general. For instance the triangulation of the heptagon given in Figure 2, is not a tree in the sense of [5], since removing the triangles and one has no facet which is a leaf.
Definition 2.3.
A (gallery) walk in a pure simplicial complex, is a sequence of facets such that each has codimension one in (and hence also in ). The left end vertex is the single element of and the right end vertex is the single element of .
If for some , we can make a shorter walk from to . If then
is a shorter walk. If , then
is a shorter walk from to .
Definition 2.4.
A path is a walk where all the are distinct. The length of the path is .
By the explanation before this definition, any walk from to may be reduced to a path between and .
Lemma 2.5.
Let be a stacked simplicial complex and a path in .
-
a.
Let come last among the facets on the path, for a stacking order of , and let be its free vertex. Then either and or and .
-
b.
All the are distinct.
Proof.
a. If , then , and so would be on two facets. But this is not so. So must be one of the end vertices and must be as above.
b. If then and as is on only one facet on the path, , contradicting that we have a path.
If , then is also a path and so and must be distinct. ∎∎
Definition 2.6.
Let be a pure simplicial complex, and faces in such that is not contained in any codimension one face. A path between and , written
is a path such that
The face-distance (or simply distance) between and is . In particular, if are contained in a common facet, and not in a codimension one face, their distance is one. If is contained in a codimension one face, a path between is an empty path consisting of no facets, written . Their distance is defined to be zero.
We mostly use this definition when and are single vertex sets and , in which case we simply write instead of , and similarly for .
Lemma 2.7.
Let be a stacked simplicial complex, and faces of .
-
a.
In a path between and we have and for each .
-
b.
Let be the facet on the path which is last for a stacking order on . The free vertex of is in or in .
Proof.
a. Suppose for there was an such that , and let be minimal such. Then and consider the path
Let be the last among these facets in the stacking order of , and its free vertex. Then or . If , since and , must contain the single vertex in , and this vertex is . But then is also in . Since is only on a single facet, then , and this contradicts all facets on a path being distinct.
b. The last facet is one of the end facets, say . If then and the statement holds. If , the and since is not on two facets in the path, we get . ∎∎
2.2. Existence and uniqueness of paths
Proposition 2.8.
Let be faces with union not contained in any codimension one face. Then there is a unique path between them.
Proof.
Existence: If is a facet , then is a path between them. Assume then is not contained in a facet.
Let be a facet containing and a facet containing . Let
be the path between them. Let be maximal such that . Let be minimal such that . Then we have a path from to :
Uniqueness: Let
be paths with .
Let be the last of the facets in these paths, in the stacking order, and with free vertex . By Lemma 2.7, is in say . As is in a single facet on these paths, we get . If we are done.
i) Suppose exactly one of is , say (and ). Then so . Since the free vertex is also in , and so in . Then , which is not so for a path.
ii) Suppose the paths have . Let
Since , we have not included in a codimension one face. So we get paths
By induction on length, these paths are equal. ∎∎
The following generalizes the well-known situation for trees.
Proposition 2.9.
Let be a pure simplicial complex of dimension with facets and vertices. Then is stacked iff and between every pair of facets there is a unique path.
Proof.
When is stacked it is clear from construction that . By Proposition 2.8 there is a unique path between any two facets.
Conversely, assume and that between every pair of facets there is a unique path. Choose a facet , order the facets of :
(1) |
such that the distance for . Let be the simplicial complex generated by . Consider the path from to :
Here all facets except the last are in as they must be listed before in (1) due to distance. Since has codimension one in , when passing from to we have added at most one new vertex. Since has vertices, we must have added exactly one new vertex each time, and so has a single free vertex, and has vertices.
We show that between any two facets of there is a unique path. By induction is a stacking order for , and so (1) gives that is also stacked.
Let be two facets in . Consider the path in . If the last facet is on this path, say , then and
This is not so, and so the path from to is entirely in . ∎∎
The facet-distance between two facets is defined to be the length of the path between them (note that and ), and this length is .
Remark 2.10.
Note that for two facets their face-distance is one more than their facet-distance. It may seem awkward to have two notions of distance. But by looking at the graph:
it is natural. The facet-distance between and is one, and the face-distance between and is two. (And the face-distance between and is also two.)
2.3. Distance neighborhoods
Let be a pure simplicial complex. Choose a codimension one face in . For , let be the simplicial complex generated by those facets of whose face-distance to is . In particular and the facets of are the facets of containing . Let be the vertices of and the vertices of for .
Lemma 2.11.
Assume is a stacked simplicial complex. For , if , there is a unique facet in containing , and is a subset of .
Proof.
Let be a facet in containing , and
the unique path from to . We have . Let be maximal with . Then in :
is the unique path from to . Since we must have , and so and . Then is the first facet in the unique path from to and . ∎∎
Corollary 2.12.
is a stacked simplicial complex on .
Proof.
Let be any ordering of the facets in such that the face-distance between and is weakly increasing with . Choose and let be the distance from to . The facets are then all in . Let be the unique path from to . Then:
-
•
If then for some ,
-
•
for some ,
-
•
,
-
•
By Lemma 2.11, is in none of the for .
Thus is a stacking order for . ∎∎
3. Bijections between partitions of facets and of vertices
We show how partitions of facets and partitions of vertices into independent sets correspond, and we show that this correspondence is really a bijection. Our arguments are by induction on the distance neighbourhood . We develop some lemmata before the proof of the main theorem.
3.1. Bijections between partitions
Definition 3.1.
Let be a be a stacked simplicial complex with vertex set , and an integer . A subset is -scattered if the face-distance between any two distinct vertices in is . The vertex set is independent if it is -scattered, i.e. no two vertices in are on the same facet.
Similarly a subset of the facets is -scattered if the facet-distance between any two facets in is .
We consider partitions of the vertices
(2) |
into non-empty disjoint sets. Note that the order here is not relevant, so if we switch and we have the same partition.
Remark 3.2.
If the are independent, this is almost the same as a graph coloring of vertices, but not quite. A coloring of the vertices is a map where is a set of colors, such that each inverse image is a set of independent vertices. The symmetric group acts on colorings by permuting the colors . So a partition as above (2) is an orbit for the action of . The class of such orbits, or equivalently of partitions (2) are also called non-equivalent vertex colorings, see [9].
We also consider partitions of the facets
3.1.1. From vertex partitions to facet partitions.
Now we make a correspondence as follows. Given a partition of into non-empty independent sets, given by an equivalence relation . For ease of following the arguments, we will think of each part as having a specific color. Make a partition of as follows. Let and be distinct facets. Consider the unique path in between them:
and let and be respectively the left and right end vertices. If and have the same color, say blue, and none of the facets has any blue vertex, then write . This means that and will be in the same part of facets, these facets get the same color. The colors of vertices and edges are however unrelated, so the facets and get some color unrelated to blue. The relation on is the equivalence relation generated by .
3.1.2. From facet partitions to vertex partitions
Conversely given a partition of the facets , given by an equivalence relation . Make a partition of the vertices as follows. Let and be independent vertices, and consider the path from to :
If and have the same color, say green, and none of the facets are green, then let . The relation is the equivalence relation generated by . See Example 1.2.
We want to show that these correspondences are inverse to each other. To do this we show:
A. From an equivalence relation on , we have constructed the equivalence relation on . We show that the equivalence relation in turn induces the equivalence relation by showing:
-
1.
If are distinct and, say blue, and
where none of have a blue vertex, then and (in the original equivalence relation for )
-
2.
If in the original relation with distinct, there is a sequence such that
(3) where is the relation constructed from .
-
3.
We also show that if the original is -scattered, then is -scattered.
B. From an equivalence relation on , we have constructed the equivalence relation on . We show that this in turn induces the equivalence relation , by showing:
-
1.
If we have a path with
where and are, say green, and none of are green, then (in the original equivalence relation for ).
-
2.
If in the original relation, there is a sequence such that
(4) where is the relation constructed from .
-
3.
We also show that if the original is -scattered, then is -scattered.
3.2. Induction arguments on
We show A, B for the by induction on . For this we need some lemmata.
Lemma 3.3.
Given a partition of the facets , and consider the relation on vertices, constructed above in Subsection 3.1.2. Let , and distinct in . If and , then .
Proof.
We show first that are independent. Recall, Lemma 2.11, that is the unique facet on containing .
i) Suppose were on the same face . Let
be the path from to . If are both on we may make a shorter path. So we may assume and not both in . Assume then that is the right end vertex of . Then the above must be the unique path from to . Since , and have the same color, say green. We have and (since are independent). Let be minimal such that . We then have a path
and this is the unique path from to . By definition of , and also have the same color, which must be green. But by definition of there should not have been any green color between the faces and . Hence must be independent.
ii) Let
(5) |
be the unique paths where by Lemma 2.11. Here and have the same color, say green, and and have the same color, also green, and none of the facets in between have color green. None of the two paths is then a subpath of the other. Hence there is an such that , and let be minimal such, so . If there is a walk
(6) |
where and are the only green facets. If then and so has codimension one. There is then a walk
(7) |
where only the end facets are green. By reducing these walks like before Definition 2.4, we get a path giving . ∎∎
Note. The process of suitably cutting the sequences (5), then splicing them, (6) or (7), and lastly reducing to a path, will be used a couple of times and we call it cut-splice-reduction.
Lemma 3.4.
Given a partition of into independent sets, and the relation constructed as in Subsection 3.1.1. Let be a facet in which is not in . If and , then .
Proof.
Note first that is for a unique . By Lemma 2.11 any path in starting from must have left end vertex . So we have the following paths
where have the same color blue and none of have blue vertices. Similarly have the same color blue, and none of have blue vertices. None of these paths is then a subpath of the other, and hence there is such that and let be minimal such. If , as above (6), we get a walk
where none of the intermediate facets have blue vertices. If , as above (7), get a walk
(8) |
Aagain as above these walks may be reduced to paths (cut-splice-reduction) and so . ∎∎
Lemma 3.5.
Suppose the relation , induces the relation on . Consider the subcomplex . i) The restricted relation then induces the restricted relation . Similarly, ii) if induces the restricted relation induces the restricted relation .
Proof.
Note that if and and is the path in between them, then since is stacked, this path is entirely in .
i) Suppose given . Let such that , so we have
Let minimal such that all . If then some where . By the above Lemma 3.3 we may replace by . In this way we may reduce the above so all , and thus induces .
3.3. The main theorem
Theorem 3.6.
Let be a stacked simplicial complex of dimension , with vertex set and facet set , and an integer . The correspondences in Subsections 3.1.1 and 3.1.2 give a one-to-one correspondence between partitions of the vertices into non-empty sets, each -scattered, and partitions of the facets into non-empty sets, each -scattered.
Proof.
A. Assume we have started from a partition of facets , and have constructed the equivalence relation corresponding to a partition of the vertices . We show properties A1, A2, A3 for by induction on , so that in turn induces the original partition .
Property A1: Suppose are distinct and, say blue, and let be minimal such that . We may assume . Suppose we have a path from to :
where have no blue vertices. We want to show (in the original equivalence relation for ), that is, they have the same color, say green. Let have color green, and let
(9) |
By Lemma 3.5 we may assume all . Also, if for some , we may by Lemma 3.3 reduce to a shorter such sequence. We may therefore assume the for are in . If , then by definition of , and we are done. So assume and consider the path in :
(10) |
Then and have the same color green by definition of and none of are green. Both and are blue. We claim that none of has any blue vertex. Otherwise, let be maximal such that has a blue vertex . We get a sequence . Then , since by Lemma 2.11, and the path from to is in ). By induction (on ) the facets and have the same color, a contradiction. Thus none of has a blue vertex.
We claim that and are independent, which is now equivalent to show that is not in . This will give . Recall by Lemma 2.11 that is the only facet in containing . If was in then , which is . In particular . By induction, since are in and are related by (9), they are either equal or independent. If equal, and are independent since , and so not both in . If and are independent, is not in . Then , and has a blue vertex , contradicting that no intermediate facet in (10) has a blue vertex. The upshot is that is not in , and so .
By cut-splice-reducing the sequences,
(11) |
as in Lemma 3.4 we reduce to a path
(12) |
where no intermediate facet has blue vertices.
Case 1: . Then by induction on , since and are in , and have the same color green. As and has the same color, green, we get that and are both green.
Case 2: We have , and only one of (i.e. ) is in . Then we can start the argument of Property A1 over again and reduce to Case 1. So we conclude again that and have the same color. Again as and have the same color, green, we get that and are green.
Property A2: Suppose are distinct and green. Let
be the unique path from to . Let be minimal such that is green, and consider the path
Then and so are, say blue. If one where has a blue vertex, let be minimal such, and let be this vertex, so we have a path
By part A1, and have the same color, which must be green. This is a contradiction and so none of has a blue vertex. Thus . Let and . Considering now the shorter path . By induction on length of path, there are
and so we get part A2.
Property A3: Suppose is -scattered. Let be distinct blue vertices whose face-distance is as small as possible. We showed in the argument of Property A1 that and are independent, and so we have a path
with . None of can then have blue vertices. Thus by what we showed in A1, and their facet-distance is . Whence and the blue vertices are -scattered.
B. We have started from a partition of the vertices into independent sets. We have constructed from this an equivalence relation and corresponding partition of the facets. We show that properties B1, B2, B3 holds for by induction on , so that induces the original partition .
Property B1: Suppose , and the path from to is
(13) |
where are green and none of are green. We show that , they have the same color, say blue.
There is a sequence
Let be smallest such that is in . By Lemma 3.5 we may assume all are in . If some for is in , by Lemma 3.4 we may reduce to a shorter sequence. So we may assume for .
If then and we are done. So assume . Since , by Lemma 2.11 we have . Now look at at the path from to
where and are blue, and do not have any blue vertex. The facets and have the same color, which is green. Are there any green facets in between? Suppose is maximal such that is green. We have a path
where all are in . By induction on , and have the same color, blue. This is a contradiction, as has no blue vertex. So and are green, while no facets in between are green.
Look at the two paths:
where . None of these is a sub-sequence of the other, as and are green, and no intermediate facet is green. As in Lemma 3.4 we may cut-splice-reduce these together to get a path
where only the end facets are green.
Case 1: . Then in the path from to , the end facets are green, and no intermediate facet is green. By induction on (since both and are in ), we get that and have the same color. Furthermore and have the same color, blue, so both and are blue.
Case 2: . We have exactly one of (i.e. ) in . The path from to has end facets green and no intermediate facet green. But then we can start the argument of Property B1 over again, and reduce to Case 1. So we conclude that and have the same color. Since and are both blue, we get that and are both blue.
Property B2: Suppose are distinct and blue. Let
be the unique path from to . Since and are independent, . Let be minimal such that contains a blue vertex . Then by construction, say they are green. Consider the path
If one for is green, let minimal such. Then we have a path
and by B1 we have , both blue. This contradicts the choice of . Thus . Now . If we have and we are done. If then . Let be maximal with such that . We then get
where both and are blue.
By induction on path length there are
and so we get part B2.
Property B3: Suppose is -scattered. Let be distinct green facets whose facet-distance is as small as possible with path
None of the intermediate facets are green. Then we have just shown in B1 that and so their face-distance . Then and the green facets are -scattered.
Final part: We show that if there are facet parts, there are vertex parts. This is by induction on the number of facets. Clearly this is true if we have one facet, a simplex. For a stacked simplicial complex let be minimal such that , and let . Let be a facet in , and the free vertex of . By induction, if there are facet parts in , there are vertex parts.
If the facet makes a part of its own in , the free vertex becomes a part of its own, by construction of vertex classes. Then we have facet parts and vertex parts in .
If the facet is put into an existing part, say the green part, look at paths where are green and the intermediate facets are not green. Then will be given the color of , say blue. If is another path with and green, and not intermediate facet is green, by Lemma 3.4 we may cut-splice-reduce and get in a path with green and with no intermediate green facets. Both and have the same color. Then is uniquely in the blue color class. So has facet parts and vertex parts. ∎∎
Corollary 3.7.
Let be a tree, and . There is a bijection between partitions of the vertices into non-empty parts, each part -scattered, and partitions of the edges into non-empty parts, each -scattered.
Corollary 3.8.
Let be a triangulation of a polygon and . There is a bijection between partitions of the vertices into non-empty parts, each part -scattered, and partitions of the triangles into non-empty parts, each -scattered.
4. Partitions of natural numbers
The main theorem here appears quite surprising and non-trivial even for the simplest of trees, the line graph. Then it corresponds to studying ordered set partitions, which has a comprehensive theory [12].
Taking the colimit of longer and longer line graphs, we get results for the natural numbers. These are simple consequences of known results for ordered set partitions [2, Thm.2.2] or in a more enumerative form [3, Thm.1], but do not seem to have been stated in this form for natural numbers. In a similar vein, [13] considers partitions of intervals , but with requirements on the parts which are different from ours here.
Consider the infinite line graph
The set of edges may be identified with the natural numbers , and also the set of vertices may be identified with . Let be the line graph with edges. The bijection between partitions edges into parts, each -scattered, and partitions of vertices into parts, each -scattered, is compatible with extending the line graph with one edge and vertex to the line graph : If is a partition of edges in corresponding to a partition of vertices. Then the partition corresponds to .
Thus taking the colimit, we get for the infinite line graph (4) a bijection between partitions of edges into parts, each -scattered, and partitions of vertices into parts, each -scattered.
Recall that a subset of natural numbers is -scattered if for every in we have .
Theorem 4.1.
There is a bijection between partitions of into sets, each -scattered, and partitions of into sets, each -scattered.
By successively going from to to and so on we get:
Corollary 4.2.
There is a bijection between partitions of into parts (each set by default being -scattered) and partitions of into parts , each -scattered.
Specializing to we get the trivial fact that there is a unique partition of into parts, each -scattered. Clearly this partition is the congruence classes modulo . However specializing to , we get the quite non-trivial:
Corollary 4.3.
For each there is a bijection between partitions of into two parts and partitions of into parts , each being -scattered.
Example 4.4.
For let the partition be , the one part consisting of a single element . This corresponds to a partition of into three parts, each being -scattered. We use to indicate arithmetic progression of step size . These parts are:
It also corresponds to a partition of into four parts, each being -scattered. (Here denotes progression with step size .) These parts are:
Example 4.5.
Let again . Consider the partition where . It corresponds to the following three parts, each -scattered. We get two cases, according to whether is even or odd. When is even:
Note that in the middle part there is quite a long gap from to . When is odd:
References
- [1] Ayah Almousa, Gunnar Fløystad, and Henning Lohne, Polarizations of powers of graded maximal ideals, Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra 226 (2022), no. 5, 106924.
- [2] William YC Chen, Eva YP Deng, and Rosena RX Du, Reduction of m-regular noncrossing partitions, European Journal of Combinatorics 26 (2005), no. 2, 237–243.
- [3] Wenchang Chu and Chuanan Wei, Set partitions with restrictions, Discrete mathematics 308 (2008), no. 15, 3163–3168.
- [4] Bryce Duncan and Rhodes Peele, Bell and Stirling numbers for graphs, J. Integer Seq 12 (2009), no. 09.7.1, 1–13.
- [5] Sara Faridi, The facet ideal of a simplicial complex, Manuscripta Mathematica 109 (2002), no. 2, 159–174.
- [6] Gunnar Fløystad and Amir Mafi, Polarizations of artin monomial ideals define triangulated balls, https://arxiv.org/abs/2212.09528 (2022).
- [7] Gunnar Fløystad and Milo Orlich, Triangulations of polygons and stacked simplicial complexes: separating their Stanley–Reisner ideals, Journal of Algebraic Combinatorics (2022), 1–28.
- [8] Branko Grünbaum, Convex polytopes, second ed., Graduate Texts in Mathematics, vol. 221, Springer-Verlag, New York, 2003, Prepared and with a preface by Volker Kaibel, Victor Klee and Günter M. Ziegler.
- [9] A Hertz and H Mélot, Counting the Number of Non-Equivalent Vertex Colorings of a Graph, Les Cahiers du GERAD ISSN G-2013-82 (2013), 1–16.
- [10] Jürgen Herzog and Takayuki Hibi, Monomial ideals, Springer, 2011.
- [11] Zsófia Kereskényi-Balogh and Gábor Nyul, Stirling numbers of the second kind and Bell numbers for graphs, Australas. J Comb. 58 (2014), 264–274.
- [12] Toufik Mansour, Combinatorics of set partitions, CRC Press Boca Raton, 2013.
- [13] Augustine O Munagi, Extended set partitions with successions, European Journal of Combinatorics 29 (2008), no. 5, 1298–1308.
- [14] Winston Yang, Bell numbers and k-trees, Discrete Mathematics 156 (1996), no. 1-3, 247–252.