This paper was converted on www.awesomepapers.org from LaTeX by an anonymous user.
Want to know more? Visit the Converter page.

On the Expressive Power of the Normal Form for Branching-Time Temporal Logics

Alexander Bolotov University of Westminster
London, UKSchool of Computer Science and Engineering [email protected]
Abstract

With the emerging applications that involve complex distributed systems branching-time specifications are specifically important as they reflect dynamic and nondeterministic nature of such applications. We describe the expressive power of a simple yet powerful branching-time specification framework – branching-time normal form, which has been developed as part of clausal resolution for branching-time temporal logics. We show the encoding of Büchi Tree Automata Tree Automata in the language of the normal form, thus representing, syntactically, tree automata in a high-level way. This enables to translate given problem specifications into the normal form and apply as a verification method a deductive reasoning technique – the clausal temporal resolution.

1 Introduction

Automata theoretic methods are fundamental in study of branching-time logics, they are widely used in the investigations into the expressiveness of branching-time formalisms and their decidability, and are in the centre of the model-checking techniques [22], being widely used in the framework of formal verification. With the emerging applications that involve complex distributed systems deployed in heterogeneous environment, for example, robotics systems [21], branching-time specifications are becoming even more important. These specifications reflect the dynamic and non-deterministic nature of such applications and one can envisage the obvious need for efficient techniques to reason about them [11]. Tree structures are the underlying models for these specifications and tree automata are well established techniques to reason about tree structures, again, widely used in modern model-checking. On the other hand, it is useful to have direct methods of deductive reasoning applied to temporal specifications that enable carrying proof. Clausal temporal resolution is one of such techniques [11]. The method is based on the concept of the separated normal form initially developed for resolution based deductive verification in the linear-time framework (see full account of the method in [19] and an overview of various developments within this framework in [11]) and later extended to Computation Tree Logic CTL [3], [7], ECTL [5] and ECTL+ [4]. These branching-time logics differ in their expressiveness, with CTL allowing only a single temporal operator preceded by a path quantifier, ECTL extending CTL by allowing combinations of temporal operators that express fairness constraints and ECTL+ allowing Boolean combinations of temporal operators and ECTL fairness constraints (but not permitting their nesting). Yet, the same formalism serves as the normal form for all these logics. For simplicity, here we call this formalism 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF}. The refinement and implementation of the clausal resolution in branching-time setting is given in [23, 24].

In [8] it was shown that the normal form for linear time is as expressive as Büchi automata on infinite words [10] while [12] defined the translation from an alternating automaton to this normal form and vice versa. In this paper we consider the analogous problem, in the branching-time setup, namely we show how 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} can represent, syntactically, Büchi tree automata in a high-level way. Note that in translating a branching-time problem specification into BNF, we actually derive clauses within a fragment of Quantified Computation Tree Logic (EQCTL) [20]. In particular, formulae within BNF are existentially quantified, moreover, this quantification is external to CTL formulae themselves. Thus, clauses of the BNF satisfy the criteria of the prenex normal form ([20]), and, translating the given branching-time specification into BNF we stay within this fragment. In order to utilize the normal form as part of proof in the branching-time framework, we effectively skolemize the normal form producing temporal formulae without any quantification.

Having established this relationship between 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} and Büchi tree automata, we justify, theoretically, that 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} is applicable to a wider class of branching-time specifications, and a resolution based verification technique can be used as reasoning tool for the obtained specification. One important contribution of this paper is that 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} specifications obtained from the initial automaton give a good insight into the temporal context, as these specifications are defined with the use of the standard future time temporal operators:   (always),   (next time), {\diamondsuit} (eventually) and, additionally, path quantifiers 𝖠{\sf A} (on all future paths) and 𝖤{\sf E} (on some future path). Finally, we note that the result of this paper enables one of the core components of the resolution method - the loop searching ([6, 11]) - to be used to extract (again syntactically) hidden invariants in a wide range of complex temporal specifications.

The rest of the paper is organised as follows. In §2 main technical terms of tree structures relevant to the paper are introduced. In §3 we overview 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} outlining its syntax in §3.1 and its semantics, in §3.2, together with an example, §3.3. In §4 we define Büchi tree automata. In §5, we show how to translate these automata into 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} and establish the correctness while in §6 the reverse translation from 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} into Büchi tree automata and its correctness are given. In §7 we give an example of the syntactical representation of a small Büchi tree automaton in 𝖡𝖭𝖥\sf BNF. Finally, in §8, we provide concluding remarks and discuss future work.

2 Tree Structure Notation

In this section we introduce main concepts of tree structures that are needed for the definition of Büchi Automata and BNF.

Definition 1 (Paths and Fullpaths of a Tree)

Given a tree T=(N,E)T=(N,E) such that NN is a set of states (nodes) and EN×NE\subset N\times N is a set of edges, with the root x_0Nx_{\_}0\in N, a path π_x_i\pi_{\_}{x_{\_}i} of a tree TT is a (possibly infinite) sequence of nodes x_i,x_i+1,x_i+2x_{\_}i,x_{\_}{i+1},x_{\_}{i+2}\dots, where for each j(ij)j~{}(i\leq j), (x_j,x_j+1)E(x_{\_}j,x_{\_}{j+1})\in E. A path π_x_0\pi_{\_}{x_{\_}0} of a tree with the root x_0x_{\_}0 is called a fullpath. We will denote the set of all paths of some tree TT by Π_T\Pi_{\_}T and the set of all fullpaths by X_TX_{\_}T.

Given a tree T=(N,E)T=(N,E) the edge relation EE is called total (or connected) if each node x_iNx_{\_}i\in N belongs to some fullpath. We will concentrate on such trees where each node is connected with the root. Now the connectivity property of a tree (N,E)(N,E) can be viewed as the following requirement: for any state x_iNx_{\_}i\in N there must be a fullpath π_x_0\pi_{\_}{x_{\_}0} such that x_iπ_x_0x_{\_}i\in\pi_{\_}{x_{\_}0}, i.e. a path exists which connects this node x_ix_{\_}i with the root x_0x_{\_}0 of a tree.

Definition 2 (Prefix and Suffix of a path)

Given a path, χ_x_i\chi_{\_}{x_{\_}i} of a tree TT and a node x_jχ_x_ix_{\_}j\in\chi_{\_}{x_{\_}i}, where iji\leq j, we call a finite sub-sequence of nodes [x_i,x_j]=x_i,x_i+1,x_j[x_{\_}i,x_{\_}j]=x_{\_}i,x_{\_}{i+1},\dots x_{\_}j a prefix of a path χ_x_i\chi_{\_}{x_{\_}i} abbreviating it with Pref(χ_x_i,[x_i,x_j])Pref(\chi_{\_}{x_{\_}i},[x_{\_}i,x_{\_}j]) (or simply as [x_i,x_j][x_{\_}i,x_{\_}j] when it is clear which path this prefix belongs to) and an infinite sub-sequence of nodes x_j,x_j+1,x_j+2,x_{\_}j,x_{\_}{j+1},x_{\_}{j+2},\dots a suffix of a path χ_x_i\chi_{\_}{x_{\_}i} abbreviating it with Suf(χ_x_i,x_j)Suf(\chi_{\_}{x_{\_}i},x_{\_}j).

We will utilise the concepts of prefix and suffix in defining the closure properties below.

Closure properties of CTL models. When trees are considered as models for distributed systems, paths through a tree are viewed as computations. The natural requirements for such models would be suffix and fusion closures. Following [13], the former means that every suffix of a path is itself a path. The latter requires that a system, following the prefix of a computation γ\gamma, at any point s_jγs_{\_}j\in\gamma, is able to follow any computation π_s_j\pi_{\_}{s_{\_}j} originating from s_js_{\_}j.

Finally, we require that “if a system can follow a path arbitrarily long, then it can be followed forever” [13]. This corresponds to limit closure property, meaning that for any fullpath γ_s_0\gamma_{\_}{s_{\_}0} and any paths π_s_j,ϕ_s_k,\pi_{\_}{s_{\_}j},\phi_{\_}{s_{\_}k},\dots such that γ_s_0\gamma_{\_}{s_{\_}0} has the prefix [s_0,s_j][s_{\_}0,s_{\_}j], π_s_j\pi_{\_}{s_{\_}j} has the prefix [s_j,s_k][s_{\_}j,s_{\_}k], ϕ_s_k\phi_{\_}{s_{\_}k} has the prefix [s_k,s_l][s_{\_}k,s_{\_}l], etc, and 0<j<k<l0<j<k<l, the following holds: there exists an infinite path α_s_0\alpha_{\_}{s_{\_}0} that is a limit of the prefixes [s_0,s_j],[s_j,s_k],[s_k,s_l],[s_{\_}0,s_{\_}j],[s_{\_}j,s_{\_}k],[s_{\_}k,s_{\_}l],\dots. Closure properties, especially, limit closure, are reflected in the formulation of the 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF}, namely, in the introduction of labels for the clauses of the 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF}.

Definition 3 (Labelled tree)

Given a tree T=(N,E)T=(N,E) and a finite alphabet, Σ\Sigma, a Σ\Sigma-labelled tree is a structure (T,L)(T,L) where LL is a mapping NΣN\longrightarrow\Sigma, which assigns to each node, element of NN, some label, element of Σ\Sigma.

Definition 4 (Branching degree of a node, Branching factor of a tree structure)

The number, dd, of
immediate successors of a node xx in a tree structure is called the branching degree of xx. Thus, xk(1kd)x\cdot k~{}(1\leq k\leq d) abbreviates the kthk-th successor of xx.

Given a set D={d_1,d_2,}D=\{d_{\_}1,d_{\_}2,\dots\}, of the branching degrees of the nodes of a tree structure, the maximal d_i(1i)d_{\_}i~{}(1\leq i) is called the branching factor of this tree structure. A tree structure with its branching factor dd is called a dd-ary tree structure.

We assume that underlying tree models are of at most countable branching factor. However, following ([13], page 1011) trees with arbitrary, even uncountable, branching, ‘as far as our branching temporal logic are concerned, are indistinguishable from trees with finite, even bounded, branching’. This makes tree automata applicable in the branching-time framework. We will also use this result to justify the labelling of BNF clauses.

Definition 5 (ω\mathbf{\omega}-tree)

An ω\mathbf{\omega}-tree (N,Eω)(N,E^{\omega}) is a tree, which satisfies the following conditions.

  1. 1.

    A tree is of at most countable branching.

  2. 2.

    The relation EE is serial, i.e. every state s_is_{\_}i must have at least one successor state.

  3. 3.

    EE induces the natural ordering \leq: if (s_i,s_j)Eω(s_{\_}i,s_{\_}j)\in E^{\omega} then iji\leq j, where \leq orders the set of natural numbers ω={0,1,2,}\omega=\{0,1,2,\dots\}.

Now, following [16], given that a CTL model structure {\cal M} (see §3.2 for the definition of a model structure) has its branching factor at most dd, there exists a dd-ary tree canonical model {\cal M}^{\prime} such that for any formula AA, {\cal M} satisfies AA if, and only if, {\cal M}^{\prime} satisfies AA. Informally, a canonical model is an unwinding of an arbitrary model {\cal M} into an infinite tree TT [16]. One of the essential properties of canonical models, which we will utilise here, is that the number of successors for every state is canonicalised by dd.

3 Normal form used for the clausal resolution for CTL-type logics

Normal form BNF which we are considering, is a formalism that has been developed as part of the clausal resolution method developed initially for linear-time temporal logic [18, 19] and then defined for branching-time temporal logics, CTL [7] and its extensions, ECTL [5] and 𝖤𝖢𝖳𝖫+{\sf ECTL}^{+} [4]. As one would expect from clausal resolution, formulae of a given logic are first translated into normal form, which is a collection of clauses, to which a resolution method is applied. The idea behind the resolution procedure in temporal context is to extract for some given formula AA a set of clauses that capture three types of ‘knowledge’ about AA - what is happening at the beginning of the computation, what are the ‘steps’ of the computation, and what are the eventualities to be fulfilled during the computation.

For a formula AA of a CTL-type branching-time logic, we will abbreviate its clausal normal form as 𝖡𝖭𝖥(A){\sf BNF}(A). Note that the standard formulation of CTL-type logics is based upon classical connectives, future time temporal operators   and 𝒰\mathcal{U} (until) (which is sufficient to introduce   and {\diamondsuit}) and path quantifiers 𝖠{\sf A} and 𝖤{\sf E}. The BNF, however, is formulated using  ,   and {\diamondsuit}, and start (which is only true at the beginning of the computation) but not utilising the 𝒰\mathcal{U} operator as it is removed during the translation to the normal form based on its fixpoint definition [7].

3.1 Language of BNF

In the language for BNF we utilise

  • classical connectives: implication (\Rightarrow), negation (¬\lnot), disjunction (\vee), and conjunction (\wedge);

  • classically defined constants true (𝐓{\bf\scriptstyle T}) and false (𝐅{\bf\scriptstyle F});

  • temporal operators ‘at the initial moment of time’ (start), eventually ({\diamondsuit}), always (  ), next time (  ), and,

  • path quantifiers: on all future paths (𝖠{\sf A}) and on some future path (𝖤{\sf E}).

In the rest of the paper we will use the following notation: T abbreviates any unary 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} temporal operator and P either of path quantifiers; any formula of the type PT is called a basic 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} modality, and a literal is a proposition or its negation.

Indices. The language for indices is based on the set of terms {IND}={𝖿,𝗀,𝗁,}\{IND\}=\{{\sf f},~{}{\sf g},~{}{\sf h},\dots\}, where 𝖿,𝗀,𝗁{\sf f,~{}g,~{}h}\dots denote constants. Note that indices play essential role in the formulation of 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} as they help identifying a specific path context for given formulae. We use indices to label all formulae of 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} that contain the basic modality 𝖤 {\sf E}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\, or 𝖤{\sf E}{\diamondsuit}. Specifically, the modality 𝖤 {\sf E}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\, is associated with 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} step clauses (see below) and, thus, if 𝖤 A_𝗀{\sf E}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,A_{\_}{\sf g} is true at some current state s_is_{\_}i then AA holds at the successor state of s_is_{\_}i along the path associated with the ‘direction’ 𝗀{\sf g} - speaking informally, we only take ‘one step’ in direction gg from s_is_{\_}i. The modality 𝖤{\sf E}{\diamondsuit} is associated with evaluating eventualities over a longer period of time, and thus if 𝖤p_𝗀{\sf E}{\diamondsuit}p_{\_}{\sf g} is true at some state s_is_{\_}i then pp is true at some state s_ks_{\_}k along the path which goes from s_is_{\_}i by making at s_is_{\_}i, and every subsequent successor state, a ‘mini-step’ along the ‘direction’ 𝗀{\sf g}. This corresponds to the limit closure of the concatenation of these ‘mini-steps’ in directions 𝗀{\sf g} and hence the existence of such a path is always guaranteed.

Definition 6 (Branching Normal Form)

Given PropProp, a set of atomic propositions, and INDIND, a countable set of indices, 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} has the structure

𝖠 [_iC_i]{\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,\displaystyle{\left[\bigwedge_{\_}iC_{\_}i\right]}

where each of the clauses C_iC_{\_}i is defined as below and each α_i\alpha_{\_}i, β_j\beta_{\_}j or γ\gamma is a literal, 𝐓{\bf\scriptstyle T} or 𝐅{\bf\scriptstyle F} and 𝗂𝗇𝖽IND{\sf ind}\in IND is some index.

start_j=1kβ_jan Initial Clause_i=1lα_i𝖠 [_j=1kβ_j]an A step clause_i=1lα_i𝖤 [_j=1kβ_j]_𝗂𝗇𝖽E step clause_i=1lα_i𝖠γan A sometime clause_i=1lα_i𝖤γ_𝗂𝗇𝖽E sometime clause\begin{array}[]{rcll}\hbox{\bf start}&\Rightarrow&\displaystyle\bigvee_{\_}{j=1}^{k}\beta_{\_}j&\hbox{an~{}Initial~{}Clause}\\[6.45831pt] \displaystyle\bigwedge_{\_}{i=1}^{l}\alpha_{\_}i&\Rightarrow&{\sf A}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,\displaystyle{\left[\bigvee_{\_}{j=1}^{k}\beta_{\_}j\right]}&\hbox{an~{}{\sf A}~{}step~{}clause}\\ \displaystyle\bigwedge_{\_}{i=1}^{l}\alpha_{\_}i&\Rightarrow&{\sf E}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,\displaystyle{\left[\bigvee_{\_}{j=1}^{k}{\beta_{\_}j}\right]_{\_}{\sf ind}}&\hbox{a~{}{\sf E}~{} step~{}clause}\\[6.45831pt] \displaystyle\bigwedge_{\_}{i=1}^{l}\alpha_{\_}i&\Rightarrow&{\sf A}{\diamondsuit}\gamma&\hbox{an~{}{\sf A}~{}sometime~{}clause}\\[6.45831pt] \displaystyle\bigwedge_{\_}{i=1}^{l}\alpha_{\_}i&\Rightarrow&{\sf E}{\diamondsuit}\gamma_{\_}{\sf ind}&\hbox{a~{}{\sf E}~{}sometime~{}clause}\\ \end{array}

 

The intuition behind this formulation is that initial clauses provide the initial conditions for the computation while each of the step clauses represents a constraint upon the future behaviour of the formula, given the current conjunction of literals. Note that the 𝖠 {\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\, constraint is only utilised BNF as the one surrounding the conjunction of clauses which gives the clauses the ‘universal’ interpretation by propagating information they represent to each state along each path of the tree structure. At the same time, the 𝖤 {\sf E}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\, constraint is not utilised in the BNF, although, obviously it can be introduced based on 𝖤 α=_𝖽𝖾𝖿𝖤¬¬α{\sf E}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,\alpha=_{\_}{\sf def}{\sf E}\lnot{\diamondsuit}\lnot\alpha. Finally note that in the eventuality clauses the argument of the {\diamondsuit} operator is a literal. This requirement is due to the potential application of the clausal resolution method to the specifications written in BNF. The clausal resolution method resolves (if possible) an eventuality, l{\diamondsuit}l in the scope of a path quantifier with the loop in ll which is defined on all or some dedicated paths, see details in [3, 5].

3.2 Interpretation of BNF

For the interpretation of 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} clauses, utilising the notation of [23], we introduce an indexed tree-like model. Given INDIND is a countable set of indices, SS is a set of states, ES×SE\subseteq S\times S is a total binary relation over SS, and LL is an interpretation function S2PropS\longrightarrow 2^{Prop}, which maps a state s_iSs_{\_}i\in S to the set of atomic propositions that are true at s_is_{\_}i. Then an indexed model structure =S,R,L,𝗂𝗇𝖽,s_0{\cal M}=\langle S,R,L,{\overrightarrow{\sf ind}},s_{\_}0\rangle where s_0Ss_{\_}0\in S, and 𝗂𝗇𝖽R{\overrightarrow{\sf ind}}\subseteq R such that it is the argument of the mapping of every index 𝗂𝗇𝖽IND{\sf ind}\in IND to the successor function 𝗂𝗇𝖽{\overrightarrow{\sf ind}} such that 𝗂𝗇𝖽{\overrightarrow{\sf ind}} is a total functional relation on SS

It is easy to see that the underlying tree model above is an ω\omega-tree satisfying the conditions of Definition 5.

A state s_jSs_{\_}j\in S is an 𝗂𝗇𝖽{\sf ind}-successor state of state s_iS(s_i,s_j)𝗂𝗇𝖽s_{\_}i\in S\Leftrightarrow(s_{\_}i,s_{\_}j)\in{\overrightarrow{\sf ind}}. An infinite path χ_s_i𝗂𝗇𝖽\chi_{\_}{s_{\_}i}^{\sf ind} is an infinite sequence of states s_i,s_i+1,s_i+2,s_{\_}i,s_{\_}{i+1},s_{\_}{i+2},\dots such that for every j(ij)j~{}(i\leq j), we have that (s_j,s_j+1)𝗂𝗇𝖽(s_{\_}j,s_{\_}{j+1})\in{\overrightarrow{\sf ind}}.

Below, we define the relation ‘\models’, omitting cases for Booleans, 𝐓{\bf\scriptstyle T} and 𝐅{\bf\scriptstyle F}. Also recall that the basic modality 𝖤 {\sf E}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\, is not used in the BNF while 𝖠 {\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\, only appears as an outer modality preceeding the conjunction of the BNF clauses.

,s_istarti=0,s_i𝖠 Bforeach𝗂𝗇𝖽INDandeachsS,if(s_i,s)𝗂𝗇𝖽then,sB,s_i𝖤 B_𝗂𝗇𝖽thereexistssS,suchthat(s_i,s)𝗂𝗇𝖽and,sB,s_i𝖠 Bforeachχ_s_iands_jχ_s_i,𝗂𝖿(ij)then,s_jB,s_i𝖠Bforeachχ_s_i,thereexistss_jS,suchthat(ij)and,s_jB,s_i𝖤B_𝗂𝗇𝖽thereexistχ_s_i𝗂𝗇𝖽ands_jχ_s_i𝗂𝗇𝖽,suchthatij,s_jB\begin{array}[]{rclll}\langle{\cal M},s_{\_}i\rangle&\models&\hbox{\bf start}&\Leftrightarrow&i=0\\ \langle{\cal M},s_{\_}i\rangle&\models&{\sf A}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,B&\Leftrightarrow&for~{}each~{}{\sf ind}\in IND~{}and~{}each~{}s^{\prime}\in S,if~{}(s_{\_}i,s^{\prime})\in\overrightarrow{\sf ind}~{}then~{}\langle{\cal M},s^{\prime}\rangle\models B\\ \langle{\cal M},s_{\_}i\rangle&\models&{\sf E}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,B_{\_}{\sf ind}&\Leftrightarrow&there~{}exists~{}s^{\prime}\in S,such~{}that~{}(s_{\_}i,s^{\prime})\in{\overrightarrow{\sf ind}}~{}and~{}\langle{\cal M},s^{\prime}\rangle\models B\\ \langle{\cal M},s_{\_}i\rangle&\models&{\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,B&\Leftrightarrow&for~{}each~{}\chi_{\_}{s_{\_}i}and~{}s_{\_}j\in\chi_{\_}{s_{\_}i},~{}{\sf if}~{}(i\leq j)~{}then~{}\langle{\cal M},s_{\_}j\rangle\models B\\ \langle{\cal M},s_{\_}i\rangle&\models&{\sf A}{\diamondsuit}B&\Leftrightarrow&for~{}each~{}\chi_{\_}{s_{\_}i},there~{}exists~{}s_{\_}j\in S,~{}such~{}that~{}(i\leq j)and~{}\langle{\cal M},s_{\_}j\rangle\models B\\ \langle{\cal M},s_{\_}i\rangle&\models&{\sf E}{\diamondsuit}B_{\_}{\sf ind}&\Leftrightarrow&~{}there~{}exist~{}\chi_{\_}{s_{\_}i}^{\sf ind}and~{}s_{\_}j\in\chi_{\_}{s_{\_}i}^{\sf ind},~{}such~{}that~{}i\leq j~{}\langle{\cal M},s_{\_}j\rangle\models B\\ \end{array}

Definition 1 (Satisfiability, Validity).

If 𝒞\cal C is in 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} then 𝒞\cal C is satisfiable if, and only if, there exists a model {\cal M} such that ,s_0𝒞\langle{\cal M},s_{\_}0\rangle\models\cal C. 𝒞\cal C is valid if, and only if, it is satisfied in every possible model.

3.3 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} examples.

Here we give an example of the normal form and informal interpretation. Noting that an initial 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} clause, startF\hbox{\bf start}\Rightarrow F, is understood as “FF is satisfied at the initial state of some model {\cal M}”and any other 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} clause is interpreted taking also into account that it occurs in the scope of 𝖠 {\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\, let us consider a clause 𝖠 (x𝖤 q_𝗂𝗇𝖽){\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,(x\Rightarrow{\sf E}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,q_{\_}{\sf ind}). It is understood as “for any fullpath χ\chi and any state s_iχ(0i)s_{\_}i\in\chi~{}(0\leq i), if xx is satisfied at a state s_is_{\_}i then qq must be satisfied at the moment, next to s_is_{\_}i, along some path associated with 𝗂𝗇𝖽{\sf ind} which departs from s_is_{\_}i”.

The clause 𝖠 (x𝖤p_𝗂𝗇𝖽){\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,(x\Rightarrow{\sf E}{\diamondsuit}p_{\_}{\sf ind}) has the following meaning “for any fullpath χ\chi and any state s_iχ(0i)s_{\_}i\in\chi~{}(0\leq i), if xx is satisfied at a state s_is_{\_}i then pp must be satisfied at some state, say s_j(ij)s_{\_}j~{}(i\leq j), along some path α_s_i\alpha_{\_}{s_{\_}i} associated with the limit closure111Observe that limit closure has the properties of the reflexive transitive closure. of 𝗂𝗇𝖽{\sf ind} which departs from s_is_{\_}i’.

4 Büchi Tree automata

Definition 4.1.

A Büchi automaton, \cal B, on an infinite tree, TT, is a tuple =Σ,D,S,δ,F_0,F_B{\cal B}=\langle\Sigma,~{}D,~{}S,\delta,F_{\_}0,~{}F_{\_}B\rangle where: Σ\Sigma is a finite alphabet; DD is a finite set of branching degrees; S={s_0,s_1,s_k}S=\{s_{\_}0,s_{\_}1,\dots s_{\_}k\} is a finite set of states; F_0SF_{\_}0\subseteq S is a set of initial states; δ\delta is a non-deterministic transition function satisfying; δ(s,σ,d)Sd\delta(s,\sigma,d)\subseteq S^{d}, for every sS,σΣs\in S,\sigma\in\Sigma and dDd\in D, and F_BSF_{\_}B\subseteq S is a set of accepting states.

The transition function δ(s,σ,d)\delta(s,\sigma,d) is the set of all tuples of states to which the automaton may evolve from state sSs\in S of the arity dDd\in D when it reads the symbol σΣ\sigma\in\Sigma.

A run, τ_:TS\tau_{\_}{\cal B}:T\longrightarrow S, of a Büchi tree automaton {\cal B} over the input Σ\Sigma-labelled tree (T,L)(T,L) is an SS labelled tree such that the root is labelled by a member of F_0F_{\_}0 and the transitions conform with the transition function δ\delta. Namely, visiting a state s_iSs_{\_}i\in S with the branching degree dd and reading σΣ\sigma\in\Sigma, an automaton makes a non-deterministic choice of a tuple s_0,s_dδ(s,σ,d)s_{\_}0,\dots s_{\_}d\in\delta(s,\sigma,d), 1dk1\leq d\leq k, makes dd copies of itself and moves to the node s_is_j(1jd)s_{\_}i\cdot s_{\_}j~{}(1\leq j\leq d).

A run, τ_\tau_{\_}{\cal B}, is successful if for every infinite branch of τ_\tau_{\_}{\cal B}, there is an accepting state sF_Bs\in F_{\_}B that occurs infinitely often in this branch. An automaton {\cal B} accepts the infinite tree TT (in other terms, the language recognised by {\cal B} is not empty) if it has a successful run τ_\tau_{\_}{\cal B}.

5 From Büchi Tree automata to 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF}

Here, given a Büchi tree automaton {\cal B}, we construct its characteristic formula, 𝖡𝖭𝖥_{\sf BNF}_{\_}{\cal B}, as a set of 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} clauses, following the main stages similar to those in [8]: encoding of the set of the initial states, representing the run of the automaton, the labelling, and the acceptance condition.

Let =Σ,D,S,δ,F_0,F_B{\cal B}=\langle\Sigma,~{}D,~{}S,\delta,F_{\_}0,~{}F_{\_}B\rangle be a Büchi tree automaton with the states labelled as follows. For every proposition pPropp\in Prop, for σΣ\sigma\in\Sigma, given s_is_kδ(s_i,σ,d)s_{\_}i\cdot s_{\_}k\in\delta(s_{\_}i,\sigma,d) (for 1kd1\leq k\leq d), if pσp\in\sigma then pL(s_is_k)p\in L(s_{\_}i\cdot s_{\_}k) else if pσp\not\in\sigma then ¬pL(s_is_k)\lnot p\in L(s_{\_}i\cdot s_{\_}k). In our translation we will explicitly encode this labelling. Now, we introduce formulae (1)–(4), which represent the main stages of the translation. Note that to simplify reading we will omit writing the outer 𝖠 {\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,, and will write a set of 𝖡𝖭𝖥_{\sf BNF}_{\_}{\cal B} clauses rather than their conjunction; in some cases we will alos give the formulation of the components of the translation not in the exact form of 𝖡𝖭𝖥_{\sf BNF}_{\_}{\cal B} clauses to make the idea behind the translation more explicit. Each of these cases, where we need further simple manipulations to obtain the required BNF form, will be marked with {}\{\star\}.

Let q_0,,q_lq_{\_}0,\dots,q_{\_}l be new propositions of our 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} language such that q_i(0il)q_{\_}i~{}(0\leq i\leq l) encodes the state s_iSs_{\_}i\in S of the automaton. Given that q_0,,q_m,(0ml)q_{\_}0,\dots,q_{\_}m,~{}(0\leq m\leq l) encode the initial states, F_0F_{\_}0, of the automaton, we specify F_0F_{\_}0 by the following 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF}:

𝖡𝖭𝖥_init_:(1.1)startq_0q_m(1.2)start¬q_i_ij(¬q_j){}{{\sf BNF}}_{\_}{init_{\_}{\cal B}}:\begin{array}[t]{rrcl}(\ref{init-snf-direct-translation}.1)&\hbox{\bf start}&\Rightarrow&q_{\_}0\vee\dots\vee q_{\_}m\\ (\ref{init-snf-direct-translation}.2)&\hbox{\bf start}&\Rightarrow&\lnot q_{\_}i\vee\displaystyle\bigwedge_{\_}{i\not=j}(\lnot{q_{\_}j})\quad\{\star\}\\ \end{array} (1)

where 0im,0jm0\leq i\leq m,~{}0\leq j\leq m. From (1) it follows that the automaton can be at only one initial state at the first moment of time. Note that constraint (1.2) of the 𝖡𝖭𝖥_init_{\sf BNF}_{\_}{init_{\_}{\cal B}} marked with ‘\star’ should be further translated to the form required by the BNF.

Next, the transition function of the automaton is represented as follows.

Given the automaton {\cal B} with the set of branching degrees D={1,,d}D=\{1,\dots,d\}, we associate with each element of the latter a set of new indices IND=ind_1,ind_dIND=ind_{\_}1,\dots ind_{\_}d used to label 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} clauses. Thus, when the automaton makes its dd copies visiting a state s_iSs_{\_}i\in S, with the branching factor dd, with each such successor node s_ns_{\_}n of s_is_{\_}i we associate an index ind_j,1jdind_{\_}j,~{}1\leq j\leq d.

𝖡𝖭𝖥_tran_:(2.1)q_i𝖤 q_n_ind_j\begin{array}[t]{ll}{{\sf BNF}}_{\_}{tran_{\_}{\cal B}}:&\quad(\ref{run-snf-direct-translation}.1)q_{\_}i\Rightarrow{\sf E}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,{q_{\_}n}_{\_}{ind_{\_}j}\\ \end{array} (2)

Thus each of dd clauses in (2) reflects a successor node of s_is_{\_}i along the path labeled by ind_jind_{\_}j. Note that unlike Büchi word automaton which can only be at one state at any particular time, a tree automaton makes copies choosing a corresponding tuple of states. This is exactly what we have represented above. Thus, for each q_iq_{\_}i of branching degree dd there are exactly dd clauses of the form (2).

Next, we represent the unique labelling of the states of the automaton by the following set of clauses, constructed for every q_iq_{\_}i and every x_iL(s_i)x_{\_}i\in L(s_{\_}i).

BNF_lab_:(3.1)start¬q_i[(_x_iL(s_i)x_i)(_x_jL(s_i)¬x_j)]{}(3.2)𝐓𝖠 (¬q_iv)((3.3)v[(_x_iL(s_i)x_i)(_x_jL(s_i)¬x_j)]{}\begin{array}[t]{ll}{BNF}_{\_}{lab_{\_}{\cal B}}:&\begin{array}[t]{rlrclr}&(\ref{labels-snf-direct-translation}.1)&\hbox{\bf start}&\Rightarrow&\lnot q_{\_}i\vee\displaystyle{\left[\left(\bigwedge_{\_}{x_{\_}i\in L(s_{\_}i)}x_{\_}i\right)\wedge\left(\bigwedge_{\_}{x_{\_}j\not\in L(s_{\_}i)}\lnot x_{\_}j\right)\right]}&\{\star\}\\ \\ &(\ref{labels-snf-direct-translation}.2)&{\bf\scriptstyle T}&\Rightarrow&{\sf A}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,(\lnot q_{\_}i\vee v)\\ \\ &((\ref{labels-snf-direct-translation}.3)&v&\Rightarrow&\displaystyle{\left[\left(\bigwedge_{\_}{x_{\_}i\in L(s_{\_}i)}x_{\_}i\right)\wedge\left(\bigwedge_{\_}{x_{\_}j\not\in L(s_{\_}i)}\lnot x_{\_}j\right)\right]}&\{\star\}\end{array}\end{array} (3)

The Büchi acceptance condition is given by the following set of 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} clauses constructred for each ind_iINDind_{\_}i\in IND.

BNF_acc_:(4.1)starty(4.2)y𝖠 u{}(4.3)u𝖤l_ind_i(4.4)l𝖤 w_ind)i(4.5)w𝖤l_ind)i(4.6)start¬lq_nq_r(4.7)𝐓𝖠 (¬lq_nq_r)\begin{array}[t]{ll}{BNF}_{\_}{acc_{\_}{\cal B}}:&\begin{array}[t]{rlrcl}&(\ref{acceptance-formula-snf-direct}.1)&\hbox{\bf start}&\Rightarrow&y\\ &(\ref{acceptance-formula-snf-direct}.2)&y&\Rightarrow&{\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,u\quad\quad\{\star\}\\ &(\ref{acceptance-formula-snf-direct}.3)&u&\Rightarrow&{\sf E}{\diamondsuit}l_{\_}{ind_{\_}i}\\ &(\ref{acceptance-formula-snf-direct}.4)&l&\Rightarrow&{\sf E}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,w_{\_}{ind)i}\\ &(\ref{acceptance-formula-snf-direct}.5)&w&\Rightarrow&{\sf E}{\diamondsuit}l_{\_}{ind)i}\\ &(\ref{acceptance-formula-snf-direct}.6)&\hbox{\bf start}&\Rightarrow&\lnot l\vee q_{\_}n\vee\dots\vee q_{\_}r\\ &(\ref{acceptance-formula-snf-direct}.7)&{\bf\scriptstyle T}&\Rightarrow&{\sf A}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,(\lnot l\vee q_{\_}n\vee\dots\vee q_{\_}r)\\ \end{array}\end{array} (4)

where

  • q_nq_rq_{\_}n\dots q_{\_}r encode the accepting states of the automaton and y,w,ly,~{}w,~{}l and zz are new propositions. This condition ensures that every path of the run hits an accepting state from F_BF_{\_}B infinitely often. The use of the indices guarantees that we are staying in the ‘context of a chosen path’ when verifying the acceptance condition.

  • Constraint 2 of the BNF_acc_{BNF}_{\_}{acc_{\_}{\cal B}} marked with ‘\star’ is the abbreviation of the ‘loop’ in uu. This loop in the BNF is represented by the following two clauses (𝗂)y(zu),(𝗂𝗂)z𝖠 (uz)({\sf i})~{}y\Rightarrow(z\wedge u),({\sf ii})~{}z\Rightarrow{\sf A}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,(u\wedge z) (recall that all clauses are in the scope of the 𝖠 {\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,): from (𝗂)({\sf i}) we know that uu is true at the state where yy is true, and also that zz is also true at that state, while from (𝗂𝗂)({\sf ii}) we derive that the every successor state should satisfy both uu and zz. This second clause (𝗂)({\sf i}) ensures the recurrent presence of zz in every subsequent state along every path, which, in turn, ensures that each subsequent state along every path also satisfies uu.

Finally, let 𝖡𝖭𝖥_init_{\sf BNF}_{\_}{init_{\_}{\cal B}}^{\prime},  𝖡𝖭𝖥_tran_{\sf BNF}_{\_}{tran_{\_}{\cal B}}^{\prime}𝖡𝖭𝖥_lab_{\sf BNF}_{\_}{lab_{\_}{\cal B}} and 𝖡𝖭𝖥_acc_B{\sf BNF}_{\_}{acc^{B}_{\_}{\cal B}} be obtained from 𝖡𝖭𝖥_init_{\sf BNF}_{\_}{init_{\_}{\cal B}}, 𝖡𝖭𝖥_tran_{\sf BNF}_{\_}{tran_{\_}{\cal B}},
  𝖡𝖭𝖥_lab_{\sf BNF}_{\_}{lab_{\_}{\cal B}} and 𝖡𝖭𝖥_acc_B{\sf BNF}_{\_}{acc^{B}_{\_}{\cal B}}, respectively, by translating their components into the required form of 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} clauses. Now, a Büchi tree automaton \cal B is characterized by the following 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} expression known as a characteristic clause set and abbreviated by 𝖡𝖭𝖥_{\sf BNF}_{\_}{\cal B}:

𝖡𝖭𝖥_init_𝖡𝖭𝖥_tran_𝖡𝖭𝖥_lab_𝖡𝖭𝖥_acc_B{\sf BNF}_{\_}{{init_{\_}{\cal B}}}^{\prime}\wedge{\sf BNF}_{\_}{{tran_{\_}{\cal B}}}^{\prime}\wedge{\sf BNF}_{\_}{{lab_{\_}{\cal B}}}\wedge{\sf BNF}_{\_}{{acc^{B}_{\_}{\cal B}}}^{\prime} (5)

5.1 Correctness

Theorem 5.1.

Given a Büchi tree automaton {\cal B}, we can construct a characteristic clause set, 𝖡𝖭𝖥_{\sf BNF}_{\_}{\cal B}, such that {\cal B} has an accepting run, τ_\tau_{\_}{\cal B} (over an infinite tree TT), if and only if, 𝖡𝖭𝖥_{\sf BNF}_{\_}{\cal B} is satisfiable.

Proof.

(I) Left to right direction. The proof effectively follows the labelling chosen for 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} clauses described above. Given a Büchi tree automaton, =Σ,D,S,δ,F_0,F_B{\cal B}=\langle\Sigma,~{}D,~{}S,\delta,F_{\_}0,~{}F_{\_}B\rangle, on an infinite tree, recall that its accepting run τ_\tau_{\_}{\cal B} is an SS-labelled tree (T,L)(T,L) such that its root is labelled by a member of F_0F_{\_}0 and the transitions conform with the transition function δ\delta.

STEP 1. First, let |IND|=d|IND|=d, where dDd\in D is the largest branching factor, and let the states of SS be obtained from the corresponding nodes of TT provided the states of a Büchi automaton are labelled as above, namely, such that for every proposition pPropp\in Prop, for σΣ\sigma\in\Sigma, given s_is_kδ(s_i,σ,d)s_{\_}i\cdot s_{\_}k\in\delta(s_{\_}i,\sigma,d) (for 1kd1\leq k\leq d), if pσp\in\sigma then pL(s_is_k)p\in L(s_{\_}i\cdot s_{\_}k) else if pσp\not\in\sigma then ¬pL(s_is_k)\lnot p\in L(s_{\_}i\cdot s_{\_}k). This labelling guarantees that the mapping 𝗂𝗇𝖽\overrightarrow{\sf ind} establishes the desired order over the states of SS so every state xkx\cdot k with the degree dd (1kd1\leq k\leq d) of the tree model, is identified with the SS-label of the node xkx\cdot k of the run τ_𝒜\tau_{\_}{\cal A}. Thus, the way how the labelling chosen for the 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} clauses guarantees that this tree becomes an underlying tree structure for the model =S,R,L,𝗂𝗇𝖽,s_0{\cal M}=\langle S,R,L,{\overrightarrow{\sf ind}},s_{\_}0\rangle such that for every p_kL(xk)p_{\_}k\in L(x\cdot k), (,sk)p_k({\cal M},s\cdot k)\models p_{\_}k.

STEP 2. Let a model =S,R,L,𝗂𝗇𝖽,s_0{\cal M}^{\prime}=\langle S^{\prime},R,L^{\prime},{\overrightarrow{\sf ind}},s_{\_}0^{\prime}\rangle be the same as {\cal M} except for the interpretation of the new propositions q_0,q_a,q_b,q_n,q_r,y,l,u,v,wq_{\_}0,q_{\_}a,\dots q_{\_}b,q_{\_}n,q_{\_}r,y,l,u,v,w and z_1z_mz_{\_}1\dots z_{\_}m which we chose to satisfy at the appropriate states of SS^{\prime}. For example, ,s_0y\langle{\cal M}^{\prime},s_{\_}0\rangle\models y and for every s_ns_0s_{\_}n\not=s_{\_}0, ,s_n⊧̸y\langle{\cal M}^{\prime},s_{\_}n\rangle\not\models y. Updating this way the model {\cal M} into {\cal M}^{\prime} we guarantee that each component of the characteristic clause set is satisfied in {\cal M^{\prime}}

(II). Right to left direction. We prove this by contradiction, i.e. assuming that the given Büchi tree automaton,

=Σ,D,S,δ,F_0,F_B{\cal B}=\langle\Sigma,~{}D,~{}S,\delta,F_{\_}0,~{}F_{\_}B\rangle

on an infinite tree, does not have an accepting run, we show that we cannot build a model for the characteristic clause set, 𝖡𝖭𝖥_{\sf BNF}_{\_}{\cal B}, for {\cal B}. The emptiness of the automaton would mean that the acceptance condition is violated. Thus, as there is no succefull run of the automaton, it should have an infinite branch χ\chi, such that there is no accepting state s_iF_Bs_{\_}i\in F_{\_}B which occurs in χ{\chi} infinitely often. According to the construction of the intermediate model structure for every p_kL(xk)p_{\_}k\in L(x\cdot k), (,sk)p_k({\cal M},s\cdot k)\models p_{\_}k. Any model =T,,I{\cal M}^{\prime}=\langle T^{\prime},\leq,I^{\prime}\rangle which agrees with {\cal M} everywhere except for the interpretation of the new propositions appeared in the characteristic clause set, does not satisfy the latter. Indeed, since q_n,,q_rq_{\_}n,\dots,q_{\_}r are labels of the accepting states, and none of the accepting states occurs in χ\chi infinitely often, for every q_j(njr)q_{\_}j~{}(n\leq j\leq r), for any {\cal M}^{\prime} we have that ¬q_j\lnot q_{\_}j becomes eventually always true along χ\chi, and hence, in {\cal M}^{\prime} the conjunction ¬q_n¬q_r\lnot q_{\_}n\wedge\dots\wedge\lnot q_{\_}r becomes always true from some point on along this path χ\chi. This contradicts the satisfiability conditions for 𝖡𝖭𝖥_{\sf BNF}_{\_}{{{\cal B}}}^{\prime}: because the conjunction ¬q_n¬q_r\lnot q_{\_}n\wedge\dots\wedge\lnot q_{\_}r becomes always true from some point on, say s_mSs_{\_}m\in S along χ\chi, given also (4.6) and (4.7) we must have a loop in ¬l\lnot l, from s_ms_{\_}m, i.e.  ¬l\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,\lnot l becomes true along χ\chi from s_ms_{\_}m. As (4.3) and (4.5) are constructed for each ind_iINDind_{\_}i\in IND, we would have a contradiction between this loop in ¬l\lnot l along χ\chi and the request to fulfil the eventuality ll along this path.

 

6 From 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} to Büchi Tree automata

In this section we show how to effectively construct a Büchi Tree automaton from a given set 𝒞{\cal C} of 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} clauses. First, let us distinguish among 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} clauses the initial clauses and the global (step and sometime) clauses. The ideology is as follows. First we apply the augmentation technique developed for the clausal resolution for CTL [3] deriving 𝒞_Aug{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug} an augmented 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF}. Then we show how to construct a model for 𝒞_Aug{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug}. This technique involves a construction of a tableau as a labelled finite directed graph. The states of the graph are labelled by the sets of subformulae of 𝒞_Aug{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug}. Let Prop(𝒞_Aug)Prop({\cal C}_{\_}{Aug}) be a set of all (different) propositions that occur within the clauses of 𝒞_Aug{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug}. The important features of the underlying transition function for the construction of the tableau is that the formula 𝖠 ϕ{\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,\phi, where ϕ\phi is a conjunction of all global clauses of 𝒞_Aug{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug}, occurs within each state. Thus, global clauses play the role of a guide for the transitions. A transition from a state s_is_{\_}i to a state s_js_{\_}j is provided if a label for s_js_{\_}j is consistent.

Once a tableau 𝒢_𝒞_Aug{\cal G}_{\_}{{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug}} is constructed, labels of some states might contain formulae of the type Pl\hbox{\rm\bf P}{\diamondsuit}l. Thus, we check if such an eventuality is satisfied. During this procedure we delete those states (and their successors) of a graph 𝒢_𝒞_Aug{\cal G}_{\_}{{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug}} which contain unsatisfied eventualities. As some states of a graph now might be without any successor, we will delete such states. The resulting graph, {\cal R}, is called a reduced tableau.

It has been shown that the set of 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} clauses is unsatisfiable, if, and only if, its reduced tableau is empty [3].

Definition 6.1 (Augmentation).

Given a set of 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} clauses, 𝒞{\cal C}, we construct an augmented set 𝒞_Aug{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug} as follows.

  1. 1.

    Create a list {EVEN}=𝖤l_1,𝖤l_2,,\{EVEN\}={\sf E}{\diamondsuit}l_{\_}1,{\sf E}{\diamondsuit}l_{\_}2,\dots, 𝖤l_n,𝖠l_n+1,𝖠l_n+2,,𝖠l_m(0nm)\dots{\sf E}{\diamondsuit}{l_{\_}n},{\sf A}{\diamondsuit}{l_{\_}{n+1}},{\sf A}{\diamondsuit}{l_{\_}{n+2}},\dots,{\sf A}{\diamondsuit}l_{\_}{m}~{}(0\leq n\leq m) of all different eventualities contained in 𝒞{\cal C}.

  2. 2.

    To keep track of the eventualities, create a list W=w_1,w_2,,w_mW=w_{\_}1,w_{\_}2,\dots,w_{\_}m of new propositions (that do not occur within clauses of 𝒞{\cal C}) such that each w_iWw_{\_}i\in W is associated with the ii-th eventuality within EVENEVEN.

  3. 3.

    For every sometime clause CPl_i_𝗂𝗇𝖽_𝗂C\Rightarrow\hbox{\rm\bf P}{\diamondsuit}{l_{\_}i}_{\_}{\sf ind_{\_}i}, to guarantee the correspondence between w_iw_{\_}i and l_il_{\_}i, add the corresponding set of formulae, defined below.

    • 3a

      If Pl_i=𝖠l_i\hbox{\rm\bf P}{\diamondsuit}l_{\_}i={\sf A}{\diamondsuit}l_{\_}i, then add to the set of 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} clauses 𝒞{\cal C}, the following formulae:

      start¬Cl_iw_iw_i𝖠 (l_iw_i)𝐓𝖠 (¬Cl_iw_i).\begin{array}[]{rcl}\hbox{\bf start}&\Rightarrow&\lnot C\vee l_{\_}i\vee w_{\_}i\\ w_{\_}i&\Rightarrow&{\sf A}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,(l_{\_}i\vee w_{\_}i)\\ {\bf\scriptstyle T}&\Rightarrow&{\sf A}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,(\lnot C\vee l_{\_}i\vee w_{\_}i).\end{array} (6)
    • 3b

      If Pl_i=𝖤l_i_𝗂𝗇𝖽\hbox{\rm\bf P}{\diamondsuit}l_{\_}i={\sf E}{\diamondsuit}{l_{\_}i}_{\_}{\sf ind}, then add to the set of 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} clauses 𝒞{\cal C}, the following formulae:

      start¬Cl_iw_iw_i𝖤 (l_iw_i)_𝗂𝗇𝖽𝐓𝖤 (¬Cl_iw_i)_𝗂𝗇𝖽\begin{array}[]{rcl}\hbox{\bf start}&\Rightarrow&\lnot C\vee l_{\_}i\vee w_{\_}i\\ w_{\_}i&\Rightarrow&{\sf E}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,(l_{\_}i\vee w_{\_}i)_{\_}{\sf ind}\\ {\bf\scriptstyle T}&\Rightarrow&{\sf E}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,(\lnot C\vee l_{\_}i\vee w_{\_}i)_{\_}{\sf ind}\end{array} (7)

Let 𝒞_Aug{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug} be an augmented set of 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} clauses. Abbreviating by InIn the conjunction of the right hand sides of the initial clauses of 𝒞_Aug{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug} and by ϕ\phi the conjunction of its step and eventuality clauses, we can represent a set, 𝒞_Aug{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug} as a formula In𝖠 ϕIn\wedge{\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,\phi. It is easy to show from the BNF semantics that the following holds: ,s_0\langle{\cal M},s_{\_}0\rangle\models 𝒞\cal C ,s_0In𝖠 ϕ\Leftrightarrow\langle{\cal M},s_{\_}0\rangle\models In\wedge{\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,\phi.

Let an elementary formula be either a literal, or has its main connective as P  . Each non-elementary formula is further classified as either a conjunctive, α\alpha-formula, or a disjunctive, β\beta-formula.

A basic 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} modality now is qualified according to its fixpoint definition (in the equations below μ\mu and ν\nu stand for ‘minimal fixpoint’ and ‘maximal fixpoint’ operators, respectively)

𝖠 φ=νρ(φ𝖠 ρ)𝖤φ=μρ(φ𝖤 ρ)𝖠φ=μρ(φ𝖠 ρ)\begin{array}[]{l}{\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,\varphi=\nu\rho(\varphi\wedge{\sf A}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,\rho)\\ {\sf E}{\diamondsuit}\varphi=\mu\rho(\varphi\vee{\sf E}\!\raisebox{-1.03331pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,\rho)\\ {\sf A}{\diamondsuit}\varphi=\mu\rho(\varphi\vee{\sf A}\!\raisebox{-1.03331pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,\rho)\end{array} (8)

The only 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} modality that occurs within 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} clauses as a maximal fixpoint is 𝖠 ϕ{\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,\phi and in our representation of a set of 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} clauses as In𝖠 ϕIn\wedge{\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,\phi, it has the only occurrence as the main connective in 𝖠 ϕ{\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,\phi, hence, the following α\alpha-expansion rules will be appropriate:

αα_1α_2BCBC𝖠 BB𝖠 𝖠 B¬(BC)¬B¬C\begin{array}[]{l|l|l}\alpha&\alpha_{\_}1&\alpha_{\_}2\\ \hline\cr B\wedge C&B&C\\ {\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,B&B&{\sf A}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,{\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,B\\ \lnot(B\vee C)&\lnot B&\lnot C\\ \end{array} (9)

𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} modalities understood as a minimal fixpoints are 𝖠ϕ{\sf A}{\diamondsuit}\phi and 𝖤ϕ{\sf E}{\diamondsuit}\phi, hence, the following β\beta-expansion rules will be appropriate:

ββ_1β_2BC¬BCBCBC𝖠BB𝖠 𝖠B𝖤B_𝗂𝗇𝖽B𝖤 𝖤B_𝗂𝗇𝖽\begin{array}[]{l|l|l}\beta&\beta_{\_}1&\beta_{\_}2\\ \hline\cr B\Rightarrow C&\lnot B&C\\ B\vee C&B&C\\ {\sf A}{\diamondsuit}B&B&{\sf A}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,{\sf A}{\diamondsuit}B\\ {\sf E}{\diamondsuit}B_{\_}{\sf ind}&B&{\sf E}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,{\sf E}{\diamondsuit}B_{\_}{\sf ind}\\ \end{array} (10)

Here the last two constraints must be further transformed into the appropriate structure of 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} clauses, however, the current representation is preferable as it illustrates the intuition. Let Even_𝒞_AugEven_{\_}{{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug}} be a list of eventualities as defined in Definition 6.1 and let Prop_𝒞_AugProp_{\_}{{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug}} be a set of all (different) propositions that occur within the clauses of 𝒞_Aug{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug}. By an evaluation of a proposition p_iProp_𝒞_Augp_{\_}i\in Prop_{\_}{{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug}} we understand the function Prop_𝒞_Aug0,1Prop_{\_}{{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug}}\longrightarrow{0,1}. Now, let Val(Prop_𝒞_Aug)Val(Prop_{\_}{{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug}}) be a set of all possible evaluations of the elements of the Prop_𝒞_AugProp_{\_}{{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug}}. Finally, let D=𝗂𝗇𝖽_𝟣,𝗂𝗇𝖽_𝟤𝗂𝗇𝖽_𝗄D={\sf ind_{\_}1},{\sf ind_{\_}2}\dots{\sf ind_{\_}k} be a list of all different indices not of the form ind which occur in 𝒞{\cal C}.

We adapt the notion of the generalized Fischer-Ladner closure [17] introduced for CTL formulae in [14] for our case of 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF}.

Definition 6.2 (Generalized Fischer-Ladner closure for 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF}).

Let 𝒞{\cal C} be a set of 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} clauses, let In𝖠 ϕIn\wedge{\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,\phi be its equivalent formula, where ‘InIn’ abbreviates the conjunction of the right hand sides of the initial clauses of 𝒞{\cal C} and ϕ\phi abbreviates the conjunction of the global clauses within 𝒞{\cal C}. Then the least set of formulae which contains 𝒞{\cal C} and satisfies the conditions below is the generalised Fischer-Ladner closure of 𝒞{\cal C}, abbreviated by GFL(𝒞)GFL({\cal C}).

    • (GFL1)

      In𝖠 ϕIn\wedge{\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,\phi is an element of GFL(𝒞)GFL({\cal C}).

    • (GFL2)

      If BB is an element of GFL(𝒞)GFL({\cal C}) then any subformula of BB is an element of GFL(𝒞)GFL({\cal C}).

    • (GFL3)

      If 𝖠 BGFL(𝒞){\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,B\in GFL({\cal C}) then 𝖠 𝖠 BGFL(𝒞)){\sf A}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,{\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,B\in GFL({\cal C})).

    • (GFL4)

      If 𝖤B_𝗂𝗇𝖽GFL(𝒞){\sf E}{\diamondsuit}B_{\_}{\sf ind}\in GFL({\cal C}) then 𝖤 𝖤B_𝗂𝗇𝖽GFL(𝒞){\sf E}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,{\sf E}{\diamondsuit}B_{\_}{\sf ind}\in GFL({\cal C}).

    • (GFL5)

      If 𝖠BGFL(G){\sf A}{\diamondsuit}B\in GFL(G) then 𝖠 𝖠BGFL(𝒞){\sf A}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,{\sf A}{\diamondsuit}B\in GFL({\cal C}).

    • (GFL6)

      If BGFL(G)B\in GFL(G) and BB is not of the form ¬C\lnot C then ¬BGFL(𝒞))\lnot B\in GFL({\cal C})).

Now given a set of 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} clauses represented by In𝖠 ϕIn\wedge{\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,\phi, we construct a labelled finite graph 𝒢{\cal G} incrementally as follows

  • 1.

    The initial state is labelled by In𝖠 ϕIn\wedge{\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,\phi.

  • 2.

    Inductively assume that a graph has been constructed with nodes labelled by the subsets of
    GFL(In𝖠 ϕ)GFL(In\wedge{\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,\phi), where some formulae during such construction are marked.

    Note: when providing the transitions from a state nn if nodes t_1t_{\_}1 and t_2t_{\_}2 have the same label and the same marked formulae, they are identified, and we delete one of them, say t_2t_{\_}2, drawing an edge to t_1t_{\_}1. Also, if a transition leads to a node which does not satisfy the propositional consistency criteria, we delete this node.

    Given a node nn with the label Γ\Gamma, choose an unmarked formula, say BB, and apply an appropriate expansion rule as follows:

    • 2a.

      If BB is an α\alpha-formula, then create a successor of nn labelled by
      Γ{α_1,α_2}\Gamma\cup\{\alpha_{\_}1,\alpha_{\_}2\} and mark BB in the label.

    • 2b.

      If BB is a β\beta-formula, then create two successors of nn and label one of them by Γ{β_1}\Gamma\cup\{\beta_{\_}1\} while another one by Γ{β_2}\Gamma\cup\{\beta_{\_}2\} and mark BB in the label.

  • 3.

    If all non-elementary formulae within a node are marked, such a node is called a state. Let ss, be a state whose label contains the following next-time formulae:

    𝖠 B_1𝖠 B_k,𝖤 C_1_𝗂𝗇𝖽_𝟣𝖤 C_r_𝗂𝗇𝖽_𝗋.{\sf A}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,B_{\_}1\dots{\sf A}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,B_{\_}k,{\sf E}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,{C_{\_}1}_{\_}{\sf ind_{\_}1}\dots{\sf E}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,{C_{\_}r}_{\_}{\sf ind_{\_}r}.

    Merge all C_i(1<iq)C_{\_}i~{}(1<i\leq q) which have identical indices, (for example, given 𝖤 p_𝖿{\sf E}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,p_{\_}{\sf f} and 𝖤 q_𝖿{\sf E}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,q_{\_}{\sf f}, producing 𝖤 (pq)_𝖿{\sf E}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,(p\wedge q)_{\_}{\sf f}) obtaining in this way

    𝖠 B_1𝖠 B_k,𝖤 C_1_𝗂𝗇𝖽_𝟣𝖤 C_m_𝗂𝗇𝖽_𝗆.{\sf A}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,B_{\_}1\dots{\sf A}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,B_{\_}k,{\sf E}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,{C_{\_}1}_{\_}{\sf ind_{\_}1}\dots{\sf E}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,{C_{\_}m}_{\_}{\sf ind_{\_}m}.

    Then create the successors d_1d_md_{\_}1\dots d_{\_}m of ss labelled respectively by

    {B_1B_k,C_1}{B_1B_k,C_m}.\{B_{\_}1\dots B_{\_}k,C_{\_}1\}\dots\{B_{\_}1\dots B_{\_}k,C_{\_}m\}.
  • 4.

    Repeat steps 2 and 3 until no more new nodes are generated.

Now a tableau is a structure 𝒢_𝒞_Aug=(N,E,L){\cal G}_{\_}{{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug}}=(N,E,L), which satisfies the following conditions

  • NN is a set of those nodes that are states in the construction above,

  • EE is a set of edges such that for s,tNs,t\in N, E(s,t)E(s,t) if, and only if, tt is an immediate successor of ss, and

  • LL is a set of labels, so for sNs\in N, the label of ss is L(s)L(s).

In the following we will utilise the concept of pseudofulfillment of eventualities, adapting a general definition to our case.

Definition 6.3.

Given a tableau 𝒞__Aug{}_{\_}{{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug}}, if a state ss contains an eventuality Pl\hbox{\rm\bf P}{\diamondsuit}l, then Pl\hbox{\rm\bf P}{\diamondsuit}l is pseudo fulfilled, if 𝒢_R{\cal G}_{\_}R satisfies the following conditions.

  • If Pl=𝖠l\hbox{\rm\bf P}{\diamondsuit}l={\sf A}{\diamondsuit}l then there exists a finite subgraph HH of 𝒢_R{\cal G}_{\_}R with ss as its root, such that for any terminal state tHt\in H, ltl\in t.

  • If Pl=𝖤l_𝖿\hbox{\rm\bf P}{\diamondsuit}l={\sf E}{\diamondsuit}l_{\_}{\sf f} then there exists a finite subgraph HH of 𝒢_R{\cal G}_{\_}R with ss as its root, such that HH has a finite path π_s\pi_{\_}{s} which departs from ss and satisfies the following condition: each state t_i+1π_st_{\_}{i+1}\in\pi_{\_}{s}, is the fthf-th successor of t_it_{\_}i, and ll is satisfied at the terminal state of π_s\pi_{\_}{s}.

Pseudo fulfilment informally means that for 𝖠l{\sf A}{\diamondsuit}l constraints we have a loop which contains a node satisfying ll and for 𝖤l_𝗂𝗇𝖽{\sf E}{\diamondsuit}l_{\_}{\sf ind} constraints we have a loop which contains a node satisfying ll where every successor node is an 𝗂𝗇𝖽{\sf ind}-successor of the previous one, i.e. the one which is the successor node along the 𝗂𝗇𝖽{\sf ind} path.

Given a tableau 𝒢_𝒞_Aug{\cal G}_{\_}{{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug}}, apply the following deletion rules. If a state has no successors, then delete this state and all edges leading to it. If a state contains an eventuality which is not pseudo fulfilled, delete this state.

Finally, if a state contains 𝖤 C_𝗂𝗇𝖽{\sf E}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,C_{\_}{\sf ind} and does not have an 𝗂𝗇𝖽{\sf ind}-successor which contains CC, then delete this state. The resulting graph is called the reduced tableau.

Theorem 6.4.

([3]) For any 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} set 𝒞\cal C, its reduced tableau is empty, if and only if, 𝒞\cal C is unsatisfiable.

Now from a non-empty reduced graph 𝒢_𝒞_Aug=(N,E,L){\cal G}_{\_}{{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug}}=(N,E,L) for an augmented 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} we can construct a Büchi Tree Automaton, =Σ,D,S,δ,F_0,F_B{\cal B}=\langle\Sigma,~{}D,~{}S,\delta,F_{\_}0,~{}F_{\_}B\rangle following the standard technique, for example, [22].

  • Σ=2Prop_𝒞_Aug\Sigma=2^{Prop_{\_}{{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug}}}, where Prop_𝒞_AugProp_{\_}{{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug}} is a set of propositions of the clause set 𝒞_Aug{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug};

  • DD is the set of indices as defined for the construction of the Generalized Fischer-Ladner closure in Def. 6.2;

  • SS is a finite set, NN, of states of 𝒞_Aug{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug};

  • δ\delta is a transition function which corresponds to the edge relation EE of the reduced tableau;

  • F_0F_{\_}0 is a set of those states that satisfy all the initial clauses occurring within the clause set 𝒞_Aug{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug};

  • F_B=S=NF_{\_}B=S=N is a set of all states in the reduced tableau.

Theorem 6.5.

Given a set, 𝒞{\cal C}, of 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} clauses, we can construct a Büchi tree automaton {\cal B} such that 𝒞{\cal C} is satisfiable, if and only if, {\cal B} has an accepting run, τ_\tau_{\_}{\cal B}.

Proof. According to Theorem 6.4, if a set, 𝒞{\cal C}, of 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} clauses is satisfiable then so is the reduced tableau for 𝒞_Aug{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug}. Due to the construction of the latter, following the transitions EE, we can unwind it into an infinite tree TT such that the root of the tree is labelled by the 𝒞_Aug{\cal C}_{\_}{Aug} and if a node s_iNs_{\_}i\in N has 𝗂𝗇𝖽{\sf ind}-successor nodes they become 𝗂𝗇𝖽{\sf ind}-successors of the corresponding node x_ix_{\_}i of TT. The labelling of the states of NN gives the labelling of Σ\Sigma for the nodes of TT. Now consider the Σ\Sigma-labelled tree T,ΣT,\Sigma as a tree over which the desired run τ\tau of the automaton can be defined. The above construction of the automaton’s accepting states guarantees that every path through the run would hit an accepting state infinitely often.

On the other hand, if we have an unsatisfiable set of 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} clauses then its reduced tableau is empty, and therefore, the automaton {\cal B} whose construction is based upon the properties of this reduced tableau, cannot have an accepting run.  

7 Example

As an example of the syntactic representation of Büchi tree automaton in terms of 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} let us consider the following small automaton =Σ,D,S,δ,F_0,F_B{\cal B}=\langle\Sigma,~{}D,~{}S,\delta,F_{\_}0,~{}F_{\_}B\rangle where: the alphabet Σ={p,r}\Sigma=\{p,r\}, the set of branching degrees is D={d_1=2}D=\{d_{\_}1=2\}; the set of states S={s_0,s_1}S=\{s_{\_}0,s_{\_}1\} with the initial states F_0=s_0F_{\_}0=s_{\_}0 and the accepting state F_B=s_1F_{\_}B=s_{\_}1. Finally, let the transition function be defined as follows:

δ(s_0,p,2)=<s_0,s_0>\delta(s_{\_}0,p,2)=<s_{\_}0,s_{\_}0>, δ(s_1,p,2)=<s_0,s_0>\delta(s_{\_}1,p,2)=<s_{\_}0,s_{\_}0>, δ(s_0,r,2)=<s_1,s_1>\delta(s_{\_}0,r,2)=<s_{\_}1,s_{\_}1>, δ(s_1,r,2)=<s_1,s_1>\delta(s_{\_}1,r,2)=<s_{\_}1,s_{\_}1>.

This is a non-empty automaton, and its accepting run hits an accepting state s_1s_{\_}1 infinitely often on every branch. Now we will present the components of the 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} for this automaton. With q_1,q_2q_{\_}1,q_{\_}2, for the encoding of the states of the automaton and selecting q_1q_{\_}1 to encode the initial state, in equations (11)-(14) we give the components of the encoding of the given automaton, noting that vv in the representation of the labelling, and y,l,u,wy,l,u,w in the representations of the acceptance conditions are fresh variables. First, the encoding of the initial states of the given automaton is represented by the set of clauses (11).

𝖡𝖭𝖥_init_.1startq_1\begin{array}[t]{rl}{\sf BNF}_{\_}{init_{\_}{\cal B}}&\\ .1&\hbox{\bf start}\Rightarrow q_{\_}1\\ \end{array} (11)

Next, the transition function of the given automaton is represented by the set of clauses (12).

𝖡𝖭𝖥_tran_12.1q_1𝖤 q_1_ind_112.2q_1𝖤 q_2_ind_212.3q_2𝖤 q_1_ind_112.4q_2𝖤 q_2_ind_2\begin{array}[t]{rcl}{\sf BNF}_{\_}{tran_{\_}{\cal B}}&\\ \ref{eq:example-transition-function}.1&q_{\_}1\Rightarrow{\sf E}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,{q_{\_}1}_{\_}{ind_{\_}1}\\ \ref{eq:example-transition-function}.2&q_{\_}1\Rightarrow{\sf E}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,{q_{\_}2}_{\_}{ind_{\_}2}\\ \ref{eq:example-transition-function}.3&q_{\_}2\Rightarrow{\sf E}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,{q_{\_}1}_{\_}{ind_{\_}1}\\ \ref{eq:example-transition-function}.4&q_{\_}2\Rightarrow{\sf E}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,{q_{\_}2}_{\_}{ind_{\_}2}\\ \end{array} (12)

The set of clauses (13) represent the labelling of the given automaton.

BNF_lab_13.1start¬q_1pr13.2start¬q_2pr13.3𝐓𝖠 (¬q_1v)13.4vpr13.5𝐓𝖠 (¬q_2v)\begin{array}[t]{rcl}{BNF}_{\_}{lab_{\_}{\cal B}}&\\ \ref{eq:example-labelling}.1&\hbox{\bf start}&\Rightarrow\lnot q_{\_}1\vee p\wedge r\\ \ref{eq:example-labelling}.2&\hbox{\bf start}&\Rightarrow\lnot q_{\_}2\vee p\wedge r\\ \ref{eq:example-labelling}.3&{\bf\scriptstyle T}&\Rightarrow{\sf A}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,(\lnot q_{\_}1\vee v)\\ \ref{eq:example-labelling}.4&v&\Rightarrow p\wedge r\\ \ref{eq:example-labelling}.5&{\bf\scriptstyle T}&\Rightarrow{\sf A}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,(\lnot q_{\_}2\vee v)\\ \end{array} (13)

Finally, for the automaton acceptance conditions we have the set of clauses (14), where l,y,u,wl,y,u,w are fresh variables.

BNF_acc_14.1starty14.2start¬lq_114.3𝐓𝖠 (¬lq_1)14.4y𝖠 u14.5u𝖤l_ind_114.6l𝖤 w_ind_114.7w𝖤l_ind_1\begin{array}[t]{rcl}{BNF}_{\_}{acc_{\_}{\cal B}}&\\ \ref{eq:example-acceptance}.1&\hbox{\bf start}&\Rightarrow y\\ \ref{eq:example-acceptance}.2&\hbox{\bf start}&\Rightarrow\lnot l\vee q_{\_}1\\ \ref{eq:example-acceptance}.3&{\bf\scriptstyle T}&\Rightarrow{\sf A}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,(\lnot l\vee q_{\_}1)\\ \ref{eq:example-acceptance}.4&y&\Rightarrow{\sf A}\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(0.0,0.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,2.0){\line(1,0){2.0}} \put(0.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \put(2.0,0.0){\line(0,1){2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,u\\ \ref{eq:example-acceptance}.5&u&\Rightarrow{\sf E}{\diamondsuit}l_{\_}{ind_{\_}1}\\ \ref{eq:example-acceptance}.6&l&\Rightarrow{\sf E}\!\raisebox{-0.86108pt}{ \mbox{\begin{picture}(2.0,2.0) \put(1.0,1.0){\circle{2.0}} \end{picture}}}\,w_{\_}{ind_{\_}1}\\ \ref{eq:example-acceptance}.7&w&\Rightarrow{\sf E}{\diamondsuit}l_{\_}{ind_{\_}1}\\ \end{array} (14)

First, we show that the acceptance condition is properly simulated by the above 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF}. Indeed, every state along every path of the underlying 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} computation tree, satisfies uu, due to clauses 14.1 and 14.4. Now, pick an arbitrary state s_is_{\_}i along some fullpath, say ξ\xi. Following 14.5, there should be a state s_js_{\_}j, iji\leq j, along the path Suf(ξ,s_j)Suf(\xi,s_{\_}j), which is labeled ind_1{ind_{\_}1} such that it satisfies ll. Following 14.6, the 𝗂𝗇𝖽{\sf ind}-successor of the state of s_js_{\_}j, say s_ms_{\_}m, jmj\leq m which satisfies ww. Hence by 14.7, there should be a state, say, s_ks_{\_}k, mkm\leq k along the path Suf(ξ,s_m)Suf(\xi,s_{\_}m) labeled by ind_1{ind_{\_}1} such that s_ks_{\_}k satisfies ll. Due to 14.3, states s_js_{\_}j and s_ks_{\_}k satisfy q_1q_{\_}1. Repeating this cain of reasoning steps regarding the satisfiability of ll we derive the recurrent satisfiability of q_1q_{\_}1, which corresponds to the acceptance condition for this automaton, to hit the acceptance state s_1s_{\_}1 infinitely often.

8 Discussion

We have shown that normal form used for clausal resolution method for a variety of CTL-type logics is expressive enough to give the succinct high-level syntactic representation of Büchi tree automaton. This represents a significant step in establishing the exact expressiveness of this formalism relating it to this important class of tree automata. As a consequence, based on the known expressiveness results, that Büchi tree automata are as expressive as CTL extended by the propositional quantification, we can also treat BNF as a kind of normal form for the latter: we can directly translate given problem specifications into 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} and apply as a verification method a deductive reasoning technique – the temporal resolution technique. This paper justifies that 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} is suitable to reason about a wider range of branching-time specifications and is able to capture exactly those that are captured by tree automata.

Moreover, another very promising route is emerging here. In 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF} we are enabled not only to represent some given, or explicit invariants, but also to discover implicit, hidden invariants. For example, invariants are extremely important in the emerging trend of developing complex but re-configurable software systems. Here one of the most challenging problems is assuring that invariants are maintained during system reconfiguration. In [9], it has been shown how the clausal temporal resolution technique developed for temporal logic provides an effective method for searching for invariants in the linear time setting. The results of this paper enable the extension of this method to branching-time framework, and the detailed analysis of this route forms one direction of future research.

Also, in the future we will investigate the representation of alternating tree automata in 𝖡𝖭𝖥{\sf BNF}, where we expect results similar to the linear-time case [8].

References

  • [1]
  • [2] Artie Basukoski & Alexander Bolotov (2005): Search Strategies for Resolution in CTL-Type Logics: Extension and Complexity. In: 12th International Symposium on Temporal Representation and Reasoning (TIME 2005), pp. 195–197, 10.1109/TIME.2005.32.
  • [3] Alexander Bolotov (2000): Clausal Resolution for Branching-Time Temporal Logic. Ph.D. thesis, Department of Computing and Mathematics, The Manchester Metropolitan University.
  • [4] Alexander Bolotov & Artie Basukoski (2006): A Clausal Resolution Method for Branching-Time Logic ECTL+. Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence 46(3), p. 235–263, 10.1007/s10472-006-9018-1.
  • [5] Alexander Bolotov & Artie Basukoski (2006): A Clausal Resolution Method for Extended Computation Tree Logic ECTL. Journal of Applied Logic 4(2), pp. 141–167, 10.1016/j.jal.2005.06.003.
  • [6] Alexander Bolotov & Clare Dixon (2000): Resolution for Branching Time Temporal Logics: Applying the Temporal Resolution Rule. In: Seventh International Workshop on Temporal Representation and Reasoning, TIME 2000, Nova Scotia, Canada, July 7-9, 2000, IEEE Computer Society, pp. 163–172, 10.1109/TIME.2000.856598.
  • [7] Alexander Bolotov & Michael Fisher (1999): A Clausal Resolution Method for CTL Branching-time Temporal Logic. Journal of experimental and theoretical artificial intelligence 11(1), pp. 77–93, 10.1080/095281399146625.
  • [8] Alexander Bolotov, Michael Fisher & Clare Dixon (2002): On the Relationship between w-automata and Temporal Logic Normal Forms. Journal of Logic and Computation 12(4), pp. 561–581, 10.1093/logcom/12.4.561.
  • [9] James Brotherston, Anatoli Degtyarev, Michael Fisher & Alexei Lisitsa (2002): Searching for Invariants Using Temporal Resolution. In Matthias Baaz & Andrei Voronkov, editors: Logic for Programming, Artificial Intelligence, and Reasoning, 9th International Conference, LPAR 2002, Tbilisi, Georgia, October 14-18, 2002, Proceedings, Lecture Notes in Computer Science 2514, Springer, pp. 86–101, 10.1007/3-540-36078-6_6.
  • [10] Julius Richard Büchi (1962): On a Decision Method in Restricted Second-order Arithmetics. In: Proceedings of the International Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, Stanford University Press, pp. 1–12.
  • [11] Clare Dixon (2021): Theorem Proving Using Clausal Resolution: From Past to Present. In Paul C. Bell, Patrick Totzke & Igor Potapov, editors: Reachability Problems - 15th International Conference, RP 2021, Liverpool, UK, October 25-27, 2021, Proceedings, Lecture Notes in Computer Science 13035, Springer, pp. 19–27, 10.1007/978-3-030-89716-1_2.
  • [12] Clare Dixon, Alexander Bolotov & Michael Fisher (2005): Alternating Automata and Temporal Logic Normal Forms. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 135(1-3), pp. 263–285, 10.1016/j.apal.2005.03.002.
  • [13] E. Allen Emerson (1990): Temporal and Modal Logic. In Jan van Leeuwen, editor: Handbook of Theoretical Computer Science: Volume B, Formal Models and Semantics, Elsevier, pp. 996–1072.
  • [14] E. Allen Emerson & Joseph Y. Halpern (1985): Decision procedures and expressiveness in the temporal logic of branching time. Journal of Computer and System Sciences 30(1), pp. 1–24, 10.1016/0022-0000(85)90001-7Get.
  • [15] E. Allen Emerson & Joseph Y. Halpern (1986): “Sometimes” and “Not Never” Revisited: On Branching versus Linear Time Temporal Logic. Journal of ACM 33(1), p. 151–178, 10.1145/4904.4999.
  • [16] E. Allen Emerson & A. Prasad Sistla (1984): Deciding Branching Time Logic. In: Proceedings of the Sixteenth Annual ACM Symposium on Theory of Computing, STOC ’84, Association for Computing Machinery, New York, NY, USA, p. 14–24, 10.1145/800057.808661.
  • [17] Michael J. Fischer & Richard E. Ladner (1979): Propositional dynamic logic of regular programs. Journal of Computer and System Sciences 18(2), pp. 194–211, 10.1016/0022-0000(79)90046-1.
  • [18] Michael Fisher (1997): A Normal Form for Temporal Logics and its Applications in Theorem-Proving and Execution. Journal of Logic and Computation 7(4), pp. 429–456, 10.1093/logcom/7.4.429.
  • [19] Michael Fisher, Clare Dixon & Martin Peim (2001): Clausal Temporal Resolution. ACM Transactions on Computational Logic 2(1), pp. 12–56, 10.1145/371282.371311.
  • [20] François Laroussinie & Nicolas Markey (2014): Quantified CTL: Expressiveness and Complexity. Logical Methods in Computer Science 10(4), pp. 1–45, 10.2168/LMCS-10(4:17)2014.
  • [21] Matt Luckcuck, Marie Farrell, Louise A. Dennis, Clare Dixon & Michael Fisher (2019): Formal Specification and Verification of Autonomous Robotic Systems: A Survey. ACM Comput. Surv. 52(5), pp. 100:1–100:41, 10.1145/3342355.
  • [22] Moshe Y. Vardi (2007): Automata-theoretic Techniques for Temporal Reasoning. In Patrick Blackburn, Johan F. A. K. van Benthem & Frank Wolter, editors: Handbook of Modal Logic, Studies in logic and practical reasoning 3, North-Holland, pp. 971–989, 10.1016/s1570-2464(07)80020-6.
  • [23] Lan Zhang, Ullrich Hustadt & Clare Dixon (2009): A Refined Resolution Calculus for CTL. In: CADE-22, pp. 245–260, 10.1007/978-3-642-02959-220.
  • [24] Lan Zhang, Ullrich Hustadt & Clare Dixon (2010): CTL-RP: A computation Tree Logic Resolution Prover. AI Commun. 23(2-3), pp. 111–136, 10.3233/AIC-2010-0463.