On the abundance of -fold semi-monotone minimal sets in bimodal circle maps
Abstract.
Inspired by a twist maps theorem of Mather we study recurrent invariant sets that are ordered like rigid rotation under the action of the lift of a bimodal circle map to the -fold cover. For each irrational in the interior of the rotation set the collection of the -fold ordered semi-Denjoy minimal sets with that rotation number contains a -dimensional ball in the weak topology on their unique invariant measures. We also describe completely their periodic orbit analogs for rational rotation numbers. The main tool is a generalization of a construction of Hedlund and Morse which generates the symbolic analogs of these -fold well-ordered invariant sets.
1. introduction
In a dynamical system a rotation number or vector measures the asymptotic speed and direction of an orbit. The rotation set collects all these together into a single invariant of the system. The natural question is how much does this invariant tell you about the dynamics? Perhaps the first issue is whether for each rotation number is there a nice invariant set in which every point has that rotation number?
This question has been studied in a number of contexts with the most complete answer known about maps of the circle, annulus and two-dimensional torus. In these cases the basic question is enhanced by requiring that the invariant set of a given rotation vector has the same combinatorics as a rigid rotation. So, for example, for a continuous degree-one map of the circle and a number in its rotation set is there an invariant set on which the action of looks like the invariant set of rigid rotation of the circle by ? This is made more precise and clear by lifting the dynamics to the universal cover . The question then translates to whether the action of the lift on the lift is order-preserving? For this class of maps the answer is yes; such invariant sets always exist ([17]).
On the torus and annulus a general homeomorphism isotopic to the identity lacks the structure to force the desired invariant sets to be order preserving so topological analogs are used ([30, 9, 40]). The required additional structure available in the annulus case is the monotone twist hypothesis. In this case the celebrated Aubry-Mather Theorem states that for each rational in the rotation set there is a periodic orbit and for each irrational a Denjoy minimal set and the action of the map on these invariant sets is ordered in the circle factor like rigid rotation. These invariant sets are now called Aubry-Mather sets.
For an area-preserving monotone twist map the minimal set with a given irrational rotation number could be an invariant circle. When a parameter is altered and this circle breaks it is replaced by an invariant Denjoy minimal set. In [35] Mather investigated what additional dynamics this forces. He showed that in the absence of an invariant circle with a given irrational rotation number there are many other invariant minimal Cantor sets with the same rotation number and the dynamics on these sets is nicely ordered under the dynamics not in the base, but rather in finite covering spaces of the annulus.
More specifically, these invariant minimal sets are Denjoy minimal sets which are uniquely ergodic. Their collection is topologized using the weak topology on these measures. Mather showed that for a given irrational rotation number in the rotation set the collection of Denjoy minimal sets with that rotation number which are ordered in the -fold cover contains a topological disk of dimension . In this paper we prove the analog of this result for a class of bimodal degree-one maps of the circle as well as describing their periodic orbits which have nicely ordered lifts in the -fold cover.
Mather’s proof use variational methods. The main methods here come from symbolic dynamics and utilize a construction that is a generalization of one due to Hedlund and Morse ([37] and [23] page 111). Such generalizations are a common tool in topological dynamics ([34], [3] pages 234-241, and [10]). This HM construction used here for a rotation number and number generates the itineraries under rigid rotation by with respect to an address systems made from intervals on the circle. The closure of this set of itineraries yields the symbolic analog of an invariant set that is nicely ordered in the -fold cover. These sets are termed symbolic -fold semi-monotone sets (symbolic kfsm sets). Varying the address system parameterizes the symbolic kfsm sets in both the Hausdorff and weak topologies.
A physical kfsm set (or just a kfsm set if the context is clear) is a -invariant set which has a lift to the -fold cover of the circle on which the lift of acts like rigid rotation. Physical and symbolic kfsm sets are connected by a second main tool.
The second tool again uses addresses and itineraries, but this time to code orbits under the bimodal map . Restricting to all orbits that land in the positive slope region we get an invariant set which is coded by an order interval in the one-sided two shift . Since we need to study invariant sets that are ordered in the -fold cover we lift this coding to one on the orbits which stay in the positive slope region under in the -fold cover . This yields a -invariant set which is then coded by a subshift .
This result connects the physical kfsm sets in , the symbolic kfsm sets in , and the symbolic sets generated by the HM construction. Part (c) will be explained below.
Theorem 1.1.
For the following are equivalent:
-
(a)
is a recurrent kfsm set for .
-
(b)
The symbolic coding of via the itinerary map is constructable via the HM process.
-
(c)
is a recurrent set of an interpolated semi-monotone map in the -fold cover.
Note that the result is restricted to recurrent kfsm sets. There are several reasons for this. First, recurrence is where the interesting dynamics occurs, second, invariant measures are always supported on recurrent sets, and finally, the HM construction produces recurrent sets. As is well-known in Aubry-Mather theory there are also nonrecurrent kfsm sets which consist of a recurrent set and orbits homoclinic to that set. We also restrict to orbits that stay in the positive slope region of . Considering kfsm sets that also have points in the negative slope region at most adds additional homoclinic orbits or shadow periodic orbits. See Section 13.2.
For each , the HM construction depends on two parameters, a rotation number and a parameter describing the address system on the circle. For a rational rotation number it produces a finite cluster of periodic orbits while for irrationals it produces a semi-Denjoy minimal set. Since is noninjective the analogs of Denjoy minimal sets have pairs of points that collapse in forward time, and hence the “‘semi” in their name.
Another main result is that the HM construction parameters yield a homeomorphic parameterization of the space of invariant measures on the recurrent symbolic kfsm sets with the weak topology. Via the itinerary map, this is pulled back to a parameterization of the space of invariant measures on the physical recurrent kfsm sets with the weak topology. It yields the following result in which is the rotation interval of .
Theorem 1.2.
Assume , , , and .
-
(a)
In the weak topology there is -dimensional disk of kfsm semi-Denjoy minimal sets with rotation number .
-
(b)
If is a sequence of rationals in lowest terms with , then the number of distinct kfsm periodic orbits of with rotation number grows like .
Informally, a kfsm semi-Denjoy minimal set wraps -times around the circle with orbits moving at different average speeds in each loop. Lifting to the -fold cover these “speeds” are given by the amount of the unique invariant measure present in a fundamental domain of : more measure means slower speed. The -dimensional vector of these measures is called the skewness of the minimal set. The sum of the components of the skewness is one and thus the collection of possible skewnesses contains a -dimensional ball. The skewness turns out to be an injective parameterization of the kfsm sets for a given irrational rotation number in the interior of the rotation set of a (see Remark 9.14).
The HM-parametrization of kfsm sets with the Hausdorff topology is only lower semicontinuous. The points of discontinuity are given in Theorem 9.5.
We will on occasion use results derived from those of Aubry-Mather theory. While the context here is a bit different the proofs are virtually identical and so are omitted. There are excellent expositions of Aubry-Mather theory; see, for example, [32], [29] Chapter 13, and [22] Chapter 2. In the context of the generalization of Aubry-Mather theory to monotone recursion maps a version of Mather’s theorem on Denjoy minimal sets is given in [44].
We restrict attention here to a particular class of bimodal circle maps defined in Section 4.1. Using the Parry-Milnor-Thurston Theorem for degree-one circle maps the results can be transferred (with appropriate alterations) to general bimodal circle maps (see Remark 4.2).
It is worth noting that the results here immediately apply to a class of annulus homeomorphisms. This application can be done either via the Brown-Barge-Martin method using the inverse limit of ([4, 12]) or via the symbolic dynamics in annulus maps with good coding like a rotary horseshoe, for example, [24, 31, 10, 19].

Figure 1 illustrates the conceptual framework that inspired the results here. It shows the graph of a map lifted to the -fold cover. At three heights the graph is cut-off yielding a semi-monotone circle map . Such maps have a unique rotation number and well understood recurrent sets which are of necessity semi-monotone sets. As is varied, the rotation number varies continuously. Thus one would expect that the level sets provide a parameterization of the kfsm sets with rotation number . In particular, for irrational this level set should be a -dimensional disk as in Theorem 1.2(a). This is true for . Figure 5 below shows some level sets. It is worth noting that this figure is not a bifurcation diagram, but rather a detailed analysis of the dynamics present in a single map.
While providing a valuable heuristic this point of view is not as technically tractable as the HM construction and we content ourselves with just a few comments on it in Section 13. One of which is the addition of item (c) to the list of equivalent conditions in Theorem 1.1.
The literature on bimodal circle map dynamics is vast and we briefly mention only two threads here. Symbolic dynamics for degree one bimodal goes back at least to [5, 26, 25]. The interpolated “flat spot” map trick for finding one-fold semi-monotone sets was discovered and used by many people in the early 80’s; references include [17, 36, 43, 42, 41, 28, 13, 39]. The author learned the trick from G.R. Hall in Spring, 1983 and the idea of applying it in finite covers emerged in conversations with him.
There are many questions raised by this work, but we mention just three here. As is well-known, the one-fold symbolic semi-monotone sets generated by the HM construction are the much-studied Sturmian sequences. The general symbolic kfsm are thus a generalization of one property of the Sturmians to more symbols (there are many other generalizations). The Sturmians have many marvelous properties such as their connection to the Farey tree and substitutions: which properties are shared by symbolic kfsm sets?
The HM construction is an explicit parameterized way of getting well controlled orbits that do not preserve the cyclic order in the base and thus in most cases force positive entropy and as well as other orbits. A second question is how does the parameterization given by the HM construction interact with the forcing orders on orbits in dimension one and two (see, for example, [1] and [11]).
A final question relates to the global parameterization of kfsm by the HM construction. Each bimodal map corresponds to a specific set of parameters, namely, those that generate symbolic kfsm whose physical counterparts are present in . What is the shape of this set of parameters?
After this work was completed the author became aware of the considerable literature studying invariant sets in the circle that are invariant and nicely ordered under the action of [16, 21, 20, 8, 7, 33]. While the exact relationship of that theory and what is contained in the paper is not clear, it is clear that the two areas share many basic ideas and methods. These include using a family of interpolated semi-monotone circle maps with flat spots, tight and loose gaps in invariant Cantor sets, parametrizing the sets using the position of the flat spots, and parametrizing the sets with irrational rotation number by an analog of skewness. Section 14 contains a few more comments on the relationship of the problems.
2. Preliminaries
2.1. Dynamics
Throughout this section is a metric space and is a continuous, onto map. Since the maps we will be considering will usually not be injective, we will be just considering forward orbits, so .
A point is recurrent if there exists a sequence with . A -invariant set is called recurrent if every point is recurrent. Note that a recurrent subset is usually different than the recurrent set, with the latter being the closure of all recurrent points. A compact invariant set is called minimal if every point has a forward orbit that is dense in .
The one-sided shift space on symbols is and that on symbols is . Occasionally we will write for . For clarity we note that in this paper . In every case we give one-sided shift spaces the lexicographic order and the left shift map is denoted , perhaps with a subscript to indicate the shift space upon which it acts. Maps between shifts and subshifts here will always be defined by their action on individual symbols so, for example, defined on symbols by means that . For a block in its cylinder set is . Note that all our cylinder sets start with index
The space-map pairs and are said to be topologically conjugate by if is a homeomorphism from onto and .
We will frequently use the standard dynamical tool of addresses and itineraries. Assume with denoting disjoint union. Define the address map as when and the itinerary map by . It is immediate that . In many cases here, will be continuous and injective yielding a topological conjugacy from to a subset of .
We will also encounter the situation where the are not disjoint, but intersect only in their frontiers . In this case we define a “good set” . In this case the itinerary map is defined as .
For , its interior, closure and frontier are denoted by and , respectively. The -ball about is . The Hausdorff distance between two sets is denoted . For an interval in , denotes it length, and for a finite set , is its cardinality. On an ordered -tuple the map is the left cyclic shift, so . On the circle , is defined as long as .
2.2. The circle, finite covers and degree one circle maps
While the only compact manifold here will be a circle it will clarify matters to use the language of covering spaces.
In general, if is a covering space, and , a lift of is any set with . The full lift of is . If lifts to and is -invariant then the full lift is -invariant, a property that is usually not shared by a lift .
The universal cover of the circle is with deck transformation and the covering space is thus . We will only study maps whose lifts commute with the deck transformation, , or . These circle maps are commonly termed degree one. Our given will usually have a preferred lift and so all other lifts are obtained as or .
Central to our study are the finite -fold covers of the circle for each , . The deck transformation is induced by on and the covering space is . A preferred lift of to induces a preferred lift that commutes with . We also need the map from the universal cover to the -fold cover treating as the base space .
A -periodic point is said to have rotation type with respect to the preferred lift if has period and for some lift , . Note that there is no requirement here that and are relatively prime.
A central concern in this paper is how -minimal sets in lift to -fold covers.
Theorem 2.1.
Let be degree one and fix .
-
(a)
If is a minimal set, then there exists an which divides so that the full lift of to satisfies
(2.1) with each minimal under , and with indices .
-
(b)
If are minimal sets, we have if and only if for some .
-
(c)
If is a periodic point with rotation type let . There exist with and
(2.2) the period of each under equal to , and with indices .
Proof.
To prove (a) we begin with two preliminary facts with similar proofs. First, we show that for any , . Let and pick . By minimality there exists . Lifting and using the compactness of there is a subsequence and a with . Thus and so .
Second, we show that for any , there exists an with . Let and . By minimality again, we have . Lifting and passing to a subsequence, there is a subsequence and a with . Thus also, so there is a with and so .
Now for the main proof, pick and let , so by the first fact, . We now show is minimal under . If not, there is a with . By the second preliminary fact, there is some with
Acting by the homeomorphism and iterating the strict inclusions we have
a contradiction, so acting on is minimal. Thus since , acting on each is minimal. Now minimal sets either coincide or are disjoint, so there is a least with .
For the proof (b), assume . Now is minimal under and thus since and minimal sets are always disjoint or equal, using (2.1) we have that for some . Similarly, for some , and thus and and so as required.
Now for (c), Since the deck group of is there is a natural identification of with with identified with zero. Since in the induced action of on is . An easy elementary number theory argument yields that this action has exactly distinct orbits. Thus has exactly distinct orbits when acting on . But are on the same orbit if and only if they are on the same orbit and each orbit in contains at least one point from . Thus acting on has exactly orbits. The rest of the form of (2.2) follows from part (a). ∎
While it is not used here a similar result holds for covers and their cyclic quotients when a map in the base has a lift that commutes with the deck transformations.
Remark 2.2.
Some special cases of (c) are worth pointing out. If , then lifts to a single period orbit in . If , then lifts to a different period- orbits in . When , there is a simple dichotomy. When is odd, lifts to one period orbit and when is even, lifts to a pair of period orbits.
2.3. Rotation number and interval
For a fixed lift of a degree one define the rotation number of as
(2.3) |
when the limit exists. Note that this value depend in a simple way on the choice of lift of , namely, . In most cases below there will be a preferred lift of a given that will be used in (2.3) and we define where is a lift of . When is understood we will just write . If is a periodic point of rotation type then .
If is a -invariant set, let
and . The latter set has been proved to be a closed interval [27, 38] and thus it is called the rotation interval of the map. We shall also have occasion to use with the obvious meaning.
There is a alternative way of computing the rotation interval using upper and lower maps that is now standard ([17, 36, 28, 13] and elsewhere). Given a lift of a degree-one circle map let and . If and are their descents to they are both semi-monotone maps and so each of their rotation sets is a single point (see Lemma 3.1 below). The rotation interval of is
(2.4) |
To define the rotation number of a -invariant Borel probability measure start by letting be which is independent of the choice of lift . Then
(2.5) |
Note that when is ergodic by the Pointwise Ergodic Theorem for a.e. , .
For points, invariant sets and measures in the cyclic cover under the preferred lift , there are two ways to consider the rotation number. The most common will be to project to the base and define
(2.6) |
For a invariant measure, let
(2.7) |
Remark 2.3.
The other way to work with rotation numbers in is to consider as a map of the circle itself. To work on the standard circle we first rescale via via . Note that is not a covering map but rather a coordinate rescaling homeomorphism. For , then is the desired rotation number. These two methods are related simply by
3. Semi-monotone degree-one maps
3.1. Definition and basic properties
In this section we give the basics of a small, but crucial expansion of the class of circle homeomorphisms, namely, continuous maps whose lifts are semi-monotone. They share many of the properties of circle homeomorphisms and are a standard and important tool in circle dynamics
Thus we consider continuous, degree one whose lifts to satisfy implies .111In topology a monotone map is one with connected point inverses. In this sense a semi-monotone map is monotone. On the other hand, considering the point of view of order relations, semi-monotone is contrast with monotone. We adapt the latter viewpoint. Note that this is independent of the choice of lift of . We shall also call such maps weakly order preserving. Let be the collection of all such maps with the -topology, and denotes all their lifts.
A flat spot for a is a nontrivial closed interval where is a constant and for which there is no larger interval containing on which is constant. A given can have at most a countable number of flat spots and we define the “positive slope region” of as . The proof of the next result is standard.
Lemma 3.1.
Assume with preferred lift .
-
(a)
The rotation number exists and is the same for all and so is a single number.
-
(b)
The map is continuous.
-
(c)
If and then .
-
(d)
If in lowest terms then all periodic orbits have rotation type and the recurrent set of consists of a union of such periodic orbits.
-
(e)
If then has exactly one recurrent set which is a minimal set and it is wholly contained in . Further, is uniquely ergodic with the unique invariant measure supported on .
Definition 3.2.
The minimal set in (e) above is called a semi-Denjoy minimal set. More generally, an abstract minimal set is called semi-Denjoy if it is topologically conjugate to the semi-Denjoy minimal set in a semi-monotone degree one circle map.
Remark 3.3.
A semi-Denjoy minimal set looks like a usual Denjoy minimal set with the added feature that endpoints of gaps can collapse to a point under forward iteration. It is clear that any is a near-homeomorphism (the uniform limit of homeomorphisms). Thus as a consequence of a theorem of Morton Brown ([14]), the inverse limit is a circle and the natural extension is a circle homeomorphism. In particular, the inverse limit of a semi-Denjoy minimal set is a Denjoy minimal set. For example, in case of single flat spot, the two endpoints of the flat spot form a gap in the minimal set and they have same forward orbit. Taking the inverse limit splits open this orbit into a forward invariant gap.
3.2. Finitely many flat spots
We next introduce a subclass of which includes the semi-monotone maps considered in this paper. Let consist of those which have exactly flat spots and in we require that is and where we have used a one-sided derivative at the end points of the flat spots.
Definition 3.4.
If and has semi-Denjoy minimal set , since for any flat spot , . The flat spot is called tight for if , and otherwise the flat spot is loose.
Lemma 3.5.
Assume .
-
(a)
If in lowest terms then the number of -periodic orbits wholly contained in is at least one and at most .
-
(b)
If , a flat spot is loose if and only if there is an and a with . In particular, there is always at least one tight flat spot.
-
(c)
If is the maximal recurrent set of in , then
(3.1) and so if then for some .
Proof.
For part (a), since in lowest terms, every periodic point has period . By the conditions on the derivatives of , there are four classes of periodic points.
-
(1)
is unstable with and .
-
(2)
is superstable with and while .
-
(3)
is superstable with and while and contains both left and right endpoints of flat spots.
-
(4)
is semistable with from one side and from the other and while and contains only left or only right endpoints of flat spots.
This implies that all periodic points are isolated so there are finitely many of them.
Let be the number of periodic orbits of type (1). Using the fixed point index on , . Each orbit of type (3) hits two flat spots and each of type (2) and (4) at least one and a flat spot can’t contain multiple periodic orbits and so . Thus the total number of periodic orbits wholly contained on is
For part (b) assume first that for all and . If was loose, there would exist with with at least one inequality strict and . Thus is a nontrivial interval with for all . This is impossible since is expanding in and so must be loose.
For the converse, say for some and first note is impossible since that would imply has a periodic point. Since is a point there exists a nontrivial interval properly containing with and so and so is a loose flat spot.
Finally, since and there are finitely many flat spots there is at least one with for all and .
For (c), assume is such that and . Let with and . Because of the uniform expansion in there is a flat spot and an so that . If , then by (c) for some , is a tight flat spot and so .
Now assume . In this case and are periodic orbits and so for all and so using the assumption that . But from (a), . Thus by monotonicity, is either always in the left component of or in the right component. This violates the expansion in and so for some , which yields (3.1). ∎
4. A class of bimodal circle maps and their positive slope orbits
4.1. The class
We introduce the class of bimodal, degree one maps of the circle that will be the focus here. The class is defined using properties of their lifts. We say that a lift is piecewise smooth if it is continuous and there are so that is in each interval and the right and left hand derivatives exist at each .
Definition 4.1.
Let be the class of all with the following properties.
-
(a)
is piecewise smooth and .
-
(b)
There are a pair of points so that in and is monotone decreasing in .
-
(c)
The class consists of all which have a lift in .
Note that without loss of generality we have assumed that . Also by assumption, and are a nonsmooth local minimum and maximum respectively. It follows from (2.4) that implies .
Standing assumption: From this point on denotes a given element of and its preferred lift is the one with .
Remark 4.2.
Using the Parry-Milnor-Thurston Theorem for degree-one circle maps a general bimodal with and not a point is semiconjugate to a PL map 222The result for circles doesn’t seem to be stated and proved anywhere in the literature, but as noted in [15] the proof in [1] works for the circle with minimal alteration. Point inverses of the semiconjugacy are either points or a closed interval. Thus using standard results from one-dimensional dynamics and various hypotheses most of the results of the paper can be transferred with appropriate alterations to a general bimodal map.
4.2. the model map
We will use a model map as a specific example throughout the paper. We shall see that, in a sense, it is the largest map in the class and all other maps may be considered subsystems.

Define on as
and extend it to to satisfy . Let be the projection of to . See Figure 2. Thus, , , and .
4.3. Positive slope orbits
Given with preferred lift let be the points whose orbits under stay in the closed region where has positive slope, so
We give the total order coming from its embedding in . Note that it is both and invariant.
Now we treat the -fold cover as and let be the orbits that stay in the positive slope region of , so
Alternatively, or .
We discuss the restriction to positive slope orbits in Section 13.2.
Standing assumption: Unless otherwise specified the terminology “physical kfsm set” or just “kfsm set” carries the additional restriction that it is contained in the positive slope region of some .
5. Symbolic description of positive slope orbits
For a map we develop in this section a symbolic coding for the orbits in for .
5.1. the itinerary maps
We work first in the universal cover or . Since , we may find points and with and and . For define a collection of intervals on by
(5.1) |
See Figure 3. Note that since we have that
Using as an address system with the dynamics let the itinerary map be . Note that is the good set and using expansion and the disjointness of the address intervals, is a homemomorphism onto its image.

Now passing to the -fold cover, to code the positive slope orbits , treat and use the dynamics with the address system . This yields an itinerary map which is also a homeomorphism onto its image.
Example: The model map For the model map we have and and so and
5.2. Symbolic analogs of covering spaces
This section develops the necessary machinery for the complete description of the image of the various itinerary maps. We will need the symbolic analogs of the covering spaces and maps described in Section 2.2.
Definition 5.1.
Define a subshift by its allowable transitions
(5.2) |
For let be the subshift of with allowable transitions as in (5.2) for and indices reduced .
Since for we have and we have:
Lemma 5.2.
For and , .
Under the itinerary maps the spaces , and will correspond to the shift spaces , and . The dynamics on the “physical spaces” induced by will correspond to left shifts on the symbol spaces. The shift spaces will also have the analogs of the covering projections and deck transformations. These maps will be indicated by a hat and defined using the action on individual symbols as follows.
The analogs of the covering translations are given by for all and given by for all , while the analogs of the covering maps are by and by . In the later we allow under the convention that , yielding . Note then that . A lift and the full lift are defined as usual with, for example, a lift of to is a set with . Note that , and are all continuous.
The roles of the maps and in Section 2.2 are played by the various shift maps on the sequence spaces. For clarity we use a subscript to indicate which space the shift is acting on: . We again allow . All the various maps satisfy the same commutativity relations as their un-hatted analogs. So, for example, , , and . The itinerary maps act naturally by transforming the spaces and maps of Section 2.2 to their symbolic analogs as in part (b) of the next Lemma.
Lemma 5.3.
For ,
-
(a)
-
(b)
-
(c)
If and , then there exists a with .
Proof.
Parts (a) and (b) are easy to verify. For (c) we prove the case which implies the cases. Assume . The transitions in (5.2) coupled with the structure of imply that once is set the parity structure of determines all of . Similarly, once is set all of is determined. Once again (5.2) implies that if then for all , . ∎
Remark 5.4.
It would perhaps seem more natural that should act as the symbolic universal cover of , but the crucial covering space property expressed by (c) wouldn’t hold in this case. For example, if and then but for all .
5.3. Rotation numbers and sets
We give the analogs of the definitions in Section 2.3 for the symbolic case. For let
(5.3) |
when the limit exists. For a shift invariant measure on , let . When is ergodic, by the Pointwise Ergodic Theorem, for a.e. ,
For let and for a invariant measure on , let .
6. Topological conjugacies and the image of the itinerary maps
In this section we develop the analog of kneading invariants for the symbolic coding of the positive slope orbits for .
Recall that is given the lexicographic order. Assume satisfy
(6.1) |
for . The corresponding dynamical order interval is
Returning to , note that and while . This implies that . Since is compact we may define and . By construction these ’s satisfy (6.1).
We showed above that . The next theorem says that the image is as constrained by the dynamical order interval . Accordingly for we define and note that this is a invariant set.
Theorem 6.1.
Assume and construct and from as above. Then for the itinerary map is a topological conjugacy from to . Further, is order preserving.
Proof.
We first prove the first assertion for or that . Let be an arbitrary symbol and define a map by
It easily follow that
and if use the dynamics with the address system the resulting itinerary map is exactly . Now since is expanding on and , is an order preserving conjugacy from to . Finally, since for all we have that for all and further that for any such there is an with . Thus .
We now show that
(6.2) |
We already know from Lemma 5.2 that the left hand side is in . Next, since using Fact 5.3(b) and the first paragraph of the proof we have
(6.3) |
so the left hand side of (6.2) is also in .
Now assume that is in the right hand side of (6.2). Certainly then and so there is an with . Pick a lift with . Again using Lemma 5.3(b)
(6.4) |
Thus using Lemma 5.3(c), there is an with and so
and . Thus as required.
For as with , since the are disjoint and the are expanding, we have that is an order preserving homeomorphisms onto its image. The fact that it is a semiconjugacy follows because it is an itinerary map. ∎
Example: The model map For the model map we have and and so in this case is the entire subshift .
Remark 6.2.
-
(a)
(when defined) and
-
(b)
For a invariant measure supported in ,
7. -fold semi-monotone sets
While our eventual interest is in invariant sets in the circle, it is convenient to first give definitions in the universal cover and the cyclic covers .
7.1. Definitions
The next definition makes sense for any degree one map but for concreteness we restrict to .
Definition 7.1.
Let have preferred lift .
-
(a)
A -invariant set is k-fold semi-monotone (kfsm) if and restricted to is weakly order preserving, or for
-
(b)
A -invariant set is k-fold semi-monotone (kfsm) if it has a -invariant lift which is.
These definitions are independent of the choice of lift . Note that the same terminology is used for sets in the universal and cyclic covers and that implicit in being a kfsm set is the fact that the set is invariant.
When the lift in the definition must satisfy and and so , the full lift to .
7.2. interpolation
To say that is -fold semi-monotone means roughly that it is semi-monotone treating as the usual circle. To formalize this as in Remark 2.3 it will be useful to rescale to using and consider the map .
Lemma 7.2.
The following are equivalent
-
(a)
The -invariant set is kfsm
-
(b)
is -fold semi-monotone under and there exists a semi-monotone circle map defined on which interpolates acting on .
-
(c)
The lift of in Definition 7.1(b) has the property that there is a continuous that interpolates acting on , is weakly order preserving, and satisfies .
We now restrict to positive slope orbits as in Section 4.3 and collect together kfsm invariant sets in and their invariant measures. We will comment on kfsm sets which intersect the negative slope region in Section 13.2. We also restrict attention to invariant sets that are recurrent.
Definition 7.3.
Given let be all compact, recurrent kfsm sets in with the Hausdorff topology and be all -invariant, Borel probability measures with the weak topology whose support is a .
Remark 7.4.
A standard argument from Aubry-Mather theory yields that the collection of all kfsm sets is compact in the Hausdorff topology. Since is compact, the collection of positive slope kfsm sets is also compact. However, since contains just the recurrent kfsm sets, it is not compact (see Section 9.1 and 13.2. We show shortly that is compact.
7.3. symbolic k-fold semi-monotone sets and the map
As with kfsm sets in the “physical” spaces and we define their symbolic analogs in the symbol spaces and where we give the symbol spaces the lexicographic order.
Definition 7.5.
-
(1)
A -invariant set is symbolic k-fold semi-monotone (kfsm) if and restricted to is weakly order preserving, or for
-
(2)
A -invariant set is symbolic k-fold semi-monotone (kfsm) if there is a -invariant lift to . (i.e., ) which is kfsm.
Everything has been organized thus far to ensure that k-fold semi-monotone sets are preserved under the itinerary maps.
Theorem 7.6.
Given for , a invariant set is kfsm if an only if is.
Proof.
We prove the case; the case follows. Theorem 6.1 shows that is an order preserving bijection. Since we have that if and only if . Using the additional fact that we have that is weakly order preserving on if and only if is weakly order preserving on ∎
In analogy with Definition 7.3 we collect together the various symbolic kfsm sets and their invariant measures.
Definition 7.7.
For given , let be all compact, invariant, recurrent symbolic kfsm sets in with the Hausdorff topology and be all -invariant, Borel probability measures with the weak topology whose support is a .
Lemma 7.8.
-
For
-
(a)
The map induces homeomorphisms and .
-
(b)
The spaces and are compact.
Proof.
For part (a) we know that is a conjugacy that that takes kfsm sets to kfsm sets which yields that is a homeomorphism. By hypothesis any is in and so there is some with on and thus on all address intervals . It is standard that this implies that is Hölder with exponent . This then implies that preserves Hausdorff convergence and so is a homeomorphism.
For part (b), since the space of all invariant Borel probability measures is compact metric, it suffices to show that is closed, and so assume and weakly with a recurrent kfsm set.
A noted in Remark 7.4 the collection of all kfsm sets in is compact in the Hausdorff topology and so there exists a kfsm set and with . A standard argument which we give here shows that . If this inclusion does not hold, there exists an , then let . Since the atoms of are countable, we may find an so that letting we have so that and so is a continuity set for thus via a standard result (page 16-17 of [6]) using the fact that . Thus for large enough , with we have and so with a contradiction. Thus . Now any invariant measure supported on must be supported on its recurrent set and so , as required. The compactness of follows from part(a). ∎
7.4. Rotation numbers and sets
For recall from section 2.3 that .
Lemma 7.9.
Assume ,
-
(a)
exists and is a single number.
-
(b)
If then is a semi-Denjoy minimal set.
-
(c)
If with , then consists of at least one and at most periodic orbits all with the same rotation number and period equal to .
-
(d)
and are continuous
Proof.
By Theorem 7.2 there exists a continuous, semi-monotone which interpolates the action of on . Rescaling to the standard circle let be defined as . By Lemma 3.1(a), is a single number and since , (a) follows. If then and so by Lemma 3.1(e) and thus is a semi-Denjoy minimal set yielding (b).
Now assume in lowest terms and so . Written in lowest terms
But since is semi-monotone, its recurrent set is a collection of periodic orbits and its rotation number in lowest terms has their period as its denominator which is thus . Since by assumption, we may choose to have flat spots then using Lemma 3.5, consists of at least one and at most periodic orbits, finishing (c).
It is standard from Aubry-Mather theory that is continuous on the collection of all kfsm sets and thus it is continuous restricted to the recurrent kfsm sets. As for measures, since (2.5) with continuous, continuity follows from the definition of weak convergence. ∎
Definition 7.10.
If and consists of a finite collection of periodic orbits it is called a cluster.
Remark 7.11.
-
(a)
For the case of general recurrent symbolic kfsm as we commented at the end of the last subsection we may consider with the model map. Using the itinerary map we have from Theorem 7.6 that is kfsm for and then all the conclusions of the previous theorem hold for it. Then using Theorem 6.1, the conclusions of the previous theorem hold with the obvious addition of hats in the appropriate places.
-
(b)
We shall need this implication of the symbolic case below. If with , tnen there exists a continuous, onto which is weakly order preserving, , and for all but a countable number of -orbits on which .
-
(c)
Using Lemma 3.1 a measure in is either the unique measure on a semi-Denjoy minimal set or a convex combination or measures supported on the periodic orbits in a cluster.
-
(d)
A is minimal if and only if it is uniquely ergodic and similarly for
8. The HM construction
For a given at this point we have reduced the identification of its positive slope kfsm sets to a question in symbolic dynamics. In this section we answer this symbolic question via a generalization of the procedure of Hedlund and Morse. The generalization constructs all symbolic kfsm recurrent sets for each .
Since a linear order is essential to the notion of semi-monotone we will again begin working on the line and then project to cyclic covers.
8.1. definition and basic properties
Fix an integer , a real number , and a vector with and . Such a pair is called allowable. Start with the intervals defined for by
(8.1) |
and then extend for and as . Thus each has width and each has width and the entire structure yields a invariant address system under the dynamics on
The good set is depends on and and is given by
Note that is dense, and has full Lebesgue measure. The itinerary map with respect to the given address system is denoted .
Definition 8.1.
Let .
Remark 8.2.
By construction, is and invariant. In addition, since for all , and we have . Also, since is compact, is also.
8.2. Cyclic covers
We now return to the compact quotients where the recurrent dynamics takes place and introduce measures into the HM-construction.
For fixed and allowable treat as an address system under the dynamics given by . Define the good set and on it define the itinerary map . We will often suppress the dependence of these quantities on various of the subscripted variables when they are clear from the context.
Definition 8.3.
Given and an allowable define the itinerary map as above. Let and where is the measure on induced by Lebesgue measure on .
Remark 8.4.
-
(1)
By construction . and so .
-
(2)
Let It is easy to check that the map is continuous on .
The next theorem describes the structure of the and shows that all symbolic kfsm sets are constructed by the HM procedure with equal to their rotation number.
Theorem 8.5.
-
(a)
For , is a semi-Denjoy minimal set with unique invariant probability measure .
-
(b)
For , is a finite collection of periodic orbits each with rotation number and period , and is a convex combination of the measures supported on the periodic orbits.
-
(c)
A is a recurrent symbolic kfsm set with if and only if for some allowable . Thus the collection of invariant probability measures supported on symbolic recurrent kfsm set is exactly the collection of for all allowable .
Proof.
We begin by proving portions of (a) and (b). For part (a) we first show that is minimal using a characterization usually attributed to Birkhoff: If is a continuous function of a compact metric space and , then is a minimal set if and only if for all there exists an so that for all there is a with . Pick in the good set , since is minimal, has the given property. Since restricted to is a homeomorphism and , has the desired property and further, is dense in and thus in . Thus is minimal under .
For part (b) note first that since is finite order and there are finitely many address intervals, must consist of finitely many periodic orbits. The other properties in (a) and (b) will follow from (c) (proved using just these two partial results on (a) and (b)) and Theorem 7.9 using Remark 7.11(a).
For part (c), we first show that is a recurrent symbolic kfsm set. By parts (a) and (b) we know that is recurrent and by Remark 8.4 that and . We show that is symbolic kfsm set by showing that its full lift to is as required by Definition 8.1. As noted in Remark 2.2, so we need to show that is semi-monotone on .
The first step is to show that is weakly order preserving. Assume with . It could happen (when is rational) that , but if there exists a least with , then since for all and is order preserving, certainly , and so is weakly order preserving.
We now show that is semi-monotone on . Let be the good set for and assume with . Then there exist with and and of necessity, and so . Since , we have
Thus is weakly order preserving on and so on . We have that satisfies all the conditions of the lift in Definition 7.5 and thus is symbolic kfsm.
Now for the converse assume that is symbolic recurrent kfsm with . Let be the lift that satisfies Definition 7.5. The proof splits into the two cases when is rational and irrational.
First assume with . We know from Lemma 7.9 and Remark 7.11 that consists of at most distinct periodic orbits each with period with . We assume for simplicity that is a single periodic orbit. The case of multiple periodic orbits is similar but with more elaborate indexing.
For let and . Since is a kfsm periodic orbit with -rotation number we may find an order preserving bijection with on . Thus acts on as reducing indices mod .
For , let where recall that is the length one cylinder set in . Since is order preserving, each consists of a collection of adjacent points from . If , let and when let . We now claim that is an address system as used in the HM-construction where is defined by and that for yielding .
Letting be the itinerary map for the address system we have by construction that for that . In addition, for all we also have . Thus for any point in the good set , for some . This shows that . The last step needed to show that is to check that the address system is of the type used in the HM construction.
We need only check that and for this it suffices to show that . Assume first that . Recalling that acts on the like , we see that there will be some and . Thus using there is a with and , a contradiction to the fact that and thus its allowable transitions are given by (5.2). On the other hand, if we have some and again yielding a contradiction to .
The irrational case is basically a continuous version of the rational one. By Remark 7.11(b) we have a continuous, onto which is weakly order preserving, , and for all but a countable number of -orbits on which .
For , let . Thus is a closed interval (perhaps empty) with , and adjacent intervals intersect only in their single common boundary point. We use as an address system with dynamics , good set , and itinerary map . By construction if with , then and so . Since is a Cantor set and is minus a countable set of -orbits we have that is dense . Thus taking closures, .
To finish we must show that is the type of address system allowable in the HM-construction. We just need for all . The proof is similar to the rational case. If then has a transition and if then has a transition . Either is a contradiction to . Thus letting for , we have .
The last sentence in (c) follows from the construction of . ∎
Remark 8.6.
In Section 9.3 below we shall see that for the irrational case that there is a unique with and for rational that there are, in general, many with . But note that if is a single periodic orbit then the proof above produces what we show is the unique with .
9. Parameterization of and by the HM construction
We know from Theorem 8.5(c) that the HM construction yields a correspondence between sets and symbolic kfsm set in . In addition, for a map using Theorem 7.6 we get a bijection from kfsm sets in to those in . Thus the HM construction provides a parameterization of . In this section we examine this parameterization as well as that of in detail.
9.1. Resonance and holes
As commented on above, the collection of all kfsm sets is closed in the compact metric space consisting of all compact -invariant sets with the Hausdorff topology. Thus the collection of all kfsm sets is complete. We have restricted attention here to recurrent kfsm sets or . This is because the recurrent ones are the most dynamically interesting and carry the invariant measures, but also as shown in Theorem 8.5, they are what is parameterized by the HM construction. As a consequence our primary space of interest is not complete, but rather has holes at points to be specified. What happens roughly is that as one takes the Hasudorff limit of recurrent kfsm sets the resulting kfsm set has homoclinic points that are not recurrent and so the limit is not recurrent and thus not any . This is a phenomenon well known in Aubry-Mather theory. Another point of view on these “holes” is given in Section 13.2 using the family of interpolated semi-monotone maps.
In the HM construction fix . For a given allowable recall the address intervals are for . Define and by . Note that with indices reduced mod .
Definition 9.1.
The pair is called resonant if for some and , . A pair that is not resonant is called nonresonant.
Remark 9.2.
Note that for a rational all are resonant as are all when some . Also, for all and ,
(9.1) |
which is the reason is restricted to in the definition.
The next lemma locates the “holes” in the space of all symbolic kfsm sets and thus in any .
Lemma 9.3.
-
(a)
Assume with is resonant. There exists a sequence and a nonrecurrent kfsm with in the Hausdorff topology on all compact subsets of .
-
(b)
Assume with . There exists a sequence and a nonrecurrent kfsm with in the Hausdorff topology on all compact subsets of .
Proof.
We suppress the dependence on to simplify notation. For (a), the resonance hypothesis implies that there are odd and with for some where we may assume . Since by shrinking some for we obtain and and arbitrarily close to it with and . In this way we can obtain sequences and with and . Thus
To simplify matters, assume that ; more complicated resonances are similar. Since using Remark 8.4(b),
Passing to a subsequence if necessary, by the compactness of the collection of symbolic kfsm sets there is a kfsm with in the Hausdorff topology and by its construction, . But can’t be recurrent since by the resonance any length block in must start with and end in .
The argument for (b) is similar, but now the perturbation must be in since if is fixed, when for all . Fix an and so . By increasing incrementally we may find sequences and with so that the initial length block of is . Thus if for small then
where . As in the proof of (a) passing to a subsequence if necessary, there is a kfsm with in the Hausdorff topology and by its construction, . But can’t be recurrent since any length block in must start and end with . ∎
9.2. continuity and injectivity
In doing the HM construction the explicit dependence of and on the pair was included. However, the elements of the pair have the interdependence and so when we treat and as functions it is sometimes better to eliminate the interdependence and treat them as functions of alone, but the two variable version will also continue to be useful. Thus we sometimes overload the function and write
and similarly for and the measure valued map . The collection of allowable parameters for each is then
The set of HM parameters corresponding to symbolic kfsm sets for is defined as
Remark 9.4.
By Theorem 8.5, is surjective and so provides a parameterization of the positive slope kfsm recurrent sets of and their invariant measures.
Example: The model map For the model map , since .
The first issue in understanding what the HM construction tells us about and is to understand the nature of the maps and . As indicated by Lemma 9.3 in the behaviour of the set-valued maps there is an essential distinction between the resonance and nonresonance cases.
Theorem 9.5.
Assume , for each ,
-
(a)
The map is onto and further it is continuous at nonresonant values and discontinuous at resonant values.
-
(b)
The map is a homeomorphism and thus is compact.
Proof.
Since we know from Lemma 7.8 that and are homemorphisms we only consider and . While these are functions of alone, for the proof it is clearer to resort to the two variable versions with the proviso that . Note that we have already shown in Theorem 8.5 that and are onto and . We will often need to include the explicit dependence of various objects on the variables, for example, , and we often suppress the dependence on .
We prove (b) first. We first show is continuous. For each and , let . The first observation from the HM construction is that
(9.2) |
For a length block in , let
and so implies that begins with the block . Also by the HM construction, with Lebesgue measure on the circle.
Recall that the weak topology on is generated by the metric
where is some enumeration of the blocks in . Since each is a (perhaps empty) interval with endpoints some , (9.2) implies that
Thus summing over blocks
so is continuous.
Since by definition in the HM construction, , is injective. Recall now that for the model map, which is compact. So is a homeomorphism with image the set of all measures on recurrent symbolic kfsm sets in . Thus, since we have that is also a homeomorphism. The compactness of was proved in Lemma 7.8.
The proof of (a) is based on the following claim: is continuous at if and only if for all there exits so that implies that for all blocks of length we have nonempty exactly when is nonempty.
To prove the claim, first note that continuity is equivalent to the following: given there exists so that implies that for each there is a with and for each there is a with . This implies that and thus . Since is small exactly when and agree in a long prefix block and , the claim follows.
We show that satisfies the condition in the claim when is nonresonant. Given for and consider again . By the HM construction we have for all , and . By nonresonance at , all the other are disjoint. Since by (9.2) each depends continuously on and the endpoints of each is some , we may find a so that implies that the are ordered around in the same way and with the same gaps between them as the . This implies that for each block of length , is nonempty exactly when is nonempty and so is continuous.
For the discontinuity, since the sets in Lemma 9.3(ab) are not recurrent, they are not equal to .
∎
Remark 9.6.
-
(a)
The parameter space is -dimensional. Assuming , then for a fixed and , the collection of all which yield is a -dimensional affine subspace. Thus the set of resonance parameters is a countable dense collection of codimension one affine subspaces and so the resonance case is full measure and dense
-
(b)
One can show that is lower semicontinuous [10], in particular if and some subsequence of converges to in the Hausdorff topology, then . The Semi-Continuity Lemma (see page 114 of [18]) yields that a lower semi-continuous set-valued function is continuous on a dense set. In the case of the last theorem exactly identifies this continuity set as the nonresonant .
9.3. Slices and skewness
Since and are defined and continuous on the various spaces etc., we may define the closed slices with a given rotation number.
Definition 9.7.
For let and and the restriction of to is denoted The slices of invariant measures and are defined similarly. The -slice of HM parameters is
Definition 9.8.
For an allowable parameter is called pure if consists of a single periodic orbit. The collection of pure parameters is denoted and it will be shown in Lemma 12.4 to be an affine lattice. For a its pure parameters are .
Remark 9.9.
For a given symbolic kfsm -periodic orbit by Theorem 8.5(c) there is some with . Since a periodic orbit is uniquely ergodic and is injective this is unique. Thus there is a bijection between symbolic kfsm -periodic orbits and .
Lemma 9.10.
Assume
-
(a)
For all , is a homeomorphism.
-
(b)
When , is injective as well as continuous at nonresonant and discontinuous at resonant .
-
(c)
When , is injective on .
Proof.
Since restricts to a homeomorphism on slices we only consider and . Part (a) follows immediately from Theorem 9.5.
For (b), when the assignment of a semi-Denjoy kfsm set with rotation number to its unique invariant measure yields a bijection and . Since by (a), is injective, we have that is also. Continuity of at nonresonant values on irrational slices follows directly from (a). Discontinuity at resonant values on irrational slices follows from Lemma 9.3(a).
∎
Remark 9.11.
Since is a finite, set the continuity of is not particularly interesting, but we will remark on it in Section 12.4.
The skewness of a -invariant measure in is the amount of measure in each fundamental domain. When its component is large, roughly its -orbits are moving slowly through . When we project to the base in the next section the skewness will thus indicate how quickly orbits are moving of the loop of the kfsm set.
Definition 9.12.
Assume
-
(a)
For ,
-
(b)
For ,
Note that the skewness takes values in the unit simplex , and contains no information about the rotation number.
Lemma 9.13.
Assume
-
(a)
-
(b)
-
(c)
For , is inverse to and so it is a homeomorphism.
-
(d)
is a homeomorphism from onto its image as is from onto its image
Remark 9.14.
The last lemma formalizes the description
in the Introduction on the
parametrization of the weak disks of
semi-Denjoy minimal sets by their speed in each “loop” around
the circle. For rational pure parameters the skewness counts the
number of elements in each fundamental domain and this thus
yields a discrete parametrization of the kfsm -periodic
orbits.
10. kfsm sets in and
10.1. In
We now return to our central concern, -invariant sets in that have a lift to that is semi-monotone. Once again the definition makes sense for any degree one circle map but we restrict to the class .
Definition 10.1.
Given , a compact -invariant set is kfsm if it has a -invariant lift which is kfsm, or equivalently, has a -invariant lift which is kfsm. Let be all compact, invariant, recurrent kfsm sets in with the Hausdorff topology and be all -invariant, Borel probability measures supported on with the weak topology
Thus when is kfsm, it has a lift to which is semi-monotone under the action of on its lift.
To make contact with the usual definitions in Aubry-Mather theory, assume that is such that is k-fold semi-monotone. This happens exactly when there is a point with and for all positive integers ,
In Aubry-Mather theory one would write .
Remark 10.2.
-
(a)
induces continuous onto maps and .
-
(b)
is kfsm if and only if is.
-
(c)
If is is a -fold semi-monotone then it is also -fold semi-monotone for any .
-
(d)
If is a periodic orbit of of type (which are perhaps not relatively prime) then has a lift to with and is monotone since implies and so is automatically -fsm.
-
(e)
Using Lemma 7.6 a recurrent kfsm set in is either a collection of periodic orbits all with the same rotation number (a cluster) or else a semi-Denjoy minimal set. A minimal kfsm set is either a single periodic orbit or else a semi-Denjoy minimal set.
-
(f)
A collection of periodic orbits all with the same rotation number that individually are kfsm when considered as a set is not of necessity a kfsm (i.e., a cluster)
10.2. Symbolic kfsm sets in
We now consider symbolic kfsm sets in the symbolic base .
Definition 10.3.
A -invariant set is kfsm if there is a -invariant lift (i.e., ) which is kfsm or equivalently, has a -invariant lift which is kfsm. Given let be all recurrent kfsm sets in with the Hausdorff topology and be all -invariant, Borel probability measures supported on with the weak topology
Using Theorem 7.6 we connect kfsm sets in to their symbolic analogs in and get
Corollary 10.4.
A invariant set is kfsm if an only if is. Further, induces homeomorphisms and .
Remark 10.5.
All the comments in Remark 10.2 hold for symbolic kfsm sets mutatis mutandis.
10.3. The HM construction and its symmetries
We bring the HM construction back into play and take the projections from to .
Definition 10.6.
Let and
We know from Theorem 9.5 that the HM construction provides a parameterization of and , the goal now is to get a parameterization of the kfsm sets and their invariant measures in , i.e., of and . For this we need to understand the symmetries inherent in the HM construction.
Recall the left shift on the parameter is . There are two types of symmetries to be considered. The first is when different give rise to the same . For minimal this happens if and only if the ’s are shifts of each other as is stated in parts (a) and (d) in the next theorem. The second sort of symmetry happens when some is also a for some , which is to say the map is not one-to-one. In the minimal case this happens if and only if as is stated in parts (b) and (c) below.
Lemma 10.7.
-
Fix and assume is allowable for .
-
(a)
For all , and so
-
(b)
If for some then
(10.1) and where .
-
(c)
If is minimal and (10.1) holds then . If for all , then is a homeomorphism.
-
(d)
If and are minimal and , then for some , .
Proof.
The fact that is an easy consequence of the HM construction and since we have , proving (a) The first part of (b) follows directly from (a) using the given fact that .
For the second part of (b), first note that if is the address system for and then since , we have . This implies that under the quotient , descends to an allowable HM-address system on using . Thus using the dynamics on both address systems, the corresponding entries of and are equal and so .
To prove the first part of (c), as remarked in Remark 7.11, if is minimal it is uniquely ergodic. Thus if (10.1) holds, then and since is injective by Theorem 9.5, . Now for the second part of (c), certainly is continuous and onto, so assume it is not injective. Then there exists with and . Thus for some , and so if , . But by assumption is minimal and so and so , a contradiction. Thus is injective, as required
For part (d), implies that
Since each and is minimal, for some , , and so by part (c), . ∎
Remark 10.8.
It is possible that if is a cluster of periodic orbits, could be injective on some of them and not on others.
10.4. continuity and injectivity
Let with equivalence classes denoted . Note that for some is resonant if and only if is, so we may call resonant or nonresonant.
Since the action preserves slices we define . The -slices of and are defined in the obvious way. If is a pure parameter so is for any and so we define . Note that is all such that is a single periodic orbit it is not all such that is a single periodic orbit.
Definition 10.9.
Lemma 10.7 implies that induces a map and that induces a map . The induced maps on slices are and
Theorem 10.10.
Assume , for each ,
-
(a)
The map is onto, continuous at nonresonant values and discontinuous at resonant values. Restricted to an irrational slice it is injective, continuous at nonresonant values and discontinuous at resonant values. Restricted to a rational slices it is injective on the pure lattice.
-
(b)
The map is a homeomorphism when restricted to irrational slices and pure rational lattices.
Proof.
By construction we have the following commuting diagram
(10.2) |
with the vertical maps all onto and continuous and the composition of the bottom horizontal maps and the map also denotes the map induced on equivalence classes in . Since the given versions of and are homeomorphisms we need only consider and . The fact that these are continuous follows from Lemma 9.10 and the just stated properties of the diagram as do the various continuity assertions in the theorem. We prove the discontinuity result for on irrational slices. The other discontinuity assertions follow similarly.
Assume is resonant with . From Lemma 9.3 and its proof we have a sequence so that and a with nonrecurrent. In the quotients and by continuity. We need to show that Now if we are done so assume . Thus for some , and so by Lemma 5.3(e), for some , . This implies that the action of on is conjugated to that on by . But by the classification Theorem 8.5, is a minimal set and thus so is and so is recurrent, a contradiction, yielding the discontinuity.
To show is injective on the sets indicated, assume with either and in the pure lattice or . In either case and are minimal and since is a semiconjugacy, and are also. Thus by Lemma 10.7(d), for some , and so .
Remark 10.11.
We remark on the relationship of pure parameters to and . As a short hand we indicate symbolic periodic orbits by their repeating block. A simple computation shows that and so . Note that as required and is the -Sturmian. Now and so . A further computation shows that both and are the unique invariant measure on and thus is not injective on rational slices of despite the fact that it is injective on rational slices of . The underlying explanation is that being a pure parameter requires to be a single periodic orbit not that be one.
Definition 10.12.
Remark 10.13.
On an irrational quotient slice , let , then is the inverse of and may be viewed as a parameterization of by skewness as in Remark 9.14. Also as in that remark, skewness also provides a parameterization of the quotient of the pure parameters.
10.5. Sturmian minimal sets, the case
We will need the special and much studied case of symbolic kfsm sets for . When there is only one allowable choice for , namely and so we write for . When is rational is a single periodic orbit and when is irrational it is a semi-Denjoy minimal set. These minimal sets (and associated sequences) have significant historical importance and an abundance of literature (see [2] for a survey). Their main importance here is as an indicator of when a given number is in the rotation set.
Definition 10.14.
The minimal set is called the Sturmian minimal set with rotation number .
To avoid confusion with the many definitions in the literature we note that here “Sturmian” refers to a minimal set and not a sequence and it is subset of the one-sided shift . The next result is standard and we remark on one proof in Remark 13.6.
Lemma 10.15.
if and only if . If , then in ,
Definition 10.16.
For a fixed , let be defined by for .
Remark 10.17.
Since if follows directly from Lemma 10.7 that for any , , the Sturmian minimal set with rotation number .
11. Structure of
One obvious property of is the symmetry for all . The full structure of for a general is quite complicated and will be saved for future papers. Here we focus on the structure near the diagonal in .
11.1. Irrationals on the diagonal
We parameterize the diagonal by using as defined in the previous section and so
For the next result asserts that for each irrational there is some so that the neighborhood . It gives the proof of Theorem 1.2(a).
Theorem 11.1.
Assume and
-
(a)
-
(b)
If with , there exists a so that .
-
(c)
If , then contains a -dimensional topological disc consisting of unique invariant measures each supported on a member of a family of -fold semi-monotone semi-Denjoy minimal sets with rotation number .
Proof.
Assume . For (a) , the Sturmian minimal set with rotation number and from Lemma 10.15, if and only if .
For (b) note that the pair is nonresonant. We will first show that if then there exists an , so that implies . Pick with . Thus by Lemma 10.15, in
and let
Thus implies that the compact, invariant set satisfies and so .
Using the continuity of at nonresonant irrationals from Theorem 10.10(a) there is a so that implies , and so .
Since , the neighborhood descends to one in and is a homeomorphism on irrational slices of (Theorem 10.10(b)) yielding (c). ∎
12. Rational Slices
In this section we study rational slices in the HM parameter and in and . As proved in Theorem 8.5, each consists of a collection of periodic orbits all of period with the same rotation number and as a set they are kfsm. Note that this is stronger than each periodic orbit being individually kfsm. The invariant measure is a convex combination of the unique measures supported on each periodic orbit.
12.1. periods in
The next lemma examines how the periods of can change after projection to via .
Lemma 12.1.
Fix and and assume is allowable for . If with and it is the least such , then the period of is .
12.2. the rational structure theorem
The theorem in this section describes in more detail how the measures on -kfsm vary with the parameter.
In the HM construction fix , with and an allowable . We often suppress dependence on these choices and so , etc. Let so is the period of acting on . Recall the address intervals are for and so . The good set is and the itinerary map is . When we write it is implicitly assumed that .
The orbit of , , partitions into pieces, each of width . Thus is a fundamental domain for the action of on in the sense that as a disjoint union. Thus for each there is a unique with , and then let . Note that since , and that all as well as both endpoints of are not in . Finally, for and , let .
Lemma 12.2.
-
Assume .
-
(a)
if and only if for all .
-
(b)
For each , if and only if and are in the same component of .
-
(c)
For each , if and only if and are in the same component of where is the circle with .
Proof.
First note that both endpoints of are not in so they are out of consideration for and in what follows.
For (a) one implication is obvious. For the other, it suffices to we show that the collection of determines . By Remark 7.11 we know that and so its one step transitions are governed by (5.2). If then or and we know which depending on whether or not. Similarly, if then is determined by whether or not. Thus is determined completing the proof of (a).
For (b), first note that and . Thus is exactly filled with iterates of with disjoint interiors. Thus for all . Thus we only consider . If is such that , then for all and if then for all . If , then for in , then and for , . The last situation to consider is . Since , we have and so then for in , then and for , , completing the proof of (b).
If every as the same number of indices in , so assume that with the other inequality being similar. If is such that then for all . If is such that then for all . If is such that then if and only if in . If is such that then if and only if in , finishing the proof. ∎
Corollary 12.3.
If the nonempty connected components of are , then consists of exactly distinct periodic orbits with if and only if . Further, with the unique invariant probability measure supported in and .
Proof.
As noted above, is a fundamental domain for the action of on and so it it suffices to study for .
Combining Lemma 12.2(a) and (b) we have that for , if and only if and are in the same component . Further, using Lemma 12.2(c), and can be on the same -orbit if and only if they are in the same component , proving the first sentence of the theorem. The second sentence follows from the definition of , the fact that , and preserves Lebesgue measure. ∎
12.3. The pure lattice and the structure of
We now describe the pure affine lattice in more detail with an eye towards counting the number of -periodic kfsm sets. For this a new method of specifying the address system in will be useful. We fix a and an and sometimes suppress dependence on them
Recall that a pair specifies an address system with each . For each let be the signed displacement of the address system from its totally symmetric position given by . Thus
(12.1) |
Since in the HM-construction is fixed for all , the vector is -dimensional and so is an affine map from the simplex to a subset of . Note that .
Lemma 12.4.
Given and there exists a with so that is a pure parameter for if and only if in .
Proof.
The structure theorem Theorem 12.3 implies that is a single periodic orbit if and only if no is in the interior of . This happens if and only if all are contained in . Now divides evenly into subintervals of length . For each let be such that is the point on that is closest to and define . Thus and is pure if and only if . ∎
Definition 12.5.
The set is called the -pure affine lattice as is its pre-image
12.4. Sub-resonance and the size of clusters
Definition 12.6.
When , the pair is called sub-resonant if for some and , .
It follows from Theorem 12.3 that the number of sub-resonances in a controls the number of distinct periodic orbits in a cluster with no sub-resonance corresponding to distinct periodic orbits and all the on a single orbit corresponding to being a single periodic orbit so is a pure parameter
The set sub-resonance parameters is a finite collection of codimension one affine subspaces in and thus the no sub-resonance case is open, dense and full measure in . Thus in the typical parameter corresponds to a cluster of periodic orbits. It also follows that the assignment restricted to is constant and thus continuous on connected components of the no sub-resonance parameters and is discontinuous at the sub-resonance parameters.
12.5. Estimating the number of kfsm sets
For a given the number of points from the pure -lattice contained in tells us how many distinct periodic orbits there are in . So by Lemma 10.7 it yields how many distinct periodic -kfsm sets has. We get an estimate for this number using the continuity properties of from Theorem 9.5 and the relationship of kfsm sets in to those in . The next result proves Theorem 1.2(b).
Theorem 12.7.
If , , and is a sequence of rationals in lowest terms with , then there exists a so that for sufficiently large the number of distinct periodic kfsm sets in is greater than or equal to .
Proof.
By Theorem 9.5(b) there is an so that where recall that is the Sturmian for on the diagonal of . Since is a homeomorphism there is an -ball in the max norm with about in with . Thus if there is a -ball in the max norm, i.e., a -dimensional hypercube , about in with .
We next estimate the number of pure resonance in . By Lemma 12.4, the pure form an affine lattice with linear separation . Thus for close enough to , the number of lattice points in is larger than
since . Thus since is a homeomorphism the same estimate holds for the number of pure lattice points in . By Theorem 9.5 this tells us how many distinct periodic are in and thus in by Theorem 7.6.
To project this estimate to kfsm sets in , recall from Theorem 10.10 that is injective on the pure lattice. The projection is at most to and so the number of distinct periodic orbits in is greater than or equal to
∎
Remark 12.8.
For a pure for when for some the period of the counted in the theorem is (Lemma 12.1). In the typical case of no such symmetry the period is . So, for example, when and are relatively prime, the counted periodic orbit has rotation type and when divides the rotation type is . By making judicious choices of the sequence , one can control the rotation types of the counted periodic orbits.
13. Parameterization via the interpolated family of maps
We return now to the heuristic description in the introduction of kfsm sets via a family of interpolated semi-monotone maps and prove a few results and connections to the HM-parameterization. Since we are mainly developing a heuristic, some details are left to the reader. In many ways this point of view is better for studying kfsm sets while the HM construction is better for measures. Initially the parameterization depends on the map but using the model map we will get a uniform parameterization.
13.1. The family of k-fold interpolated maps for
Fix with preferred lift . For there is a unique with . Denote this as ( for branch). Let and with the as defined in Section 5.1. Note from the definition of the class , and by equivariance, and .
Definition 13.1.
For define via for .
Fix . For and for define on as
and extend to so that . See Figure 1. Next define as the descent of to .
Example: The model map For the model map , and .
Given a compact , for let
If for some we have let otherwise let . Similarly, and if for some , we have let otherwise let . Not that these ’s and ’s are unrelated to those in Section 9.1.
Theorem 13.2.
Assume is compact and invariant. The following are equivalent
-
(a)
is a kfsm set
-
(b)
For , .
-
(c)
for
(13.1) thus .
Proof.
If for some , then restricted to doesn’t preserve the cyclic order, and so (a) implies (b). (c) implies (a) since invariant sets in nondecreasing maps are always kfsm. Finally, (b) says that for in the given range. ∎
Definition 13.3.
For , let
and so .
Remark 13.4.
-
(a)
Nothing in the theorem requires to be recurrent. If it is, so , from Theorem 8.5, where and .
-
(b)
When is a periodic orbit or cluster, is -dimensional. When is a periodic orbit cluster its box is equal to the intersections of the boxes of its constituent single periodic orbits.
-
(c)
When is a semi-Denjoy minimal set contained in recall that a tight flat spot of is one for which both endpoints of a flat spot of are in . The dimension of is the same as the number of loose flat spots in . Since by Lemma 3.5(b), cannot have tight flat spots, the dimension of is between and .
-
(d)
Note that in contrast, in the HM parameterization, each single periodic orbit or semi-Denjoy minimal corresponds to just one point.
-
(e)
When , if from the HM construction then the number of loose flat spots of is the same as the number of resonances of i.e., with for some which is then the same as the dimension of .
13.2. Nonrecurrence and kfsm sets that hit the negative slope region
Throughout this paper we have assumed that the kfsm sets were recurrent and avoided the negative slope region. In this section we use the interpolated maps to motivate these assumptions.
Assume now that is a kfsm set for some and contains points in the negative slope region of . It still follows that is an invariant set of some . Let be the maximal recurrent set in . A gap of is a component of the complement of that contains a flat spot of . In formulas, a gap is an interval for some . Since acting on is semi-monotone, can contain at most one point in the negative slope region within each gap.
There are two cases. In the first, which may happen for both rational and irrational rotation number, for all there is some so that for all . This implies that for all and so by Lemma 3.5(c), there is an so that for all . Thus in this case negative slope orbits add no additional recurrent dynamics. In Figure 4 the disks give part of a periodic kfsm set and the squares show additional homoclinic points to this kfsm set in the negative and positive slope region.

The second case holds for just rational rotation number and is when some is a periodic point; this does add new recurrent kfsm sets. Since the periodic points on the endpoint of a gap always return, there is, in fact, a periodic point in the negative slope region of each gap of . By adjusting we can assume that all these gap periodic orbits are also superstable periodic orbits of . Since the periodic points in are all unstable the periodic points of must alternate with these gap periodic points. In particular, the number of gap periodic orbits equals the number of periodic orbits in . Thus the addition of the negative slope periodic orbits just adds a factor of two to the basic estimates of Section 12.5.
We again use Figure 4 but this time to discuss the holes in the space of recurrent kfsm sets. Let be an interploted map whose flat spot contains the homoclinic points indicated by squares. Assume we are in the case and so each interpolated map contains exactly one recurrent semi-monotone set in its positive slope region. As increases to the sets converge in the Hausdorff topology to not just but to that set union the boxed point in the positive slope region. A similar phenomenon happens as decreases to . This phenomenon also clearly happens for loose gaps of semi-Denjoy minimal sets and happens for all . This is the geometric explanation of the holes in and the discontinuity of discussed in Section 9.1.
13.3. The rotation number diagram
Fix . Since we define . Thus if is compact invariant then . We treat as a function .
Let . The open projective positive cone in is . For a given define as
where . So and give the top and bottom edges of the level set when view from the origin.
Theorem 13.5.
Assume and construct as above
-
(a)
is continuous function and is nondecreasing in along any line with all .
-
(b)
For all the functions and are continuous.
-
(c)
For rational , while for then . Thus each level set is homeomorphic to a -dimensional open disk product a nontrivial closed interval while each is homeomorphic to a -dimensional open disk.
-
(d)
Proof.
Part (a) follows directly from Lemma 3.1(b) and (c). For (b) assume to the contrary that is not continuous. Then there is a sequence with . Passing to a subsequence if necessary, there is some with . By the continuity of , and by the nonconvergence assumption, there is some with . Thus again by the continuity of for large enough there is some with , a contradiction. Therefore, is continuous: the continuity of is similar.
For (c), pick any and with and let . Then by Lemma 3.5, has a periodic orbit . Since is a finite set there is a nontrivial interval so that implies and so .
To complete (c), assume to the contrary that for some , . Thus by the continuity of there is an open ball . Pick and let be the semi-Denjoy minimal set in guaranteed by Lemma 3.5 which has at least one tight gap, say the gap associated with the first coordinate of . Let be the -coordinate of the right hand endpoint of this gap and so . Since is minimal under there are points with and arbitrarily close to which have a with . Now let and and we have that which says that the iterate of the first coordinate flat spot of is in that flat spot. Thus has a periodic orbit and so for some arbitrarily close to , a contradiction.
For (d), assume and . Let be the semi-monotone map constructed from to have a single flat spot of height and similarly constructed having a single flat spot of height . Since , we have . Now by Lemma 3.5, there is a compact invariant and so and so and so . Similarly, . Note that by definition of , the compact invariant also satisfies and so . Similarly, . Thus . Finally, consider the entire family for . Since is continuous in , for each there is a with . Further, for each there is a compact invariant and and thus
∎
Remark 13.6.
-
(a)
Note that and and thus implies . Further, it follows from (d) that the image of each is .
-
(b)
Part (b) deals only with the part of the level sets of in the open set . The extension to all of is technical and not very illuminating so we leave it to the interested reader.
-
(c)
Let act on as the left cyclic shift. It easily follows that .
-
(d)
When there is a one-dimensional family for . The rotation number is nondecreasing in and assumes each irrational value at a point and each rational value on an interval by (a) and (c). For each there is a unique recurrent and is the Sturmian with the given rotation number. This along with the geometry of the family give the proof of Lemma 10.15.
13.4. Comparing to the model map
In this section we use the interpolation parameter to parameterize the for a general . Notice that for the model map, is all of . Thus and so we can pass back to using the inverse of the itinerary map. Thus we can use a subset of the interpolation parameters of the model map to parameterize using the symbolic representation of a kfsm set as the link. This subset turns out to be a square of the form . In this section we often add an additional subscript of or to indicate which map or is involved
Since we may define by . By Theorem 6.1 is an orientation preserving homeomorphism onto its image as well as a conjugacy. It thus induces a map .
Recall that the parameters for the model map are . For a map extend it to the Cartesian product as .
Theorem 13.7.
Given and construct the interpolation parameters . There exists an interval and an orientation preserving homeomorphism so that for all , and for all , . Where
Proof.
Construct as above. Its properties imply that
(13.2) |
for all and . Let and . Then restricts to . Since and is compact we can extend equivariantly to a homeomorphism which using (13.2) satisfies . Finally, since (recall is the left cyclic shift) there is a with . ∎
Thi result implies that the -diagram for looks like -dimensional cube cut from inside the -diagram of the model map and perhaps rescaled.
13.5. The case : numerics
Figure 5 shows the rotation number diagram for the model map . Each connected union of rectangles is the level set of some rational. The rationals with denominator less than are shown. Only the center rectangle is labeled for each rational. In the figure each rectangle corresponds to a different -fold semi-monotone periodic orbit. The intersections of these rectangles correspond to which have a cluster of two periodic orbits

The computation of this diagram used a discrete version of the HM construction. The construction depends on integers with , and relatively prime, and . The discrete circle is the finite cyclic group and it is acted on by . The address intervals are , and . Let be the itinerary of the point under .
Using Theorem 8.5(b), when is odd, has a single period orbit in . Expanding the points in to intervals in the circle as in the proof of Theorem 8.5(c), we see that by varying the construction generates all the symbolic -periodic -fold semi-monotone sets in .
Now when is even, has a pair of period orbits. When is odd, these generate different periodic orbits . However, even corresponds to a pure parameter and so varying through the even generates all the symbolic -periodic -fold semi-monotone sets in .
The next step is to use to compute its symbolic box as in Corollary 14.1 below. Finally, we take the inverse of the itinerary map for the model map to get a box in the parameter. Because the map has uniform slope of three in its positive slope region the formula for this inverse is ,
(13.3) |
14. Symbolic kfsm sets and the map
Using the model map Theorem 13.2 characterising “physical” kfsm sets can be directly transformed into a characterization of symbolic kfsm sets. For compact for define
Since is order preserving and onto for the model map we have
Corollary 14.1.
Assume is compact and shift invariant. The following are equivalent
-
(1)
is kfsm
-
(2)
For , with indices reduced mod
If is recurrent we know that each has for some allowable which yields an indirect connection between the interpolated semi-monotone maps and HM parameterization.
There is a well known connection between the dynamics of and the full shift on symbols. This yields a connection of the symbolic kfsm sets as described by this corollary to invariant sets of the circle on which the action of is semi-monotone, sometimes call circular orbits.

In Figure 6 we show the conditions forced by Corollary 14.1 as flat spots in the graph of for and . There are two classes of flat spots. Those in class A are forced by the condition that and thus satisfies (5.2). These are the intervals of width , and . These conditions are satisfied by all symbolic kfsm sets in the corollary. The other three flat spots in class B are determined by the conditions in part (b) of the corollary and vary with the symbolic kfsm set. Note that the result of addding all the flat spots is a degree one semi-monotone circle map as expected. See figures in [20] and [33].
The figure also illustrates a clear difference between the kfsm sets for bimodal circle maps and circular orbits for -one. Specifically, the kfsm sets correspond to a specific subclass of circular orbits for . On the other hand, there is clearly a tight relationship between the theories which needs to be investigated. Perhaps the degree reduction process described in [7, 33] would be a good place to start.
References
- [1] Lluís Alsedà, Jaume Llibre, and MichałMisiurewicz, Combinatorial dynamics and entropy in dimension one, second ed., Advanced Series in Nonlinear Dynamics, vol. 5, World Scientific Publishing Co., Inc., River Edge, NJ, 2000. MR 1807264
- [2] P. Arnoux, Sturmian sequences, Substitutions in dynamics, arithmetics and combinatorics, Lecture Notes in Math., vol. 1794, Springer, Berlin, 2002, pp. 143–198. MR 1970391
- [3] Joseph Auslander, Minimal flows and their extensions, North-Holland Mathematics Studies, vol. 153, North-Holland Publishing Co., Amsterdam, 1988, Notas de Matemática [Mathematical Notes], 122. MR 956049
- [4] Marcy Barge and Joe Martin, The construction of global attractors, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 110 (1990), no. 2, 523–525. MR 1023342
- [5] C. Bernhardt, Rotation intervals of a class of endomorphisms of the circle, Proc. London Math. Soc. (3) 45 (1982), no. 2, 258–280. MR 670037
- [6] Patrick Billingsley, Convergence of probability measures, second ed., Wiley Series in Probability and Statistics: Probability and Statistics, John Wiley & Sons, Inc., New York, 1999, A Wiley-Interscience Publication. MR 1700749
- [7] Alexander Blokh, James M. Malaugh, John C. Mayer, Lex G. Oversteegen, and Daniel K. Parris, Rotational subsets of the circle under , Topology Appl. 153 (2006), no. 10, 1540–1570. MR 2216120
- [8] David Bowman, Ross Flek, and Greg Markowsky, Rotation numbers and symbolic dynamics, Ann. Acad. Sci. Fenn. Math. 40 (2015), no. 1, 227–234. MR 3310081
- [9] Philip Boyland, Rotation sets and monotone periodic orbits for annulus homeomorphisms, Comment. Math. Helv. 67 (1992), no. 2, 203–213. MR 1161281
- [10] by same author, Weak disks of Denjoy minimal sets, Ergodic Theory Dynam. Systems 13 (1993), no. 4, 597–614. MR 1257024
- [11] by same author, Topological methods in surface dynamics, Topology Appl. 58 (1994), no. 3, 223–298. MR 1288300
- [12] Philip Boyland, André de Carvalho, and Toby Hall, Inverse limits as attractors in parameterized families, Bull. Lond. Math. Soc. 45 (2013), no. 5, 1075–1085. MR 3104999
- [13] Philip L. Boyland, Bifurcations of circle maps: Arnol’d tongues, bistability and rotation intervals, Comm. Math. Phys. 106 (1986), no. 3, 353–381. MR 859816
- [14] M. Brown, Some applications of an approximation theorem for inverse limits, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 11 (1960), 478–483. MR 0115157 (22 #5959)
- [15] Karen M. Brucks and Henk Bruin, Topics from one-dimensional dynamics, London Mathematical Society Student Texts, vol. 62, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2004. MR 2080037
- [16] Shaun Bullett and Pierrette Sentenac, Ordered orbits of the shift, square roots, and the devil’s staircase, Math. Proc. Cambridge Philos. Soc. 115 (1994), no. 3, 451–481. MR 1269932
- [17] Alain Chenciner, Jean-Marc Gambaudo, and Charles Tresser, Une remarque sur la structure des endomorphismes de degré du cercle, C. R. Acad. Sci. Paris Sér. I Math. 299 (1984), no. 5, 145–148. MR 756312
- [18] Gustave Choquet, Lectures on analysis. Vol. II: Representation theory, W. A. Benjamin, Inc., New York-Amsterdam, 1969, Edited by J. Marsden, T. Lance and S. Gelbart. MR 0250012
- [19] Bráulio A. Garcia and Valentín Mendoza, Non-monotone periodic orbits of a rotational horseshoe, Ergodic Theory Dynam. Systems 39 (2019), no. 7, 1870–1903. MR 3961679
- [20] Lisa Goldberg and Charles Tresser, Rotation orbits and the Farey tree, Ergodic Theory Dynam. Systems 16 (1996), no. 5, 1011–1029. MR 1417771
- [21] Lisa R. Goldberg, Fixed points of polynomial maps. I. Rotation subsets of the circles, Ann. Sci. École Norm. Sup. (4) 25 (1992), no. 6, 679–685. MR 1198093
- [22] Christophe Golé, Symplectic twist maps, Advanced Series in Nonlinear Dynamics, vol. 18, World Scientific Publishing Co., Inc., River Edge, NJ, 2001, Global variational techniques. MR 1992005
- [23] Walter Helbig Gottschalk and Gustav Arnold Hedlund, Topological dynamics, American Mathematical Society Colloquium Publications, Vol. 36, American Mathematical Society, Providence, R.I., 1955. MR 0074810
- [24] Kevin Hockett and Philip Holmes, Josephson’s junction, annulus maps, Birkhoff attractors, horseshoes and rotation sets, Ergodic Theory Dynam. Systems 6 (1986), no. 2, 205–239. MR 857198
- [25] by same author, Bifurcation to badly ordered orbits in one-parameter families of circle maps, or angels fallen from the devil’s staircase, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 102 (1988), no. 4, 1031–1051. MR 934888
- [26] by same author, Bifurcation to rotating Cantor sets in maps of the circle, Nonlinearity 1 (1988), no. 4, 603–616. MR 967473
- [27] Ryuichi Ito, Rotation sets are closed, Math. Proc. Cambridge Philos. Soc. 89 (1981), no. 1, 107–111. MR 591976
- [28] Leo P. Kadanoff, Supercritical behavior of an ordered trajectory, J. Statist. Phys. 31 (1983), no. 1, 1–27. MR 711468
- [29] Anatole Katok and Boris Hasselblatt, Introduction to the modern theory of dynamical systems, Encyclopedia of Mathematics and its Applications, vol. 54, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1995, With a supplementary chapter by Katok and Leonardo Mendoza. MR 1326374
- [30] Patrice Le Calvez, Propriétés dynamiques des difféomorphismes de l’anneau et du tore, Astérisque (1991), no. 204, 131. MR 1183304
- [31] Mark Levi, Qualitative analysis of the periodically forced relaxation oscillations, Mem. Amer. Math. Soc. 32 (1981), no. 244, vi+147. MR 617687
- [32] Robert MacKay and Jaroslav Stark, Lectures on orbits of minimal action for area-preserving maps, Warwick Maths Institute preprint (1985 (corrected 1989)).
- [33] James Martin Malaugh, Rotational sets of the circle under z(d), ProQuest LLC, Ann Arbor, MI, 2003, Thesis (Ph.D.)–The University of Alabama at Birmingham. MR 2705028
- [34] Nelson G. Markley and Michael E. Paul, Almost automorphic symbolic minimal sets without unique ergodicity, Israel J. Math. 34 (1979), no. 3, 259–272 (1980). MR 570885
- [35] John N. Mather, More Denjoy minimal sets for area preserving diffeomorphisms, Comment. Math. Helv. 60 (1985), no. 4, 508–557. MR 826870
- [36] MichałMisiurewicz, Rotation intervals for a class of maps of the real line into itself, Ergodic Theory Dynam. Systems 6 (1986), no. 1, 117–132. MR 837979
- [37] Marston Morse and Gustav A. Hedlund, Symbolic dynamics II. Sturmian trajectories, Amer. J. Math. 62 (1940), 1–42. MR 745
- [38] S. Newhouse, J. Palis, and F. Takens, Bifurcations and stability of families of diffeomorphisms, Inst. Hautes Études Sci. Publ. Math. (1983), no. 57, 5–71. MR 699057
- [39] S. Ostlund, DA Rand, E Siggia, and J Sethna, Supercritical behavior of an ordered trajectory, Physica D 8 (1983), no. 3, 303–342.
- [40] Kamlesh Parwani, Monotone periodic orbits for torus homeomorphisms, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 133 (2005), no. 6, 1677–1683. MR 2120254
- [41] J. J. P. Veerman, Irrational rotation numbers, Nonlinearity 2 (1989), no. 3, 419–428. MR 1005057
- [42] Peter Veerman, Symbolic dynamics and rotation numbers, Phys. A 134 (1986), no. 3, 543–576. MR 861742
- [43] by same author, Symbolic dynamics of order-preserving orbits, Phys. D 29 (1987), no. 1-2, 191–201. MR 923891
- [44] Ya-Nan Wang and Wen-Xin Qin, Many Denjoy minimal sets for monotone recurrence relations, Nonlinearity 27 (2014), no. 9, 2393–2408. MR 3266859