This paper was converted on www.awesomepapers.org from LaTeX by an anonymous user.
Want to know more? Visit the Converter page.

\providecommand\drfi

draft \isopage[12] \setlrmargins**1 \checkandfixthelayout

Nonexistence of colimits in naive discrete homotopy theory

Daniel Carranza    Krzysztof Kapulkin    Jinho Kim
Abstract

We show that the quasicategory defined as the localization of the category of (simple) graphs at the class of A-homotopy equivalences does not admit colimits. In particular, we settle in the negative the question of whether the A-homotopy equivalences in the category of graphs are part of a model structure.

00footnotetext: 2020 Mathematics Subject Classification: 05C25 (primary), 55U35, 18N60, 18N50 (secondary).

During a recent workshop “Discrete and Combinatorial Homotopy Theory” at the American Institute of Mathematics, it was asked whether A-homotopy equivalences are part of a model structure on the category of simple graphs. In this short note, we settle this question in the negative by considering the quasicategory associated to the marked category (i.e., a category along with a distinguished wide subcategory) of simple graphs and A-homotopy equivalences does not have pushouts. The result then follows, since model categories are known to present quasicategories that are both complete and cocomplete.

A-homotopy theory, introduced by Barcelo and collaborators [barcelo-kramer-laubenbacher-weaver, babson-barcelo-longueville-laubenbacher, barcelo-laubenbacher] based on the earlier work of Atkin [atkin:i, atkin:ii], uses methods of homotopy theory to study combinatorial properties of graphs. In studying A-homotopy theory, one considers two classes of maps: A-homotopy equivalences, i.e., maps with inverses up to A-homotopy, and weak A-homotopy equivalences, i.e., maps inducing isomorphisms on all A-homotopy groups These two choices lead to two distinct homotopy theories, and we refer to the former of those as the naive discrete homotopy theory and the latter as the discrete homotopy theory.

A concise, 3-page introduction to A-homotopy theory can be found in [carranza-kapulkin-lindsey:calculus-of-fractions, §12] and we will follow the notation established there. In particular, we write 𝖦𝗋𝖺𝗉𝗁\mathsf{Graph} for the (locally Kan) cubical category of graphs and N𝖦𝗋𝖺𝗉𝗁{\operatorname{N}}_{\mathord{\square}}\mathsf{Graph} for its cubical homotopy coherent nerve. As observed there, the quasicategory N𝖦𝗋𝖺𝗉𝗁{\operatorname{N}}_{\mathord{\square}}\mathsf{Graph} is the localization of the category of simple graphs at the class of A-homotopy equivalences. The box product of graphs is denoted \otimes and its right adjoint by hom(,=)\operatorname{hom}^{\otimes}(-,=). The nerve of a graph GG is a cubical set NG\mathrm{N}G. The geometric product of cubical sets is also denoted by \otimes. The right adjoint to the functor X-\otimes X (or XX\otimes-) is denoted by homL(X,)\operatorname{hom}_{L}(X,-) (respectively, homR(X,)\operatorname{hom}_{R}(X,-)).

Our main theorem (Theorem 5) asserts that a certain span does not admit a colimit, revealing an inherent rigidity of A-homotopy equivalences. From that, we deduce that A-homotopy equivalences are not part of any model or cofibration category structure on the category of simple graphs. This is of course not an issue with discrete homotopy theory, but instead with the class of A-homotopy equivalences, which for independent reasons is not useful for combinatorial applications either.

Lastly, we mention that Goyal and Santhanam have recently established similar results [goyal-santhanam:i, goyal-santhanam:ii] in the context of Dochtermann’s ×\times-homotopy theory [dochtermann:hom-complex-and-homotopy]. Their techniques are more direct and do not involve higher category theory. Our proof implies not only that there is no model/cofibration category structure on simple graphs with A-homotopy equivalences, but also that there cannot be such a structure on any marked category DK-equivalent to it. In other words, we identify a problem with the homotopy theory, not a presentation thereof.

Sepcifically, we consider the following diagram

I0I0{I_{0}\sqcup I_{0}}I0{I_{0}}I0{I_{0}}

which we denote by D:Λ02N𝖦𝗋𝖺𝗉𝗁D\colon\Lambda^{2}_{0}\to{\operatorname{N}}_{\mathord{\square}}\mathsf{Graph}. We will show that this diagram does not admit a pushout. Informally, the outline of our argument is as follows.

  1. 1.

    We give an explicit description of the objects and morphisms (i.e. the 1-skeleton) of the quasicategory of cones under DD. A cone under DD may be thought of as a graph GG and a cycle in GG. A morphism between cones consists of a graph map f:GHf\colon G\to H and a homotopy between the induced cycles in HH.

  2. 2.

    This description then shows there is no initial cone under DD: given a cycle in a graph GG of length mm, its image under any map GCm+1G\to C_{m+1} must be null-homotopic (where Cm+1C_{m+1} denotes the cycle graph with m+1m+1 vertices). This implies there can be no homotopy from the image of this cycle to the tautological cycle in the graph Cm+1C_{m+1}. That is, for every cone λ\lambda under DD, there exists a cone λ\lambda^{\prime} for which there is no morphism λλ\lambda\to\lambda^{\prime}.

The formal statement and proof of (1) may be found in Theorems 2 and 4. The precise formulation of (2) is given by Theorem 5.

We begin with a short calculation.

Lemma 1.

For any graph GG and set SS, we have an isomorphism

𝖼𝖲𝖾𝗍(n,Nhom(S×I0,G))𝖼𝖲𝖾𝗍(S×n,NG)\mathsf{cSet}(\mathord{\square^{n}},\mathrm{N}\operatorname{hom}^{\otimes}(S\times I_{0},G))\cong\mathsf{cSet}(S\times\mathord{\square^{n}},\mathrm{N}G)

natural in GG.

Proof.

We calculate

𝖼𝖲𝖾𝗍(n,Nhom(S×I0,G))\displaystyle\mathsf{cSet}(\mathord{\square^{n}},\mathrm{N}\operatorname{hom}^{\otimes}(S\times I_{0},G)) 𝖼𝖲𝖾𝗍(n,homL(S×0,NG)) by [carranza-kapulkin:cubical-graphs, Prop. 3.10]\displaystyle\cong\mathsf{cSet}(\mathord{\square^{n}},\operatorname{hom}_{L}(S\times\mathord{\square^{0}},\mathrm{N}G))\text{ by \cite[cite]{[\@@bibref{}{carranza-kapulkin:cubical-graphs}{}{}, Prop.~{}3.10]}}
𝖼𝖲𝖾𝗍(n(S×0),NG)\displaystyle\cong\mathsf{cSet}(\mathord{\square^{n}}\otimes(S\times\mathord{\square^{0}}),\mathrm{N}G)
𝖼𝖲𝖾𝗍(S×(n0),NG)\displaystyle\cong\mathsf{cSet}(S\times(\mathord{\square^{n}}\otimes\mathord{\square^{0}}),\mathrm{N}G)
𝖼𝖲𝖾𝗍(S×n,NG).\displaystyle\cong\mathsf{cSet}(S\times\mathord{\square^{n}},\mathrm{N}G).\qed

For a graph map f:IGf\colon I_{\infty}\to G that is stable in the positive (or negative) direction, we write f()f(\infty) (or f()f(-\infty), respectively) for the value of ff in the stable range.

Theorem 2.

There is a bijection between the set of objects of the quasicategory of cones under DD and the set of tuples (G,p1,p2,p3,p4)(G,p_{1},p_{2},p_{3},p_{4}), where

  • GG is a graph; and

  • p1,p2,p3p_{1},p_{2},p_{3} and p4p_{4} are maps IGI_{\infty}\to G which are stable in both directions such that

    p1()=p2()p1()=p3()p2()=p4()p3()=p4().\begin{array}[]{l l l l}p_{1}(\infty)=p_{2}(\infty)&p_{1}(-\infty)=p_{3}(-\infty)&p_{2}(-\infty)=p_{4}(-\infty)&p_{3}(\infty)=p_{4}(\infty).\end{array}
Proof.

As Λ02Δ0Δ1×Δ1\Lambda^{2}_{0}\ast\mathord{\Delta}^{0}\cong\mathord{\Delta}^{1}\times\mathord{\Delta}^{1}, a cone under DD is a square λ:Δ1×Δ1N𝖦𝗋𝖺𝗉𝗁\lambda\colon\mathord{\Delta}^{1}\times\mathord{\Delta}^{1}\to{\operatorname{N}}_{\mathord{\square}}\mathsf{Graph} such that the maps λ|id×0,λ|0×id:Δ1N𝖦𝗋𝖺𝗉𝗁{\lambda}|_{\operatorname{id}\times 0},{\lambda}|_{0\times\operatorname{id}}\colon\mathord{\Delta}^{1}\to{\operatorname{N}}_{\mathord{\square}}\mathsf{Graph} are both I0I0I0I_{0}\sqcup I_{0}\to I_{0}. Identifying Δ1×Δ1\mathord{\Delta}^{1}\times\mathord{\Delta}^{1} as the pushout

Δ1{\mathord{\Delta}^{1}}Δ2{\mathord{\Delta}^{2}}Δ2{\mathord{\Delta}^{2}}Δ1×Δ1{\mathord{\Delta}^{1}\times\mathord{\Delta}^{1}}1\scriptstyle{\partial_{1}}1\scriptstyle{\partial_{1}}{\ulcorner}

by the N\mathfrak{C}\dashv{\operatorname{N}}_{\mathord{\square}}-adjunction, this corresponds to a commutative square

[1]{\mathfrak{C}[1]}[2]{\mathfrak{C}[2]}[2]{\mathfrak{C}[2]}𝖦𝗋𝖺𝗉𝗁{\mathsf{Graph}}1\scriptstyle{\partial_{1}}1\scriptstyle{\partial_{1}}

i.e. two cubical functors T,U:[2]𝖦𝗋𝖺𝗉𝗁T,U\colon\mathfrak{C}[2]\to\mathsf{Graph} such that T2,U2:[1]𝖦𝗋𝖺𝗉𝗁T\partial_{2},U\partial_{2}\colon\mathfrak{C}[1]\to\mathsf{Graph} are both the map I0I0I0I_{0}\sqcup I_{0}\to I_{0}. We depict TT and UU as two homotopy-commutative triangles in the diagram,

I0I0{I_{0}\sqcup I_{0}}I0{I_{0}}I0{I_{0}}G{G}[v1,v3]\scriptstyle{[v_{1},v_{3}]}v2\scriptstyle{v_{2}}p12\scriptstyle{p_{12}}v4\scriptstyle{v_{4}}p34\scriptstyle{p_{34}}

where p12:1Nhom(I0I0,G)p_{12}\colon\mathord{\square^{1}}\to\mathrm{N}\operatorname{hom}^{\otimes}(I_{0}\sqcup I_{0},G) denotes the image of the non-degenerate 1-cube in [2](0,2)\mathfrak{C}[2](0,2) under TT, and p34:1Nhom(I0I0,G)p_{34}\colon\mathord{\square^{1}}\to\mathrm{N}\operatorname{hom}^{\otimes}(I_{0}\sqcup I_{0},G) denotes its image under UU. By Lemma 1, we may identify p12p_{12} and p34p_{34} with maps [p1,p2],[p3,p4]:11NG[p_{1},p_{2}],[p_{3},p_{4}]\colon\mathord{\square^{1}}\sqcup\mathord{\square^{1}}\to\mathrm{N}G respectively, and naturality gives that:

p11,0=v1p11,1=v2p21,0=v3p21,1=v2p31,0=v1p31,1=v4p41,0=v3p41,1=v4.\begin{array}[]{c c c c}p_{1}\partial_{1,0}=v_{1}&p_{1}\partial_{1,1}=v_{2}&p_{2}\partial_{1,0}=v_{3}&p_{2}\partial_{1,1}=v_{2}\\ p_{3}\partial_{1,0}=v_{1}&p_{3}\partial_{1,1}=v_{4}&p_{4}\partial_{1,0}=v_{3}&p_{4}\partial_{1,1}=v_{4}.\end{array}

By definition, the 1-cubes p1,p2,p3,p4:1NGp_{1},p_{2},p_{3},p_{4}\colon\mathord{\square^{1}}\to\mathrm{N}G are stable maps IGI_{\infty}\to G that satisfy the desired endpoint equalities. ∎

Remark 3.

Let (G,p1,p2,p3,p4)(G,p_{1},p_{2},p_{3},p_{4}) be a cone under DD (under the bijection in Theorem 2). One may identify each pi:IGp_{i}\colon I_{\infty}\to G with a map ImGI_{m}\to G where mm is the smallest positive integer which makes pip_{i} stable. With this, the concatenation p1p21p4p31p_{1}\cdot p_{2}^{-1}\cdot p_{4}\cdot p_{3}^{-1} gives a cycle in GG,

v1v_{1}\dotsp1p_{1}v2v_{2}\vdotsp2p_{2}v3v_{3}\vdotsp3p_{3}v4v_{4}\dotsp4p_{4}

thus justifying the intuition that a cone under DD corresponds to a cycle in a graph GG. However, this process does not give a well-defined function from cones under DD to tuples (G𝖦𝗋𝖺𝗉𝗁,f:CmG)(G\in\mathsf{Graph},f\colon C_{m}\to G). For instance, if one modifies the cycle p1p21p4p31p_{1}\cdot p_{2}^{-1}\cdot p_{4}\cdot p_{3}^{-1} by repeating any endpoint of some pip_{i} then one obtains a different cycle CnGC_{n}\to G which corresponds to the same cone under DD. However, each pip_{i} induces a well-defined path up to homotopy, thus the cycle p1p21p4p31p_{1}\cdot p_{2}^{-1}\cdot p_{4}\cdot p_{3}^{-1} represents a well-defined element of the discrete fundamental group of GG.

Theorem 4.

Under the bijection of Theorem 2, let (G,p1,p2,p3,p4)(G,p_{1},p_{2},p_{3},p_{4}) and (H,q1,q2,q3,q4)(H,q_{1},q_{2},q_{3},q_{4}) be two cones under DD. There is a bijection between the set of 1-simplices in in the quasicategory of cones under DD from (G,p1,p2,p3,p4)(G,p_{1},p_{2},p_{3},p_{4}) to (H,q1,q2,q3,q4)(H,q_{1},q_{2},q_{3},q_{4}) and the set of tuples (f,α1,α2,α3,α4)(f,\alpha_{1},\alpha_{2},\alpha_{3},\alpha_{4}) where

  • ff is a graph map GHG\to H; and

  • αi\alpha_{i} is a homotopy I2HI_{\infty}^{\otimes 2}\to H from fpif\circ p_{i} to qiq_{i} for i=1,2,3,4i=1,2,3,4.

Proof.

A map λλ\lambda\to\lambda^{\prime} between cones under DD is a map α:Λ02Δ1N𝖦𝗋𝖺𝗉𝗁\alpha\colon\Lambda^{2}_{0}\ast\mathord{\Delta}^{1}\to{\operatorname{N}}_{\mathord{\square}}\mathsf{Graph} such that α|Λ02{0}=λ{\alpha}|_{\Lambda^{2}_{0}\ast\{0\}}=\lambda and α|Λ02{1}=λ{\alpha}|_{\Lambda^{2}_{0}\ast\{1\}}=\lambda^{\prime}. Writing Λ02Δ1\Lambda^{2}_{0}\ast\mathord{\Delta}^{1} as a pushout:

Δ2{\mathord{\Delta}^{2}}Δ3{\mathord{\Delta}^{3}}Δ3{\mathord{\Delta}^{3}}Λ02Δ1{\Lambda^{2}_{0}\ast\mathord{\Delta}^{1}}1\scriptstyle{\partial_{1}}1\scriptstyle{\partial_{1}}{\ulcorner}

as before, this corresponds to the data of two cubical diagrams T,U:[3]𝖦𝗋𝖺𝗉𝗁T,U\colon\mathfrak{C}[3]\to\mathsf{Graph}, which we depict below

G{G}I0I0{I_{0}\sqcup I_{0}}I0{I_{0}}H{H}f\scriptstyle{f}[v1,v3]\scriptstyle{[v_{1},v_{3}]}[w1,w3]\scriptstyle{[w_{1},w_{3}]}v2\scriptstyle{v_{2}}w2\scriptstyle{w_{2}}      G{G}I0I0{I_{0}\sqcup I_{0}}I0{I_{0}}H{H}f\scriptstyle{f}[v1,v3]\scriptstyle{[v_{1},v_{3}]}[w1,w3]\scriptstyle{[w_{1},w_{3}]}v4\scriptstyle{v_{4}}w4\scriptstyle{w_{4}}

(note our depiction omits the data of the 1-cubes and 2-cube in the mapping spaces of [3]\mathfrak{C}[3]). Let α12,α34:2Nhom(I0I0,H)\alpha_{12},\alpha_{34}\colon\mathord{\square^{2}}\to\mathrm{N}\operatorname{hom}^{\otimes}(I_{0}\sqcup I_{0},H) denote the images of the non-degnerate 2-cube in [3](0,3)\mathfrak{C}[3](0,3) under TT and UU, respectively. By Lemma 1, we identify α12\alpha_{12} and α34\alpha_{34} with maps [α1,α2],[α3,α4]:22NH[\alpha_{1},\alpha_{2}],[\alpha_{3},\alpha_{4}]\colon\mathord{\square^{2}}\sqcup\mathord{\square^{2}}\to\mathrm{N}H and apply naturality to identify the faces of each square. We depict these 2-cubes below:

w1{w_{1}}w2{w_{2}}fv1{fv_{1}}fv2{fv_{2}}q1\scriptstyle{q_{1}}α1{\alpha_{1}}fp1\scriptstyle{f\circ p_{1}}   w3{w_{3}}w2{w_{2}}fv3{fv_{3}}fv2{fv_{2}}q2\scriptstyle{q_{2}}α2{\alpha_{2}}fp2\scriptstyle{f\circ p_{2}}   w1{w_{1}}w4{w_{4}}fv1{fv_{1}}fv4{fv_{4}}q3\scriptstyle{q_{3}}α3{\alpha_{3}}fp3\scriptstyle{f\circ p_{3}}   w3{w_{3}}w4{w_{4}}fv3{fv_{3}}fv4{fv_{4}}q4\scriptstyle{q_{4}}α4{\alpha_{4}}fp4\scriptstyle{f\circ p_{4}}

Theorem 5.

For any cone λ\lambda under DD, there exists a cone λ\lambda^{\prime} under DD such that there is no cone map λλ\lambda\to\lambda^{\prime}. In particular, the diagram DD does not have a pushout in N𝖦𝗋𝖺𝗉𝗁{\operatorname{N}}_{\mathord{\square}}\mathsf{Graph}.

Proof.

Fix a cone λ\lambda under DD. By Theorem 2, we identify λ\lambda as a tuple (G,p1,p2,p3,p4)(G,p_{1},p_{2},p_{3},p_{4}). As the concatenation p1p21p4p31p_{1}\cdot p_{2}^{-1}\cdot p_{4}\cdot p_{3}^{-1} represents a well-defined element of A1(G,v1)A_{1}(G,v_{1}) (see Remark 3), let φ:CmG\varphi\colon C_{m}\to G be a cycle of minimal length which represents this concatenation.

Let ψ:ICm+5\psi\colon I_{\infty}\to C_{m+5} denote the identity cycle on Cm+5C_{m+5} based at 0 and 𝖼𝗈𝗇𝗌𝗍0:ICm+5\mathsf{const}_{0}\colon I_{\infty}\to C_{m+5} denote the constant map at 0. By Theorem 2, the tuple (Cm+5,ψ,𝖼𝗈𝗇𝗌𝗍0,𝖼𝗈𝗇𝗌𝗍0,𝖼𝗈𝗇𝗌𝗍0)(C_{m+5},\psi,\mathsf{const}_{0},\mathsf{const}_{0},\mathsf{const}_{0}) is a cone over DD. We assume there exists a morphism of cones from (G,p1,p2,p3,p4)(G,p_{1},p_{2},p_{3},p_{4}) to (Cm+5,ψ,𝖼𝗈𝗇𝗌𝗍0,𝖼𝗈𝗇𝗌𝗍0,𝖼𝗈𝗇𝗌𝗍0)(C_{m+5},\psi,\mathsf{const}_{0},\mathsf{const}_{0},\mathsf{const}_{0}) and derive a contradiction.

By Theorem 4, this morphism corresponds to a tuple (f,α1,α2,α3,α4)(f,\alpha_{1},\alpha_{2},\alpha_{3},\alpha_{4}). The horizontal concatenation α1α21α4α31\alpha_{1}\cdot\alpha_{2}^{-1}\cdot\alpha_{4}\cdot\alpha_{3}^{-1} induces a square

0{0}0{0}fv1{fv_{1}}fv1{fv_{1}}ψ\scriptstyle{\psi}γ\scriptstyle{\gamma}γ\scriptstyle{\gamma}fφ\scriptstyle{f\circ\varphi}

where γ\gamma denotes the restriction α1|(,):ICm+5{\alpha_{1}}|_{(-\infty,-)}\colon I_{\infty}\to C_{m+5} of the square α1\alpha_{1} to its left leg. The cycle fφf\circ\varphi is (based) homotopic to the constant path as it has length at most mm. Thus, this square yields a chain of based homotopies

γγ(fφ)ψγ.\gamma\sim\gamma\cdot(f\circ\varphi)\sim\psi\cdot\gamma.

This implies ψ\psi is based homotopic to the constant cycle, which is a contradiction as Cm+5C_{m+5} is a cycle of length greater than 5. ∎

Corollary 6.

The class of A-homotopy equivalences is not part of a model structure or a cofibration category structure on the category of simple graphs.

Proof.

By the preceding theorem, the localization of simple graphs at the class of A-homotopy equivalences does not admit pushouts. Since the localization of a model category or a cofibration category at its weak equivalences must be cocomplete [kapulkin-szumilo:frames, szumilo:frames], the result follows. ∎

Acknowledgements. We thank the anonymous referee for insightful comments that helped restructure the paper and make arguments cleaner.

This material is based upon work supported by the National Science Foundation under Grant No. DMS-1928930 while the first two authors participated in a program hosted by the Mathematical Sciences Research Institute in Berkeley, California, during the 2022–23 academic year.

References