[datatype=bibtex] \map[overwrite=true] \step[fieldset=url, null] \step[fieldset=doi, null] \step[fieldset=isbn, null] \step[fieldset=issn, null]
Model-completeness for the lattice of finite unions of closed intervals of a dense linear order
1. Introduction
Let be any dense linear order with left endpoint but no right endpoint. We consider , the collection of finite unions of closed intervals of . This collection arises naturally in the setting of o-minimality, as precisely the lattice of closed definable sets in any o-minimal expansion of . Our main result is theorem 7.1 which says that , the expansion of the lattice by constants for the empty set and (here is the left endpoint of ) as well as four unary functions, is model-complete.
The proof makes use of previous results regarding the weak monadic second order theory of from the authors PhD thesis [Lin21].
2. Definitions and setup
Throughout the note we fix a dense linear order , which has a left endpoint but no right endpoint. By the fact that any completion of the theory of dense linear orders is -categorical, and using Proposition 2.7 from [Tre17], it follows that our results do not depend the particular choice of .
Our logical notation, where not explicitly defined, is taken from [Hod93].
Definition 2.1.
Let be a set. We write for the powerset of . We write for the collection of finite subsets of .
Definition 2.2.
Let be any linear order. A closed interval of is a subset of one of the following forms,
-
(1)
for ,
-
(2)
for ,
-
(3)
for .
We will write for the set of finite unions of closed intervals of .
Note that .
Definition 2.3.
Let be a discrete linear order with endpoints (i.e. is finite, or has order type for some linear order type ).
We will write for the successor function and for the predecessor function .
We will moreover write for the function sending to , and for the function sending to .
Definition 2.4.
Let be any linear order. We call discrete if the restriction of to is a discrete linear order.
For discrete we will write (respectively ) for the successor (respectively predecessor) function on the restriction of to a linear ordering on . Note that every finite subset of is discrete.
3. , the weak monadic second order version of
Recall that is a dense linear order with left endpoint but no right endpoint that we fixed at the outset.
Definition 3.1.
We write for the left endpoint of , i.e. the smallest element with respect to the ordering. We write for the signature .111This comprises in order, two binary function symbols, two constants, two unary function symbols, and a binary function symbol. Then is the -structure with,
-
(1)
universe , the collection of finite subsets of ,
-
(2)
interpreted as the operations of union and intersection,
-
(3)
interpreted as the empty set,
-
(4)
interpreted as ,
-
(5)
and interpreted as the operations taking a non-empty finite set to the singleton containing its minimum and maximum respectively, with respect to the ordering of (and both fixing ),
-
(6)
being the binary function given by,
i.e. is a single binary function which encodes the (preimage map associated to) the family of successor functions on finite subsets of .
Notation 3.2.
As is conventional, we will sometimes use as a shorthand for the formula . Note that in doing so we conceal an unnested atomic formula, so this shorthand will never lead us to mistake an existential formula for a quantifier-free formula.
Lemma 3.3.
The following are equivalent for each ,
-
(1)
,
-
(2)
or .
Proof.
: If and then it is immediate that is not . This gives us that is defined (i.e. has a successor in ). Then which by definition gives us .
: Suppose . From this it follows immediately that . Moreover which is , hence . β
Definition 3.4.
Recall that for sets and , the relative complement of inside , denoted by , is the set .
Proposition 3.5.
Every quantifier-free -formula is equivalent to a positive (i.e. negation free) existential -formula over the the theory of .
Proof.
First note that for each , if and only if,
Therefore every positive existential -formula is equivalent to a positive existential -formula (working in , with a binary function symbol interpreted as relative complement). So it is enough to check that every quantifier-free -formula is equivalent to a positive existential -formula. It is enough to check that the negation of an atomic -formula is equivalent to a positive existential -formula in . Atomic formulas are all of the form for -terms . Let be shorthand for , i.e. the symmetric difference of and . The formula is equivalent over to,
but using lemma 3.3 this in turn is equivalent over to,
which is positive existential as required. β
Theorem 3.6.
is positive-model-complete in the signature .
Proof.
That is model-complete is proved in my thesis [Lin21] (see theorem 5.4.7 on page 141). The result then follows immediately from proposition 3.5. β
4. , finite unions of closed intervals of
Definition 4.1.
We write for the signature .222This comprises in order, two binary function symbols, two constants, and four unary function symbols.
is the -structure with,
-
(1)
universe , the collection of finite unions of closed intervals of ,
-
(2)
interpreted as the operations of union and intersection,
-
(3)
interpreted as the empty set,
-
(4)
interpreted as ,
-
(5)
and interpreted as the operations taking an element of to the singleton containing its minimum and maximum respectively, with respect to the ordering of (we set , and in the case is unbounded we set ),
-
(6)
and are interpreted as the operations taking an element of to the set of its left and right endpoints respectively.
Notation 4.2.
For we will sometimes write and in place of and respectively. We will write as shorthand for .
Lemma 4.3.
The bounded elements of form a definable subset in , which we will denote by .
Proof.
Under our interpretation, an element is bounded if and only if or . Conversely the unbounded elements are precisely those for which and .
Therefore is in fact a quantifier-free definable set in . β
5. Interpreting in
Proposition 5.1.
The set is quantifier-free definable in .
Proof.
The formula defines in . β
We will use this as the foundation for our interpretation of in .
In the remainder of this section we will outline how to define the remaining -structure carried by within on the set .
It will be important for us, when transferring model-completeness from to in section 7, that existential -formulae are used to do so.
Remark 5.2.
If is an unnested atomic formulae in the signature , i.e. , we have that,
As such for unnested atomic formulae in this reduct, we need do nothing when giving the interpretation. Here we use unnested atomic -formulas, which a fortiori are existential.
All that is left is to produce an -formula which defines in .
Remark 5.3.
Let . If or then . Therefore in defining we can assume that .
Moreover we have that . From this it is clear that it is sufficient to define the relation in the case where .
Proposition 5.4.
Let with . Then if and only if there exists such that one of the following holds,
-
(1)
, , , and , or,
-
(2)
, , , and .
Proof.
First suppose that , we will show that one of the two conditions must then hold. Let be the union of all of the open intervals of of the form for some and such that . Now take .
By definition we get that . Then follows from the choice that be made up from intervals where . For if then we get such that for some with we have , a contradiction.
For our choice of , it is easy to check that and is either,
-
(i)
if , or,
-
(ii)
if .
Taking the complement, we interchange left and right endpoints, and introduce as a left endpoint. This gives us precisely that or hold for our choice of .
Now for the other direction, suppose that exists such that holds. We want to show that . Let , so is such that . Now implies that , contradicting our assumption that . So we have established that follows from . Let , so by we have . Suppose towards a contradiction that . Then moreover . This again gives us that , contradicting our assumption that . Therefore we have shown that follows from .
We leave the checking of details in showing that follows from to the reader. β
Corollary 5.5.
There is an existential -formula such that for all , if and only if .
Corollary 5.6.
For each -formula there is an -formula (with and having the same length) such that for each ,
Moreover can always be chosen to be an existential -formula.
6. Interpreting in
To make things more easily digestible, we will use as an intermediary between and .
It is straightforward, using modified versions of arguments from [Tre17], to show that and have the same definable subsets. Using this result, together with the interpretation of in which we are about to give, we will indicate a particular interpretation of in .
Lemma 6.1.
Let . The following are equivalent,
-
(1)
there is such that and ,
-
(2)
, , and one of the following holds,
-
(a)
,
-
(b)
.
-
(a)
Proof.
Suppose holds. Then we can rewrite as follows,
-
(2)
, , and one of the following holds,
-
(a)
,
-
(b)
.
-
(a)
Intuitively then, (2) first says that has at least one left endpoint, and that the smallest endpoint of is a left endpoint. Then both (a) and (b) simply say that the proper left endpoints and proper right endpoints appear in pairs, with proper right endpoints immediately preceded by proper left endpoints. An exception is needed simply for the case where is unbounded, in which case the largest endpoint is a proper left endpoint which is not the predecessor of a proper right endpoint (this is dealt with by (b)).
Conversely, suppose that holds. It is straightforward to construct such that and . β
This lemma gives us the universe for our interpretation of in . We will identify an element with the pair . The lemma tells us precisely that the image of the map given by is definable in . As moreover this map is injective, our interpretation can make use of the equality in to interpret equality from , in particular we do not need to take a quotient of the image by a definable equivalence relation.
It remains to show that the relation on is interpretable in .
Lemma 6.2.
There is an -formula such that for any and , if and only if,
Proof.
We split into two cases, according to whether is bounded or unbounded (see lemma 4.3). Let be the -formula,
this βsaysβ that the predecessor of is a proper left endpoint and that is the predecessor of a right endpoint, Then let be the -formula,
this βsaysβ that the condition in holds or that is greater than or equal to all left and right endpoints. Then for each and the following are equivalent,
-
(1)
,
-
(2)
(so that ) and one of the following holds,
-
(a)
or,
-
(b)
and , or,
-
(c)
and .
-
(a)
In other words if and only if is nonempty and either is an endpoint of , or sits between a left and right endpoint of , or is unbounded and sits in the unbounded part of . The latter we have shown is definable in by giving -formulas, so exists. β
Proposition 6.3.
There is an -formula such that for any , if and only if,
Proof.
Let be the formula . In this defines the collection of singletons. Therefore we can take for the -formula,
This says that every singleton contained in is contained in , as required. β
Theorem 6.4.
There is an interpretation of in , for which the co-ordinate map is given by .
Corollary 6.5.
For each -formula there is an -formula such that for each ,
7. Transfer of model-completeness from to
Theorem 7.1.
The -structure is model-complete.
Proof.
Let be an -formula. We will show that over the formula is equivalent to an existential formula .
Using our interpretation of in (in particular corollary 6.5), for each -formula there is an -formula such that for each ,
Without loss of generality we can take to be a positive existential -formula. This is because theorem 3.6, the positive model-completeness of , tells us precisely that every -formula is equivalent to some positive existential -formula over .
Using our interpretation of in (in particular corollary 5.6), for each -formula there is an -formula such that for each ,
and so in particular taking we get,
Moreover, as is a positive existential -formula, corollary 5.6 tells us that can additionally be chosen to be an existential -formula. Note that without the positive model-completeness of , we could not have taken positive existential, and therefore could not have taken to be existential.
Combining and we get that for each ,
Now, and are part of the signature , so we take to be the formula . Our choice of is clearly existential, as is existential. Putting everything together, we get that,
and hence is model-complete. β
References
- [Hod93] Wilfrid Hodges βModel theoryβ 42, Encyclopedia of Mathematics and its Applications Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1993, pp. xiv+772
- [Lin21] Deacon V. Linkhorn βMonadic Second Order Logic and Linear Ordersβ Thesis (Ph.D.)βThe University of Manchester (United Kingdom) ProQuest LLC, Ann Arbor, MI, 2021, pp. 148
- [Tre17] Marcus Tressl βOn the strength of some topological latticesβ In Ordered algebraic structures and related topics 697, Contemp. Math. Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, RI, 2017, pp. 325β347