Mixed pairwise cross intersecting families (I)††thanks: This work is supported by NSFC (Grant No. 11931002). E-mail addresses: [email protected] (Yang Huang), [email protected] (Yuejian Peng, corresponding author).
Abstract
Families and are cross-intersecting if for any and . If , all families and are cross intersecting and we say that and are cross intersecting freely. An -cross intersecting system is a set of non-empty pairwise cross-intersecting families with and . If an -cross intersecting system contains at least two families which are cross intersecting freely and at least two families which are cross intersecting but not freely, then we say that the cross intersecting system is of mixed type. All previous studies are on non-mixed type, i.e, under the condition that . In this paper, we study for the first interesting mixed type, an -cross intersecting system with , i.e., families and are cross intersecting freely if and only if . Let denote the maximum sum of sizes of families in an -cross intersecting system. We determine and characterize all extremal -cross intersecting systems for .
A result of Kruskal-Katona allows us to consider only families whose elements are the first elements in lexicographic order (we call them L-initial families). Since , and are cross intersecting freely. Thus, when we try to bound by a function, there are two free variables (the last element of ) and (the last element of ). This causes more difficulty to analyze properties of the corresponding function comparing to non-mixed type problems (single-variable function). To overcome this difficulty, we introduce new concepts ‘-partner’ and ‘parity’, develop some rules to determine whether two L-initial cross intersecting families are maximal to each other, and prove one crucial property that in an extremal L-initial -cross intersecting system (, , , ), the last element of and the last element of are ‘parities’ (see Section 2 for the definition) to each other. This discovery allows us to bound by a single variable function , where is the last element of . Another crucial and challenge part is to verify that has unimodality. Comparing to the non-mixed type, we need to overcome more difficulties in showing the unimodality of function since there are more terms to be taken care of. We think that the characterization of maximal cross intersecting L-initial families and the unimodality of functions in this paper are interesting in their own, in addition to the extremal result. The most general condition on is that (If , then is cross intersecting freely with any other , and consequently in an extremal -cross intersecting system and we can remove .). This paper provides foundation work for the solution to the most general condition .
Key words: Cross intersecting families; Extremal finite sets
2010 Mathematics Subject Classification. 05D05, 05C65, 05D15.
1 Introduction
Let . For , let denote the family of all -subsets of . A family is -uniform if . A family is intersecting if for any and . Many researches in extremal set theory are inspired by the foundational result of Erdős–Ko–Rado [1] showing that a maximum -uniform intersecting family is a full star. This result of Erdős–Ko–Rado has many interesting generalizations. Two families and are cross-intersecting if for any and . Note that and are cross-intersecting is equivalent to that is intersecting. We call families pairwise cross-intersecting families if and are cross-intersecting when . Additionally, if for each , then we say that are non-empty pairwise cross-intersecting. For given integers , if families are non-empty pairwise cross intersecting and , then we call an -cross intersecting system.
Define
(1) |
We say that an -cross intersecting system is extremal if . In [5] (Theorem 1.1), the authors determined for and characterized the extremal families attaining the bound.
Theorem 1.1 (Huang-Peng [5]).
Let be non-empty pairwise cross intersecting families with , , and . Then
The equality holds if and only if one of the following holds.
(i) , and there is some -element set such that and for each ;
(ii) , there are some such that , and there is some such that for each ;
(iii) , and ;
(iv) , fix some , for all , where is an intersecting family with size , and
.
Theorem 1.1 generalized the results of Hilton-Milner in [8], Frankl-Tokushige in [4] and Shi-Qian-Frankl in [13]. In Theorem 1.1, taking and , we obtain the result of Hilton-Milner in [8]. Taking , we obtain the result of Frankl-Tokushige in [4]. Taking , we obtain the result of Shi-Qian-Frankl in [13]. Note that if , any family and any family are cross intersecting. In this case, we say that families and are cross intersecting freely. If an -cross intersecting system contains at least two families which are cross intersecting freely and at least two families which are cross intersecting but not freely, then we say that the cross intersecting system is of mixed type. Otherwise, we say that it is of non-mixed type. All previous studies are of non-mixed type, i.e., . It would be interesting to study for mixed type. The first interesting case is to study an -cross intersecting system for . In this case, and are cross intersecting freely if and only if . In this paper, we focus on this case, we determine and characterize all extremal -cross intersecting systems. Let us look at the following -cross intersecting systems.
Construction 1.2.
Let and . For each , we denote
Note that
Construction 1.3.
Let and . For or , let
and for , let
Note that
Our main result is that an extremal -cross intersecting system must be isomorphic to Construction 1.2 or Construction 1.3 if .
Theorem 1.4.
In proving Theorem 1.1 in [5], the authors applied a result of Kruskal-Katona (Theorem 2.1) allowing us to consider only families whose elements are the first elements in lexicographic order (we call them L-initial families). We bounded by a function of the last element in the lexicographic order of an L-initial family ( is called the ID of ), and showed that has unimodality. To prove our main result (Theorem 1.4) in this paper, by the result of Kruskal-Katona (Theorem 2.1), we can still consider only pairwise cross-intersecting non-empty L-initial families . However, in this paper, the condition on is relaxed to , so and are cross intersecting freely. When we try to bound by a function, there are two free variables (the ID of ) and (the ID of ). This causes more difficulty to analyze properties of the corresponding function, comparing to the problem in [5]. To overcome this difficulty, we introduce new concepts ‘-partner’ and ‘parity’, develop some rules to determine whether a pair of L-initial cross intersecting families are maximal to each other (see precise definition), and prove one crucial property that for an extremal L-initial -cross intersecting system (, , , ), the ID of and the ID of are ‘parities’ to each other (Lemma 3.8). This discovery allows us to bound by a single variable function . Another crucial and challenge part is to verify the unimodality of (Lemmas 3.12, 3.13 and 3.14). Comparing to the function in [5], we need to overcome more difficulties in dealing with function since there are more ‘mysterious’ terms to be taken care of. We take advantage of some properties of function obtained in [5] and come up with some new strategies in estimating the change as the ID of increases from to (Sections 6 and 7).
The most general condition on is that . If , then is cross intersecting freely with any other , and consequently in an extremal -cross intersecting system and can be removed. The most general case is more complex and we will deal with it in a forthcoming paper [7]. The work in this paper provides important foundation for the solution to the most general condition .
To obtain the relationship between the ID of and the ID of , we build some foundation work in Section 2, for example, we come up with new concepts ‘-partners’ and ‘parity’, and give a necessary and sufficient condition on maximal cross intersecting L-initial families. In Section 3, we give the proof of Theorem 1.4 by assuming the truth of Lemmas 3.8, 3.12, 3.13 and 3.14. In Section 4, we list some results obtained for non-mixed type in [5] which we will apply. In Sections 6 and 7, we give the proofs of Lemmas 3.8, 3.12, 3.13 and 3.14.
2 Partner and Parity
In this section, we introduce new concepts ‘-partner’ and ‘parity’, develop some rules to determine whether a pair of L-initial cross intersecting families are maximal to each other (precise definitions will be given in this section). We prove some properties which are foundation for the proof of our main results.
When we write a set , we always assume that throughout the paper. Let denote the maximum element of , let denote the minimum element of and denote the -th element of . Let us introduce the lexicographic (lex for short) order of subsets of positive integers. Let and be finite subsets of the set of positive integers . We say that if either or . In particular, . Let and in with . We write if there is no other such that .
Let denote the first subsets in in the lex order. Given a set , we denote . Whenever the underlying set is clear, we shall ignore it and write , for short. Let be a family, we say is L-initial if for some -set . We call the ID of .
The well-known Kruskal-Katona theorem [11, 12] will allow us to consider only L-initial families. An equivalent formulation of this result was given in [3, 9] as follows.
Theorem 2.1 (Kruskal-Katona theorem [3, 9]).
For and , if and are cross intersecting, then and are cross intersecting as well.
In [5], we proved the following important result.
Proposition 2.2.
[5] Let are positive integers and . For with , let be the partner of . Then is the maximum L-initial -uniform family that are cross intersecting to .
In [5], we worked on non-mixed type: Let , and and families be non-empty pairwise cross-intersecting (not freely). Let be the ID of , and be the partner of . In the proof of Theorem 1.1, one important ingredient is that by Proposition 2.2, can be bounded by a function of as following.
(2) |
By Theorem 2.1, to prove the quantitative part of Theorem 1.4 we may also assume that is L-initial, that is, for each . In the rest of this chapter, we assume that is an extremal non-empty -cross intersecting system with , , and is L-initial for each with ID .
However, the condition on is relaxed to , so and are cross intersecting freely. When we try to bound by a function, there are two free variables (the ID of ) and (the ID of ). This causes more difficulty to analyze properties of the corresponding function, comparing to the problem in [5]. To overcome this difficulty, we introduce new concepts ’-partner’ and ’parity’, develop some rules to determine whether a pair of L-initial cross intersecting families are maximal to each other (see precise definition).
Let and be cross intersecting families. We say that is maximal or and are maximal cross intersecting families if whenever and are cross intersecting with and , then and .
Let and be two subsets of . We say is maximal if there are two L-initial families and with IDs and respectively such that is maximal. We say two families and are maximal pair families if and for every , there is a unique such that is maximal.
Let . We denote
Let be a set. We denote
Let and be two subsets of with size and . We say that and strongly intersect at their last element if there is an element such that and . We also say is the partner of , or is the partner of . Let be an integer, we define the -partner of as follows. For , let . If , then let . We can see that . Indeed, since and intersect at their last element, , so . If , then let be the last -set in such that , in other words, there is no -set satisfying . By the definition of -partner, we have the following remark.
Remark 2.3.
Let with and . Suppose that is the partner of , and is the k-partner of , then we have .
Fact 2.4.
Let with and . Then the -partner of is the same as the -partner of .
Proof.
If , then we are fine. Suppose and . Let and be the partners of and respectively. Then , consequently , and . Suppose that and are the -partners of and respectively. By the definition of -partner, we can see that if , then , as desired; if , then and , as desired; if , then and , as desired. ∎
Fact 2.5.
Let be positive integers and . For with , let be the -partner of , then is the maximum L-initial -uniform family that are cross intersecting to . We also say that is maximal to , or say is maximal to .
Remark 2.6.
Note that families and which mentioned in Fact 2.5 may not be maximal cross intersecting, since we don’t know whether is maximal to . For example, let , , and . Then the -partner of is . Although is maximal to , and are not maximal cross intersecting families since , and and are cross intersecting families.
Frankl-Kupavskii [2] gave a sufficient condition for a pair of maximal cross intersecting families, and a necessary condition for a pair of maximal cross intersecting families as stated below.
Proposition 2.7 (Frankl-Kupavskii [2]).
Let . Let and be non-empty subsets of with and . If is the partner of , then and are maximal cross intersecting families. Inversely, if and are maximal cross intersecting families, let be the smallest element of , and . Then , and , satisfy the following conditions: , , and is the partner of .
Based on Proposition 2.7, we point out a necessary and sufficient condition for a pair of maximal cross intersecting families in terms of their IDs.
Fact 2.8.
Let and be nonempty subsets of with . Let and . Then is maximal if and only if is the partner of .
Proof.
Let and . From the definitions of and , we can see that and . First we show the sufficiency. Suppose that is the partner of . Since and , by Proposition 2.7, and are maximal cross intersecting families. Thus and are maximal cross intersecting families, in other words, is maximal. Next, we show the necessity. Suppose that is maximal. Let be the smallest element of , and . By Proposition 2.7, , ; , and is the partner of . Since and , then we . Similarly, . By the definitions of and , we have and . Since is the partner of , is the partner of . ∎
By Fact 2.8 and the definition of the -partner, we have the following property.
Fact 2.9.
Let be integers with . Let be an -subset of . Suppose that is the -partner of and there exists a -set such that is maximal and let . Then is maximal if and only if .
Fact 2.10.
Let be positive integers and . Suppose that is an -subset of , and is the -partner of . Let be the -partner of , then is maximal. Moreover, if , then .
Proof.
If is maximal, then is the -partner of and , we are fine. Suppose that is not maximal. By Fact 2.5, is maximal to , so is not maximal to . Let be the -partner of . By Fact 2.5 again, is maximal to and . Since is maximal to , for any -set satisfying , we have and are not cross intersecting. So is maximal to . Hence is maximal. ∎
Definition 2.11.
Let be positive integers, and be subsets of with sizes and respectively. We say is the -parity of , or is the -parity of if and .
Remark 2.12.
Let be positive integers and with . Then has an -parity if and only if , and has an -parity if and only if .
Note that for a given integer and a subset , if has a -parity, then it has the unique one. The following fact is derived from the above definition directly.
Fact 2.13.
Let and be an -set for . If is the -parity of and is the -parity of , then is the -parity of . Also, if is the -parity of and is the -parity of , then is the -parity of .
Fact 2.14.
Let be positive integers and . Let and be two subsets of with sizes and . Suppose that and are the -partners of and respectively. If , then . In particular, if is the -parity of , then .
Definition 2.15.
Let . For two families and , we say that is the -parity of , or is the -parity of if
(i) for any , the -parity of exists and must be in ;
(ii) for any , either has no -parity or it’s -parity is in .
Proposition 2.16.
Let be positive integers with and . Let
Let and be the families such that and are maximal pair families and and are maximal pair families. Then is the -parity of ; ; and for any , let be the -parity of and such that is maximal, then is maximal.
Proof.
If , then and . So we may assume that for some . For any , there is the unique such that is maximal. Let and . Then, by Fact 2.8, and are partners of each other . So . Let . Then , and . Then, by Definition 2.11, is the -parity of . Let . So . Furthermore, and are partners of each other. By Fact 2.8 again, we can see that is maximal. So , and is the -parity of , as desired. For any , let be the -parity of and be the set such that is maximal. By Fact 2.14, is maximal, as desired. And this implies . The proof is complete. ∎
Fact 2.17.
Let be positive integers, and , and let be a -subset of . Suppose that is the -partner of and is the -partner of , then or is the -parity of .
Proof.
If , then , we are done. Assume . Let be the partner of and let . If , then . By the definitions of -partner and -partner and , we can see that is the -parity of . If , then we have , so . At last, suppose . Let be the first elements of . If for all , then is the -parity of . Otherwise, we have . ∎
3 Proofs of Theorem 1.4
Recall that , is an extremal -cross intersecting system, each is L-initial, and are the IDs of respectively throughout the paper. From Constructions 1.2 and 1.3, we have
(3) |
We are going to prove that .
Claim 3.1.
We may assume that .
Proof.
We consider the case . Suppose that . Then . Since is a cross intersecting system, then for any and , we have . Thus,
So we may assume that . ∎
From now on, .
For the case , the authors in [6] (Corollary 1.12) have already given a positive answer. Although we can prove for this case in this paper, for simplicity, we assume that
In [6], the authors proved the following result.
Theorem 3.2.
[6] Let , , be positive integers and be positive numbers. Let be non-empty cross-intersecting families with for some . Let be the minimum integer among , where . If for all , then
The equality holds if and only if one of the following holds.
(1) If , then there is some -element set such that and for each .
(2) If
,
then there is some such that for each .
(3) If and . If , then with and .
(4)
If holds for every and , then for all , where is an intersecting family with size , and .
Claim 3.3.
and , in other words, and .
Proof.
If for each , then , a contradiction to (3). So there is such that .
Suppose that firstly. Since , and therefore for all . Let . Taking in Theorem 3.2, we obtain
In [6] (Proposition 2.20 [6]), we have shown that
So
where the last inequality holds by and . Thus if , then the last inequality holds strictly, it makes a a contradiction to (3). Suppose that . Then Claim 3.3 follows from Theorem 3.2 (see the item (2) of Theorem 3.2). So . Without loss of generality, let . Since , then any two families and are cross intersecting freely. Since and is L-initial, . Note that for each and is cross intersecting with but not freely for each , every member of contains 1. Since is extremal, all -subsets contianing 1 are contained in , so , this implies . This completes the proof of Claim 3.3. ∎
The following observation is simple and frequently used in this paper.
Remark 3.4.
Let be an integer, we consider L-initial families , , . For and let be the set of all satisfying that . Suppose that . If and are cross intersecting for each , then , are pairwise cross intersecting families since for any , every member of contains .
Combining Claim 3.3, Proposition 2.2 and is extremal, we have that for , is -partner of (if ) or (if ).
Since is extremal, (ID of ) must be contained in , which are defined as below.
For , let
For a family with ID , let
For L-initial cross intersecting families and with IDs and respectively, let
Proposition 3.5.
If or (or or ), then .
Proof.
The proofs for and are similar, so we only prove for . Suppose that firstly. Since , . By Fact 2.14, we have
(4) |
Since is extremal,
Next we consider . For each , since and are cross intersecting and , every element of must contain . Since and are cross intersecting for every , and is extremal, we can see that , that is the last element of . Therefore, , as desired. ∎
By Proposition 3.5, the proof of the quantitative part of Theorem 1.4 will follow from the following proposition.
Proposition 3.6.
If and , then .
In order to prove Proposition 3.6, we need some preparations.
Definition 3.7.
Let and be such that and are maximal pair families.
The following lemma whose proof will be given in Section 5 is crucial. It tells us that for an extremal -cross intersecting system with , the ID of is the parity of the ID of .
Lemma 3.8.
Let be an extremal L-initial -cross intersecting system with IDs of respectively. Then and satisfy
(5) |
Recall that , and . Let . Let be the -parity of . Then from Fact 2.14, we have the following claim.
Remark 3.9.
For any , and have the same -partner.
Fixing any , let be the -parity of , and for any , let by the -partner of . By Claim 3.3 and Remark 3.4, we can see that , …, are pariwise cross-intersecting. Furthermore, combining Fact 2.5 and Remark 3.9, we conclude that
(6) |
Now we are ready to express in terms of a function of .
Remark 3.10.
Definition 3.11.
For each , let and . Denote . For any and any , we define .
We will prove several key lemmas to show the ‘local unimodality’ of in Section 5. Before stating these crucial lemmas, we need to introduce some definitions.
Let be a family and . We say that is -sequential if there are with and (For a set , denote and ) such that , then we say that is -sequential, write , where , ,, , we also say that and are -sequential. In particular, if , we write ; if , write . Note that if , then is -sequential for any . Let be a family and . If and there is no such that , then we say that in , or simply if there is no confusion.
We will prove the following crucial lemmas in Sections 6 and 7. They show that function has local unimodality.
Lemma 3.12.
For any , let and with . Then implies .
Lemma 3.13.
Let and with , and . Then implies .
Lemma 3.14.
Let and with , and . Then implies .
Claim 3.15.
Let be a -subset of with . Suppose and . If , then .
Proof.
Let and be the partners of and respectively. Since , . Thus, . Let if , otherwise, let . Then is the -partner of . Fact 2.9 implies that is maximal, thus . ∎
Claim 3.16.
Let be a -subset of with . Suppose that and (if , then ). If and , then .
Proof.
Let and be the partners of and respectively. Then and . Since , by Definition 3.7, there is such that is maximal. By Fact 2.8, , and . We claim that . Since otherwise , this implies that and then
this is a contradiction to . Let if , and otherwise. Thus,
Therefore, . Trivially, . By Fact 2.8 again, is maximal and since , we have , as desired. ∎
Definition 3.17.
Let and such that and are maximal pair families. By Proposition 2.16, . Let be the subfamily of such that and are maximal pair families.
Observation 3.18.
Assuming that Lemmas 3.8, 3.12, 3.13 and 3.14 hold, we are going to complete the proof of Proposition 3.6. We will prove Lemmas 3.8, 3.12, 3.13 and 3.14 in Sections 5, 6 and 7.
Definition 3.19.
For a family , denote .
Proof of Proposition 3.6.
Applying Lemma 3.12 and Observation 3.18 repeatedly, we have
(10) |
By Lemma 3.13, we have
(11) |
and
(12) |
By Lemma 3.14, we have
(13) |
and
(14) |
In Section 7, we will prove the following proposition.
Proposition 3.20.
(15) | ||||
(16) |
Proof of Theorem 1.4.
Propositions 3.5 and 3.6 imply the quantitative part of Theorem 1.4. Now we show that extremal -cross intersecting systems with must be isomorphic to Constructions 1.2 or 1.3. By Claim 3.3, Propositions 3.5 and 3.6, and Theorem 2.1, we conclude that: if is an -cross intersecting system with , then either for each , or , and holds for each . If the previous happens, then is an -cross intersecting system with and is an -cross intersecting system with . By Theorem 1.1, is isomorphic to which is defined in Construction 1.2. If the later happens, then is an -cross intersecting system with and is an -cross intersecting system with . By Theorem 1.1, is isomorphic to which is defined in Construction 1.3. This completes the proof of Theorem 1.4. ∎
We owe the proofs of Lemmas 3.8, 3.12, 3.13, 3.14 and Proposition 3.20. Before giving their proofs, we list some results obtained in [5] for non-mixed type in the next section. Figure 1 is the flow chart of the proofs of the main theorem and lemmas.

4 Results of non-mixed type
In [5], we worked on non-mixed type: Let , and and families be non-empty pairwise cross-intersecting (not freely). Let be the ID of , and be the partner of . In the proof of Theorem 1.1, one important ingredient is that by Proposition 2.2, can be bounded by a function of as in the following lemma.
Lemma 4.1.
[5] Let , and be a non-empty L-initial -cross intersecting system with . Let be the ID of and be the partner of . Then
(20) |
Another crucial part in the proof of Theorem 1.1 is to show local unimodality of . Let and be -subsets of satisfying . In order to analyze , two related functions are defined in [5] as follows.
Definition 4.2.
Let , be positive integers with and . Let and be -subsets of satisfying and let and be the partners of and respectively. We define
(21) | ||||
(22) |
It is easy to see that
Let
In order to show local unimodality of , we proved the following results in [5]. These results give us some foundation in showing local unimodality of (recall (7)).
Proposition 4.3.
[5] Let and . Then . If holds for any , then ; otherwise, we have and decrease as increase.
Lemma 4.4.
[5] Let and . If are -sequential, are -sequential and , then and .
Definition 4.5.
For , let , and . In addition, we will write .
Remark 4.6.
When we consider , we regard the ground set as . For , we write simply, in fact, .
Lemma 4.7.
[5] Let and . Let and , are -sequential, , are -sequential. If , then and .
The following two lemmas confirm that has local unimodality.
Lemma 4.8.
[5] Suppose that if , then . For any , let and , , be contained in with . If , then .
Lemma 4.9.
[5] Suppose that if , then . Let and . If , then .
5 Verify Parity: Proof of Lemma 3.8
In this section, we will give the proof of Lemma 3.8. The proof is divided into two cases.
Case 1: .
By Fact 2.14 , Fact 2.5, Remark 3.4 and is extremal, we have that for each , is the -partner of . By Fact 2.17, for all , we have
(23) |
Claim 5.1.
is maximal.
Proof.
Assume on the contrary that is not maximal. Let be the -partner of for each , by Fact 2.10, is maximal. Since is not maximal, . By (23) and Fact 2.14, we have for all . This implies that for , and are cross intersecting. Further more, is an -cross intersecting system. However, implies , this is a contradiction to the assumption that is extremal. ∎
Claim 5.1 tells us that . By Proposition 2.16, is the -parity of . Then there exists such that is the -parity of . If , then and satisfy (5), as desired. So we may assume . By Proposition 2.16, is maximal. Since and are cross intersecting, . Let be the -partner of for each . It follows from Fact 2.14 that , . Therefore, is an -cross intersecting system. However, implies , this is a contradiction to the assumption that is extremal.
Case 2: .
Using a similar argument to Case 1, we conclude the following three properties:
(a) is the -partner of for each ;
(b) for all , or is the -parity of ;
(c) is maximal and .
If is maximal, then , and Proposition 2.16 implies that is the -parity of . However, implies that is not the -parity of , a contradiction. Therefore is not maximal. Since is extremal, combining (b), Fact 2.14 and Fact 2.5, we have that is the -partner of . Therefore, Fact 2.10 implies that the -partner of is such that is maximal. So . By Proposition 2.16, there exists such that is the -parity of . For , let be the -partner of . It follows from Facts 2.14 and 2.5 that is maximal to for all . Combining with Remark 3.4, we conclude that is an -cross intersecting system. Since is extremal,
This implies that
(24) |
Let and . Recall that is the -partner of , is not maximal and is maximal. It follows from Facts 2.9 and 2.4 that
Let be the first elements of . Let be the subscript such that and for all , where if for all . Since is the -partner of and is maximal, we can see that if , then , if , then . Since is the -parity of and , we get and
Claim 5.2.
Proof.
Obviously, . We are going to prove . Notice that and , these imply . If , then . So since , this is a contradiction to . ∎
Since is an -cross intersecting system with , is an -cross intersecting system with . Denote
Suppose that is an -cross intersecting system with such that and . Since is the -parity of and , we have that either (if ) or is the -parity of (if ). Thus, is an -cross intersecting system as well. Since is extremal, we have . Therefore,
(25) |
To complete the proof of Lemma 3.8, we only need to prove the following claim since it makes a contradiction to (25) and Claim 5.2.
Claim 5.3.
Let be an L-initial -cross intersecting system with and be the ID of satisfying . Then if and only if or .
Proof.
Denote
Then (recall that ). For each , denote
To prove Claim 5.3 is equivalent to prove the following claim.
Claim 5.4.
, and for any with , we have .
Proof.
By the definitions of and , we can see that , and for each , . Denote
Then is the -set with . Applying Lemma 4.8 repeatedly, we obtain
Thus
Since and , . Then by Lemma 4.8 again, we can see that for any , we have . Combing with the following Claims 5.5 and 5.6, we will get Claim 5.4.
Claim 5.5.
.
Proof.
If , then we are fine. We may assume that . Let . To prove Claim 5.5, it is sufficient to prove that for any , if , then . Let . Clearly, and . Let and be the -sets such that and . Then . Let be the -set such that . Then , are -sequential and , are -sequential. Clearly, and . Applying Lemma 4.4, we have
and . | (26) |
If , then . In this case, . By Proposition 4.3 and (since and ), we have . So , as desired. Next we may assume that . Clearly, . By Proposition 4.3 and , we have . Combining with (26), we get
and . |
Thus since . Note that and , so and . Since , . And in , we have
Recall that . By Lemma 4.8 and , we obtain , as required. ∎
Claim 5.6.
If , then .
Proof.
6 Verify Unimodality: Proof of Lemma 3.12
In this section, we are going to prove a more general result Lemma 6.10 which will be applied for the most general case in [7]. Lemma 3.12 will follow from Lemma 6.10 immediately. Before stating the result, we need to make some preparations.
Definition 6.1.
Suppose that is a positive integer, , and . We define for every as follows. For , let
For , let
In Section 3, we defined notations , . Throughout the paper except in this section, follows from the definitions in Section 3. in this section follows from the above definition. When , they are consistent.
Definition 6.2.
Let and be two subsets of with different sizes. We write if and there is no other set such that and .
By the definition of parity, we have the following simple remark.
Remark 6.3.
For any and , has a -parity if and only if .
From the above observation, for any and , we define the corresponding -set of as follows.
Definition 6.4.
Let and . If has a -parity, then let be the -parity of ; otherwise, let be the -set such that . We call the corresponding -set of .
Definition 6.5.
Let . For each , let be the corresponding -set of as in Definition 6.4 and for each , let be the -partner of . We denote
Definition 6.6.
For each , let
For any and any , we define . For example, .
Definition 6.7.
Let with and for any , be the -partners of respectively, and for each , let be the corresponding -sets of respectively as in Definition 6.4. We define the following functions.
For , let
Definition 6.8.
For any and any with , we define for each , and .
From the above definition, we have
Remark 6.9.
Suppose that with . Then for any , , and , .
We will prove the following more general lemma, which implies Lemma 3.12.
Lemma 6.10.
Let and with for some . If , then .
Let us explain why Lemma 6.10 implies Lemma 3.12. Take (see Definition 6.1). Take satisfying the condition (see Lemma 3.12). Let and . Then and , and (see Definition 3.11). Let be the -parities of respectively. (Proposition 2.16) guarantees the -parities of exist.) Take in Lemma 6.10. Let , and . Then with and , and (see Definition 6.6). By Fact 2.14, for each , and have the same -partner, and have the same -partner and and have the same -partner. Therefore, , and . Now applying Lemma 6.10, we have that if , then .
Before proving Lemma 6.10, we need to make some preparations. Denote
(27) |
The following remark is useful.
Remark 6.11.
Claim 6.12.
Let with and Then for each , we have
In particular, if and only if . Furthermore, if , then .
Proof.
Clearly, for , . We next consider for . In this case, . Let and be the corresponding -sets of and respectively as in Definition 6.4. Then , moreover and if and only if clearly. implies , furthermore, . Then we can see that if , then . Therefore, , as required. We next assume that is the -parirty of . So . In this case, since , . If , then and , as required. Last, we assume that is the -parirty of . So . Let . In this case we have
Then
as required. ∎
Remark 6.13.
For any with , we have that holds for each , and .
Claim 6.14.
Let , and . Suppose that are -sequential and are -sequential with and . Then and . In particular, if , and , then and .
Proof.
Claim 6.15.
Let and be an integer. Suppose , and for some . Then . If , then . If , then , equality holds if and only if does not have -parity (recall that is the integer such that ).
Proof.
Let and be the -sets such that and . Then , and , are -sequential, , are -sequential. Note that , then applying Lemma 4.4 and Reamrk 6.13, we have that holds for each and . Clearly, holds for each and using Proposition 4.3 and Remark 6.13, we have . Therefore, by Remark 6.9, we have . Clearly, for each ,
(28) |
Since , . By the definitions of , , and , if , then , and if , then and . Using Claim 6.14, for each , we have
(29) |
If the previous case happens, then , so Claim 6.12 gives for each . Combing this with (28), (29) and Remark 6.9, we get
as desired. If the later case happens, then , by Claim 6.12, since and , then for each , we have if , i.e., dest not have -parity; and if , i.e., has -parity. Note that , so if does not have -parity, then it does not have any -parity for . Therefore, , and the equality holds if and only if has -parity, that is, , and the equality holds if and only if does not have -parity, as desired. ∎
We are going to prove Lemma 6.10 by induction on .
6.1 The Base Case
We are going to show that Lemma 6.10 holds for . Assume that with for some and , we are going to show that . Since with , , and . Let and be the -sets such that and . we first show the following observation.
Claim 6.16.
Let be the -set such that , where is the number of -subsets satisfying . If , then , where , increases on , in particular, .
Proof.
By Claim 6.16, next we may assume that
(30) |
Note that
(31) | ||||
(32) |
Since , by Claim 6.12, for each , we have
(33) |
Clearly, for , . So . Note that , combining Proposition 4.3, Remark 6.11, Remark 6.13 and (30), we obtain . Combining with equalities (31) and (32), to show , it is sufficient to show the following claim.
Claim 6.17.
.
Proof.
If , then and . Since , , as desired. Thus, we have proved for .
Next, we consider . In this case, and . Let be the -set such that . Therefore, and . Note that . By Lemma 4.4 and Remark 6.13, we have and . Let be the -set such that . Thus, , and satisfy the condition of Claim 6.15. So we conclude that and . Note that
Thus, to show is sufficient to show the following claim.
Claim 6.18.
.
Proof.
Suppose on the contrary that . Since holds for each and holds for each (see (33)), . Since and , . Therefore, since . Hence, since . This implies . Therefore, and . Since , we may assume that there exists some -set and some integer such that and if . Then .
The forthcoming claim will be used to make a contradiction to , thereby ending the proof of Claim 6.18. We will explain this after stating the claim.
Claim 6.19.
Let be a positive integer, for some set with and . Suppose and is the -set such that . Let . We define -sets as follows. If , then let and for each , when , we regard as an empty set. If , then let for each , when , we regard as an empty set. If , then for each , .
To finish the proof of Claim 6.18, we only need to prove Claim 6.19. Assume that Claim 6.19 holds, taking , , and in Claim 6.19, we can see that and . Since , then Claim 6.19 gives , which is a contradiction to the assumption that . This completes the proof of Claim 6.18 by assuming the truth of Claim 6.19. ∎
Proof for Claim 6.19.
We are going to prove Claim 6.19 by induction on .
We first consider the case . In this case, . If , then we have nothing to say. We may assume . If , then since . Note that we have already proved Lemma 6.10 when . By taking in Lemma 6.10, we have , a contradiction. Using the same argument, we can see that for each , , as required.
We next consider the case and assume that Claim 6.19 holds for . If , then since . Note that . By replacing with and with in Claim 6.19, we define as definitions of . Then by induction hypothesis, we obtain
holds for each . | (34) |
For convenience, we denote . We have the following claim.
Claim 6.20.
For each , . For each , and .
Proof.
Note that , , and . By Claim 6.12, for each , . Trivially, for each , , therefore, , as required.
For each , let and be the -sets such that and . Thus, for each , and we have and Then for each , we have . By Claim 6.14, and . Note that for each , and , hence Claim 6.12 gives , Proposition 4.3 and Remark 6.13 give . So for each , we have
and
Since , and . By Proposition 4.3 and Remark 6.13, . This completes the proof of Claim 6.20. ∎
This completes the base case of Lemma 6.10. We next to consider the induction step.
6.2 The Induction Step
Recall that for . The authors have shown the following result in [5].
Claim 6.21.
[5] Let , in , and . Then and .
We have the following claim.
Claim 6.22.
Let , and in , and with in . Then and .
Proof.
We are ready to give the induction step of Lemma 6.10.
Proof of Lemma 6.10.
By induction on . We have shown that it holds for in Section 6.1. Suppose it holds for , we are going to prove it holds for . Let with and , i.e., . We are going to apply induction hypothesis to show , i.e., . Let and . Then . Moreover, in .
Let be the -sets satisfying and in . Let , . Then . We can see that if , then
(35) |
If , then
(36) |
Claim 6.23.
Proof.
Suppose on the contrary that We first consider the case . By (35),
Note that and , therefore, implies . Since , then
(37) |
Note that with in (i.e., ). By Claim 6.22, we have and . Note that , and , it follows from Claim 6.14 that and Then
Similarly, we have
So inequality (37) gives . Note that in for , by induction hypothesis, . A contradiction to our assumption.
Claim 6.24.
.
Proof.
Since , and in , we will meet the following two cases: and . We first consider the case . Then by Claim 6.22, we have and . Therefore,
as desired. Next we assume that . If , then . By Claim 6.12,
where the last equality holds by Proposition 4.3, as required. If , then , and . By Claim 6.12 and Remark 6.9,
as required. ∎
Consequently, following from Claim 6.24. Recall that and . Hence, by applying Claim 6.14. This implies , as desired.
This completes the proof of Lemma 6.10. ∎
7 Verify Unimodality: The Proofs of Lemmas 3.13, 3.14 and Proposition 3.20
Lemma 7.1.
Let with , and . For , let . Suppose that for some and , then .
Let us explain why Lemma 7.1 implies Lemmas 3.13 and 3.14. Let be as in Lemma 3.13 or Lemma 3.14. Let be the -parities of respectively (Proposition 2.16 guarantees that exists).
By Fact 2.14, for each , and have the same -partner. Take (see Definition 6.1), we have , and . We may take , and . So implies
Then by Lemma 7.1, we have . So
Proof for Lemma 7.1.
Clearly, and . Let and be the -sets such that and . Then . Let be the -set such that . Then are -sequential and are -sequential. Clearly, and . By Claim 6.14,
and . | (40) |
If , then . By Proposition 4.3, . By Claim 6.12, we have . So . So if , then , as desired. We next assume that . Then . If , then . Since and , or , and if and only if (see Proposition 4.3). This is a contradiction to (since and ). So . Consequently, there exists such that . Let be any integer that satisfies the above condition. By Claim 6.12, . Since , . By Claim 6.12 again, . By the arbitrariness of and the definitions of and (see Definition 6.7), we conclude that . Combining with , we have . So if , then , as desired.
Proof for Proposition 3.20.
Let and be the -parity of . Since , . So . Let be the -parity of . So . To prove (15), it is equivalent to prove that . Let . Note that , and are contained in and
in . Let (if , then ). Since , . Let be the set such that and . Clearly, . We may also assume that since otherwise, , we are done. Based on these, we may apply Lemma 7.1 to . Since , Lemma 7.1 gives . Consequently, by Lemma 6.10, , as desired. ∎
8 Acknowledgements
This work was supported by NSFC (Grant No. 11931002).
References
- [1] P. Erdős, C. Ko, R. Rado, Intersection theorems for systems of finite sets, Quart. J. Math. Oxf. 2(12) (1961) 313–320.
- [2] P. Frankl, A. Kupavskii, Erdős-Ko-Rado theorem for {0, ±1}-vectors, J. Comb. Theory Ser. A 155 (2018), 157–179.
- [3] P. Frankl, A. Kupavskii, Sharp results concerning disjoint cross intersecting families, Europ J. Combin 86 (2020) 103089.
- [4] P. Frankl, N. Tokushige, Some best possible inequalities concerning crossing-intersecting families, J. Combin. Theory Ser. A 61 (1992) 87-97.
- [5] Yang Huang, Yuejian Peng, The maximum sum of sizes of non-empty pairwise cross intersecting families. arXiv: 2306.03473.
- [6] Yang Huang, Yuejian Peng, Coefficients added non-empty pairwise cross intersecting families. Manuscript.
- [7] Yang Huang, Yuejian Peng, Mixed pairwise cross intersecting families (II). In preparation.
- [8] A.J.W. Hilton, E.C. Milner, Some intersection theorems for systems of finite sets, Quart. J. Math. Oxf. 2 (18) (1967) 369-384.
- [9] A.J.W. Hilton, The Erdős-Ko-Rado theorem with valency conditions, Unpublished Manuscript, 1976.
- [10] A.J.W. Hilton, An intersection theorem for a collection of families of subsets of a finite set, J. London Math. Soc. 2 (1977) 369-376.
- [11] G.O.H. Katona, A theorem of finite sets, in: Theory of Graphs, Proc. Colloq. Tihany, Akadémai Kiadó, (1968) 187-207.
- [12] J.B. Kruskal, The number of simplices in a complex, in: Math. Opt. Techniques, Univ. of Calif. Press, (1963) 251-278.
- [13] C. Shi, P. Frankl, J. Qian, On non-empty cross-intersecting families, Combinatorica 42 (2022) 1513–1525