This paper was converted on www.awesomepapers.org from LaTeX by an anonymous user.
Want to know more? Visit the Converter page.

Logics of False Belief and Radical Ignorance

Jie Fan
Institute of Philosophy, Chinese Academy of Sciences;
School of Humanities, University of Chinese Academy of Sciences
[email protected]
Abstract

In the literature, the question about how to axiomatize the transitive logic of false belief is thought of as hard and left as an open problem. In this paper, among other contributions, we deal with this problem. In more details, although the standard doxastic operator is undefinable with the operator of false belief, the former is almost definable with the latter. On one hand, the involved almost definability schema guides us to find the desired core axioms for the transitive logic and the Euclidean logic of false belief. On the other hand, inspired by the schema and other considerations, we propose a suitable canonical relation, which can uniformly handle the completeness proof of various logics of false belief, including the transitive logic. We also extend the results to the logic of radical ignorance, due to the interdefinability of the operators of false belief and radical ignorance.

Keywords: false belief, radical ignorance, axiomatizations, expressivity, frame definability

1 Introduction

The prime motivation of this paper is to deal with an open problem about how to axiomatize the transitive logic of false belief.

The discussion about false belief dates back to Plato [1, Sec. 7]. This notion is related to a well-known distinction between knowledge and belief: knowledge must be true, but belief can be false, that is, there are false beliefs. Besides, this notion is popular in the field of cognitive science, see e.g. [12].

The first logical study on false belief is done by Steinsvold in [14], where a logic of false belief is proposed that has the operator WW as a sole primitive modality. There, WφW\varphi is read “one is wrong about φ\varphi”, or “φ\varphi is a false belief”, meaning that φ\varphi is false though believed. This logic is axiomatized over the class of all frames and over various frame classes, and some results of frame definability are presented. The logic is then interpreted over neighborhood semantics in [10] and [5], and analyzed in the intuitionistic setting in [15].

Although both [14, Sec. 5] and [10, Sec. 2.4] spend a whole section on discussing the problem about how to axiomatize the transitive logic of false belief, they think it is difficult. To our best knowledge, this open problem has not been solved until now. Two difficulties are involved. One is how to find the desired core axiom, and the other is how to define a suitable canonical relation.

In this paper, we will show that although the standard doxastic operator is undefinable with the operator of false belief, the former is almost definable with the latter. On one hand, the involved almost definability schema guides us to find the desired core axioms for the transitive logic and the Euclidean logic of false belief. On the other hand, inspired by the schema and other considerations, we propose a suitable canonical relation, which can uniformly handle the completeness proof of various logics of false belief, including the transitive logic, thereby solving the open problem in [14].

Moreover, we extend the results to the logic of radical ignorance. The notion of radical ignorance is proposed in [9], to (hopefully) adequately express the important properties in the phenomenon of the Dunning–Kruger effect. This notion is formalized by using a KT4-B4 framework, in which the epistemic accessibility relation RKR_{K} is reflexive and transitive, the doxastic accessibility relation RBR_{B} is transitive, and RBR_{B} is included in RKR_{K}. An agent is radically ignorant about φ\varphi iff the agent does not know φ\varphi and also does not know ¬φ\neg\varphi,111The original wording on page 611 of [9] is “the agent does not know both φ\varphi and ¬φ\neg\varphi”, where there is a danger of misunderstanding because of a scope ambiguity. and either the agent believes φ\varphi but it is the case that ¬φ\neg\varphi, or it is the case that φ\varphi but the agent believes ¬φ\neg\varphi; in symbol, IRφ=df((¬Kφ¬K¬φ)((Bφ¬φ)(B¬φφ)))I_{R}\varphi=_{df}((\neg K\varphi\land\neg K\neg\varphi)\land((B\varphi\land\neg\varphi)\vee(B\neg\varphi\land\varphi))), where KK and BB are standard opeartors of knowledge and belief, resepctively. Under very natural assumptions, namely KφφK\varphi\to\varphi, KφBφK\varphi\to B\varphi and ¬(BφB¬φ)\neg(B\varphi\land B\neg\varphi), the definition can be simplified to the following: IRφ=df((Bφ¬φ)(B¬φφ))I_{R}\varphi=_{df}((B\varphi\land\neg\varphi)\vee(B\neg\varphi\land\varphi)).222There is an error on page 611 of [9]: it says this simplification can be done in the framework KT4-B4, but the serial axiom for the belief operator, viz. ¬(BφB¬φ)\neg(B\varphi\land B\neg\varphi), is lacking. So it is KT4-BD4 (instead of KT4-B4) frames, where the doxastic accessibility relation is serial as well, that are the frames which the framework of the cited paper is actually based on. However, there have been no formal systems characterizing the notion of radical ignorance.

A related work in the literature is the investigation on the notion of reliable belief in [4], with different motivations though. Note that the operator \mathcal{R} of reliable belief is the negation of IRI_{R}, since φ\mathcal{R}\varphi is equivalent to (Bφφ)(B¬φ¬φ)(B\varphi\to\varphi)\land(B\neg\varphi\to\neg\varphi). The minimal logic and the serial logic of reliable belief are axiomatized there. However, the canonical model there does not apply to the transitive logic of reliable belief, thus not to the transitive logic of radical ignorance either.

As we will see, the operators of radical ignorance and false beliefs are interdefinable with each other. This may indicate that one can translate the results about false belief into those about radical ignorance via the translation induced by the definability of the operator WW in terms of the operator of radical ignorance. Unfortunately, this holds for all but the minimal proof system.333Note that this is not new. Even if two operators are interdefinable with each other, it is not necessary that the axiomatizations of the logic with one operator as a sole modality can be obtained from those of the logic with the other operator as a sole modality via the translation induced by the interdefinability of the operators. For instance, although the necessity operator \Box and the dyadic contingency operator are interdefinable with each other, the serial logic of dyadic contingency cannot be obtained from the serial system KD via the translation induced by the interdefinability of the operators, see [6, p. 214]. We will illustrate this with the axiomatizations of the logic of radical ignorance over all frames and over serial and transitive frames.

The remainder of this paper is organized as follows. After introducing the language and semantics of the logic of false belief, we propose an almost definability schema (Sec. 2.1). Then we compare the expressive powers of the logic of false belief and standard doxastic logic, and investigate the frame definability of the former (Sec. 2.2). Sec. 2.3 axiomatizes the logic of false belief over various frame classes, including the transitive logic (Sec. 2.3.4) specially, thereby solving an open problem raised in [14]. The canonical relation here is inspired by the aforementioned almost definability schema and other considerations. Moreover, the desired core axioms for the transitive logic and the Euclidean logic of false belief are obtained from the familiar axioms via a translation induced by the almost definability schema. Last but not least, we axiomatize the logic of radical ignorance (Sec. 3). After briefly reviewing the language and semantics of the logic of radical ignorance, we note that the operators of radical ignorance and of false beliefs are interdefinable with each other. Then we axiomatize the minimal logic (Sec. 3.1) and the serial and transitive logic (Sec. 3.2) of radical ignorance.

2 False belief

2.1 Syntax and Semantics

Throughout the paper, we assume P to be a nonempty set of propositional variables. We first define a logical language including both false belief and belief operators. The language of the standard doxastic logic and the language of the logic of false belief can be viewed as two fragment of this language. It is the latter that is our main focus in the rest of the paper.

Definition 1.

The language (W,)\mathcal{L}(W,\Box) is defined recursively as follows.

φ::=p¬φ(φφ)Wφφ,\begin{array}[]{lll}\varphi&::=&p\mid\neg\varphi\mid(\varphi\land\varphi)\mid W\varphi\mid\Box\varphi,\\ \end{array}

where pPp\in\textbf{P}. The language of the logic of false belief, denoted (W)\mathcal{L}(W), is the fragment of (W,)\mathcal{L}(W,\Box) without the construct φ\Box\varphi. The language of standard doxastic logic, denoted ()\mathcal{L}(\Box), is the fragment of (W,)\mathcal{L}(W,\Box) without the construct WφW\varphi.

Other connectives are defined as usual. The formula WφW\varphi is read “φ\varphi is a false belief of the agent”, or “the agent is wrong about φ\varphi”.444In a deontic setting, W¬φW\neg\varphi (that is, ¬φφ\Box\neg\varphi\land\varphi) is read “φ\varphi ought not to be done but done”, which expresses some kind of vice: one did what one ought not to have done. In a metaphysical setting, W¬φW\neg\varphi is read “φ\varphi is strongly accidental”, c.f. [13]. The language is interpreted on models.

Definition 2.

A model is a triple =S,R,V\mathcal{M}=\langle S,R,V\rangle, where SS is a nonempty set of states, RR is a binary relation over SS, called ‘accessibility relation’, and VV is a valuation. A frame is a model without valuations; in this case, we also say that the model is based on the frame. We use sRt{\sim}sRt to mean that “it does not hold that sRtsRt”.

Definition 3 (Semantics).

Given a model =S,R,V\mathcal{M}=\langle S,R,V\rangle and a state sSs\in S, the semantics of (W,)\mathcal{L}(W,\Box) is defined recursively as follows.

,spiffsV(p),s¬φiff,sφ,sφψiff,sφ and ,sψ,sWφiff,sφ and for all t, if sRt then ,tφ,sφifffor all t, if sRt then ,tφ.\begin{array}[]{|lll|}\hline\cr\mathcal{M},s\vDash p&\text{iff}&s\in V(p)\\ \mathcal{M},s\vDash\neg\varphi&\text{iff}&\mathcal{M},s\nvDash\varphi\\ \mathcal{M},s\vDash\varphi\land\psi&\text{iff}&\mathcal{M},s\vDash\varphi\text{ and }\mathcal{M},s\vDash\psi\\ \mathcal{M},s\vDash W\varphi&\text{iff}&\mathcal{M},s\nvDash\varphi\text{ and for all }t,\text{ if }sRt\text{ then }\mathcal{M},t\vDash\varphi\\ \mathcal{M},s\vDash\Box\varphi&\text{iff}&\text{for all }t,\text{ if }sRt\text{ then }\mathcal{M},t\vDash\varphi.\\ \hline\cr\end{array}

If ,sφ\mathcal{M},s\vDash\varphi, we say that φ\varphi is true in (,s)(\mathcal{M},s), and sometimes write sφs\vDash\varphi if \mathcal{M} is clear. If for all frames \mathcal{F} in FF, for all models \mathcal{M} based on \mathcal{F}, for all ss in \mathcal{M} we have ,sφ\mathcal{M},s\vDash\varphi, then we say that φ\varphi is valid on FF and write FφF\vDash\varphi; when FF is the class of all frames, we say φ\varphi is valid and write φ\vDash\varphi. The notions for a set of formulas are defined similarly.

From the above semantics, it follows easily that WW is definable in terms of \Box, as Wφ(φ¬φ)\vDash W\varphi\leftrightarrow(\Box\varphi\land\neg\varphi). In contrast, as we will show in Prop. 7, the converse does not hold, since \Box is not definable in terms of WW in various classes of models.

Let R(s)={tsRt}R(s)=\{t\mid sRt\}. The semantics of WW can be rewritten as follows:

,sWφiff,sφ and R(s)φ.\begin{array}[]{lll}\mathcal{M},s\vDash W\varphi&\text{iff}&\mathcal{M},s\nvDash\varphi\text{ and }R(s)\vDash\varphi.\\ \end{array}

Although \Box is undefinable with WW, we have the following important schema, which says that \Box is almost definable in terms of WW. We call it ‘Almost Definability Schema’.

Proposition 4.

Wψ(φW(φψ)).\vDash W\psi\to(\Box\varphi\leftrightarrow W(\varphi\land\psi)).

Proof.

Let =S,R,V\mathcal{M}=\langle S,R,V\rangle be a model and sSs\in S. Suppose that ,sWψ\mathcal{M},s\vDash W\psi, to show that ,sφW(φψ)\mathcal{M},s\vDash\Box\varphi\leftrightarrow W(\varphi\land\psi).

First, assume that ,sφ\mathcal{M},s\vDash\Box\varphi, to prove that ,sW(φψ)\mathcal{M},s\vDash W(\varphi\land\psi). By assumption, we infer that R(s)φR(s)\vDash\varphi. By supposition, we have ,sψ\mathcal{M},s\nvDash\psi and R(s)ψR(s)\vDash\psi, thus ,sφψ\mathcal{M},s\nvDash\varphi\land\psi and R(s)φψR(s)\vDash\varphi\land\psi. This implies that ,sW(φψ)\mathcal{M},s\vDash W(\varphi\land\psi).

Conversely, assume that ,sW(φψ)\mathcal{M},s\vDash W(\varphi\land\psi), then R(s)φψR(s)\vDash\varphi\land\psi. So R(s)φR(s)\vDash\varphi, and therefore ,sφ\mathcal{M},s\vDash\Box\varphi. ∎

This schema is very important, since it not only guides us to find out the desired core axioms of transitive logic and Euclidean logic for (W)\mathcal{L}(W), it also motivates the canonical relation in the construction of canonical model for (W)\mathcal{L}(W). With this relation we can show the completeness of all axiomatizations uniformly, as we will see below.

2.2 Expressivity and Frame Definability

In this part, we investigate the expressive power and frame definability of (W)\mathcal{L}(W). To begin with, we have the following useful observation, which follows directly from the semantics of WW.

Fact 5.

For all φ\varphi, WφW\varphi is false in each reflexive state.

Proposition 6.

For any reflexive frames \mathcal{F} and \mathcal{F}^{\prime}, for any φ(W)\varphi\in\mathcal{L}(W), φ\mathcal{F}\vDash\varphi iff φ\mathcal{F}^{\prime}\vDash\varphi.

Proof.

Let =S,R\mathcal{F}=\langle S,R\rangle and =S,R\mathcal{F}^{\prime}=\langle S^{\prime},R^{\prime}\rangle be reflexive frames, and let φ(W)\varphi\in\mathcal{L}(W).

Suppose that φ\mathcal{F}\nvDash\varphi, then there is a valuation VV and a state ss such that F,V,sφ\langle F,V\rangle,s\nvDash\varphi. Since SS^{\prime}\neq\emptyset, we may assume that sSs^{\prime}\in S. Define a valuation VV^{\prime} on \mathcal{F}^{\prime} as follows: sV(p)s^{\prime}\in V^{\prime}(p) iff sV(p)s\in V(p) for all pPp\in\textbf{P}. Since \mathcal{F} and \mathcal{F}^{\prime} are both reflexive, both ss and ss^{\prime} are reflexive. By Fact 5, this means that all WφW\varphi are false in both states. Then by induction on ψ(W)\psi\in\mathcal{L}(W), we can show that ,V,sψ\langle\mathcal{F},V\rangle,s\vDash\psi iff ,V,sψ\langle\mathcal{F}^{\prime},V^{\prime}\rangle,s^{\prime}\vDash\psi. Hence ,V,sψ\langle\mathcal{F}^{\prime},V^{\prime}\rangle,s^{\prime}\nvDash\psi, and therefore φ\mathcal{F}^{\prime}\nvDash\varphi. The converse is similar. ∎

It turns out that (W)\mathcal{L}(W) is less expressive than ()\mathcal{L}(\Box) on various classes of models.

Proposition 7.

(W)\mathcal{L}(W) is less expressive than ()\mathcal{L}(\Box) on the class of 𝒮5\mathcal{S}5-models. As a consequence, (W)\mathcal{L}(W) is less expressive than ()\mathcal{L}(\Box) on the class of 𝒦\mathcal{K}-models, 𝒟\mathcal{D}-models, 𝒯\mathcal{T}-models, 4-models, \mathcal{B}-models, 5-models, 𝒟4\mathcal{D}4-models, 𝒟45\mathcal{D}45-models.

Proof.

As mentioned above, WW is definable in terms of \Box, thus ()\mathcal{L}(\Box) is at least as expressive as (W)\mathcal{L}(W). For the strict part, consider the following 𝒮5\mathcal{S}5-models:

\textstyle{\mathcal{M}}s:p\textstyle{s:p\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}\textstyle{\mathcal{M}^{\prime}}s:p\textstyle{s^{\prime}:p\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}t:¬p\textstyle{t^{\prime}:\neg p\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}

Using Fact 5, we can show by induction that for all φ(W)\varphi\in\mathcal{L}(W), ,sφ\mathcal{M},s\vDash\varphi iff ,sφ\mathcal{M}^{\prime},s^{\prime}\vDash\varphi. Thus (,s)(\mathcal{M},s) and (,s)(\mathcal{M}^{\prime},s^{\prime}) cannot be distinguished by (W)\mathcal{L}(W).

However, these two models can be distingished by ()\mathcal{L}(\Box), since ,sp\mathcal{M},s\vDash\Box p but ,sp\mathcal{M}^{\prime},s^{\prime}\nvDash\Box p. ∎

It may be natural to ask if there is a class of frames where \Box is definable in terms of WW. The answer is positive. We borrow a notion of narcissistic from [14, Def. 2.1]. Call ss narcissistic if and only if ss relates to itself and only to itself. Call a frame narcissistic if all the worlds are narcissistic; that is,

x(xRxy(xRyx=y)).\forall x(xRx\land\forall y(xRy\to x=y)).
Proposition 8.

On the class of narcissistic frames, \Box is definable in terms of WW. As a consequence, (W)\mathcal{L}(W) and ()\mathcal{L}(\Box) are equally expressive on the class of narcissistic models.

Proof.

Let FnarF_{nar} be the class of narcissistic frames. It is straightforward to verify that FnarφφF_{nar}\vDash\Box\varphi\leftrightarrow\varphi. This means that on the frame classes in question, \Box is already definable in the language of propositional logic; needless to say, \Box is definable in terms of WW. ∎

Remark 9.

In [11, Sect. 1.4], the authors compare the expressive power of (I)\mathcal{L}(I) and ()\mathcal{L}(\Box).555In [11], (I)\mathcal{L}(I) is the language of the logic of factive ignorance that has the operator II of factive ignorance as a sole primitive modality. Boolean formulas are interpreted as usual, and IφI\varphi is interpreted as follows: given a model =S,R,V\mathcal{M}=\langle S,R,V\rangle and a state sSs\in S, ,sIφ\mathcal{M},s\vDash I\varphi iff ,sφ\mathcal{M},s\vDash\varphi and for all tSt\in S, if sRtsRt and sts\neq t, then ,tφ\mathcal{M},t\nvDash\varphi. It turns out that neither of II and \Box is, in general, definable in terms of the other. In particular, it is shown in [11, Coro. 1.31] that the indefinability of \Box in terms of II applies to a wide variety of frame classes. In the meanwhile, the authors ask whether there exist any interesting classes of frames in which \Box is definable in terms of II and they think the answer is negative (see [11, p. 878]). However, the answer is actually positive, since on the class of narcissistic frames, \Box is definable in terms of II. The same class of frames also establishes the definability of II in terms of \Box, since as one may show, FnarIφφF_{nar}\vDash I\varphi\leftrightarrow\varphi, where FnarF_{nar} is the class of narcissistic frames.

The following result is shown in [14, Thm. 4.8], where the proof is based on a canonical model. Here we give a much simpler proof, without need of canonical models.

Proposition 10.

The following frame properties are all undefinable in (W)\mathcal{L}(W):666To say a frame property P is definable in a logic \mathcal{L}, if there is a set Γ\Gamma of \mathcal{L}-formulas such that for all frames \mathcal{F}, Γ\mathcal{F}\vDash\Gamma iff \mathcal{F} has P.

  • (1)

    Transitivity,

  • (2)

    Euclideanness,

  • (3)

    Symmetry,

  • (4)

    weak connectedness xyz((xRyxRz)(yRzy=zzRy))\forall x\forall y\forall z((xRy\land xRz)\to(yRz\vee y=z\vee zRy)),

  • (5)

    weak directedness xyz((xRyxRz)v(yRvzRv))\forall x\forall y\forall z((xRy\land xRz)\to\exists v(yRv\land zRv)),

  • (6)

    partial functionality xyz((xRyxRz)z=y)\forall x\forall y\forall z((xRy\land xRz)\to z=y),

  • (7)

    narcissism x(xRxy(xRyx=y))\forall x(xRx\land\forall y(xRy\to x=y)),

  • (8)

    partial narcissism xy(xRyx=y)\forall x\forall y(xRy\to x=y).

Proof.

Consider the following frames:

:\textstyle{\mathcal{F}:}s\textstyle{s\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}:\textstyle{\mathcal{F}^{\prime}:}u\textstyle{u^{\prime}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}s\textstyle{s^{\prime}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}t\textstyle{t^{\prime}\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces\ignorespaces}

One may check that for any frame property PP in (1)-(8), it is not the case that \mathcal{F} has PP iff \mathcal{F}^{\prime} has PP. However, since \mathcal{F} and \mathcal{F}^{\prime} are both reflexive, by Prop. 6, for all φ(W)\varphi\in\mathcal{L}(W), we have that φ\mathcal{F}\vDash\varphi iff φ\mathcal{F}^{\prime}\vDash\varphi. This entails that the frame properties in question are all undefinable in (W)\mathcal{L}(W). ∎

2.3 Axiomatizations

This section presents the axiomatizations of (W)\mathcal{L}(W) over various frame classes.

2.3.1 Minimal Logic

Definition 11.

The minimal logic of (W)\mathcal{L}(W), denoted 𝐊𝐖{\bf K^{W}}, consists of the following axioms and inference rules:

A0all instances of propositional tautologiesA1Wφ¬φA2WφWψW(φψ)MPφφψψR1φψWφ¬ψWψ\begin{array}[]{ll}\text{A0}&\text{all instances of propositional tautologies}\\ \text{A1}&W\varphi\to\neg\varphi\\ \text{A2}&W\varphi\land W\psi\to W(\varphi\land\psi)\\ \text{MP}&\dfrac{\varphi\leavevmode\nobreak\ \leavevmode\nobreak\ \leavevmode\nobreak\ \varphi\to\psi}{\psi}\\ \text{R1}&\dfrac{\varphi\to\psi}{W\varphi\land\neg\psi\to W\psi}\\ \end{array}

The notions of theorems, provability, and derivation are defined as usual.

This system is called 𝐒𝐖{\bf S^{W}} in [14]. Intuitively, axiom A1 says that false beliefs are false, A2 says that false beliefs are closed under conjunction: the conjunction of two false beliefs are still a false belief. The rule R1 stipulates the almost monotonicity of the false belief operator. It is shown in [14, Thm. 3.1] that the substituition rule of equivalents for the operator WW, i.e. φψ/WφWψ\varphi\leftrightarrow\psi\leavevmode\nobreak\ /\leavevmode\nobreak\ W\varphi\leftrightarrow W\psi, denoted REW, is admissible in 𝐊𝐖{\bf K^{W}}. Moreover, we have the following.

Proposition 12.

The following rule is admissible in 𝐊𝐖{\bf K^{W}}:

φψW(φχ)¬ψWψ.\dfrac{\varphi\to\psi}{W(\varphi\land\chi)\land\neg\psi\to W\psi}.
Proof.

We have the following proof sequence in 𝐊𝐖{\bf K^{W}}.

(1)φψhypothesis(2)Wφ¬ψWψ(1),R1(3)φχφA0(4)W(φχ)¬φWφ(3),R1(5)W(φχ)¬φ¬ψWψ(2),(4)(6)W(φχ)¬ψWψ(1),(5)\begin{array}[]{lll}(1)&\varphi\to\psi&\text{hypothesis}\\ (2)&W\varphi\land\neg\psi\to W\psi&(1),\text{R1}\\ (3)&\varphi\land\chi\to\varphi&\text{A0}\\ (4)&W(\varphi\land\chi)\land\neg\varphi\to W\varphi&(3),\text{R1}\\ (5)&W(\varphi\land\chi)\land\neg\varphi\land\neg\psi\to W\psi&(2),(4)\\ (6)&W(\varphi\land\chi)\land\neg\psi\to W\psi&(1),(5)\\ \end{array}

We can generalize the above proposition to the following.

Proposition 13.

Let nn\in\mathbb{N}. If χ1χnφ\vdash\chi_{1}\land\cdots\land\chi_{n}\to\varphi, then W(χ1ψ)W(χnψ)¬φWφ\vdash W(\chi_{1}\land\psi)\land\cdots\land W(\chi_{n}\land\psi)\land\neg\varphi\to W\varphi.

Proof.

By induction on nn\in\mathbb{N}. The case n=0n=0 is obvious. The case n=1n=1 is shown as in Prop. 12.

Now suppose that the statement holds for mm (IH), to show that it also holds for m+1m+1. For this, we have the following proof sequence:

(1)χ1χm+1φpremise(2)(χ1χ2)χm+1φ(1)(3)W((χ1χ2)ψ)W(χm+1ψ)¬φWφ(2),IH(4)W(χ1ψ)W(χ2ψ)W((χ1χ2)ψ)A2(5)W(χ1ψ)W(χm+1ψ)¬φWφ(3),(4)\begin{array}[]{lll}(1)&\chi_{1}\land\cdots\land\chi_{m+1}\to\varphi&\text{premise}\\ (2)&(\chi_{1}\land\chi_{2})\land\cdots\land\chi_{m+1}\to\varphi&(1)\\ (3)&W((\chi_{1}\land\chi_{2})\land\psi)\land\cdots\land W(\chi_{m+1}\land\psi)\land\neg\varphi\to W\varphi&(2),\text{IH}\\ (4)&W(\chi_{1}\land\psi)\land W(\chi_{2}\land\psi)\to W((\chi_{1}\land\chi_{2})\land\psi)&\text{A2}\\ (5)&W(\chi_{1}\land\psi)\land\cdots\land W(\chi_{m+1}\land\psi)\land\neg\varphi\to W\varphi&(3),(4)\\ \end{array}

The completeness of 𝐊𝐖{\bf K^{W}} is shown via the construction of a canonical model.

Definition 14.

The canonical model for 𝐊𝐖{\bf K^{W}} is c=Sc,Rc,Vc\mathcal{M}^{c}=\langle S^{c},R^{c},V^{c}\rangle, where

  • Sc={ss is a maximal consistent set for 𝐊𝐖}S^{c}=\{s\mid s\text{ is a maximal consistent set for }{\bf K^{W}}\},

  • for all s,tScs,t\in S^{c}, RcR^{c} is defined as follows:

    • if WψsW\psi\in s for no ψ\psi, then sRctsR^{c}t iff s=ts=t, and

    • if WψsW\psi\in s for some ψ\psi, then sRctsR^{c}t iff for all φ\varphi, if W(φψ)sW(\varphi\land\psi)\in s, then φt\varphi\in t.

  • Vc(p)={sScps}V^{c}(p)=\{s\in S^{c}\mid p\in s\}.

It is worth noting that the above definition of TcT^{c} is inspired by Almost Definability Schema (Prop. 4). Recall that in the construction of the canonical model of standard doxastic logic, the canonical relation RcR^{c} is usually defined as follows: sRctsR^{c}t iff for all φ\varphi, if φs\Box\varphi\in s, then φt\varphi\in t. According to Almost Definability Schema, φs\Box\varphi\in s can be replaced by W(φψ)sW(\varphi\land\psi)\in s provided that WψsW\psi\in s for some ψ\psi. This is similar to the case for minimal contingency logic [8].

However, unlike the case for minimal contingency logic [8], here “WψsW\psi\in s for some ψ\psi” should be a precondition, instead of a conjunction, of the aforementioned replacement.777In other words, in the case of WψsW\psi\in s for some ψ\psi, we replace φs\Box\varphi\in s with W(φψ)sW(\varphi\land\psi)\in s in the definition of the canonical relation of the canonical model for standard doxastic logic. Moreover, if this precondition is not satisfied, then ss can and only can access itself. As we will see, the case-by-case definition enables us to prove the completeness of the minimal system and its extensions, which however cannot be done if we use “WψsW\psi\in s for some ψ\psi” as a conjunction (as the reader may verify).

Also notice that our definition differs from the canonical relation in [14, Def. 4.2] in that we have W(φψ)sW(\varphi\land\psi)\in s instead of WφsW\varphi\in s. Besides, as already mentioned above, our definition is motivated by Almost Definability Schema. As we will see, the slight distinction enables us to show the completeness of the transitive system of (W)\mathcal{L}(W) (Sec. 2.3.4), which cannot be done with WφsW\varphi\in s instead.

The following result states that the truth lemma holds for 𝐊𝐖{\bf K^{W}}.

Lemma 15.

For all φ(W)\varphi\in\mathcal{L}(W) and for all sScs\in S^{c}, we have

c,sφ iff φs.\mathcal{M}^{c},s\vDash\varphi\text{\leavevmode\nobreak\ iff\leavevmode\nobreak\ }\varphi\in s.
Proof.

By induction on φ\varphi. We only consider the case WφW\varphi.

‘If’: suppose that WφsW\varphi\in s, to show that c,sWφ\mathcal{M}^{c},s\vDash W\varphi. By supposition and axiom A1, ¬φs\neg\varphi\in s, and thus φs\varphi\notin s. By IH, we have c,sφ\mathcal{M}^{c},s\nvDash\varphi. Now let tSct\in S^{c} such that sRctsR^{c}t, by IH, it suffices to show that φt\varphi\in t. By definition of TcT^{c} and supposition, we infer that for all χ\chi, if W(χφ)sW(\chi\land\varphi)\in s, then χt\chi\in t. By letting χ\chi be φ\varphi, we derive that φt\varphi\in t.

‘Only if’: assume that WφsW\varphi\notin s, to show that c,sWφ\mathcal{M}^{c},s\nvDash W\varphi. If WψsW\psi\in s for no ψ\psi, then we are done, since otherwise we would have c,sφ\mathcal{M}^{c},s\vDash\varphi and c,sφ\mathcal{M}^{c},s\nvDash\varphi. Now we consider the case that WψsW\psi\in s for some ψ\psi. For this, suppose that ¬φs\neg\varphi\in s, by IH and Lindenbaum’s Lemma, we only need to show that {χW(χψ)s}{¬φ}\{\chi\mid W(\chi\land\psi)\in s\}\cup\{\neg\varphi\} (denoted Γ\Gamma) is consistent.

Since WψsW\psi\in s, {χW(χψ)s}\{\chi\mid W(\chi\land\psi)\in s\} is nonempty. If Γ\Gamma is not consistent, then there are χ1,,χn\chi_{1},\dots,\chi_{n} such that W(χiψ)sW(\chi_{i}\land\psi)\in s for all i=1,,ni=1,\dots,n and

χ1χnφ.\vdash\chi_{1}\land\cdots\land\chi_{n}\to\varphi.

By Prop. 13,

W(χ1ψ)W(χnψ)¬φWφ.\vdash W(\chi_{1}\land\psi)\land\cdots\land W(\chi_{n}\land\psi)\land\neg\varphi\to W\varphi.

As W(χiψ)sW(\chi_{i}\land\psi)\in s for all i=1,,ni=1,\dots,n and ¬φs\neg\varphi\in s, we infer that WφsW\varphi\in s, which contradicts the assumption, as desired. ∎

It is now routine to show the following.

Theorem 16.

𝐊𝐖{\bf K^{W}} is sound and strongly complete with resepct to the class of all frames.

2.3.2 Serial Logic

Let 𝐊𝐃𝐖{\bf KD^{W}} denote 𝐊𝐖+AD{\bf K^{W}}+\text{AD}, where AD is ¬W\neg W\bot.

Theorem 17.

𝐊𝐃𝐖{\bf KD^{W}} is sound and strongly complete with respect to the class of serial frames.

Proof.

For soundness, by Thm. 16, it remains only to show the validity of the axiom AD.

If there is a serial model =S,T,V\mathcal{M}=\langle S,T,V\rangle and a state sSs\in S such that ,sW\mathcal{M},s\vDash W\bot. Then ,s\mathcal{M},s\vDash\top and for all tt, if sRtsRt then ,t\mathcal{M},t\vDash\bot. This is impossible since RR is serial. Hence ¬W\neg W\bot is valid over the class of serial models.

For completeness, define c\mathcal{M}^{c} w.r.t. 𝐊𝐃𝐖{\bf KD^{W}} as in Def. 14. By Thm. 16, it suffices to prove that RcR^{c} is serial. For this, assume that sScs\in S^{c}. We consider two cases. If there is no ψ\psi such that WψsW\psi\in s, then by definition of RcR^{c}, sRcssR^{c}s. The remainder is the case that there is some ψ\psi such that WψsW\psi\in s. In this case, the set {φW(φψ)s}\{\varphi\mid W(\varphi\land\psi)\in s\} is nonempty. By definition of RcR^{c} and Lindenbaum’s Lemma, we only need to show that this set is consistent.

If not, then there are φ1,,φn\varphi_{1},\dots,\varphi_{n} such that W(φiψ)sW(\varphi_{i}\land\psi)\in s for all i=1,,ni=1,\dots,n, and

φ1φn.\vdash\varphi_{1}\land\cdots\land\varphi_{n}\to\bot.

By Prop. 13,

W(φ1ψ)W(φnψ)¬W.\vdash W(\varphi_{1}\land\psi)\land\cdots\land W(\varphi_{n}\land\psi)\land\neg\bot\to W\bot.

Since W(φiψ)sW(\varphi_{i}\land\psi)\in s for all i=1,,ni=1,\dots,n, and ¬s\neg\bot\in s, we infer that WsW\bot\in s, which contradicts the fact that ¬W\vdash\neg W\bot. ∎

2.3.3 Reflexive Logic

Let 𝐓𝐖{\bf T^{W}} denote 𝐊𝐖+¬Wφ{\bf K^{W}}+\neg W\varphi.

Theorem 18.

𝐓𝐖{\bf T^{W}} is sound and strongly complete with respect to the class of reflexive frames.

Proof.

For soundness, by Thm. 16, it remains only to show the validity of ¬Wφ\neg W\varphi, which can be obtained from Fact 5.

For completeness, define c\mathcal{M}^{c} w.r.t. 𝐓𝐖{\bf T^{W}} as in Def. 14. By Thm. 16, it suffices to show that RcR^{c} is reflexive. For this, let sScs\in S^{c}. Since ¬Wφ\vdash\neg W\varphi, there is no ψ\psi such that WψsW\psi\in s. By definition of RcR^{c}, we derive that sRcssR^{c}s, as desired. ∎

2.3.4 Transitive Logic

Let 𝐊𝟒𝐖{\bf K4^{W}} denote the extension of 𝐊𝐖{\bf K^{W}} with the following axiom:

A4WψW(φψ)W((WχW(φχ))ψ).\begin{array}[]{ll}\text{A4}&W\psi\land W(\varphi\land\psi)\to W((W\chi\to W(\varphi\land\chi))\land\psi).\\ \end{array}

As mentioned in the introduction, a difficult thing in axiomatizing (W)\mathcal{L}(W) over transitive frames is how to find the desired core axiom. Here the axiom A4 is obtained from the modal axiom 4 (i.e. φφ\Box\varphi\to\Box\Box\varphi) via a translation induced by Almost Definability Schema.

Wψ(φ(Wχφ))(1)Wψ(W(φψ)W((Wχφ)ψ)(2)Wψ(W(φψ)W((WχW(φχ))ψ))(3)WψW(φψ)W((WχW(φχ))ψ)(4)\begin{array}[]{llr}&W\psi\to(\Box\varphi\to\Box(W\chi\to\Box\varphi))&(1)\\ \Longleftrightarrow&W\psi\to(W(\varphi\land\psi)\to W((W\chi\to\Box\varphi)\land\psi)&(2)\\ \Longleftrightarrow&W\psi\to(W(\varphi\land\psi)\to W((W\chi\to W(\varphi\land\chi))\land\psi))&(3)\\ \Longleftrightarrow&W\psi\land W(\varphi\land\psi)\to W((W\chi\to W(\varphi\land\chi))\land\psi)&(4)\\ \end{array}

We write Wψ(φ(Wχφ))W\psi\to(\Box\varphi\to\Box(W\chi\to\Box\varphi)) rather than φφ\Box\varphi\to\Box\Box\varphi, since \Box is definable in terms of WW under the condition WψW\psi for some ψ\psi. Note that every transformation is equivalent. The above transitions from (1) to (2) and from (2) to (3) follow from Prop. 4. By using propositional calculus (axiom A0), we then obtain the axiom (4), that is, A4.

Proposition 19.

A4 is valid on the class of transitive frames.

Proof.

Let =S,R,V\mathcal{M}=\langle S,R,V\rangle be a transitive model and sSs\in S. Suppose, for reductio, that ,sWψW(φψ)\mathcal{M},s\vDash W\psi\land W(\varphi\land\psi) but ,sW((WχW(φχ))ψ)\mathcal{M},s\nvDash W((W\chi\to W(\varphi\land\chi))\land\psi). From ,sWψ\mathcal{M},s\vDash W\psi it follows that R(s)ψR(s)\vDash\psi and ,sψ\mathcal{M},s\nvDash\psi, thus ,s(WχW(φχ))ψ\mathcal{M},s\nvDash(W\chi\to W(\varphi\land\chi))\land\psi. This plus ,sW((WχW(φχ))ψ)\mathcal{M},s\nvDash W((W\chi\to W(\varphi\land\chi))\land\psi) implies that R(s)(WχW(φχ))ψR(s)\nvDash(W\chi\to W(\varphi\land\chi))\land\psi, that is, there exists tt such that sRtsRt and ,t(WχW(φχ))ψ\mathcal{M},t\nvDash(W\chi\to W(\varphi\land\chi))\land\psi. Since R(s)ψR(s)\vDash\psi, we infer that ,tψ\mathcal{M},t\vDash\psi, thus ,tWχW(φχ)\mathcal{M},t\nvDash W\chi\to W(\varphi\land\chi), namely tWχt\vDash W\chi and tW(φχ)t\nvDash W(\varphi\land\chi). This entails that tχt\nvDash\chi and thus tφχt\nvDash\varphi\land\chi, hence there is a uu such that tRutRu and ,uφχ\mathcal{M},u\nvDash\varphi\land\chi. However, we have also ,uφχ\mathcal{M},u\vDash\varphi\land\chi: ,uχ\mathcal{M},u\vDash\chi follows from tWχt\vDash W\chi and tRutRu, whereas ,uφ\mathcal{M},u\vDash\varphi is due to the fact that sRusRu (this is because sRtsRt and tRutRu and RR is transitive) and sW(φψ)s\vDash W(\varphi\land\psi). A contradiction. ∎

With the previous preparation in hand, we can show the following.

Theorem 20.

𝐊𝟒𝐖{\bf K4^{W}} is sound and strongly complete with respect to the class of transitive frames.

Proof.

The soundness follows immediately from Thm. 16 and Prop. 19.

For completeness, define c\mathcal{M}^{c} w.r.t. 𝐊𝟒𝐖{\bf K4^{W}} as in Def. 14. By Thm. 16, it suffices to show that RcR^{c} is transitive. Let s,t,uScs,t,u\in S^{c}. Suppose that sRctsR^{c}t and tRcutR^{c}u, to prove that sRcusR^{c}u. We consider the following cases.

  • WψsW\psi\in s for no ψ\psi. In this case, by definition of RcR^{c}, s=ts=t. Then sRcusR^{c}u.

  • WψtW\psi\in t for no ψ\psi. Similar to the first case, we can show that sRcusR^{c}u.

  • WψsW\psi\in s for some ψ\psi and WψtW\psi^{\prime}\in t for some ψ\psi^{\prime}. In this case, assume for all φ\varphi that W(φψ)sW(\varphi\land\psi)\in s, to show that φu\varphi\in u. Using axiom A4, we derive that W((WψW(φψ))ψ)sW((W\psi^{\prime}\to W(\varphi\land\psi^{\prime}))\land\psi)\in s. By sRctsR^{c}t and definition of RcR^{c}, we infer that WψW(φψ)tW\psi^{\prime}\to W(\varphi\land\psi^{\prime})\in t, thus W(φψ)tW(\varphi\land\psi^{\prime})\in t. Now using tRcutR^{c}u and definition of RcR^{c}, we conclude that φu\varphi\in u, as desired.

We have thus solved an open problem raised in [14]. By Thm. 17 and Thm. 20, we have the following.

Theorem 21.

𝐊𝐃𝟒𝐖{\bf KD4^{W}} is sound and strongly complete with respect to the class of 𝒟4\mathcal{D}4-frames.

This also answers another open problem raised in [14, Sect. 5].

2.3.5 Euclidean Logic

Let 𝐊𝟓𝐖{\bf K5^{W}} denote the extension of 𝐊𝐖{\bf K^{W}} with the following axiom:

A5Wψ¬W(φψ)W((Wχ¬W(φχ))ψ)\begin{array}[]{ll}\text{A5}&W\psi\land\neg W(\varphi\land\psi)\to W((W\chi\to\neg W(\varphi\land\chi))\land\psi)\\ \end{array}

Again, the axiom A5 is obtained from the modal axiom 5 (i.e. ¬φ¬φ\neg\Box\varphi\to\Box\neg\Box\varphi) via a translation induced by Almost Definability Schema.

Wψ(¬φ(Wχ¬φ))(1)Wψ(¬W(φψ)W((Wχ¬φ)ψ)(2)Wψ(¬W(φψ)W((Wχ¬W(φχ))ψ))(3)Wψ¬W(φψ)W((Wχ¬W(φχ))ψ)(4)\begin{array}[]{llr}&W\psi\to(\neg\Box\varphi\to\Box(W\chi\to\neg\Box\varphi))&(1^{\prime})\\ \Longleftrightarrow&W\psi\to(\neg W(\varphi\land\psi)\to W((W\chi\to\neg\Box\varphi)\land\psi)&(2^{\prime})\\ \Longleftrightarrow&W\psi\to(\neg W(\varphi\land\psi)\to W((W\chi\to\neg W(\varphi\land\chi))\land\psi))&(3^{\prime})\\ \Longleftrightarrow&W\psi\land\neg W(\varphi\land\psi)\to W((W\chi\to\neg W(\varphi\land\chi))\land\psi)&(4^{\prime})\\ \end{array}

Here, we write Wψ(¬φ(Wχ¬φ))W\psi\to(\neg\Box\varphi\to\Box(W\chi\to\neg\Box\varphi)) instead of ¬φ¬φ\neg\Box\varphi\to\Box\neg\Box\varphi, since \Box is definable in terms of WW provided that WψW\psi for some ψ\psi. Again, every transformation is equivalent. The above transitions from (1)(1^{\prime}) to (2)(2^{\prime}) and from (2)(2^{\prime}) to (3)(3^{\prime}) follow from Prop. 4. Then by using axiom A0, we get the axiom (4)(4^{\prime}), that is, A5.

Different from our 𝐊𝟓𝐖{\bf K5^{W}}, the Euclidean system in [14], denoted 𝐒𝐖AQ{\bf S^{W}}\oplus\text{A}^{Q} there, is defined as the extension of 𝐒𝐖{\bf S^{W}} (that is, our 𝐊𝐖{\bf K^{W}}) with AQ\text{A}^{Q}, where AQ\text{A}^{Q} is WφW(¬Wψφ)W\varphi\to W(\neg W\psi\land\varphi). It is shown in [14, Thm. 4.15] that 𝐒𝐖AQ{\bf S^{W}}\oplus\text{A}^{Q} is sound and complete with respect to the class of Euclidean (and transitive) frames. In what follows, we show that AQ\text{A}^{Q} is provable in 𝐊𝟓𝐖{\bf K5^{W}}.

Proposition 22.

AQ\text{A}^{Q} is provable in 𝐊𝟓𝐖{\bf K5^{W}}.

Proof.

We have the following proof sequence in 𝐊𝟓𝐖{\bf K5^{W}}.

(1)Wψ¬W(¬Wψφ)W((Wψ¬W(¬Wψψ))φ)A5(2)ψ¬WψA1(3)(¬Wψψ)ψ(2),A0(4)W(¬Wψψ)Wψ(3),REW(5)(Wψ¬W(¬Wψψ))(Wψ¬Wψ)(4),A0(6)(Wψ¬W(¬Wψψ))¬Wψ(5),A0(7)((Wψ¬W(¬Wψψ))φ)(¬Wψφ)(6),A0(8)W((Wψ¬W(¬Wψψ))φ)W(¬Wψφ)(7),REW(9)Wψ¬W(¬Wψφ)W(¬Wψφ)(1),(8)(10)WψW(¬Wψφ)(9),A0\begin{array}[]{lll}(1)&W\psi\land\neg W(\neg W\psi\land\varphi)\to W((W\psi\to\neg W(\neg W\psi\land\psi))\land\varphi)&\text{A5}\\ (2)&\psi\to\neg W\psi&\text{A1}\\ (3)&(\neg W\psi\land\psi)\leftrightarrow\psi&(2),\text{A0}\\ (4)&W(\neg W\psi\land\psi)\leftrightarrow W\psi&(3),\text{REW}\\ (5)&(W\psi\to\neg W(\neg W\psi\land\psi))\leftrightarrow(W\psi\to\neg W\psi)&(4),\text{A0}\\ (6)&(W\psi\to\neg W(\neg W\psi\land\psi))\leftrightarrow\neg W\psi&(5),\text{A0}\\ (7)&((W\psi\to\neg W(\neg W\psi\land\psi))\land\varphi)\leftrightarrow(\neg W\psi\land\varphi)&(6),\text{A0}\\ (8)&W((W\psi\to\neg W(\neg W\psi\land\psi))\land\varphi)\leftrightarrow W(\neg W\psi\land\varphi)&(7),\text{REW}\\ (9)&W\psi\land\neg W(\neg W\psi\land\varphi)\to W(\neg W\psi\land\varphi)&(1),(8)\\ (10)&W\psi\to W(\neg W\psi\land\varphi)&(9),\text{A0}\\ \end{array}

Below, we will demonstrate that our axiom A5 is valid over the class of Euclidean frames.

Proposition 23.

A5 is valid on the class of Euclidean frames.

Proof.

Let =S,R,V\mathcal{M}=\langle S,R,V\rangle be an Euclidean model and sSs\in S.

Suppose, for reductio, that ,sWψ¬W(φψ)\mathcal{M},s\vDash W\psi\land\neg W(\varphi\land\psi) but ,sW((Wχ¬W(φχ))ψ)\mathcal{M},s\nvDash W((W\chi\to\neg W(\varphi\land\chi))\land\psi). Then ,sψ\mathcal{M},s\nvDash\psi, thus ,sφψ\mathcal{M},s\nvDash\varphi\land\psi and ,s(Wχ¬W(φχ))ψ\mathcal{M},s\nvDash(W\chi\to\neg W(\varphi\land\chi))\land\psi. It follows that there exists tt such that sRtsRt and ,tφψ\mathcal{M},t\nvDash\varphi\land\psi, and there exists uu such that sRusRu and ,u(Wχ¬W(φχ))ψ\mathcal{M},u\nvDash(W\chi\to\neg W(\varphi\land\chi))\land\psi. Using sWψs\vDash W\psi again, we derive that tψt\vDash\psi and uψu\vDash\psi, and then tφt\nvDash\varphi and uWχ¬W(φχ)u\nvDash W\chi\to\neg W(\varphi\land\chi), that is, uWχW(φχ)u\vDash W\chi\land W(\varphi\land\chi). By sRusRu and sRtsRt and the Euclideanness of RR, we have uRtuRt. Then it follows from uW(φχ)u\vDash W(\varphi\land\chi) that tφt\vDash\varphi, as desired. ∎

Proposition 24.

𝐊𝟓𝐖{\bf K5^{W}} is sound with respect to the class of Euclidean frames.

Now we demonstrate the completeness of 𝐊𝟓𝐖{\bf K5^{W}} over Euclidean frames. Our proof is different from that used in [14, Thm. 4.15]. The proof is nontrivial. This is because the canonical model is secondarily reflexive (defined later), not Euclidean. Thus we need to transform the secondarily reflexive model into an Euclidean model, and the truth values of (W)\mathcal{L}(W)-formulas have to be preserved during the transformation. This is our strategy. To begin with, we need a notion of secondary reflexivity.

We say that a model =S,R,V\mathcal{M}=\langle S,R,V\rangle is secondarily reflexive, if for all s,tSs,t\in S, sRtsRt implies tRttRt. We have the following general result, which will be used in the proof of the completeness of 𝐊𝟓𝐖{\bf K5^{W}} (Thm. 26).

Proposition 25.

For every secondarily reflexive model =S,R,V\mathcal{M}=\langle S,R,V\rangle, there exists an Euclidean model =S,R,V\mathcal{M}^{\prime}=\langle S,R^{\prime},V\rangle such that for all sSs\in S, for all φ(W)\varphi\in\mathcal{L}(W), ,sφ\mathcal{M},s\vDash\varphi iff ,sφ\mathcal{M}^{\prime},s\vDash\varphi.

Proof.

Let =S,R,V\mathcal{M}=\langle S,R,V\rangle be a secondarily reflexive model. Construct a model =S,R,V\mathcal{M}^{\prime}=\langle S,R^{\prime},V\rangle such that R=R{(y,z)xRyandxRz for some x,xS}R^{\prime}=R\cup\{(y,z)\mid xRy\leavevmode\nobreak\ \text{and}\leavevmode\nobreak\ x^{\prime}Rz\text{\leavevmode\nobreak\ for some\leavevmode\nobreak\ }x,x^{\prime}\in S\}.

First, \mathcal{M}^{\prime} is Euclidean. Let s,t,uSs,t,u\in S such that sRtsR^{\prime}t and sRusR^{\prime}u. The goal is to show tRutR^{\prime}u. By definition of RR^{\prime}, we consider the following cases.

  • sRtsRt and sRusRu. Then tRutR^{\prime}u.

  • sRt{\sim}sRt and sRusRu. Then xRsxRs and xRtx^{\prime}Rt for some x,xSx,x^{\prime}\in S. Then tRutR^{\prime}u.

  • sRtsRt and sRu{\sim}sRu. Similar to the second case, we can show that tRutR^{\prime}u.

  • sRt{\sim}sRt and sRu{\sim}sRu. Then xRsxRs and xRtx^{\prime}Rt for some x,xSx,x^{\prime}\in S, and yRsyRs and yRuy^{\prime}Ru for some y,ySy,y^{\prime}\in S. Then tRutR^{\prime}u.

It remains only to show that for all sSs\in S, for all φ(W)\varphi\in\mathcal{L}(W), we have

,sφ iff ,sφ.\mathcal{M},s\vDash\varphi\text{\leavevmode\nobreak\ iff\leavevmode\nobreak\ }\mathcal{M}^{\prime},s\vDash\varphi.

We proceed by induction on φ\varphi. The nontrivial case is WφW\varphi.

Suppose that ,sWφ\mathcal{M},s\nvDash W\varphi, to show that ,sWφ\mathcal{M}^{\prime},s\nvDash W\varphi. By supposition, either ,sφ\mathcal{M},s\vDash\varphi or for some tt such that sRtsRt we have ,tφ\mathcal{M},t\nvDash\varphi. By induction hypothesis and RRR\subseteq R^{\prime}, ,sφ\mathcal{M}^{\prime},s\vDash\varphi or for some tt such that sRtsR^{\prime}t and ,tφ\mathcal{M}^{\prime},t\nvDash\varphi. Thus ,sWφ\mathcal{M}^{\prime},s\nvDash W\varphi.

Conversely, assume that ,sWφ\mathcal{M}^{\prime},s\nvDash W\varphi, to prove that ,sWφ\mathcal{M},s\nvDash W\varphi. By assumption, either ,sφ\mathcal{M}^{\prime},s\vDash\varphi or for some tt such that sRtsR^{\prime}t we have ,tφ\mathcal{M}^{\prime},t\nvDash\varphi. If the first case holds, by induction hypothesis, we derive that ,sφ\mathcal{M},s\vDash\varphi, thus ,sWφ\mathcal{M},s\nvDash W\varphi. If the second case holds, according to the definition of RR^{\prime}, we consider the following two cases.

  • sRtsRt. By ,tφ\mathcal{M}^{\prime},t\nvDash\varphi and induction hypothesis, ,tφ\mathcal{M},t\nvDash\varphi. Thus ,sWφ\mathcal{M},s\nvDash W\varphi.

  • xRsxRs and xRtx^{\prime}Rt for some x,xSx,x^{\prime}\in S. Since xRsxRs and \mathcal{M} is secondarily reflexive, it follows that sRssRs. Then using Fact 5, we conclude that ,sWφ\mathcal{M},s\nvDash W\varphi.

The reader may ask if the above statement can be extended to the case of transitivity and serial. That is, do we have the following: Every (serial,) transitive and secondarily reflexive model is (W)\mathcal{L}(W)-equivalent to a (serial,) transitive and Euclidean model? We do not the answer. As we check, the construction \mathcal{M}^{\prime} in the proof of Prop. 25 does not preserve transitivity. We will come back to this issue.

Theorem 26.

𝐊𝟓𝐖{\bf K5^{W}} is sound and strongly complete with respect to the class of Euclidean frames.

Proof.

By Prop. 24, it suffices to show the completeness of 𝐊𝟓𝐖{\bf K5^{W}}. For this, define c\mathcal{M}^{c} w.r.t. 𝐊𝟓𝐖{\bf K5^{W}} as in Def. 14. Firstly, we show that c\mathcal{M}^{c} is secondarily reflexive, that is, the following holds:

(*) for all s,tScs,t\in S^{c}, if sRctsR^{c}t then tRcttR^{c}t.

Let s,tScs,t\in S^{c}. Suppose that sRctsR^{c}t, to show that tRcttR^{c}t. According to the definition of RcR^{c}, we consider the following cases.

  • There is no ψ\psi such that WψsW\psi\in s. Then s=ts=t. Thus tRcttR^{c}t.

  • There is no ψ\psi^{\prime} such that WψtW\psi^{\prime}\in t. Then as t=tt=t, we also have tTcttT^{c}t.

  • WψsW\psi\in s and WψtW\psi^{\prime}\in t for some ψ\psi and ψ\psi^{\prime}. If it fails that tRcttR^{c}t, according to the definition of RcR^{c}, it follows that for some φ\varphi, W(φψ)tW(\varphi\land\psi^{\prime})\in t and φt\varphi\notin t. As sRctsR^{c}t, we must have W(φψ)sW(\varphi\land\psi)\notin s, thus ¬W(φψ)s\neg W(\varphi\land\psi)\in s. Using axiom A5, we infer that W((Wψ¬W(φψ))ψ)sW((W\psi^{\prime}\to\neg W(\varphi\land\psi^{\prime}))\land\psi)\in s. Using sRctsR^{c}t again, we derive that Wψ¬W(φψ)tW\psi^{\prime}\to\neg W(\varphi\land\psi^{\prime})\in t, thus ¬W(φψ)t\neg W(\varphi\land\psi^{\prime})\in t, which is contrary to W(φψ)tW(\varphi\land\psi^{\prime})\in t and the consistency of tt.

We have thus shown (*). This implies that c\mathcal{M}^{c} is a secondarily reflexive model. That is to say, every consistent set is satisfiable in a secondarily reflexive model.

Now by Prop. 25, we obtain that every consistent set is satisfiable in an Euclidean model, as desired. ∎

It may be worth remarking that axiom A4 is provable in 𝐊𝟓𝐖{\bf K5^{W}}, because it is valid on the class of Euclidean frames.

Proposition 27.

A4 is valid on the class of Euclidean frames.

Proof.

Let =S,R,V\mathcal{M}=\langle S,R,V\rangle be an Euclidean model and sSs\in S. Suppose, for a contradiction, that ,sWψW(φψ)\mathcal{M},s\vDash W\psi\land W(\varphi\land\psi) and ,sW((WχW(φχ))ψ)\mathcal{M},s\nvDash W((W\chi\to W(\varphi\land\chi))\land\psi). Then ,sψ\mathcal{M},s\nvDash\psi, thus s(WχW(φχ))ψs\nvDash(W\chi\to W(\varphi\land\chi))\land\psi. It then follows that there exists tt such that sRtsRt and ,t(WχW(φχ))ψ\mathcal{M},t\nvDash(W\chi\to W(\varphi\land\chi))\land\psi. Moreover, as sWψs\vDash W\psi, tψt\vDash\psi, thus tWχW(φχ)t\nvDash W\chi\to W(\varphi\land\chi), and hence tWχt\vDash W\chi. However, since sRtsRt and RR is Euclidean, tRttRt. By Fact 5, we should have also tWχt\nvDash W\chi. A contradiction. ∎

So 𝐊𝟒𝐖𝐊𝟓𝐖{\bf K4^{W}}\subseteq{\bf K5^{W}}. Note that in the above proof, sW(φψ)s\vDash W(\varphi\land\psi) is not needed. This means that a stronger version of A4, that is, WψW((WχW(φχ))ψ)W\psi\to W((W\chi\to W(\varphi\land\chi))\land\psi) is valid over the class of Euclidean frames, thus provable in 𝐊𝟓𝐖{\bf K5^{W}}. In contrast, this formula is not valid over the class of transitive frames (as one may verify), thus not provable in 𝐊𝟒𝐖{\bf K4^{W}}. This establishes that 𝐊𝟒𝐖𝐊𝟓𝐖{\bf K4^{W}}\subset{\bf K5^{W}}.

Moreover, 𝐊𝟒𝟓𝐖=𝐊𝟓𝐖{\bf K45^{W}}={\bf K5^{W}}, where 𝐊𝟒𝟓𝐖{\bf K45^{W}} is the extension of 𝐊𝟓𝐖{\bf K5^{W}} with the axiom A4. As a consequence, we have another completeness result.

Theorem 28.

𝐊𝟒𝟓𝐖{\bf K45^{W}} is sound and strongly complete with respect to the class of Euclidean frames.

Theorem 29.

𝐊𝟓𝐖(=𝐊𝟒𝟓𝐖){\bf K5^{W}}(={\bf K45^{W}}) is sound and strongly complete with respect to the class of transitive and Euclidean frames.

Proof.

The soundness is direct from Thm. 26.

For the completeness, define c\mathcal{M}^{c} w.r.t. 𝐊𝟓𝐖{\bf K5^{W}} as in Def. 14. We have shown that c\mathcal{M}^{c} is transitive (Thm. 20) and secondarily reflexive (Thm. 26). This entails that every consistent set, say Γ\Gamma, is satisfiable in a transitive and secondarily reflexive model, say (,s)(\mathcal{M},s). Let =S,R,V\mathcal{M}^{\prime}=\langle S,R,V\rangle is the submodel of \mathcal{M} generated by ss. By the generated submodel theorem for standard modal logic ()\mathcal{L}(\Box), we have ,sΓ\mathcal{M}^{\prime},s\vDash\Gamma. Now construct a new model 𝒩=S,R,V\mathcal{N}=\langle S,R^{\prime},V\rangle such that R=R(Z(s)×Z(s))R^{\prime}=R\cup(Z(s)\times Z(s)), where Z(s)={xsRx}Z(s)=\{x\mid sRx\}. We can see that 𝒩\mathcal{N} is transitive and Euclidean.

It remains only to show that for all xSx\in S, for all φ(W)\varphi\in\mathcal{L}(W), ,xφ\mathcal{M}^{\prime},x\vDash\varphi iff 𝒩,xφ\mathcal{N},x\vDash\varphi. We proceed by induction on φ\varphi. The only nontrivial case is WφW\varphi.

Suppose that ,xWφ\mathcal{M}^{\prime},x\nvDash W\varphi. Then ,xφ\mathcal{M}^{\prime},x\vDash\varphi or for some yy such that xRyxRy and ,yφ\mathcal{M}^{\prime},y\nvDash\varphi. By induction hypothesis and RRR\subseteq R^{\prime}, 𝒩,xφ\mathcal{N},x\vDash\varphi or for some yy such that xRyxR^{\prime}y and ,yφ\mathcal{M}^{\prime},y\nvDash\varphi. Thus 𝒩,xWφ\mathcal{N},x\nvDash W\varphi.

Conversely, assume that 𝒩,xWφ\mathcal{N},x\nvDash W\varphi. Then 𝒩,xφ\mathcal{N},x\vDash\varphi or for some yy such that xTyxT^{\prime}y and 𝒩,yφ\mathcal{N},y\nvDash\varphi. If 𝒩,xφ\mathcal{N},x\vDash\varphi, by induction hypothesis, ,xφ\mathcal{M}^{\prime},x\vDash\varphi, thus ,xWφ\mathcal{M}^{\prime},x\nvDash W\varphi. If for some yy such that xRyxR^{\prime}y and 𝒩,yφ\mathcal{N},y\nvDash\varphi, according to the defintion of RR^{\prime}, we consider two cases.

  • xRyxRy. Then by induction hypothesis and 𝒩,yφ\mathcal{N},y\nvDash\varphi, we have ,yφ\mathcal{M}^{\prime},y\nvDash\varphi, and then ,xWφ\mathcal{M}^{\prime},x\nvDash W\varphi.

  • (x,y)Z(s)×Z(s)(x,y)\in Z(s)\times Z(s). Then xZ(s)x\in Z(s), that is, sRxsRx. Since RR is secondarily reflexive (note that the property of secondary reflexivity is preserved under generated submodels), it follows that xRxxRx. By Fact 5, ,xWφ\mathcal{M}^{\prime},x\nvDash W\varphi.

Since ,sΓ\mathcal{M}^{\prime},s\vDash\Gamma, we infer that 𝒩,sΓ\mathcal{N},s\vDash\Gamma. Thus Γ\Gamma is satisfiable in a transitive and Euclidean model, as desired. ∎

Similarly, we can show the following. Let 𝐊𝐃𝟓𝐖{\bf KD5^{W}} is the extension of 𝐊𝟓𝐖{\bf K5^{W}} with the axiom ¬W\neg W\bot.

Theorem 30.

𝐊𝐃𝟓𝐖=𝐊𝐃𝟒𝟓𝐖{\bf KD5^{W}}={\bf KD45^{W}} is sound and strongly complete with respect to the class of serial, transitive and Euclidean frames.

Going back to the discussion after Prop. 25, although the construction \mathcal{M}^{\prime} in the proof of Prop. 25 does not preserve transitivity, this property is indeed preserved under generated submodels and the construction of 𝒩\mathcal{N} in Thm. 29 and also Thm. 30.

In a similar vein, by translating axiom BB (viz. ¬φ¬φ\neg\varphi\to\Box\neg\Box\varphi) via the translation induced by Almost Definability Schema, we can obtain an axiom Wψ¬φW((Wχ¬W(φχ))ψ)W\psi\land\neg\varphi\to W((W\chi\to\neg W(\varphi\land\chi))\land\psi) of (W)\mathcal{L}(W) (denoted AB) over symmetric frames. One may verify that AB is valid over the class of symmetric frames.

3 Radical Ignorance

Definition 31 (Language).

The language of the logic of radical ignorance, denoted (IR)\mathcal{L}(I_{R}), is defined recursively as follows:

φ::=p¬φ(φφ)IRφ.\varphi::=p\mid\neg\varphi\mid(\varphi\land\varphi)\mid\textit{I}_{R}\varphi.

Intuitively, IRφ\textit{I}^{R}\varphi is read “one is Rumsfeld ignorant of φ\varphi”. Other connectives are defined as usual.

The notions of models and frames are defined as in Def. 2, and the semantics of (IR)\mathcal{L}(I_{R}) is defined as in Def. 3, except that

,sIRφiffeither (R(s)φ and ,sφ)or (R(s)¬φ and ,sφ).\begin{array}[]{lll}\mathcal{M},s\vDash\textit{I}_{R}\varphi&\text{iff}&\text{{\em either} }(R(s)\vDash\varphi\text{ and }\mathcal{M},s\nvDash\varphi)\\ &&\text{\em or }(R(s)\vDash\neg\varphi\text{ and }\mathcal{M},s\vDash\varphi).\\ \end{array}

Note that the semantics of IRφ\textit{I}_{R}\varphi is equivalent to the following one.

,sIRφiff(R(s)φ or ,sφ) and(R(s)¬φ or ,s¬φ)\begin{array}[]{lll}\mathcal{M},s\vDash\textit{I}_{R}\varphi&\text{iff}&(R(s)\vDash\varphi\text{ or }\mathcal{M},s\vDash\varphi)\text{ and}\\ &&(R(s)\vDash\neg\varphi\text{ or }\mathcal{M},s\vDash\neg\varphi)\\ \end{array}

We will use the two semantics of IR\textit{I}_{R} interchangeably.

Recall that the operator WW of false belief is interpreted as follows:

,sWφiffR(s)φ and ,sφ.\begin{array}[]{lll}\mathcal{M},s\vDash W\varphi&\text{iff}&R(s)\vDash\varphi\text{ and }\mathcal{M},s\nvDash\varphi.\\ \end{array}

One may check that the operators of radical ignorance and of false belief are interdefined with each other, as IRφ(WφW¬φ)\vDash I_{R}\varphi\leftrightarrow(W\varphi\vee W\neg\varphi) and Wφ(IRφ¬φ)\vDash W\varphi\leftrightarrow(I_{R}\varphi\land\neg\varphi). This may indicate that one can translate the results about false belief into those about radical ignorance via the translation induced by the interdefinability of the operators. Unfortunately, this holds for all but proof systems. Here we illustrate this with the axiomatizations of the logic of radical ignorance over all frames and over serial and transitive frames.

3.1 Minimal logic

The minimal logic of (IR)\mathcal{L}(I_{R}), denoted 𝐊𝐑𝐈{\bf K^{RI}}, consists of the following axioms and inference rules:

A0all instances of propositional tautologiesRI-EquIRφIR¬φRI-ConIRφ¬φIRψ¬ψIR(φψ)MPφ,φψψRI-RφψIRφ¬φIRψψ\begin{array}[]{ll}\text{A0}&\text{all instances of propositional tautologies}\\ \text{RI-Equ}&\textit{I}_{R}\varphi\leftrightarrow\textit{I}_{R}\neg\varphi\\ \text{RI-Con}&\textit{I}_{R}\varphi\land\neg\varphi\land\textit{I}_{R}\psi\land\neg\psi\to\textit{I}_{R}(\varphi\land\psi)\\ \text{MP}&\dfrac{\varphi,\varphi\to\psi}{\psi}\\ \text{RI-R}&\dfrac{\varphi\to\psi}{\textit{I}_{R}\varphi\land\neg\varphi\to\textit{I}_{R}\psi\vee\psi}\\ \end{array}

Note that the above axioms and inference rules can be obtained from those of 𝐊𝐖{\bf K^{W}} by a translation induced by the definability of WW in terms of IRI_{R}, that is Wφ(IRφ¬φ)\vDash W\varphi\leftrightarrow(I_{R}\varphi\land\neg\varphi), except for axiom RI-Equ. Actually, the translation only gives us an incomplete proof system, since the axiom RI-Equ is valid, but not provable in the translated system. To see this, consider an auxiliary semantics in which all formulas of the form IRφI_{R}\varphi are interpreted as φ\varphi. Under this semantics, the translated system are sound, but RI-Equ is not valid.

Proposition 32.

The following rule is admissible in 𝐊𝐑𝐈{\bf K^{RI}}:

φψIR(φχ)¬(φχ)IRψψ.\dfrac{\varphi\to\psi}{I_{R}(\varphi\land\chi)\land\neg(\varphi\land\chi)\to I_{R}\psi\vee\psi}.
Proof.

We have the following proof sequence in 𝐊𝐑𝐈{\bf K^{RI}}.

(1)φψpremise(2)IRφ¬φIRψψ(1),RI-R(3)IRφIRψψφ(2)(4)φχφA0(5)IR(φχ)¬(φχ)IRφφ(4),RI-R(6)IR(φχ)¬(φχ)IRψψφ(3),(5)(7)IR(φχ)¬(φχ)IRψψ(1),(6)\begin{array}[]{lll}(1)&\varphi\to\psi&\text{premise}\\ (2)&I_{R}\varphi\land\neg\varphi\to I_{R}\psi\vee\psi&(1),\text{RI-R}\\ (3)&I_{R}\varphi\to I_{R}\psi\vee\psi\vee\varphi&(2)\\ (4)&\varphi\land\chi\to\varphi&\text{A0}\\ (5)&I_{R}(\varphi\land\chi)\land\neg(\varphi\land\chi)\to I_{R}\varphi\vee\varphi&(4),\text{RI-R}\\ (6)&I_{R}(\varphi\land\chi)\land\neg(\varphi\land\chi)\to I_{R}\psi\vee\psi\vee\varphi&(3),(5)\\ (7)&I_{R}(\varphi\land\chi)\land\neg(\varphi\land\chi)\to I_{R}\psi\vee\psi&(1),(6)\\ \end{array}

We can generalize the above result to the following.

Proposition 33.

The following rule is admissible: for all nn\in\mathbb{N},

χ1χnφIR(χ1ψ)¬(χ1ψ)IR(χnψ)¬(χnψ)IRφφ.\dfrac{\chi_{1}\land\cdots\land\chi_{n}\to\varphi}{I_{R}(\chi_{1}\land\psi)\land\neg(\chi_{1}\land\psi)\land\cdots\land I_{R}(\chi_{n}\land\psi)\land\neg(\chi_{n}\land\psi)\to I_{R}\varphi\vee\varphi}.
Proof.

By induction on nn\in\mathbb{N}. The case n=0n=0 is obvious. The case n=1n=1 is shown as in Prop. 32.

Now suppose that the statement holds for the case n=mn=m (IH), to show it also holds for the case n=m+1n=m+1. For this, we have the following proof sequence:

(1)χ1χm+1φpremise(2)(χ1χ2)χm+1φ(1)(3)IR(χ1χ2ψ)¬(χ1χ2ψ)IR(χm+1ψ)¬(χm+1ψ)IRφφ(2),IH(4)IR(χ1ψ)¬(χ1ψ)IR(χ2ψ)¬(χ2ψ)IR(χ1χ2ψ)¬(χ1χ2ψ)RI-Con(5)IR(χ1ψ)¬(χ1ψ)IR(χm+1ψ)¬(χm+1ψ)IRφφ(3),(4)\begin{array}[]{lll}(1)&\chi_{1}\land\cdots\land\chi_{m+1}\to\varphi&\text{premise}\\ (2)&(\chi_{1}\land\chi_{2})\land\cdots\land\chi_{m+1}\to\varphi&(1)\\ (3)&I_{R}(\chi_{1}\land\chi_{2}\land\psi)\land\neg(\chi_{1}\land\chi_{2}\land\psi)\land\cdots\land&\\ &\leavevmode\nobreak\ \leavevmode\nobreak\ \leavevmode\nobreak\ \leavevmode\nobreak\ \leavevmode\nobreak\ \leavevmode\nobreak\ I_{R}(\chi_{m+1}\land\psi)\land\neg(\chi_{m+1}\land\psi)\to I_{R}\varphi\vee\varphi&(2),\text{IH}\\ (4)&I_{R}(\chi_{1}\land\psi)\land\neg(\chi_{1}\land\psi)\land I_{R}(\chi_{2}\land\psi)\land\neg(\chi_{2}\land\psi)\to&\\ &\leavevmode\nobreak\ \leavevmode\nobreak\ \leavevmode\nobreak\ \leavevmode\nobreak\ \leavevmode\nobreak\ \leavevmode\nobreak\ I_{R}(\chi_{1}\land\chi_{2}\land\psi)\land\neg(\chi_{1}\land\chi_{2}\land\psi)&\text{RI-Con}\\ (5)&I_{R}(\chi_{1}\land\psi)\land\neg(\chi_{1}\land\psi)\land\cdots\land I_{R}(\chi_{m+1}\land\psi)&\\ &\leavevmode\nobreak\ \leavevmode\nobreak\ \leavevmode\nobreak\ \leavevmode\nobreak\ \leavevmode\nobreak\ \leavevmode\nobreak\ \land\neg(\chi_{m+1}\land\psi)\to I_{R}\varphi\vee\varphi&(3),(4)\\ \end{array}

By Def. 14 and the definability of WW in terms of IRI_{R}, we obtain the canonical model for 𝐊𝐑𝐈{\bf K^{RI}} as follows.

Definition 34.

The canonical model for 𝐊𝐑𝐈{\bf K^{RI}} is c=Sc,Rc,Vc\mathcal{M}^{c}=\langle S^{c},R^{c},V^{c}\rangle, where

  • Sc={ss is a maximal consistent set for }S^{c}=\{s\mid s\text{ is a maximal consistent set for }\}

  • if IRψ¬ψsI_{R}\psi\land\neg\psi\in s for no ψ\psi, then sRctsR^{c}t iff s=ts=t, and
    if IRψ¬ψsI_{R}\psi\land\neg\psi\in s for some ψ\psi, then sRctsR^{c}t iff for all φ\varphi, if IR(φψ)¬(φψ)sI_{R}(\varphi\land\psi)\land\neg(\varphi\land\psi)\in s, then φt\varphi\in t.

  • Vc(p)={sScps}V^{c}(p)=\{s\in S^{c}\mid p\in s\}.

Lemma 35.

For all φ(IR)\varphi\in\mathcal{L}(I_{R}), for all sScs\in S^{c}, we have

c,sφ iff φs.\mathcal{M}^{c},s\vDash\varphi\text{\leavevmode\nobreak\ iff\leavevmode\nobreak\ }\varphi\in s.
Proof.

By induction on φ(IR)\varphi\in\mathcal{L}(I_{R}). The nontrivial case is IRφI_{R}\varphi.

Suppose that IRφsI_{R}\varphi\in s (thus IR¬φsI_{R}\neg\varphi\in s), to show that c,sIRφ\mathcal{M}^{c},s\vDash I_{R}\varphi. By induction hypothesis, we show that

  • (*)

    if φs\varphi\notin s, then for all xScx\in S^{c} such that sRcxsR^{c}x, we have φx\varphi\in x, and if φs\varphi\in s, then for all yScy\in S^{c} such that sRcysR^{c}y, we have φy\varphi\notin y.

Firstly, we assume that φs\varphi\notin s, then ¬φs\neg\varphi\in s. By supposition, IRφ¬φsI_{R}\varphi\land\neg\varphi\in s. Let xScx\in S^{c} such that sRcxsR^{c}x. Then according to the definition of RcR^{c}, we have: for all χ\chi, if IR(χφ)¬(χφ)sI_{R}(\chi\land\varphi)\land\neg(\chi\land\varphi)\in s, then χx\chi\in x. By letting χ\chi be φ\varphi, we can show that φx\varphi\in x. A similar argument applies to the second conjunct of (*).

Conversely, suppose that IRφsI_{R}\varphi\notin s (thus IR¬φsI_{R}\neg\varphi\notin s), to prove that c,sIRφ\mathcal{M}^{c},s\nvDash\textit{I}_{R}\varphi. By induction hypothesis, it suffices to show the following fails:

  • (a)

    either φs\varphi\notin s and for all xScx\in S^{c} such that sRcxsR^{c}x, we have φx\varphi\in x, or φs\varphi\in s and for all yScy\in S^{c} such that sRcysR^{c}y, we have φy\varphi\notin y.

This amounts to showing the following (a1) and (a2) hold.

  • (a1)

    if φs\varphi\notin s, then for some xScx\in S^{c} such that sRcxsR^{c}x, we have φx\varphi\notin x, and

  • (a2)

    if φs\varphi\in s, then for some yScy\in S^{c} such that sRcysR^{c}y, we have φy\varphi\in y.

For (a1), assume that φs\varphi\notin s. If IRψ¬ψsI_{R}\psi\land\neg\psi\in s for no ψ\psi, then according to the definition of RcR^{c}, we have sRcssR^{c}s. In this case, ss is a desired xx. If IRψ¬ψsI_{R}\psi\land\neg\psi\in s for some ψ\psi, by definition of RcR^{c} and Lindenbaum’s Lemma, it remains only to show that the set {χIR(χψ)¬(χψ)s}{¬φ}\{\chi\mid I_{R}(\chi\land\psi)\land\neg(\chi\land\psi)\in s\}\cup\{\neg\varphi\} (denoted Γ\Gamma) is consistent.

If Γ\Gamma is not consistent, then there exist χ1,,χn\chi_{1},\ldots,\chi_{n} such that IR(χiψ)¬(χiψ)sI_{R}(\chi_{i}\land\psi)\land\neg(\chi_{i}\land\psi)\in s for i=1,,ni=1,\ldots,n and

χ1χnφ.\vdash\chi_{1}\land\cdots\land\chi_{n}\to\varphi.

By Prop. 33, we infer that

IR(χ1ψ)¬(χ1ψ)IR(χnψ)¬(χnψ)IRφφ.\vdash I_{R}(\chi_{1}\land\psi)\land\neg(\chi_{1}\land\psi)\land\cdots\land I_{R}(\chi_{n}\land\psi)\land\neg(\chi_{n}\land\psi)\to I_{R}\varphi\vee\varphi.

As IR(χiψ)¬(χiψ)sI_{R}(\chi_{i}\land\psi)\land\neg(\chi_{i}\land\psi)\in s for i=1,,ni=1,\ldots,n, we derive that IRφφsI_{R}\varphi\vee\varphi\in s, which contradicts the supposition and the assumption. Thus we complete the proof of (a1).

Similarly, we can prove (a2), by using IR¬φsI_{R}\neg\varphi\notin s and ¬φs\neg\varphi\notin s instead. ∎

Theorem 36.

𝐊𝐑𝐈{\bf K^{RI}} is sound and strongly complete with respect to the class of all frames.

3.2 Serial and transitive logic

In this section, we consider the extension of 𝐊𝐑𝐈{\bf K^{RI}} over serial and transitive frames. This is in line with the frames that the framework of [9] is actually based on, where the doxastic accessibility relation is serial and transitive, see Fn. 2 for the remark.

Define 𝐊𝐃𝟒𝐑𝐈{\bf KD4^{RI}} to be the extension of 𝐊𝐑𝐈{\bf K^{RI}} with the axiom RI-D (¬IR\neg I^{R}\bot) and the following axiom (denoted RI-4):

IRψ¬ψIR(φψ)¬(φψ)IR((IRχ¬χIR(φχ)¬(φχ))ψ)¬((IRχ¬χIR(φχ)¬(φχ))ψ)\begin{array}[]{l}I_{R}\psi\land\neg\psi\land I_{R}(\varphi\land\psi)\land\neg(\varphi\land\psi)\to I_{R}((I_{R}\chi\land\neg\chi\to I_{R}(\varphi\land\chi)\\ \leavevmode\nobreak\ \leavevmode\nobreak\ \leavevmode\nobreak\ \leavevmode\nobreak\ \leavevmode\nobreak\ \leavevmode\nobreak\ \land\neg(\varphi\land\chi))\land\psi)\land\neg((I_{R}\chi\land\neg\chi\to I_{R}(\varphi\land\chi)\land\neg(\varphi\land\chi))\land\psi)\\ \end{array}

Again, the above axioms RI-D and RI-4 are obtained from, respectively, axioms AD and A4 via a translation induced by the interdefinability of WW in terms of IRI_{R}.

Theorem 37.

𝐊𝐃𝟒𝐑𝐈{\bf KD4^{RI}} is sound and strongly complete with respect to the class of serial and transitive frames.

Proof.

For soundness, by Thm. 36, it suffices to show the validity of axioms RI-D and RI-4 over serial and transitive frames. This follows directly from the validity of AD and A4 over the frames under discussion (Thm. 17 and Prop. 19) with the definability of WW in terms of IRI_{R}.

For completeness, define c\mathcal{M}^{c} w.r.t. 𝐊𝐃𝟒𝐑𝐈{\bf KD4^{RI}} as in Def. 34. By Thm. 36, it remains only to show that RcR^{c} is serial and transitive.

For seriality, suppose that sScs\in S^{c}. If IRψ¬ψsI_{R}\psi\land\neg\psi\in s for no ψ\psi, then according to the definition of RcR^{c}, we derive that sRcssR^{c}s. If IRψ¬ψsI_{R}\psi\land\neg\psi\in s for some ψ\psi, by definition of RcR^{c} and Lindenbaum’s Lemma, it suffices to prove that {χIR(χψ)¬(χψ)s}\{\chi\mid I_{R}(\chi\land\psi)\land\neg(\chi\land\psi)\in s\} is consistent.

Since IRψ¬ψsI_{R}\psi\land\neg\psi\in s, the set {χIR(χψ)¬(χψ)s}\{\chi\mid I_{R}(\chi\land\psi)\land\neg(\chi\land\psi)\in s\} is nonempty. If the set is not consistent, then there are χ1,,χn\chi_{1},\ldots,\chi_{n} such that IR(χiψ)¬(χiψ)sI_{R}(\chi_{i}\land\psi)\land\neg(\chi_{i}\land\psi)\in s for i=1,,ni=1,\ldots,n and

χ1χn.\vdash\chi_{1}\land\cdots\land\chi_{n}\to\bot.

By Prop. 33,

IR(χ1ψ)¬(χ1ψ)IR(χnψ)¬(χnψ)IR.\vdash I_{R}(\chi_{1}\land\psi)\land\neg(\chi_{1}\land\psi)\land\cdots\land I_{R}(\chi_{n}\land\psi)\land\neg(\chi_{n}\land\psi)\to I_{R}\bot\vee\bot.

As IR(χiψ)¬(χiψ)sI_{R}(\chi_{i}\land\psi)\land\neg(\chi_{i}\land\psi)\in s for i=1,,ni=1,\ldots,n, we conclude that IRsI_{R}\bot\vee\bot\in s. As s\bot\notin s, IRsI_{R}\bot\in s. However, by axiom RI-D, ¬IRs\neg I_{R}\bot\in s. This contradicts the consistency of ss.

For transitivity, let s,t,uScs,t,u\in S^{c}. Assume that sRctsR^{c}t and tRcutR^{c}u, to show that sRcusR^{c}u. We consider the following three cases.

  • IRψ¬ψsI_{R}\psi\land\neg\psi\in s for no ψ\psi. In this case, by definition of RcR^{c} and sRctsR^{c}t, it follows that s=ts=t, thus sRcusR^{c}u by assumption that tRcutR^{c}u.

  • IRψ¬ψtI_{R}\psi\land\neg\psi\in t for no ψ\psi. In this case, by definition of RcR^{c} and tRcutR^{c}u, it follows that t=ut=u, thus sRcusR^{c}u by assumption that sRctsR^{c}t.

  • IRψ¬ψsI_{R}\psi\land\neg\psi\in s for some ψ\psi, and IRψ¬ψtI_{R}\psi^{\prime}\land\neg\psi^{\prime}\in t for some ψ\psi^{\prime}. In this case, suppose that for any φ\varphi we have IR(φψ)¬(φψ)sI_{R}(\varphi\land\psi)\land\neg(\varphi\land\psi)\in s, we need to show that φu\varphi\in u. Since IRψ¬ψsI_{R}\psi\land\neg\psi\in s, by supposition and axiom RI-4, we derive that IR((IRψ¬ψIR(φψ)¬(φψ))ψ)¬((IRψ¬ψIR(φψ)¬(φψ))ψ)sI_{R}((I_{R}\psi^{\prime}\land\neg\psi^{\prime}\to I_{R}(\varphi\land\psi^{\prime})\land\neg(\varphi\land\psi^{\prime}))\land\psi)\land\neg((I_{R}\psi^{\prime}\land\neg\psi^{\prime}\to I_{R}(\varphi\land\psi^{\prime})\land\neg(\varphi\land\psi^{\prime}))\land\psi)\in s. As sRctsR^{c}t, it follows that IRψ¬ψIR(φψ)¬(φψ)tI_{R}\psi^{\prime}\land\neg\psi^{\prime}\to I_{R}(\varphi\land\psi^{\prime})\land\neg(\varphi\land\psi^{\prime})\in t, thus IR(φψ)¬(φψ)tI_{R}(\varphi\land\psi^{\prime})\land\neg(\varphi\land\psi^{\prime})\in t. As tRcutR^{c}u, we conclude that φu\varphi\in u, as desired.

Remark 38.

In the introduction, we note that the canonical model in [4] does not apply to the transitive logic of reliable belief, thus not apply to the transitive logic of radical ignorance. Recall from [4, Def. 6.3] that the canonical model for the logic of reliable belief is defined such that sRctsR^{c}t iff for all φ\varphi, ¬φ¬φs\neg\mathcal{R}\varphi\land\neg\varphi\in s implies φt\varphi\in t. As observed in the introduction, IRI_{R} is equivalent to the negation of \mathcal{R}. Accordingly, in the case of radical ignorance, sRctsR^{c}t iff for all φ\varphi, IRφ¬φsI_{R}\varphi\land\neg\varphi\in s implies φt\varphi\in t. As the reader check, RcR^{c} is not transitive. In contrast, our RcR^{c} in Def. 34 is indeed transitive, as shown in Thm. 37.

4 Conclusion and Discussions

In this paper, we investigated the logics of false belief and radical ignorance. We proposed an almost definability schema, called ‘Almost Definability Schema’, which guides us to find the desired core axioms for the transitive logic and the Euclidean logic of false belief, and (with other considerations) also inspires us to propose a suitable canonical relation in the construction of the canonical model for the minimal logic of false belief. The canonical relation can uniformly handle the completeness proof of various logics of false belief, including the transitive logic, thereby solving an open problem in [14]. We explored the expressivity and frame definability of the logic of false belief. Moreover, due to the interdefinability of the operators of radical ignorance and false belief, we also axiomatized the logic of radical ignorance over the class of all frames and the class of serial and transitive frames. When translating the minimal logic of false belief to that of radical ignorance, we need to be cautious, since the translation only gives us an incomplete proof system, and one special axiom needed to be considered as well.

The almost definability schema is an important and useful tool in finding the suitable canoical relation and the desired core axioms for the special systems. Such usage has been made in the literature, see [7, 8, 2, 3]. This seems to be incomparable with other methods. We can try to extend such almost definability schema to other logics.

Coming back to the logics involved in this paper, one can explore the bisimulation notion for the logics of false belief and radical ignorance. Note that the almost definability schema is not enough for the notion of the bisimulation here, as in the case of the canonical relation. More things are needed to be taken account of. This is unlike the bisimulation of the contingency logic in the literature [7].

Another future work is to axiomatize the logic of false belief over symmetric frames. As remarked before Sec. 3, Almost Definability Schema also guides us to find an axiom AB, that is, Wψ¬φW((Wχ¬W(φχ))ψ)W\psi\land\neg\varphi\to W((W\chi\to\neg W(\varphi\land\chi))\land\psi) of (W)\mathcal{L}(W), which is valid over the class of symmetric frames. If we define the canonical model c\mathcal{M}^{c} for the system 𝐁𝐖{\bf B^{W}} (that is, the extension of 𝐊𝐖{\bf K^{W}} with the axiom AB) as in Def. 14, we can show that c\mathcal{M}^{c} is almost symmetric: let s,tScs,t\in S^{c}, if sRctsR^{c}t and WψtW\psi\in t for some ψ\psi, then tRcstR^{c}s. However, c\mathcal{M}^{c} is not symmetric, since if WψtW\psi\in t for no ψ\psi and tst\neq s, then according to the definition of RcR^{c}, tRcs{\sim}tR^{c}s, even if sRctsR^{c}t. Therefore, in order to axiomatize the symmetric logic of false belief, more work needs to be done.

References

  • [1] Sophie-Grace Chappell. Plato on Knowledge in the Theaetetus. In Edward N. Zalta, editor, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, Winter 2019 edition, 2019.
  • [2] J. Fan. Bimodal logics with contingency and accident. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 48:425–445, 2019.
  • [3] J. Fan. A logic for disjunctive ignorance. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 50(6):1293–1312, 2021.
  • [4] J. Fan. Logics of (in)sane and (un)reliable beliefs. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 30(1):78–100, 2022.
  • [5] J. Fan. Unknown truths and false beliefs: Completeness and expressivity results for the neighborhood semantics. Studia Logica, 110:1–45, 2022.
  • [6] J. Fan. Some notes on dyadic contingency. Journal of Logic, Language and Information, 32(2):209–217, 2023.
  • [7] J. Fan, Y. Wang, and H. van Ditmarsch. Almost necessary. In Advances in Modal Logic, volume 10, pages 178–196, 2014.
  • [8] J. Fan, Y. Wang, and H. van Ditmarsch. Contingency and knowing whether. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 8(1):75–107, 2015.
  • [9] V. Fano and P. Graziani. A working hypothesis for the logic of radical ignorance. Synthese, pages 1–16, 2020.
  • [10] D. Gilbert and G. Venturi. Neighborhood semantics for logics of unknown truths and false beliefs. The Australasian Journal of Logic, 14(1):246–267, 2017.
  • [11] E. and Petrolo M. and Venturi G. Gilbert, D. and Kubyshkina. Logics of ignorance and being wrong. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 30(5):870–885, 2022.
  • [12] K. H. Onishi and R. Baillargeon. Do 15-month-old infants understand false beliefs? Science, 308(5719):255–258, 2005.
  • [13] T. Pan and C. Yang. A logic for weak essence and strong accident. Logique et Analyse, 238:179–190, 2017.
  • [14] C. Steinsvold. Being wrong: Logics for false belief. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 52(3):245–253, 2011.
  • [15] T. Witczak. A note on the intuitionistic logic of false belief. Bulletin of the Section of Logic, 51(1):57–71, 2022.