Initial Tukey Structure Below A Stable Ordered-Union Ultrafilter
Tan Özalp
Department of Mathematics, University of Notre Dame, Notre Dame, IN 46556, USA
[email protected]
Abstract.
Answering a question of Dobrinen and Todorcevic asked in [DT11], we prove that below any stable ordered-union ultrafilter , there are exactly four nonprincipal Tukey classes: , and . This parallels the classification of ultrafilters Rudin-Keisler below by Blass in [Bla87]. A key step in the proof involves modifying the proof of a canonization theorem of Klein and Spinas [KS05] for Borel functions on to obtain a simplified canonization theorem for fronts on , recovering Lefmann’s ([Lef96]) canonization for fronts of finite uniformity rank as a special case. We use this to classify the Rudin-Keisler classes of all ultrafilters Tukey below , which is then applied to achieve the main result.
Tukey introduced the notion of Tukey ordering to study the theory of convergence in topology [Tuk40]. The study of the Tukey ordering of a particular class of partial orders, namely that of the class of ultrafilters, started with Isbell’s [Isb65] and independently Juhász’s [Juh67] constructions of ultrafilters with maximum Tukey degree. This study was revived with Milovich [Mil08], and continued with a detailed investigation by Dobrinen and Todorcevic in [DT11]. Further major developments include [RT12], [DT14], [DT15], [BDR15], [Dob16a], [Dob16b], [DMT17], [RS17], [KR18] [RV19], [Dob20], [BD23], [Ben23], [BD], [BW24], and the survey papers [Dob15], [Dob21], and [KR24].
Two types of the important questions asked about the structure of the Tukey types of ultrafilters are the following: Which partial orders can be embedded into the Tukey ordering of the ultrafilters? Given an ultrafilter , what is the structure of the Tukey/Rudin-Keisler types of ultrafilters below ? In Section of [DT11], Dobrinen and Todorcevic obtained partial results on the initial Tukey structure below a stable ordered-union ultrafilter, but left the question of exact classification open. We shall answer this question in this paper.
In order to discuss our results, we now provide some definitions. Ultrafilters considered throughout the paper are assumed to be on countable base sets. For ultrafilters and , we say is Tukey reducible to (or is Tukey below ), and write , if there is a map which sends every filter base for to a filter base for . We say that and are Tukey equivalent, and write , if both and . We call the collection of ultrafilters Tukey equivalent to the Tukey type of , and denote it by . We call the collection of Tukey types Tukey below the initial Tukey structure below .
The first initial Tukey structure result was Todorcevic’s 111It is explained in the introduction of [RT12] that the result is due to Todorcevic. proof of the Tukey minimality of Ramsey ultrafilters in [RT12], which mirrors the result of Blass that Ramsey ultrafilters are Rudin-Keisler minimal ([Bla73]). Later, the initial Tukey structures below ultrafilters forced by to Laflamme’s partial orders ([Laf89]), and the isomorphism classes inside these Tukey classes were classified in [DT14] and [DT15], analogously to Laflamme’s results for the Rudin-Keisler order. Further work includes the classification of the initial Tukey structure and the isomorphism classes inside the Tukey classes below ultrafilters forced by for all in [Dob16a], and below ultrafilters associated to topological Ramsey spaces constructed from Fraïssé classes in [DMT17]. See the survey [Dob21] for the full results.
We let denote the set of all finite nonempty subsets of and define the maps , , , and by , , , , and for all . The object of our study is an ultrafilter on the base set satisfying a certain partition property, called a stable ordered-union ultrafilter (see Definition2.13). Letting denote a principal ultrafilter and writing , and for the -images of under the respective maps (see Definition2.2), we have .
We fix an arbitrary stable ordered-union ultrafilter on the base set . Denote the Rudin-Keisler equivalence of ultrafilters by (Definition2.2), and let us note that Rudin-Keisler reduction implies Tukey reduction. Recall the following theorem of Blass:
Let be a nonprincipal ultrafilter on such that . Then is Rudin-Keisler equivalent to exactly one of or . Moreover, and are -incomparable. This results in the following picture, where the arrows represent strict Rudin-Keisler reducibility:
Figure 1. Rudin-Keisler classes below .
As for the Tukey order, Corollary and the subsequent remark in [DT11] showed that and are Tukey-incomparable. Theorem of the same paper included the construction of a particular stable ordered-union such that , assuming . This results in a similar picture to Figure1 with respect to the Tukey order, but the exact Tukey structure below was not classified, even under .
1.2 and 1.4 below are Question and Question in [DT11]. 1.3 is motivated by prior work on initial Tukey structures:
Question 1.2.
What ultrafilters are Tukey reducible to ?
Question 1.3.
What are the isomorphism types of ultrafilters Tukey reducible to ?
Question 1.4.
If is any stable ordered-union, does it follow that ?
Let be an arbitrary stable ordered-union ultrafilter. We answer 1.2 in Theorem5.12 by proving that every nonprincipal ultrafilter is Tukey equivalent to exactly one of or , and so the Tukey structure below is exactly like the Rudin-Keisler structure illustrated in Figure1 (the exactness part of the statement is proved in Theorem3.6, which answers 1.4). 1.3 is answered in Theorem5.4, which proves that every nonprincipal ultrafilter Tukey below is isomorphic to a countable Fubini iterate of ultrafilters from the set (see Definition2.15).
Let be a Ramsey ultrafilter on and assume that is nonprincipal with . Then is a countable Fubini iterate of , and in particular .
The proof of this theorem included Pudlák and Rödl’s canonization theorem ([PR82]) as a key step. In [DT14] and [DT15], new topological Ramsey spaces dense in Laflamme’s forcings were constructed, and new canonization results for equivalence relations (equivalently, functions) on the fronts on these spaces were proved to be employed in the classifications of the initial Tukey structures. Ramsey-classification results, i.e., canonization theorems for fronts on the newly constructed topological Ramsey spaces, were proved and used as a key step of the classifications of the initial Tukey structures in [Dob16a], [Dob16b], and [DMT17], as well.
In this paper, we will work with Milliken’s ([Mil75]) topological Ramsey space (see Definition2.5), and adapt the main result of [KS05] to prove a simplified canonization result for equivalence relations on fronts on . This will yield Lefmann’s canonization in [Lef96] as a special case. The canonization theorem will then be used in the proof of the main result.
Section2 provides the notation and states some well-known facts that will be used throughout the paper. Section3 states more facts related to . In that section, we prove that is rapid and , in . This answers 1.4, which was asked in [DT11], and was restated in [KR24]. In Section4, we modify the main theorem of [KS05] to prove a canonization theorem that will better serve our purposes. Finally, Section5 includes the main results, Theorem5.4 and Theorem5.12.
Acknowledgments
I am profoundly grateful to my advisor Natasha Dobrinen for introducing me to this problem, for her constant support and guidance, and for her invaluable feedback throughout the writing process. I would also like to thank Burak Kaya for his influence on my education and for his helpful comments.
2. Notation and Background
Whenever is a function and , we will use and interchangeably to mean the image of under . Let us define the following well-known notions:
Definition 2.1.
Let and be ultrafilters on countable base sets and , respectively.
(i)
is a filter base for (or a cofinal subset of) if for every , there is such that .
(ii)
is monotone if for all .
(iii)
is cofinal if for every base , is a base for .
Note that if is a monotone map, then is cofinal if and only if is a filter base for .
Let be a countable base set. Let be a set of infinite subsets of . We define .
Let us also define the appropriate notion of isomorphism between ultrafilters:
Definition 2.2.
Let and be ultrafilters on countable base sets and , respectively. Let be a map. Then is an ultrafilter on called the -image of under . We say is Rudin-Keislerreducible to (or is Rudin-Keislerbelow ) and write , if there is a map such that . We say that and are isomorphic or Rudin-Keisler equivalent and write , if there are maps and such that and . Equivalently, if there is a bijection (equivalently, an injection) such that . More information on the Rudin-Keisler order on ultrafilters can be found in [Bla10] and [Hal17].
It follows from the definitions that . The following fact can be found in [DT11]:
Fact 2.3.
For ultrafilters and , if , then there exists a monotone cofinal map .
For an ultrafilter on the base set and , let denote ; note that is an ultrafilter on the base set . Consider given by for all . Then is injective and for all , we get . Hence,
Fact 2.4.
For any , .
Definition 2.5.
By a block sequence, we mean a sequence such that for all . will mean initial segment and will mean proper initial segment. We assume that the empty sequence is an initial segment of every sequence. Let denote the set of all finite block sequences of length , and let denote the set of all infinite block sequences. For , we denote , including the empty sequence. Finally, when we refer to a topology on , we refer to the topology arising from the metric for , where is the least with .
Definition 2.6.
Throughout the paper capital letters , and denote elements of ; small letters and denote elements of ; and denote elements of .
(i)
if and only if . Similarly, if and only if and if and only if , whenever . and are defined similarly.
(ii)
Assume that . denotes the block sequence . is defined similarly.
(iii)
and . Whenever we write expressions of the kind “”, is implicitly assumed to be an infinite block sequence.
(iv)
if and only if for all , . and are defined similarly. denotes the set of infinite block sequences with . For , denotes the set of block sequences with , and .
(v)
Let . , where is the least index with . We will also write to mean for , and to mean for .
(vi)
if and only if there is with .
For and , let . is defined to be the empty sequence. Recall the famous theorem of Hindman:
Let . For every coloring , there is some such that is constant.
It was first proved by Milliken in [Mil75] that is a topological Ramsey space. The following is a straightforward corollary of Theorem2.7, proved in [Tay76]:
A set is called small if it does not contain for any . Let , let be a family, and let . is -uniform on if one of the following holds:
(i)
and ,
(ii)
and for all , is -uniform on .
(iii)
is a limit ordinal and for all , is -uniform for some , and for each is small.
We call a uniform family on if it is -uniform for some .
Note that for every , every uniform family on is a front. Also, it follows by induction on that if is -uniform on and , then is also -uniform on . In this case, we will call the uniformity rank of . Observe that fronts of finite uniformity rank have the form for , and .
For , we define iff . Then well-orders with order-type . For , we let iff or , where is minimal with . If is a front on some , then well-orders , and the following can be proved by induction on the order-type of with respect to this ordering:
Let be a front on . Then there is such that is an -uniform front on , for some .
The defining property of the ultrafilters we are interested in is that they give witnesses to Lemma2.8. These ultrafilters are called stable ordered-union ultrafilters, which were studied in detail by Blass and Hindman in [Bla87] and [BH87].
Definition 2.13.
Let be a an ultrafilter on the base set . is called ordered-union, if there is a filter basis for such that every member of is of the form for some .
is called stable ordered-union, if it is ordered-union and for every with and for all , there is such that for all .
Let be an ordered-union ultrafilter on . The following are equivalent:
(i)
is a stable ordered-union ultrafilter.
(ii)
For all and for all , there is such that is constant on (Ramsey property).
(iii)
If is metrically analytic, then there is such that or (-dimensional Ramsey property) .
(iv)
If for all , then there is such that for all (selectivity).
(v)
For every Nash-Williams family and every , there is such that or (Nash-Williams property).
(vi)
For every function , there is and such that; if and only if , for all (canonical partition property).
Lastly, we define the Fubini limit of ultrafilters:
Definition 2.15.
Let be an ultrafilter on and let be ultrafilters on for all . We define the following ultrafilter on :
If all of the ’s are the same ultrafilter , we denote . Finally, we will write instead of .
To finish this section, let us remark that one can construct a stable ordered-union ultrafilter under (or just ) inductively, using Theorem2.7. Another approach to construct is the following: Take a generic filter for the poset and let . However, the existence of a stable ordered-union is unprovable in , since it implies the existence of selective ultrafilters (see Theorem3.3), and there are models of without selective ultrafilters ([Kun76], [Wim82], [She98]). Finally, we mention that Raghavan and Steprāns recently solved a longstanding open problem, asked in [Bla87], by constructing a model of with at least two non-isomorphic selective ultrafilters, but without any stable ordered-union ultrafilters [RS23].
3. Properties of
In this section, we recall some facts about and answer a question asked in [DT11] by proving that (Theorem3.6). Let us recall the following types of ultrafilters on :
Definition 3.1.
Let be an ultrafilter on .
(i)
is a p-point if for every , there is some such that for all .
(ii)
is a q-point if for each partition of into finite pieces , there is such that for all .
(iii)
is Ramsey if for every and every , there is such that is constant.
(iv)
is rapid if for all , there exists such that for every .
In Theorem of [Mil80], Miller proved the following alternate characterization of rapid ultrafilters:
Definition 3.2.
Let be a nonprincipal ultrafilter on the countable base set . is called rapid if one of the following equivalent conditions holds:
(i)
Given finite subsets , there is with for each .
(ii)
There is such that given finite subsets , there is with for each .
Now let be a stable ordered-union ultrafilter. Denote the -images by , , and , which are ultrafilters on , and , respectively. By definition, ; hence also . In the following theorem (i)-(ii) are well-known. We prove (v) because it seems to be missing from the previous literature.
To finish this section, we show that . Following the notation in [Dob20], for a subset , we let . For and , we let . Since and and are p-points, Theorem of [Dob20] applied to and in our notation yields:
Lemma 3.5.
Let be an ultrafilter on the base set and let be a monotone cofinal map. Then there is , an increasing sequence , and a map such that for all with , we have , where for each .
In this case, we say that the finitary map generates on . Recall that . We now answer Question of [DT11] using this lemma:
Theorem 3.6.
.
Proof.
Assume towards a contradiction that . Then there is a monotone cofinal . By Lemma3.5, we may take the corresponding and the finitary map which generates on . Note that generates a map, say , on the set by , where for each , and agrees with on .
Let us note that is a closed subset of . Moreover, for fixed and , is closed. We conclude that is also a closed subset of .
Now define , , and . By the previous paragraph, we see that is closed, is analytic, and is closed.
We let . It follows that is analytic, so Theorem2.14 part (iii) is applicable to . Hence, there is such that or . Applying the argument from the proof of Theorem in [DT11] that was used to construct a stable ordered-union with , we will show that the latter case is not possible.
Assume towards a contradiction that . If there is no , then we can use Theorem2.14 part (ii) to find with . Hence we would have , which contradicts .
Now we can assume that there is some . If there is such that for all , we have , then , which contradicts again.
Otherwise, for all , there is some with . Let for all . Find such that . Then for all , where is itself a block sequence. Let and . For all , set . Then , and . Finally, we have
which is disjoint from . Hence, and we contradict in this case as well.
It follows that , and in particular . If , then , which cannot happen. If , then there is no with , which contradicts the cofinality of . Finally, if , then , which is again a contradiction. ∎
4. Canonization Theorems on
This section adapts a canonization result of Klein and Spinas in [KS05] to be applied in the classification of the initial Tukey structure in the next section. The results to be stated are about defining a class of canonical equivalence relations, and showing that every equivalence relation restricts to such a relation. Since every equivalence relation corresponds to a function and vice versa, we can state the results mentioning only functions.
We define the following maps as in [KS05]: For ; , the least element of , , , and .
To motivate our result in this section, let us recall the remarkable theorem of Taylor:
Let be a Borel map. Then there exists and such that for all ;
In this section, using the same machinery as in [KS05] and the lemmas used in that paper, we will prove a simplified version of Theorem4.3 for functions defined on fronts on , which will be utilized in Section5 to find the exact Tukey structure below . This simplification includes the notion of admissibility (Definition4.4), which is motivated by the canonization of Lefmann in [Lef96] (see Theorem4.5). As a result, the simplified version will recover Lefmann’s canonization theorem for functions on fronts of finite uniformity rank as a special case. The essential modification we need concerns the definition of :
Definition 4.4.
Let be a front on . Define , including the empty sequence. Consider a map . We shall say that is admissible if the following hold:
(i)
For , if , then for all with , if there is a least with , then for every we have .
(ii)
Let . Then either for all with and for all , we have , or for all with , there is such that .
(iii)
Let be with , and assume that for all with , there is such that . Then either for all with , we have , where is the least with ; or for all with , we have , where is the least with .
For admissible and , define as follows: and given , if , then is the least with if it exists, otherwise . If and the least (if it exists) with satisfies , then . Finally, if and we are not in the previous case, then . Let be the least natural number with . Now define
Now we recall Lefmann’s canonization theorem for functions on fronts of finite uniformity rank, in our notation:
For every and every function , there are and admissible minmax-sep, such that whenever are with , and for all ;
We will use the separating and mixing technique which has its origins in [PV85] and was the main tool in [KS05]. Analogously to [KS05], for , denotes the block sequence , and denotes the block sequence . Finally, is a placeholder to mean either or .
The main theorem of this section is the following, a simplification of Theorem4.3 that employs Definition4.4 to define , which has Theorem4.5 as a special case:
Theorem 4.6.
Let be a front on some , and let be a function. Then there is and such that for each ,
Let us now define the notions we need and do the preparation for the proof of Theorem4.6. Fix a front on and let be a function. We may as well assume that , since otherwise the result will follow trivially. By Lemma2.12, we may assume that is -uniform for some to ease up the computations. Let and for , denote .
For and , we say that separates and if for every such that , (note that we allow the cases or ). We say that mixes and if no separates and . Finally, we say that decides and if it either separates or mixes and .
The proof of the following general Ramsey theoretic fact is a straightforward fusion argument and in the lines of the proof of Lemma in [DT14]:
Lemma 4.8.
1) Let be a property such that:
(i)
For all and , (hereditary).
(ii)
For all and , there is with (density).
Then for all , there is such that for all and for all , holds.
2) Let be a property such that:
(i)
For all and , (hereditary).
(ii)
For all and , there is with (density).
Then for all , there is such that for all and for all , holds.
It follows by definition that for every and for every , there is which decides and . Also, if decides and , then any decides and in the same way as does. This observation together with Lemma4.8 implies the following:
For all , there is such that for all , and are decided by .
We note that our separating-mixing notions are technically different from the ones used in [KS05]. The notions there were defined with respect to block sequences starting after and , since the function to be canonized there was a Borel function defined on . Here, our theorem will be a simplified version only for fronts, so the notions are adjusted in a suitable way. Since any function induces a unique continuous function on , almost all of the lemmas in [KS05] will have straightforward translations to our setting and the proofs will essentially be the same. As a result, it should be noted here that most of the lemmas and definitions in this section will be direct translations of those that were used in [KS05], and they will be included for the readability of the proof of the main result in this section.
The first of such lemmas is the transitivity of mixing, which directly follows from Lemma in [KS05]:
For every , there is which decides every and with , and one of the following holds:
(i)
For all , and are mixed by .
(ii)
For all , and are mixed by if and only if .
(iii)
For all , and are mixed by if and only if .
(iv)
For all , and are mixed by if and only if .
(v)
For all , and are mixed by if and only if .
Proof.
First, by Lemma4.9, we pick which decides every and with . Then we note that for every , since is -uniform on for some , it follows that for all . To finish, we apply Theorem4.1 to the function that corresponds to the equivalence relation on defined by if and only if and are mixed by , for , and get the corresponding . ∎
Let us remark here that, if and , then similarly to the argument in the proof of Lemma4.11, .
We say is strongly mixed by if and are mixed by for all .
(ii)
We say is min-separated by if for all , and are mixed by if and only if .
(iii)
We say is max-separated by if for all , and are mixed by if and only if max-sep.
(iv)
We say is minmax-separated by if for all , and are mixed by if and only if .
(v)
We say is strongly separated by if for all , and are mixed by if and only if .
(vi)
Finally, we say is separated in some sense by if one of the last four bullet points holds for . Also, is completely decided by if it is either strongly mixed or separated in some sense by .
Let us remark here that, for , although this definition still makes sense for , it doesn’t make sense for . Thus, we will just declare to be strongly mixed whenever .
The following straightforward consequence, Lemma in [KS05], is the reason we omitted the in some of the alternatives:
For all , there is which completely decides every with .
We augment the definition of canonical in [KS05] by adding the last condition in the following:
Definition 4.16.
We say that is canonical for if the following hold:
(i)
For all , decides and .
(ii)
Every is completely decided by .
(iii)
Let . Then and are either separated by for all , or mixed by for all . If , then the same result holds for and . Similarly, and , and , and , and finally and are in each case either separated by for all or mixed by for all , whenever there are with and with . The analogous result also holds for if .
(iv)
If , then either for all such that and for all , is strongly mixed by ; or for all with , there is such that is separated in some sense by . The same also holds for when .
(v)
Let and assume that is min-separated by . Assume also that for all with , there is such that is separated in some sense by . Then either for all with , the least such that is separated in some sense by is max-separated by ; or for all with , the least such that is separated in some sense by is not max-separated by .
Lemma 4.17.
There is which is canonical for .
Proof.
The proof proceeds along the lines of the proof of Lemma in [KS05]. By Lemma4.9 and Lemma4.15, we can find such that (i) and (ii) of being canonical are satisfied for . Next, we can apply Lemma2.8 and Lemma4.8 to to get such that (i)-(iii) of being canonical are satisfied for in the following way:
For the case with and , we color for arbitrary , into two colors by if and only if and are mixed by . Then we pick homogeneous for this coloring. Hence the density assumption of Lemma4.8 is satisfied, which means that there is for which (iii) of canonical is satisfied for the case of and . The other mentioned combinations are handled via similar colorings. For example, assume that there are with and with . Hence, is -uniform for at least . The same assertion also holds for . We first color into colors by if and only if . The homogeneous then has to be homogeneous with color , since . Similarly, we get the corresponding for . Then for arbitrary , we define by if and only if and are mixed by . We apply Lemma2.8 to to get homogeneous . It follows that the density assumption of Lemma4.8 is satisfied again.
By 2.11, there is such that or . The argument is exactly the same for when . This shows that the density assumption holds, so it follows by Lemma4.8 that there is such that (iv) holds for .
(v) is handled similarly to (iv) to get the final . ∎
From now on we fix a canonical and let , which is also canonical, to make sure that the maps , and will have disjoint images on . Finally, we let , for technical reasons. The rest of the results in this section until the main theorem hold for both and , but they will only be stated for .
Let be strongly separated by . Since is canonical, as in [KS05], we can split this into two cases:
(i)
We say is still strongly separated by if for all , and are mixed by .
(ii)
We say is very strongly separated by if for all , and are separated by .
It follows that for , if is still strongly separated by , then is still strongly separated by for all . The same holds for very strong separation as well.
We will need the technical lemmas used in [KS05]. The following includes Lemmas in [KS05] adapted to our setting. The proofs are exactly the same as the versions in [KS05].
Let . In the following statement, all and are assumed to be nonempty.
(i)
Assume that and are mixed by and and are both min-separated by . If and are with , then . In this case, and are mixed by for all with .
(ii)
Assume that and are mixed by and and are both max-separated by . If and are with , then . In this case, and are mixed by for all with .
(iii)
Assume that and are mixed by and and are both minmax-separated by . If and are with , then . In this case, and are mixed by for all . Furthermore, and are mixed by for all with and .
(iv)
Assume that and are mixed by and and are both strongly separated by . If and are with , then either is an initial segment of or is an initial segment of .
(v)
Assume that and are mixed by and and are both very strongly separated by . If and are with , then . In this case, and are mixed by for all .
Now we state the translations of Lemma and of [KS05]:
Let . Assume that and are mixed by . Furthermore, assume that is min-separated by and is minmax-separated by . Then if and are with , then and . In this case, and are mixed by for all .
Assume that both and are still strongly separated by . Then and are mixed by for every .
(ii)
Assume that is still strongly separated by and is very strongly separated by . Then and are mixed by for all . Furthermore, and are separated by for all .
(iii)
Assume that both and are very strongly separated by . Then and are mixed by for all . Furthermore, and are separated by for all .
Assume that and are mixed by . If is min-separated by , then is neither max-separated nor strongly separated by . The same result holds when and as well.
(ii)
Assume that and are mixed by . If is max-separated by , then is neither minmax-separated nor strongly separated by . The same result holds when and and as well.
(iii)
Assume that and are mixed by . If is minmax-separated by , then is not strongly separated by . The same result holds when and as well.
Now we start to prove new lemmas to be used in this paper.
Lemma 4.22.
Assume that is still strongly separated by . Let be with . If there is a least with very strongly separated by , then for any is either strongly mixed or still strongly separated by .
Proof.
Let . Since is still strongly separated, we know that and are mixed by , and we also know that is still strongly separated by . Now, Lemma4.21 implies that is either strongly mixed or strongly separated by . If is very strongly separated by , then we are done. If is still strongly separated by , then we can do the same argument to see that is either strongly mixed or strongly separated by . Finally, if is strongly mixed by , then Lemma4.14 part (i) implies that and are mixed by , which means and are mixed by , and so is either strongly mixed or strongly separated by . Now fix and suppose that is either strongly mixed or strongly separated by for all . Find the greatest for which is strongly separated by . If is very strongly separated by , then we get the result. Otherwise, by the argument in the base case and repeated applications of Lemma4.14 part (i), and are mixed by , and is still strongly separated by . By Lemma4.21, is either strongly mixed or strongly separated by , finishing the induction. ∎
Lemma 4.23.
Let and assume that and are mixed by . Furthermore, assume that both and are separated in some sense by . Then either and have the same separation type, or is minmax-separated by and is min-separated by , or vice versa. Moreover, if is minmax-separated by and is min-separated by , then there is such that and there is for which is separated in some sense by . Finally, in this case, for all such that , there is some for which is separated in some sense by , and is max-separated by , where is the least such .
Proof.
The first assertion directly follows from Lemma4.21. Now let us assume that are mixed by , is minmax-separated by and is min-separated by . Take with . Assume towards a contradiction that for all , is strongly mixed by . It follows that and are mixed by . Take such that but . By definition of mixing, and are mixed by . Since is min-separated by , and are mixed by . It follows by transitivity of mixing that and are mixed by . Find such that and . This contradicts Lemma4.19 since .
To finish, assume that are mixed by , is minmax-separated by and is min-separated by . Take with . By the preceding paragraph and (iv) of canonical, there is a least such that is separated in some sense by . By (v) of canonical, it suffices to show that is max-separated by . Indeed, since , by Lemma4.19, we know that and . Find and , such that and . It follows by Lemma4.19 that and are mixed by . By Lemma4.14 part (ii), and are mixed by . Finally, by Lemma4.14 part (i), we see that and are mixed by . It follows that and are mixed by . But now, by Lemma4.13, is max-separated by . Since is separated in some sense by , it follows from Lemma4.21 that is max-separated by . ∎
We now define the parameter function :
Definition 4.24.
For , we let if is strongly mixed by , if is min-separated by , if is max-separated by , if is minmax-separated by , if is still strongly separated by , and if is very strongly separated by .
Note that by Lemma4.22 and (v) of canonical, is admissible. Let us assume that is not trivial; i.e., assume that there is with . It then follows that for all . and being defined, we can start the proof of the theorem:
Let be a front on some , and let be a function. Pick a canonical for . The following four claims will finish the proof:
Claim 4.25.
Let . Take and with , and assume it is not the case that and (or vice versa) where and are maximal with . Then and are mixed by .
Proof.
Let , take and with , and assume it is not the case that and (or vice versa) where and are maximal with . Let us prove the result by induction on .
The case when follows by successive applications of Lemma4.14 part (i).
Now let us assume that and the result holds for all , with and . Find maximal and with and . It follows that , and so the induction hypothesis implies that and are mixed by . Recall that the images of , , and on are disjoint. Let . We split into cases.
First, assume that is in the range of . Since and were maximal, it follows that and are both min-separated by and . It follows by Lemma4.18 part (i) that and are mixed by . Since all of the proper initial segments of extending
, and all of the proper initial segments of extending
are strongly mixed by , by repeated applications of Lemma4.14 part (i), we get that and are mixed by .
If is in the range of , then the claim similarly follows by Lemma4.18 part (ii).
Assume that is in the range of . Since and were maximal we have four alternatives:
If and are both minmax-separated by , then the proof works similarly to the previous two cases.
Assume that is minmax-separated by and is min-separated by , and the least with satisfies . Since , we know that . It follows that and for some and for some with . It follows by Lemma4.19 that and are mixed by . Since is min-separated by , by Lemma4.13 we may conclude that is strongly mixed by , and it then follows by Lemma4.14 part (i) that and are mixed by . Again by Lemma4.14 part (i), we see that and are mixed by . Finally, since by Lemma4.13 is max-separated by , and being mixed by and the fact that , by Lemma4.18 part (ii), implies that and are mixed by . It then follows by successive applications of Lemma4.14 part (i) that and are mixed by , and hence also by .
Now assume that is min-separated by , and the least with satisfies and also is min-separated by , and the least with satisfies . It follows by Lemma4.18 part (i) that and are mixed by and so and are mixed by as well. Since , we get the result.
Finally, assume that is in the range of . Since and were maximal, it follows that and are both strongly separated by . We shall consider three cases.
First, assume that both and are very strongly separated by . By construction it follows that and . Similarly to the above arguments, we see that and as well as and are mixed by . Since , by Lemma4.18 part (v) we conclude that and are mixed by .
Second, assume that one of and is still strongly separated by and the other is very strongly separated by . Without loss of generality, we may assume that is still strongly separated by and is very strongly separated by . It follows that . By Lemma4.22, we define a sequence as follows: Let be given and find the least with or . If , stop; if , then similarly find the least with or . At the end, we find an , and obtain a sequence for some (by the assumption on and ) such that for all and . It follows that . Lemma4.20 part (ii) implies that and are mixed by . By Lemma4.14 part (i), and are mixed by . It follows that and are also mixed by . Since is very strongly separated, is very strongly separated as well. In general, given and mixed by , we can do the same argument to see that and are mixed by . At the end we will see that and are mixed by , and and are both very strongly separated by . It follows by Lemma4.18 part (v) that and are mixed by , and we get the result by Lemma4.14 part (i).
To finish, assume that both and are still strongly separated by . Repeating the construction from the previous paragraph, we get sequences and for some and such that for all , and or ; and similarly for all , and or . Note by the assumption on and that if and only if . By the assumption, .
We claim that and are mixed by . Indeed, find the least with (if and for all , then it follows from successive applications of Lemma4.20 part (ii) that and are mixed by , and the respective part of Lemma4.19 or Lemma4.18 proves the claim). Note that . Since , either is a proper initial segment of or vice versa. Without loss of generality, assume that is a proper initial segment of . It follows by Lemma4.20 part (i) that and are mixed by . Note that is still strongly separated by . Find the least with . If , let ; otherwise let . In either case, and are still strongly separated by ; also and are mixed by . Repeating this argument, by , we without loss of generality see that and are mixed by for some with (we allow with the convention “”). Note that either both and are still strongly separated by or both and are very strongly separated by . In the former case, since , we see by Lemma4.20 part (i) that and are mixed by . In the latter case, this time by Lemma4.18 part (v), we see that and are mixed by , and we are done. ∎
Claim 4.26.
Let . If , then .
Proof.
Let and take maximal with . Assume towards a contradiction that . It follows that and are mixed. Take (possibly empty) with . Since were maximal, it follows by Lemma4.14 part (i) that and are mixed by . Similarly, and are also mixed by . Hence, and are mixed by , which contradicts the fact that is strongly separated by .
It follows that 4.25 is applicable. Therefore, and are mixed by . By definition of mixing, since , it follows that . ∎
Claim 4.27.
Let . Then .
Proof.
This directly follows by the observation that no can be mixed with some which is separated in some sense by . Indeed, if there is such that , it follows that and are mixed by , contradicting the fact that is separated in some sense by . ∎
Claim 4.28.
Let . If , then .
Proof.
Let and assume towards a contradiction that . By 4.27, choose maximal with (we allow ). Choose maximal and with and . Note that both and are separated in some sense by . By definition of , the hypothesis of 4.25 is satisfied for and . It follows that and are mixed by . By Lemma4.23, we only have the following cases:
First, assume that both and are min-separated by . By Lemma4.18 part (i), it follows that . Since was chosen to be maximal, without loss of generality there is minimal such that is separated in some sense by . It follows from the above proof that there is also minimal such that is separated in some sense by . By construction of , both and are max-separated by . It follows that and are mixed by . By Lemma4.18 part (ii), we get , which contradicts the maximality of .
The cases when either and are both max-separated by or are both minmax-separated by reach a contradiction by the respective parts of Lemma4.18.
Assume that is min-separated by and is minmax-separated by . It follows by Lemma4.19 that , and . By Lemma4.23, there is minimal such that is separated in some sense by , and actually is max-separated by . By the argument in the proof of Lemma4.23, we in fact see that and are mixed by , where satisfies . Since is max-separated by , by Lemma4.18 part (ii), it follows that , which contradicts the maximality of .
Assume that both and are strongly separated by . By Lemma4.18 part (iv), either is an initial segment of or is an initial segment of . By Lemma4.18 part (v), at least one of or has to be still strongly separated by .
Assume that is still strongly separated by and is very strongly separated by . We cannot have , since it would imply that and are mixed by , contradicting Lemma4.20 part (ii). Again by Lemma4.20 part (ii), cannot be a proper initial segment of . It follows that is a proper initial segment of , and so and are mixed by . Find minimal such that is separated in some sense by . By Lemma4.22, is strongly separated by . Note that and are mixed by , and is very strongly separated by . If is very strongly separated by , then by Lemma4.18 part (v), and we contradict the maximality of . If is still strongly separated by , then we can similarly find minimal such that is strongly separated by . In general, suppose that is given with strongly separated by , and mixed by , and . If is very strongly separated by , then by the above argument , and we contradict the maximality of . If, on the other hand, is still strongly separated by , then we find the least such that is separated in some sense by . By the argument in the base case, is a proper initial segment of . At the end we get some with and mixed by , and is very strongly separated by . This contradicts the maximality of , as in the previous cases.
Assume that both and are still strongly separated by . By Lemma4.18 part (iv), either is an initial segment of or is an initial segment of . Let increasingly enumerate the natural numbers such that is still strongly separated by for all and is very strongly separated by . Similarly, let increasingly enumerate the natural numbers such that is still strongly separated by for all and is very strongly separated by . If , then we see that and are mixed by , which implies that and are also mixed by , and the argument will be similar to the next case. Suppose now that is a proper initial segment of . Then and are mixed by , and so and are also mixed by . Note that is still strongly separated by . It follows that either is an initial segment of , or vice versa.
Observe that, if is very strongly separated by (i.e., if ), then has to be a proper initial segment of (otherwise we contradict Lemma4.20 part (ii)). We see that and are mixed by . Note that is very strongly separated by . If is very strongly separated by , then by Lemma4.18 part (v) , and we contradict the maximality of . If, on the other hand, is still strongly separated by , then it follows similarly that has to be a proper initial segment of . At the end of finitely many steps, we reach , which is very strongly separated by . Also, and are mixed by and we have , which again contradicts the maximality of .
Finally, if is still strongly separated by , then we repeat the same argument until we without loss of generality reach and , which is very strongly separated by . Then the argument in the preceding paragraph applied to contradicts the maximality of . ∎
Observe that the canonical function we defined on is minimal in the following sense: If we take an arbitrary and define a parameter with respect to the separation types by , for any , we will have .
Let and take a function . Since is a front, by Theorem4.6, we may find and such that for all , if and only if . For , define . Note that there are only finitely many ’s. It follows by 2.11 that there is a and such that for all , and the result follows. ∎
Before we conclude this section, recall that we fixed a stable ordered-union . The following lemma, which follows the proof of Lemma4.17, states that the canonical can be chosen with as long as we have to begin with, and will be used in the next section:
Lemma 4.29.
Assume that is a front on some with , and is a function. Then there is a canonical with . In particular, there is some with which satisfies the conclusion of Theorem4.6, as well as of 4.25, 4.26, 4.27, and 4.28, which means that is canonized on .
Proof.
We sketch the argument. One can prove by induction on that the set of for which is -uniform is a closed set. Moreover, for fixed , the set of which decides and is coanalytic. Thus, if we let , by Theorem2.14 part (iii), there will be some such that or . The latter cannot happen by density of the block sequences that decide and . It follows that, for any , one can find , which decides every with . Utilizing Theorem2.14 part (iv) in place of Lemma4.8, one can find , , which satisfies (i) of canonical. Similarly, one can use Theorem2.14 part (vi) for (ii) of canonical, part (ii) for (iii) of canonical, and part (v) for (iv) and (v) of canonical to get with , which is canonical for . ∎
5. Initial Tukey Structure Below
This section contains the main results of the paper, Theorem5.4 and Theorem5.12. We fix a stable ordered-union ultrafilter on . Since and , the maps and are technically different, as well as the other ones. The following is routine to show:
Fact 5.1.
Assume that the maps , , , and have disjoint images on . Then the -image is an ultrafilter on . Moreover, , and .
Therefore, from now on, it is justified to use the maps and interchangeably.
For notational simplicity, define and define . Also, for , denote and . We will need the following lemma:
Whenever is a nonprincipal ultrafilter on and is monotone (meaning that ) and cofinal, there is and a monotone function such that
(i)
is continuous with respect to the metric topology on ,
(ii)
,
(iii)
There is such that; , , and for all , .
Define the following class of ultrafilters on for :
(i)
,
(ii)
.
(iii)
for limit ,
(iv)
.
Before stating Theorem5.4, let us note that given a front on some , we may construct a new ultrafilter on the base set in the following way:
Definition 5.3.
Let be a front on . We define .
By Theorem2.14 part (v), is an ultrafilter on the base set .
We will build on the technique Todorcevic developed in [RT12] to prove that Ramsey ultrafilters are Tukey minimal, which was outlined in [Dob21], and was extended to other ultrafilters in [DT14], [DT15], [Dob16a], and [DMT17].
Theorem 5.4.
Let be a nonprincipal ultrafilter on a countable index set with . Then is isomorphic to an ultrafilter from the class .
Proof.
Let be a nonprincipal ultrafilter, without loss of generality on , such that . By 2.3, there is a monotone and cofinal . Define by . By Lemma5.2, find and such that , , and for all , . By Theorem2.14 part (iii), we can find such that for all , there is with .
Define . By the minimality condition and the choice of , is a front on . Without loss of generality we may assume that is a uniform front on . Consider the map given by for all . The following is straightforward to show:
Claim 5.5.
.
By Lemma4.29, we may take canonical which witnesses the conclusion of Theorem4.6, along with all of the results in Section3. Let be the corresponding parameter function (Definition4.24).
Note that , hence . The rest of the proof will contain similar arguments to the related results in [DT14], in [DT15], or in [DMT17]. Define
Let denote the -image , an ultrafilter on the base set .
Claim 5.6.
.
Proof.
Define by , for each . Since if and only if for all , is well-defined and injective. Thus it suffices to show that .
Indeed, let be arbitrary. Then . Note that by definition of -image (Definition2.2), is cofinal in . Therefore, sends a cofinal subset of to a cofinal subset of , and we are done. ∎
Let us assume that is not constant, i.e., is not the constant -map; otherwise is a principal ultrafilter. Now we classify . Let
Since is a front on , has no infinite ascending sequences with respect to . The following is a straightforward consequence of this fact and the construction of :
Lemma 5.7.
There is no such that for all .
For , define the set . Since , by 4.27, any is separated in some sense by .
For , fix some . Set . We define the following filter:
Lemma 5.8.
For all , is an ultrafilter isomorphic to an ultrafilter from the set .
Proof.
Let .
First, assume that is max-separated by . For all , it follows that , and the result follows.
Assume that is minmax-separated by . For all , it follows that , and the result follows.
Assume that is min-separated by and suppose it is not the case that the least such that is separated in some sense by is max-separated by . For all , it follows that , and the result follows.
Assume that is min-separated by , and suppose there is least such that is separated in some sense by , and moreover is max-separated by . For all , it follows that . Conversely, let . Define by if and only if there is such that , for all . By Theorem2.14 part (ii), find such that is constant. Take any . Let . Find the least such that is separated in some sense by . It follows that . But then . It follows that , and so . But then . Therefore, is cofinal in and is cofinal in , and the result follows.
Assume that is strongly separated by . For all , it follows that . Conversely, let . Define by if and only if there is such that , for all . Take any . Let . Let increasingly enumerate those ’s such that is strongly separated by . It follows that for all and . But then . Thus, and so . We see that , and the result follows similarly to above. ∎
Recall the following notion used in [DT14], [DT15], and [DMT17]:
Definition 5.9.
We call a tree if , is closed under initial segments, and maximal nodes of are in . We call well-founded if does not have any infinite cofinal branches. We call a -tree if is a tree and for all , where and , if we denote , then . For a well-founded -tree , will denote the set of cofinal branches through .
By Lemma5.7, is a well-founded tree. It is straightforward to check that the set of ’s, where is a -tree, generates a filter on . Let us call this filter . Following is the key result:
Lemma 5.10.
. Therefore, is isomorphic to an ultrafilter of -trees, where is a well-founded tree, , and each is isomorphic to exactly one of , , , or .
Proof.
It suffices to show that contains a cofinal subset of . Let be arbitrary. Set . Let denote the set of initial segments of elements of (including the empty sequence). The proof will be complete if we can show that is a -tree, since and the set of cofinal branches through is .
Indeed, let . Pick and maximal such that . It follows that and are mixed by , and hence by . Set . Let
By Theorem2.14 part (v), we can find such that or . The latter case cannot happen since and are mixed. Therefore,
Since , we are done. ∎
For , we define if and only if . By Lemma5.7, is well-founded on . Hence, for , we can define . We let . The following now follows by induction on :
Claim 5.11.
is isomorphic to an ultrafilter from the set . In other words, is a countable Fubini iterate of , , , and .
As , we see that is a countable Fubini iterate of , , , and . This completes the proof of Theorem5.4. ∎
Theorem 5.12.
Let be a nonprincipal ultrafilter on a countable index set with . Then is Tukey equivalent to an ultrafilter from the set .
Proof.
By Theorem5.4, is isomorphic to an ultrafilter from the class . It suffices to show that the ultrafilters in are Tukey equivalent to one from the set . This is indeed clear for . Now assume that every ultrafilter from is Tukey equivalent to one from for all . Take . Write , where and each for some . By the induction assumption, each is Tukey equivalent to an ultrafilter from . Let be the one for which there is some with for every . It follows that , where . By Theorem3.4, we see that is Tukey equivalent to an ultrafilter from . ∎
and consist of countable Fubini iterates of and , respectively. consists of countable Fubini iterates of and that include both of and at a step of the iteration. Finally, consists of countable Fubini iterates of , , and that include at a step of the iteration.
References
[AT05]
Spiros A. Argyros and Stevo Todorcevic, Ramsey methods in analysis, Advanced Courses in Mathematics. CRM Barcelona, Birkhäuser Verlag, Basel, 2005.
[BD]
Tom Benhamou and Natasha Dobrinen, Cofinal types of ultrafilters over measurable cardinals, arXiv:2304.07214, Journal of Symbolic Logic, To appear.
[BD23]
by same author, On the Tukey types of Fubini products, arXiv:2311.15492, (2023).
[BDR15]
Andreas Blass, Natasha Dobrinen, and Dilip Raghavan, The next best thing to a P-point, The Journal of Symbolic Logic 80 (2015), no. 3, 866–900.
[Ben23]
Tom Benhamou, Commutativity of cofinal types, arXiv:2312.15261, (2023).
[BH87]
Andreas Blass and Neil Hindman, On strongly summable ultrafilters and union ultrafilters, Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 304 (1987), no. 1, 83–97.
[Bla73]
Andreas Blass, The Rudin-Keisler ordering of -points, Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 179 (1973), 145–166.
[Bla87]
Andreas Blass, Ultrafilters related to Hindman’s finite-unions theorem and its extensions, Contemporary Mathematics 65 (1987), no. 3, 89–124.
[Bla10]
Andreas Blass, Ultrafilters and set theory, Ultrafilters across mathematics, Contemp. Math., vol. 530, Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, RI, 2010, pp. 49–71.
[BW24]
Tom Benhamou and Fanxin Wu, Diamond principles and Tukey-top ultrafilters on a countable set, arXiv:2404.02379, (2024).
[DMT17]
Natasha Dobrinen, José G. Mijares, and Timothy Trujillo, Topological Ramsey spaces from Fraïssé classes, Ramsey-classification theorems, and initial structures in the Tukey types of p-points, Archive for Mathematical Logic 56 (2017), no. 7-8, 733–782.
[Dob15]
Natasha Dobrinen, Survey on the Tukey theory of ultrafilters, Zbornik Radova. (Beograd) 17(25) (2015), 53–80.
[Dob16a]
by same author, High dimensional Ellentuck spaces and initial chains in the, The Journal of Symbolic Logic 81 (2016), no. 1, 237–263.
[Dob16b]
by same author, Infinite-dimensional Ellentuck spaces and Ramsey-classification theorems, Journal of Mathematical Logic 16 (2016), no. 1, 1650003, 37.
[Dob20]
by same author, Continuous and other finitely generated canonical cofinal maps on ultrafilters, Fundamenta Mathematicae 249 (2020), no. 2, 111–147.
[DT11]
Natasha Dobrinen and Stevo Todorcevic, Tukey types of ultrafilters, Illinois Journal of Mathematics 55 (2011), no. 3, 907–951.
[DT14]
by same author, A new class of Ramsey-classification theorems and their application in the Tukey theory of ultrafilters, Part 1, Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 366 (2014), no. 3, 1659–1684.
[DT15]
by same author, A new class of Ramsey-classification theorems and their applications in the Tukey theory of ultrafilters, Part 2, Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 367 (2015), no. 7, 4627–4659.
[Hal17]
Lorenz J. Halbeisen, Combinatorial set theory: With a gentle introduction to forcing, second ed., Springer Monographs in Mathematics, Springer, Cham, 2017.
[Hin74]
Neil Hindman, Finite sums from sequences within cells of a partition of , Journal of Combinatorial Theory. Series A 17 (1974), 1–11.
[Isb65]
J. R. Isbell, The category of cofinal types. II, Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 116 (1965), 394–416.
[Juh67]
I. Juhasz, Remarks on a theorem of B. Pospíšil, Commentationes Mathematicae Universitatis Carolinae 8 (1967), 231–247.
[KR18]
Borisa Kuzeljevic and Dilip Raghavan, A long chain of P-points, Journal of Mathematical Logic 18 (2018), no. 1, 1850004, 38.
[KR24]
Borisa Kuzeljevic and Dilip Raghavan, Order structure of P-point ultrafilters and their relatives, arXiv:2404.03238, (2024).
[KS05]
Olaf Klein and Otmar Spinas, Canonical forms of Borel functions on the Milliken space, Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 357 (2005), no. 12, 4739–4769.
[Kun76]
Kenneth Kunen, Some points in , Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society 80 (1976), no. 3, 385–398.
[Laf89]
Claude Laflamme, Forcing with filters and complete combinatorics, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 42 (1989), no. 2, 125–163.
[Lef96]
H. Lefmann, Canonical partition relations for ascending families of finite sets, Studia Scientiarum Mathematicarum Hungarica. Combinatorics, Geometry and Topology (CoGeTo) 31 (1996), no. 4, 361–374.
[Mij07]
José G. Mijares, A notion of selective ultrafilter corresponding to topological Ramsey spaces, MLQ. Mathematical Logic Quarterly 53 (2007), no. 3, 255–267.
[Mil75]
Keith R. Milliken, Ramsey’s theorem with sums or unions, Journal of Combinatorial Theory. Series A 18 (1975), 276–290.
[Mil80]
Arnold W. Miller, There are no -points in Laver’s model for the Borel conjecture, Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society 78 (1980), no. 1, 103–106.
[Mil08]
David Milovich, Tukey classes of ultrafilters on , Topology Proceedings 32 (2008), 351–362, Spring Topology and Dynamics Conference.
[PR82]
Pavel Pudlák and Vojtˇech Rödl, Partition theorems for systems of finite subsets of integers, Discrete Mathematics 39 (1982), no. 1, 67–73.
[PV85]
Hans Jürgen Prömel and Bernd Voigt, Canonical forms of Borel-measurable mappings , Journal of Combinatorial Theory. Series A 40 (1985), no. 2, 409–417.
[RS17]
Dilip Raghavan and Saharon Shelah, On embedding certain partial orders into the P-points under Rudin-Keisler and Tukey reducibility, Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 369 (2017), no. 6, 4433–4455.
[RS23]
Dilip Raghavan and Juris Steprāns, Stable ordered-union versus selective ultrafilters, arXiv:2302.05539, (2023).
[RT12]
Dilip Raghavan and Stevo Todorcevic, Cofinal types of ultrafilters, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 163 (2012), no. 3, 185–199.
[RV19]
Dilip Raghavan and Jonathan L. Verner, Chains of P-points, Canadian Mathematical Bulletin. Bulletin Canadien de Mathématiques 62 (2019), no. 4, 856–868.
[She98]
Saharon Shelah, Proper and improper forcing, second ed., Perspectives in Mathematical Logic, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1998.
[Tay76]
Alan D. Taylor, A canonical partition relation for finite subsets of , Journal of Combinatorial Theory. Series A 21 (1976), no. 2, 137–146.
[Tuk40]
John W. Tukey, Convergence and Uniformity in Topology, Annals of Mathematics Studies, vol. No. 2, Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 1940.
[Wim82]
Edward L. Wimmers, The Shelah -point independence theorem, Israel Journal of Mathematics 43 (1982), no. 1, 28–48.
[Zhe17]
Yuan Yuan Zheng, Selective ultrafilters on FIN, Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society 145 (2017), no. 12, 5071–5086.