[1]\fnmJavier \surBracho
[1]\orgdivInstituto de Matemáticas, \orgnameUniversidad Nacional Autónoma de México, \orgaddress\streetCiudad Universitaria, \cityMexico City, \postcode04510, \countryMexico
Harmonic curves and the beauty of Projective Geometry
Abstract
The purpose of this paper is to present projective geometry in a synthetic, visual and intuitive style through the central notion of harmonicity which leads to harmonic curves. This presentation includes new results, unpublished proofs of some classic theorems and a slight reformulation of its axiomatics.
keywords:
Harmonicity, Conic Curves, Ruled Surfaces, Projective Geometrypacs:
[MSC Classification]51A05, 97G10, 97G40, 51A30
1 Introduction
A conic curve or section is defined as the intersection of a circular cone with a plane. This concept is inherently metric. However, that conic curves somehow belong to projective geometry is well known, but not clear how. For example, the statement that ellipses are what we see when we look at a circle, which is how we should present them to children, makes many of us unconfortable because we didn’t hear it in class and don’t have a simple proof at hand. Trying to make sense of this incongruent state of affairs, we were lead to define harmonic curves in a purely projective style (they are basically the locus of points in the plane that see a quadrangle as a harmonic set) and study their properties without any reference to metric concepts. Yes, harmonic curves become conic sections in the euclidean plane, but they have a rich set of purely projective properties so that their study constitutes a beautiful approach to projective geometry. Such approach is what this paper is all about.
Motivated by the technics of perspective drawing, which were discovered by the painters of the renaissance to represent realisticly three dimensional scenes on flat canvases, Girard Desargues (1591-1661) initiated the development of Projective Geometry expanding the concept of space to include ideal points (also known as points at infinity), [6]. Mostly forgotten through the following two centuries, his visionary work was revived and recognized as fundamental during the first half of the XIX century, when Projective Geometry was firmly established as a field on its own. In 1872 Felix Klein opened his famous Erlangen Program, [9], with the statement “Among the advances of the last fifty years in the field of geometry, the development of Projective Geometry occupies the first place”. One of the mathematicians whose work deserved such praise is Karl Georg Christian von Staudt (1798-1867). In his treatise on the subject [13], he proves that the notions of harmonicity, i.e. the concepts of harmonic sets and pencils, are entirely projective and independent of metric ones like distances or angles. He also shows that conic curves may be defined through the abstract, and purely projective concept of polarity.
In an attempt to make these facts accesible to high-school teachers, and inspired by [11] where John Stillwell argues that such goal is not only worthwhile and culturally urgent, but also feasible, the authors of this article developed the dynamic geometry system ProGeo3D [1] which is specialized in projective geometry. In particular, it incorporates harmonicity as a construction tool. All the figures of this paper are snapshots of constructions in ProGeo3D. To appreciate their dynamic capacity and the 3D nature of some (e.g., Figure 2.a), we present them in a web site111https://arquimedes.matem.unam.mx/harmonic_curves/scenes.html. Playing with this system, we discovered several interesting constructions, proofs and new results that do not seem to be included in the known literature on the subject. This paper presents them to propose an alternative approach to projective geometry which is intuitive, synthetic and, in our subjective opinion, beautiful.
We start by reviewing von Staudt’s definition of harmonicity, emphasizing the duality it intrinsically carries. That leads us to a simple definition of what we call harmonic curves to differentiate them from the classic treatment of conic sections, although in euclidean space they are the same. In the following section, we relate them to von Staudt’s definition, which uses polarities, but now it must be stated as a theorem, the “Polarity Theorem” (Thm. 2). Its proof uses the classic idea in projective geometry of going out to 3D, finding a way to work out things there, and coming back to 2D. The first to use our explicit technic out in 3D, was Germinal Pierre Dandelin (1794–1847) to prove Pascal’s Hexagon Theorem in [5]. It is deeply related to ruled surfaces as defined by Hilbert and Cohn-Vossen in [7] using only incidence geometry. This suggests the formulation of a new axiom for Projective Geometry, which we call the Equipal Axiom. It is shown to be equivalent to Pappus’ Theorem and thus to other equivalent axioms frequently used in projective geometry. In the final section we discuss the axiomatic foundations of our approach in which the use of 3 dimensions is fundamental.
2 Harmonic sets, pencils and reflections
One of the seminal contributions of Karl von Staudt was to prove that harmonicity (the notion of harmonic conjugates which had been used since antiquity in terms of distances) only depends on incidence using quadrangles.
A quadrangle, , is defined as four points in the projective plane in general position (i.e., no three of them are collinear), called its vertices, together with 4 lines, called its sides, such that their incidence relation is a 4-cycle (each object of one type is incident with two of the other); that is, is defined by its vertices (4 points in general position) together with a dihedral (i.e., a cyclic but non-oriented) order on them which yields the 4 sides.
The term “quadrangle” is adequate because at any vertex, its two incident lines (an “angle”) distinguish two adjacent vertices and thus, it also determines the opposite vertex (as the remaining one); note that the partition of vertices into opposite pairs determines the quadrangle. The center of the quadrangle is the intersection of its two diagonal lines (the lines that join opposite vertices); and its horizon is the line joining the intersection of opposite sides, which are called its two diagonal points.
The notion of a quadrangle is autodual, but in a quadrilateral the stress is given on the 4 sides, so that its dual-center is the horizon of the corresponding quadrangle whose center is the dual-horizon of the quarilateral. However, we will keep the “horizon” and “center” terminology: understood always as a line and a point, respectively. These terms are natural because if a square tile is drawn on a canvas, the center of the tile and the horizon of the square tiling of the plane which it generates should be drawn, respectively, at the center and the horizon of the quadrangle which such a drawing determines.
Four points in general position are the vertices of three quadrangles. Their corresponding centers and horizons form its diagonal triangle.
\begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{armonia_y_dual.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf a)}} \end{overpic} \begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{harmonic_pencil.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf b)}} \end{overpic}
Four collinear points , as in Figure 1.a, are said to be a harmonic set,222The terms “harmonic quadruple” or “harmonic range” are also used, but we stick to “harmonic set” as in the classic texts [12] and [4]. if there exists a quadrangle such that its diagonal points are and (hence the horizon of the quadrangle is their support line) and the other pair, and , are incident with the diagonal lines. Dually, four concurrent lines are called a harmonic pencil333The term “harmonic set of lines” is also used, e.g. [12, 4]; but we will use “pencil” for simplicity and to distinguish them immediately from harmonic sets (of points). if there exists a quadrangle such that one pair of lines are the diagonal lines of the quadrangle (hence, its center is the concurrency point of the pencil, also called its center) and the other two lines are incident to the diagonal points of the quadrangle, see Figure 1.b.
As stated, the pairs of elements in the definitions play a different role but, as we will see, they are interchangeable, so that both notions include an explicit dihedral order of the four elements involved, which coincides with their geometric placement (points within a projective line or lines about a point).
Let us now show that these definitions are sound. Given a collinear triple with distinguished, two auxiliary points out of the support line and collinear with determine a unique quadrilateral as in Figure 1.a, and therefore produce the point as the intersection of the other diagonal line with the horizon; this construction, called the harmonic fourth, has as outcome the point , called the harmonic conjugate of with respect to and . Since for the triple , one can choose the other opposite pair of vertices of as auxiliary points and then obtain as outcome, we can further say that the (unordered) pair of points are harmonic conjugates with respect to , [4, 12].
Theorem 1 (Harmonic Theorem).
The outcome of the harmonic fourth construction does not depend on the choice of the auxiliary points.
The proof is well known and follows from Desargues’ Theorem. It may also be directly proved in 3D using only incidence arguments (see Figure 2.a), and deducing the planar case imediatly from it. We omit the details for brevity.
\begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{harmonic_theorem_in3D.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf a)}} \end{overpic} \begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{Symmetry_of_harmonicity.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf b)}} \end{overpic}
Finally, to see that the definition of harmonic set is symmetric with regard to the role played by the two pairs of points, extend the quadrangle to a 2 by 2 tiling drawn in perspective, as in Figure 2.b (the know-how comes from the renaissance artists and the coincidences follow from the Harmonic Theorem). Then, the quadrilateral of (dashed) diagonals not incident with its center proves that are harmonic conjugates with respect to .
Since the point in Figure 2.b may be chosen to be any point not on the support line of the harmonic set, we obtain that any such point sees them as harmonic, that is, the lines to them with their dihedral order is a harmonic pencil. Dually, there is also a harmonic fourth construction for lines and any line not through the center of a harmonic pencil cuts it in a harmonic set. Thus, harmonic sets and pencils are preserved by projections.
The harmonic fourth construction also makes sense in the singular cases when or . In them, the outside quadrangle collapses to a line, but the diagonals do not collapse and so the construction holds in the sense of not becoming ambiguous, and it yields or , respectively. Therefore, given two (distinct) points and in a line we get a well defined map
called the harmonic reflection of with respect to and : it fixes these two points and it gives the harmonic conjugate elsewhere. is an involution which interchanges the two segments in which the points and divide their projective line. And in particular, it interchanges its ideal point at infinity with the (euclidean) midpoint of and , making the harmonic fourth construction a very useful tool for perspective drawing.
The natural generalization to the projective plane (space) is the harmonic reflection with respect to a point , called the center, and a non-incident line (plane) , called the mirror.444In the plane, Coxeter calls it harmonic homology in [4]. It is defined on every line through as the harmonic reflection with respect to and the intersection of with . If we denote by , “join”, and , “meet”, the basic projective operations of linear span and intersection, respectivelly, we may write for :
where note that we write the action of maps or functions on the right. This notion amalgamates two classic euclidean examples: the central inversions, when the mirror is the line (plane) at infinity, and the reflections when the center is the ideal point in the direction perpendicular to the mirror.
Harmonic reflections are collineations (i.e., they send lines to lines). They act in the dual plane as harmonic reflections in the sense that if is a line different from the mirror , then is a harmonic pencil centered at .
Lemma 1 (Klein’s Triangle).
Given a triangle with respective opposite sides , then 555 is the projective plane and stands for its identity map. is the Klein four-group.
Proof.
Since the three non-trivial elements are involutions, we need only to show that the composition of any two of them gives the third, which is the definition of the Klein four-group. Consider a point not in the triangle. We claim that the quadruple has as its diagonal triangle. In Figure 3, the three dashed lines through have harmonic sets that define the corresponding three points other than . The gray lines from a vertex (say ) to one of them (say, ) pass through another one () because the two corresponding harmonic sets (in and ) are projected to each other from the vertex () and projections preserve harmonicity.
It is easy to see that these gray lines through the vertices cut the opposite side in its corresponding harmonic conjugate, and that for points in the triangle the maps behave as they should. This completes the proof. ∎
Thus, the generic orbits of the Klein four-group associated to a triangle are the quadruples that have it as diagonal triangle, and any of the four triangular regions in which the three lines cut the projective plane are the fundamental regions of the group action which has the vertices as fixed points.
We define the harmonic group () as the group of transformations generated by the harmonic reflections on . Of course, they turn out to be the classic groups of projectivities, but this requires proof.
3 Harmonic curves and bundles
We define the harmonic curve, , of a quadrangle as the locus of points that are centers of harmonic pencils transversal to . By transversal we mean that each vertex of is incident to a line of the pencil and this correspondence preserves the dihedral orders. Dually, the harmonic bundle of a quadrilateral consists of the lines that support a harmonic set transversal to its sides and with corresponding dihedral orders.
\begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{Quadrangle_with_tangent_lines_to_its_harmonic_curve.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf a)}} \end{overpic} \begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{curva_de_armonia.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf b)}} \end{overpic}
Consider a quadrangle with vertices . First observe that the vertices are points of its harmonic curve . Indeed, for each vertex, the harmonic conjugate of its diagonal with respect to its sides completes a harmonic pencil centered at it which is transversal to , see Figure 4.a. These new lines are the tangent lines to at the vertices and will be denoted by the corresponding lower case letter. The harmonic bundle of the quadrilateral is called the tangent bundle of and will be denoted .
Now consider a point different from the vertices, we call it generic, see Figure 4.b. By definition, the four lines from to the vertices are a harmonic pencil centered at . Let and . Then is a harmonic set. Therefore, we can recover from by defining
(1) |
But this makes sense for ranging over all of and gives the four vertices (at a harmonic set), so that is parametrized by via this construction. We call this the HC-construction.
Lemma 2 (Duality lemma).
Points in the harmonic curve are paired (i.e., in bijective correspondence) by incidence with lines in its tangent bundle .
Proof.
Let us continue with the notation above, so that , is the quadrilateral whose harmonic bundle is . As before, these four generating lines belong to the bundle because the vertex to which they are tangent (called their contact point) can be obtained as the harmonic fourth of their intersection to the other three lines (see Figure 4.a). Going further on the HC-construction (1), and dualizing it (see Figure 5): let , and , so that is generically a harmonic pencil centered at . Then, is a line of the bundle , and any such line is uniquely expressed in this way.
To prove that for different from and , define and consider the triangle with respective opposite sides . By the definitions, we have (), and by Klein’s Triangle Lemma, , then (). But and , so that (dually, ). Hence, the fact that , implies that as we wished. is called the contact point of which is the tangent line to at . ∎
As a corollary, we can express the harmonic curve as a family of harmonic reflections applied to a single point
(2) |
where , which only depends on three points and the two tangent lines incident to , respectively; we will call this, the A-construction.
Clearly, harmonic curves are sent to harmonic curves under projections because projections preserve harmonicity. So that the fact that the classic conic sections are harmonic curves follows from the fact that a circle is a harmonic curve. Indeed, consider an inscribed square to a circle as a quadrangle. Use the inscribed angle theorem to see that each point in the circle is the center of a transversal pencil to the quadrangle with consecutive lines at angles , which is a harmonic pencil.
4 Polarities and hyperbolic geometry
A polarity in the plane (in space) is a bijective correspondence between points and lines (planes) that preserves incidence; the terms polar of a point, pole of a line (plane) or a polar pair are used666An extra hypothesis is required in [4]. Namely, that for some line, the map to the line pencil of its pole be a projectivity. But we do not need to stress this issue..
Theorem 2 (Polarity).
A harmonic curve induces a polarity (expressed by upper and lower case of the same letter) satisfying:
-
i)
-
ii)
If then the harmonic reflection , with as center and its non-incident polar line as mirror, leaves invariant.
We have already seen a part of item (i) as Lemma 2 because tangent lines to points in a harmonic curve are defined as their polar lines. The rest of the proof will be given in the next section as a consequence of an analogue in 3D, Theorem 4. For the moment, let us make two remarks about this theorem and, assuming it is true, explore some of its profound consequences.
The two mathematicians that father this theorem are Jean-Victor Poncelet (1788-1867) and Karl G. C. von Staudt (1798-1867). Poncelet proved the relation of poles and polars for conic sections using harmonicity (in its metric version), and soon after, von Staudt developed polarities as a general concept and used it as an alternative way to define conic curves within projective geometry with no metric or algebraic considerations, [13]. This definition via polarities is the one Coxeter uses in his influential book [4], and calls it “extraordinarily natural and symmetrical” because it has duality built into it. In general, there are two types of polarities: euclidian in which no point is incident with its polar line, and hyperbolic when there exist pole and polar incident pairs. The terms used are related to the groups generated by harmonic reflections of non-incident polar pairs. So that von Staudt’s definition of a conic curve is equivalent to item (i) of the theorem for a hyperbolic polarity, while Poncelet’s results can be rephrased as item (ii).
As examples of polar pairs, we have named lines and points in Figure 5 according to the upper and lower case rule for poles and polars with respect to the displayed harmonic curve . Indeed, a point and the corresponding line in described in Lemma 2 constitute a polar pair satisfying (i).
We now prove that von Staudt’s definition of conic curves with mild extra hypothesis gives harmonic curves.
Lemma 3.
Given a polarity in the plane, let be the set of points that are incident to their polar line and suppose item (ii) of Theorem 2 holds. If every line meets in at most two points and contains at least three points, then is a harmonic curve.
Proof.
Let be three points. By the hypothesis on the lines, they are not collinear. Let be the respective polar lines of , so that and . Let ; it is the pole of because polarities preserve incidence, which also implies that . Finally, let be the quadrangle . To conclude the proof we show that .
Given , its polar, , is a line through different from and . Let . Then, since leaves and invariant and , it transposes and , so that is a harmonic set. Since the polarity satisfies (ii) of Theorem 2, , so that the A-construction (2) for implies that . Finally, given different from , let , then because the line has no point in other than and by hypothesis. Therefore, . ∎
As a corollary to the proof of this lemma (and assuming the Polarity Theorem) we can now say which quadrangles inscribed in a harmonic curve generate it as its harmonic curve, that is, are such that . Precisely the ones in which the pole of one diagonal line lies in the other diagonal. And moreover, for any triplet of points (with distinguished) in , we have such a quadrangle .
The abstract resemblance of these facts to the harmonic fourth construction and the existence of harmonic sets in the projective line lead to the theorem stated and proved bellow. But we must also remark that it is deeply related to the projective model of the hyperbolic plane due to Beltrami and Klein, which he used as an important example for his Erlangen Program, [9].
If we fix a harmonic curve , any two points in define a hyperbolic line and a hyperbolic reflection where is the pole of .
Then we have a subgroup of , called the hyperbolic group, which is generated by all the hyperbolic reflections on hyperbolic lines. This group acts on the inside of the harmonic curve which is taken as the hyperbolic plane for the Beltrami-Klein model, and hyperbolic geometry can be built from there, but we have no space here to follow it through; for such treatments see, e.g., [3, 10, 2] . However, we should remark that the generating quadrangles of have as diagonals the pairs of perpendicular hyperbolic lines.
The usual way to state the following theorem is in the context of the upper half plane model of the hyperbolic plane and referring to matrix groups.
Theorem 3.
.
Proof.
First, we define the tangential map from to a tangent line, Figure 6.a. Let be a point in and let be its tangent (or polar) line. For every other than , let , where is the tangent line to at . Taking , this gives a bijective map between and , because (the polar of ) cuts in and for , see Figure 6.a.
\begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{tangential_map.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf a)}} \end{overpic} \begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{generating_quadrangle.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf b)}} \end{overpic}
Considering as , the theorem follows from the fact that generating quadrangles of and harmonic sets of correspond to each other, because then harmonic reflections and hyperbolic reflections (the generators of the groups) correspond under the tangential map.
Let be a generating quadrangle of , and let be their respective tangent lines. By Lemma 2, the harmonic bundle of this quadrilateral is the tangent bundle of and it contains . Therefore, by the definition of harmonic bundles, we have that is a harmonic set, see Figure 6.b. ∎
This proof was the primal motivation for our definition of harmonic curves.
5 Doubly ruled surfaces
The following proof of the Polarity Theorem (2) is inspired by Dandelin’s proof of Pascal’s Hexagonal Theorem. Given a conic curve, Dandelin constructs, in [5], a hyperboloid of revolution that has it as a plane section; then, using the fact that this surface is doubly-ruled, he obtains a configuration of 6 lines in three dimensional space associated to the six points of the hexagon in the conic, and argues with the geometric-combinatorial properties of the configuration to conclude the proof. We use the same general idea and get to the same configuration of 6 lines, but instead of hyperboloids of revolution we can now use general ruled surfaces following Hilbert and Cohn-Vossen’s construction of ruled surfaces in [7], which appeared in print almost a century after Dandelin’s proof, and made clear that they can be constructed by simple incidence arguments.
Consider two lines and in three dimensional projective space. They touch if and only if they are coplanar. If this is not the case, they can be called a generating pair because for any point not in them, there exists a unique line through transversal (i.e., with a common point) to and ; namely:
Now consider three lines , , in general position (i.e., each pair is generating, or equivalently, no pair of them is coplanar). The transversal ruling to , denoted , is the set of lines that are transversal to them (i.e., that touch all three); any such set of lines will be called a ruling and its elements are called its rules, see Figure 8.a. If we denote , the above observation implies that is parametrized by incidence with the points in any of the three generating lines (through any point in them there passes a unique rule). It will be important to note that, dually, is also parametrized by planes containing one of the lines; if we denote planes by greek letters (points and lines are, respectivelly, upper and lower case latin) we have, for example, that
(3) |
\begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{blue_ruling.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf a)}} \end{overpic} \begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{red_ruling.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf b)}} \end{overpic}
Every pair of rules in is generating, otherwise, their three transversal lines would be coplanar. Thus, for any triplet we get a transversal rulling that contains the original three lines, ; this ruling is an extension of , see Figure 8.b. In real projective space there is only one extension to a ruling of three lines in general position, but this is not true in all projectives spaces. In what follows we will assume that our projective space does have this property, that is, we will assume it as an axiom:
Equipal Axiom.777Equipal is a classic mexican style of furniture that uses double rulings for bases, [2]. Three lines in general position belong to a unique ruling.
Later on we will prove it is equivalent to Pappus’ Theorem and thus to other classic statements that are commonly adopted as axioms in projective geometry. Another name for it could be the “Double-ruling Axiom” because it immediately implies that rulings are matched or paired: any ruling has an opposite ruling which is the transversal ruling to any three of its rules. The doubly-ruled surface (we also refer to it simply as a ruled surface) obtained as the union of the rules in any such ruling is also the union of the rules in its opposite ruling.
Hence, every point on a ruled surface has a tangent plane, the one generated by the unique rules through the point in the opposite rulings of the surface.
Theorem 4 (Polarity of ruled surfaces).
The pairing of points in a ruled surface with their tangent planes extends to a polarity of projective space. Furthermore, if then is not incident with its polar plane and the harmonic reflection , with as center and as mirror, leaves invariant.
Proof.
The ruled surface has two opposite rulings and such that
To define the polarity induced by in its complement, fix three rules in the ruling , and beware that we have inverted the notational use of primes: their transversal ruling is now .
Consider a point ; dually, we could start with a non-tangent plane.
Let . There is a well defined rule for which (namely, , as in (3)). Let . Observe that must be in the polar plane of because polarities preserve incidence and is in the polar plane of .
Analougously, we obtain , for which and . Let and , so that the polar plane to has to be
\begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{polar_plane_of_point_with_respect_to_ruled_surface.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf a)}} \end{overpic} \begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{dandelin_configuration_from_ruled_surface.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf b)}} \end{overpic}
If we had started, dually, with a non tangent plane we would have found as the intersection of the three tangent planes at , , ; and would be the rules in passing through respectively. So that the pairing of points and planes is now well defined.
We have distinguished what we will call a Dandelin configuration: six lines of two types or colors, three of each, and —unprimed and primed in the text, red and blue in the pictures as in Figure 8.b— such that a pair of them touch if and only if they have opposite types. This produces nine basic points and nine tangent planes by the “meet” () or “join” () of lines of different colors; but it also comes with a derived configuration of other lines and planes that naturally arise from them. The geometric richness of this configuration, closely related to the combinatorics of determinants, is what Dandelin exploited in [5]; and we follow suit.
Now, we will prove that the harmonic reflection, , with center and mirror interchanges the lines respectively with in the opposite ruling. By the triangular symmetry of the construction, it will sufffice to prove that:
in the tangent plane to , , the lines are a harmonic pencil centered at .
Because this happens if and only if interchanges the lines and .
The tangent plane contains five of the nine basic points of our Dandelin configuration. Namely, the -quadrangle:
with its center and its diagonals are and . The remaining four basic points outside of , break naturally into two pairs whose generated lines are incident with the two diagonal points of the -quadrangle. This follows because these diagonal points can be seen as the intersection of three tangent planes. Namely, and (see Figure 9).
Thus, interchanges the rules and . Analogously, it interchanges with and with . Then, it gives a bijection between the transversal rulings of and , which are and respectively, because a line transversal to is sent by to a line transversal to and viceversa. Therefore, leaves invariant, as we wished to prove.
In particular, since a harmonic reflection sends a line to a line concurrent with the mirror and coplanar with the center, our definition of the polarity does not depend on the choice of generating rules .
Finally, the proof that the polarity we have defined preserves incidence follows in cases, but in a straightforward manner from the fact that if the tangent plane to a point in , say as above, contains a point not in , say , then the polar plane of contains . ∎
Observe that, because of the incidence invariance, the polarity extends naturally to a pairing of lines. The polar of a line is the intersection of all the polar planes of its points, or of any two of them.
This polarity theorem asserts that what one sees as the contour of a ruled surface is exactly its section with the polar plane of the viewpoint. Sections and the contour of projections coincide. We now prove that sections of ruled surfaces are harmonic curves, and that the corresponding harmonic bundle is the projection from the pole of any one of the two rulings.
Proof of Theorem 2. Consider a harmonic curve, , in a plane . Our basic aim is to prove that
there exists a ruled surface that has as a section,
that is, such that . This will induce the desired polarity in to complete the proof of the theorem.
By definition, is the harmonic curve of a quadrangle . Let and be the tangents at and , respectively; and let , . We know that and that is obtained by the A-construction (2).
Choose two points and not in and colinear with (see Figure 10.a).
Let . Since , the four lines from and to and can be colored red and blue so that only lines of opposite colors touch. Finally, consider the red (blue) line through transversal to the two blue (red) lines. We now have a Dandelin configuration of six lines colored red and blue: let be the doubly ruled surface it defines (Figure 10.b). By construction, and are a polar pair with respect to .
\begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{A_Dandelin_conf_from_A_constr_of_harm_curve.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf a)}} \end{overpic} \begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{Ruled_surface_from_A_constr_of_harm_curve.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf b)}} \end{overpic}
The polarity induced by restricts naturally to a polarity in the plane as follows. The polar line of a point in is the intersection of its polar plane with , and the pole of a line in is the pole of the plane it generates with —or the intersection with of its polar line. In particular, item (i) of Theorem 2 follows for .
Since harmonic reflections preserve the planes through their center, those for non-incident polar pairs with pole in , restrict to harmonic reflections of that leave invariant. Therefore, item (ii) of Theorem 2 follows for .
That now follows from Lemma 3 and its proof (identifying in both settings) because a line that intersects in three different points is easily seen to be a rule of and contains no such rules. ∎
Observe that, within the above framework, for any point in the intersection with of its tangent plane to is the projection to from of any of its two rules. So that we may state the following theorem as a corollary to the preceding proofs.
Theorem 5.
Harmonic curves are the sections of ruled surfaces with non-tangent planes. Moreover, harmonic bundles are the projection of rulings from external points, and the tangent bundle of a section of a ruled surface is the projection from the corresponding pole of any of its two rulings. ∎
Finally, we prove the following theorem, making the appropriate remarks to acknowledge Dandelin’s original proof of Pascal’s Hexagon Theorem that inspired our treatment.
Theorem 6.
The Equipal Axiom is equivalent to Pappus’ Theorem.
Proof.
First, we must state Pappus’ Theorem:
The opposite sides of a planar hexagon whose vertices lie alternatively in two lines, meet in three collinear points.
Let and be coplanar lines with points and , so that the hexagon of Pappus’ hypothesis is considered cyclically, and the theorem asserts that the three “Pappus’ points”
where , are collinear.
The hypothesis of Pascal’s Theorem is that the six points named above lie not on two lines, but on a harmonic curve and the conclusion is exactly the same. Dandelin’s proof considers rules ( and , ) through the vertices alternatively in the two rulings of a ruled surface. For the case of Pascal, this would now follow immediately from Theorem 5; for Pappus, we need to work a little more because the plane will turn out to be a tangent one.
Let be a pair of generating lines that meet in respectively. Let so that and let be the rules through respectively. Now, let so that and finally, let be the rule through .
We have defined eight lines of two types or colors, and with , such that all pairs of different color except one do meet, namely, meets for all . The Equipal Axiom implies that and thus, that meets . But moreover, the Equipal Axiom follows if this is always true for this general setting of eight lines, because it implies letting run in all of ; and then moving the ’s around , this implies that extend to the unique ruling .
So, we are left to prove that the Pappus’s points are collinear if and only if and meet, see Figure 11.
Suppose that and meet. Then and , with form a Dandelin configuration. For any such we have that
So that the Pappus’ points may be seen as lines intersecting :
(4) |
for . But these three lines meet pairwise, therefore they lie in a plane that defines the Pappus’ line:
which proves Pappus’ Theorem and, for non-tangent planes constitutes Dandelin’s proof of Pascal’s Theorem.
We are left to prove that Pappus implies the Equipal Axiom which, as we have seen, follows from proving that meets assuming that lie in a line . Observe that (4) still holds for (and ), so that
is a plane because the two lines meet at . It contains the lines
which give us a point . To see that and to conclude the proof, observe that can be seen as the intersection of three planes in two ways; namely, of and . ∎
6 Loose ends on axioms and projectivities.
What we have done in this paper works verbatim in the abstract setting of projective geometry. The included images, which are designed to help the reader to understand intuitively the abstract arguments are, of course, drawn in euclidean 2 and 3 dimensional spaces. However no euclidean arguments are used except for a few statements, e.g., when showing that harmonic curves are conic sections and for the model of the hyperbolic plane (the plane not the group!). Since Projective Geometry has always been ground for considerations about math foundations, we think it is appropriate to close with a few remarks concerning axiomatics and the rigorous mathematical content of our proofs.
The axioms on which our presentation is based and all its theorems are proved are the following. A projective space consists of a ground set, or space, of points with a well defined family of subsets called lines, satisfying:
-
1.
Any two distinct points and lie on a unique line .
-
2.
If are four distinct points and lines and meet, then the lines and also meet.
-
3.
There are two lines that do not meet.
-
4.
Lines have more than two points.
-
5.
The harmonic fourth of three collinear points is neither of them.
-
6.
The Equipal Axiom.
These axioms are a variation of those commonly used (e.g., the ones suggested by Stillwell in [11]). The main difference being the replacement of Pappus’s Theorem by the Equipal (or Double-rulings) Axiom. Axioms 1 and 2 are the fundamental incidence axioms. The statement of Axiom 2 is attributed to Pash and Veblen; it cleverly says that two lines meet if and only if they are coplanar without the need of having planes previously defined. Axiom 3 means the space is at least three dimensional (more than a plane), and it is known to be equivalent to Desargues’ Theorem. Axiom 4 is required for geometry to become interesting and not simply some trivialized set theory.
The two final axioms depend on some further development of the theory; they are not primitive. Axiom 5 guarantees that the ground field is of characteristic different from or, equivalently, that the geometry does not contain the Fano Plane. The characteristic of a projective space can be defined geometrically using the harmonic fourth construction; essentially from how far can one go in a harmonic sequence without returning. It is needed here to make sense of harmonic curves (and that harmonic reflections are not the identity) because it implies that harmonic sets that have exactly four points do exist. Axiom 6 is a required additional principle for geometry to be rich enough to have a deep relation to other classic branches of mathematics like analysis and topology; bellow, we will discuss the several versions it may adopt.
From the first 4 axioms, flats can be defined as the closed subsets under the operation of taking lines, and then, the dimension of a flat is obtained as one less than the number of points needed to generate it; so that planes are defined as flats of dimension 2, [12]. The incidence properties of planes and lines in a space of dimension 3 are obtained from this; and the Hilbert-Cohn Vossen construction of ruled surfaces follows, making sense of the statement of the Equipal Axiom.
Since the Equipal Axiom is equivalent to Pappus’ Theorem, the arithmetization of projective space yields as ground field a commutative one. In [11] commutativity is proved from Pappus’ Theorem and the ground field is described from scratch. The necessity of the axiom is proved by constructing a projective space over a non-commutative field like the quaternions.
Another widely used version of Axiom 6 is as the uniqueness part of the Fundamental Theorem of Projective Geometry. It is usually stated in the context of planar geometry where Axioms 1 and 2 become appealingly dual (and Axiom 3 is false but replaced by Desargues’ Theorem). A projectivity is defined as the composition of projections between (points in) lines or (lines in) concurrent pencils; they are always bijections. It is not hard to construct a projectivity determined by it’s (arbitrary) effect on (any) three elements of it’s domain. This is the existence part of the Fundamental Theorem. However, the uniqueness is proved to be equivalent to Pappus’ Theorem, so one must be assumed to prove the other, see [4], [12].
We think that Axiom 3 is natural because, among other things, it responds and gives credit to the original motivation for the creation of Projective Geometry which is renaissance perspective, for which dimension 3 is quintessential. But then, if one thinks about projectivities between non coplanar lines in a three dimensional projective space, one is naturally lead to consider ruled surfaces. Indeed, given a projectivity from a line to a non coplanar line , the set of lines joining a point in to its image in turns out to be a ruling. So, the Equipal Axiom is intimately related to the uniqueness of projectivities given by three arbitrary values (the projectivity is determined by the extended ruling of three lines). Moreover, this association of a set of lines to a map between lines is also a classic idea. It is the dual of how Jakob Steiner (1796–1863) defined conic curves in a purely projective manner; and is a natural, visual way of presenting them, see e.g., [12].
Projective geometry is remarkable in many ways. One of them is the importance of some mathematical notions that were worked and experimented within it long before their abstract general acknowledgement. For example, projectivities were masterly used almost one century before the notion of sets and the language of abstract functions was stablished; moreover, together they constitute what we now call a groupoid (defined in the mid XX century within category theory). And of course, there is the leading role it played in broadening our notion of geometry and its influence on the dawn of topology. There are many ways to approach it and present it. We hope this paper contributes to the awareness of its cultural significance and the convenience and possibility of finding “its way down into secondary schools”, [8], or at least into early undergraduate courses.
Acknowledgments J. Bracho acknowledges support from PAPIIT-UNAM Project IN109023.
Declarations
The authors declare that there is no conflict of interest.
References
-
[1]
J. L. Abreu, J. Bracho, ProGeo3D; a dynamic geometry system. (2016-2023). https://descartes.matem.unam.mx/ejemplos/pg3d/index.html
Links to the interactive scenes for figures in this article:
https://arquimedes.matem.unam.mx/harmonic_curves/scenes.html -
[2]
J. L. Abreu, J. Bracho, Geometría Visual; las matemáticas que surgen de cómo vemos el mundo (preliminary version). (2023).
https://arquimedes.matem.unam.mx/roli/GeometriaVisual/ - [3] H. S. M. Coxeter, Non-Euclidean Geometry; Toronto University Press (1947).
- [4] H. S. M. Coxeter, Projective Geometry; 2nd Edition; Springer Verlag (1987) and Toronto University Press (1974). First Edition (1964).
- [5] G. P. Dandelin, Memoire sur l’hyperboloïde de révolution, et sur les hexagones de Pascal et de M. Brianchon, Nouveau memoires de l’Académie Royale de Sciences et Belles-Lettres de Bruxelles, T II, p. 3-16, (1826).
- [6] G. Desargues, N. G. Poudra (ed.) Oeuvres de Desargues. Cambridge University Press. (2011).
- [7] D. Hilbert, S. Cohn-Vossen, Geometry and the Imagination, AMS Chelsea Publishing (1952, 1983, 1990). First Edition (1932).
- [8] D. N. Lehmer, An Elementary Course in Synthetic Projective Geometry, CRC Press (2018).
- [9] F. Klein, Erlangen Program: A Comparative review of resent researches in geometry; Translated by Dr. M. W. Haskell. Published in Bull. New York Math. Soc. 2, 215-249, (1892-1893). First published (1872).
- [10] L. A. Santaló, Geometrías no Euclidianas; Editorial Universitaria de Buenos Aires, (1961).
- [11] J. Stillwell, Yearning for the impossible: the surprising truths of mathematics, AK Peters (2006); CRC Press (2018).
- [12] O. Veblen and J. W. Young, Projective Geometry; Ginn and Company, (1910).
- [13] K. G. C. von Staudt, Geometrie der Lage, Vernag der Fr. Korn’schen Buchhandlung, Nürnberg (1847).