This paper was converted on www.awesomepapers.org from LaTeX by an anonymous user.
Want to know more? Visit the Converter page.

[1]\fnmJavier \surBracho

[1]\orgdivInstituto de Matemáticas, \orgnameUniversidad Nacional Autónoma de México, \orgaddress\streetCiudad Universitaria, \cityMexico City, \postcode04510, \countryMexico

Harmonic curves and the beauty of Projective Geometry

\fnmJosé Luis \surAbreu [email protected]    [email protected] *
Abstract

The purpose of this paper is to present projective geometry in a synthetic, visual and intuitive style through the central notion of harmonicity which leads to harmonic curves. This presentation includes new results, unpublished proofs of some classic theorems and a slight reformulation of its axiomatics.

keywords:
Harmonicity, Conic Curves, Ruled Surfaces, Projective Geometry
pacs:
[

MSC Classification]51A05, 97G10, 97G40, 51A30

1 Introduction

A conic curve or section is defined as the intersection of a circular cone with a plane. This concept is inherently metric. However, that conic curves somehow belong to projective geometry is well known, but not clear how. For example, the statement that ellipses are what we see when we look at a circle, which is how we should present them to children, makes many of us unconfortable because we didn’t hear it in class and don’t have a simple proof at hand. Trying to make sense of this incongruent state of affairs, we were lead to define harmonic curves in a purely projective style (they are basically the locus of points in the plane that see a quadrangle as a harmonic set) and study their properties without any reference to metric concepts. Yes, harmonic curves become conic sections in the euclidean plane, but they have a rich set of purely projective properties so that their study constitutes a beautiful approach to projective geometry. Such approach is what this paper is all about.

Motivated by the technics of perspective drawing, which were discovered by the painters of the renaissance to represent realisticly three dimensional scenes on flat canvases, Girard Desargues (1591-1661) initiated the development of Projective Geometry expanding the concept of space to include ideal points (also known as points at infinity), [6]. Mostly forgotten through the following two centuries, his visionary work was revived and recognized as fundamental during the first half of the XIX century, when Projective Geometry was firmly established as a field on its own. In 1872 Felix Klein opened his famous Erlangen Program, [9], with the statement “Among the advances of the last fifty years in the field of geometry, the development of Projective Geometry occupies the first place”. One of the mathematicians whose work deserved such praise is Karl Georg Christian von Staudt (1798-1867). In his treatise on the subject [13], he proves that the notions of harmonicity, i.e. the concepts of harmonic sets and pencils, are entirely projective and independent of metric ones like distances or angles. He also shows that conic curves may be defined through the abstract, and purely projective concept of polarity.

In an attempt to make these facts accesible to high-school teachers, and inspired by [11] where John Stillwell argues that such goal is not only worthwhile and culturally urgent, but also feasible, the authors of this article developed the dynamic geometry system ProGeo3D [1] which is specialized in projective geometry. In particular, it incorporates harmonicity as a construction tool. All the figures of this paper are snapshots of constructions in ProGeo3D. To appreciate their dynamic capacity and the 3D nature of some (e.g., Figure 2.a), we present them in a web site111https://arquimedes.matem.unam.mx/harmonic_curves/scenes.html. Playing with this system, we discovered several interesting constructions, proofs and new results that do not seem to be included in the known literature on the subject. This paper presents them to propose an alternative approach to projective geometry which is intuitive, synthetic and, in our subjective opinion, beautiful.

We start by reviewing von Staudt’s definition of harmonicity, emphasizing the duality it intrinsically carries. That leads us to a simple definition of what we call harmonic curves to differentiate them from the classic treatment of conic sections, although in euclidean space they are the same. In the following section, we relate them to von Staudt’s definition, which uses polarities, but now it must be stated as a theorem, the “Polarity Theorem” (Thm. 2). Its proof uses the classic idea in projective geometry of going out to 3D, finding a way to work out things there, and coming back to 2D. The first to use our explicit technic out in 3D, was Germinal Pierre Dandelin (1794–1847) to prove Pascal’s Hexagon Theorem in [5]. It is deeply related to ruled surfaces as defined by Hilbert and Cohn-Vossen in [7] using only incidence geometry. This suggests the formulation of a new axiom for Projective Geometry, which we call the Equipal Axiom. It is shown to be equivalent to Pappus’ Theorem and thus to other equivalent axioms frequently used in projective geometry. In the final section we discuss the axiomatic foundations of our approach in which the use of 3 dimensions is fundamental.

2 Harmonic sets, pencils and reflections

One of the seminal contributions of Karl von Staudt was to prove that harmonicity (the notion of harmonic conjugates which had been used since antiquity in terms of distances) only depends on incidence using quadrangles.

A quadrangle, 𝒬\mathcal{Q}, is defined as four points in the projective plane in general position (i.e., no three of them are collinear), called its vertices, together with 4 lines, called its sides, such that their incidence relation is a 4-cycle (each object of one type is incident with two of the other); that is, 𝒬\mathcal{Q} is defined by its vertices (4 points in general position) together with a dihedral (i.e., a cyclic but non-oriented) order on them which yields the 4 sides.

The term “quadrangle” is adequate because at any vertex, its two incident lines (an “angle”) distinguish two adjacent vertices and thus, it also determines the opposite vertex (as the remaining one); note that the partition of vertices into opposite pairs determines the quadrangle. The center of the quadrangle 𝒬\mathcal{Q} is the intersection of its two diagonal lines (the lines that join opposite vertices); and its horizon is the line joining the intersection of opposite sides, which are called its two diagonal points.

The notion of a quadrangle is autodual, but in a quadrilateral the stress is given on the 4 sides, so that its dual-center is the horizon of the corresponding quadrangle whose center is the dual-horizon of the quarilateral. However, we will keep the “horizon” and “center” terminology: understood always as a line and a point, respectively. These terms are natural because if a square tile is drawn on a canvas, the center of the tile and the horizon of the square tiling of the plane which it generates should be drawn, respectively, at the center and the horizon of the quadrangle which such a drawing determines.

Four points in general position are the vertices of three quadrangles. Their corresponding centers and horizons form its diagonal triangle.

\begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{armonia_y_dual.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf a)}} \end{overpic}    \begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{harmonic_pencil.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf b)}} \end{overpic}

Figure 1: a) A harmonic set. b) A harmonic pencil with dashed lines.

Four collinear points A,C,B,DA,C,B,D, as in Figure 1.a, are said to be a harmonic set,222The terms “harmonic quadruple” or “harmonic range” are also used, but we stick to “harmonic set” as in the classic texts [12] and [4]. if there exists a quadrangle such that its diagonal points are AA and BB (hence the horizon of the quadrangle is their support line) and the other pair, CC and DD, are incident with the diagonal lines. Dually, four concurrent lines are called a harmonic pencil333The term “harmonic set of lines” is also used, e.g. [12, 4]; but we will use “pencil” for simplicity and to distinguish them immediately from harmonic sets (of points). if there exists a quadrangle such that one pair of lines are the diagonal lines of the quadrangle (hence, its center is the concurrency point of the pencil, also called its center) and the other two lines are incident to the diagonal points of the quadrangle, see Figure 1.b.

As stated, the pairs of elements in the definitions play a different role but, as we will see, they are interchangeable, so that both notions include an explicit dihedral order of the four elements involved, which coincides with their geometric placement (points within a projective line or lines about a point).

Let us now show that these definitions are sound. Given a collinear triple A,C,BA,C,B with CC distinguished, two auxiliary points out of the support line and collinear with CC determine a unique quadrilateral 𝒬\mathcal{Q} as in Figure 1.a, and therefore produce the point DD as the intersection of the other diagonal line with the horizon; this construction, called the harmonic fourth, has as outcome the point DD, called the harmonic conjugate of CC with respect to AA and BB. Since for the triple A,D,BA,D,B, one can choose the other opposite pair of vertices of 𝒬\mathcal{Q} as auxiliary points and then obtain CC as outcome, we can further say that the (unordered) pair of points C,DC,D are harmonic conjugates with respect to A,BA,B, [4, 12].

Theorem 1 (Harmonic Theorem).

The outcome of the harmonic fourth construction does not depend on the choice of the auxiliary points.

The proof is well known and follows from Desargues’ Theorem. It may also be directly proved in 3D using only incidence arguments (see Figure 2.a), and deducing the planar case imediatly from it. We omit the details for brevity.

\begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{harmonic_theorem_in3D.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf a)}} \end{overpic}    \begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{Symmetry_of_harmonicity.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf b)}} \end{overpic}

Figure 2: a) Visual proof of the harmonic theorem in 3D. b) Symmetry of harmonic pairs.

Finally, to see that the definition of harmonic set is symmetric with regard to the role played by the two pairs of points, extend the quadrangle 𝒬\mathcal{Q} to a 2 by 2 tiling drawn in perspective, as in Figure 2.b (the know-how comes from the renaissance artists and the coincidences follow from the Harmonic Theorem). Then, the quadrilateral of (dashed) diagonals not incident with its center OO proves that A,BA,B are harmonic conjugates with respect to C,DC,D.

Since the point OO in Figure 2.b may be chosen to be any point not on the support line of the harmonic set, we obtain that any such point sees them as harmonic, that is, the lines to them with their dihedral order is a harmonic pencil. Dually, there is also a harmonic fourth construction for lines and any line not through the center of a harmonic pencil cuts it in a harmonic set. Thus, harmonic sets and pencils are preserved by projections.

The harmonic fourth construction also makes sense in the singular cases when C=AC=A or C=BC=B. In them, the outside quadrangle collapses to a line, but the diagonals do not collapse and so the construction holds in the sense of not becoming ambiguous, and it yields D=AD=A or D=BD=B, respectively. Therefore, given two (distinct) points AA and BB in a line \ell we get a well defined map

ρA,B:\rho_{A,B}:\ell\to\ell

called the harmonic reflection of \ell with respect to AA and BB: it fixes these two points and it gives the harmonic conjugate elsewhere. ρA,B\rho_{A,B} is an involution which interchanges the two segments in which the points AA and BB divide their projective line. And in particular, it interchanges its ideal point at infinity with the (euclidean) midpoint of AA and BB, making the harmonic fourth construction a very useful tool for perspective drawing.

The natural generalization to the projective plane (space) is the harmonic reflection ρC,m\rho_{C,m} with respect to a point CC, called the center, and a non-incident line (plane) mm, called the mirror.444In the plane, Coxeter calls it harmonic homology in [4]. It is defined on every line \ell through CC as the harmonic reflection with respect to CC and the intersection of \ell with mm. If we denote by \vee, “join”, and \wedge, “meet”, the basic projective operations of linear span and intersection, respectivelly, we may write for XCX\neq C:

XρC,m=XρC,(XC)m,X\cdot\rho_{C,m}=X\cdot\rho_{C,(X\vee C)\wedge m}\,,

where note that we write the action of maps or functions on the right. This notion amalgamates two classic euclidean examples: the central inversions, when the mirror is the line (plane) at infinity, and the reflections when the center is the ideal point in the direction perpendicular to the mirror.

Harmonic reflections are collineations (i.e., they send lines to lines). They act in the dual plane as harmonic reflections in the sense that if \ell is a line different from the mirror mm, then ,m,ρC,m,(m)C\ell,m,{\ell\cdot\rho_{C,m}},{(\ell\wedge m)\vee C} is a harmonic pencil centered at m\ell\wedge m.

Lemma 1 (Klein’s Triangle).

Given a triangle ABCABC with respective opposite sides abcabc, then {id2,ρA,a,ρB,b,ρC,c}\{\,id_{\mathbb{P}^{2}},\rho_{A,a},\rho_{B,b},\rho_{C,c}\,\}5552\,\,\mathbb{P}^{2} is the projective plane and id2id_{\mathbb{P}^{2}} stands for its identity map. is the Klein four-group.

Proof.

Since the three non-trivial elements are involutions, we need only to show that the composition of any two of them gives the third, which is the definition of the Klein four-group. Consider a point XX not in the triangle. We claim that the quadruple {X,XρA,a,XρB,b,XρC,c}\{\,X,X\cdot\rho_{A,a},X\cdot\rho_{B,b},X\cdot\rho_{C,c}\,\} has ABCABC as its diagonal triangle. In Figure 3, the three dashed lines through XX have harmonic sets that define the corresponding three points other than XX. The gray lines from a vertex (say AA) to one of them (say, XρC,cX\cdot\rho_{C,c}) pass through another one (XρB,bX\cdot\rho_{B,b}) because the two corresponding harmonic sets (in CXC\vee X and BXB\vee X) are projected to each other from the vertex (AA) and projections preserve harmonicity.

Refer to caption

Figure 3: Klein’s Triangle Lemma.

It is easy to see that these gray lines through the vertices cut the opposite side in its corresponding harmonic conjugate, and that for points XX in the triangle the maps behave as they should. This completes the proof. ∎

Thus, the generic orbits of the Klein four-group associated to a triangle are the quadruples that have it as diagonal triangle, and any of the four triangular regions in which the three lines cut the projective plane are the fundamental regions of the group action which has the vertices as fixed points.

We define the harmonic group ar(n)\mathcal{H}ar(n) (n=1,2,3n=1,2,3) as the group of transformations generated by the harmonic reflections on n\mathbb{P}^{n}. Of course, they turn out to be the classic groups of projectivities, but this requires proof.

3 Harmonic curves and bundles

We define the harmonic curve, 𝒞𝒬\mathcal{C}_{\mathcal{Q}}, of a quadrangle 𝒬\mathcal{Q} as the locus of points that are centers of harmonic pencils transversal to 𝒬\mathcal{Q}. By transversal we mean that each vertex of 𝒬\mathcal{Q} is incident to a line of the pencil and this correspondence preserves the dihedral orders. Dually, the harmonic bundle of a quadrilateral consists of the lines that support a harmonic set transversal to its sides and with corresponding dihedral orders.

\begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{Quadrangle_with_tangent_lines_to_its_harmonic_curve.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf a)}} \end{overpic}    \begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{curva_de_armonia.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf b)}} \end{overpic}

Figure 4: a) Quadrangle 𝒬\mathcal{Q} with tangent lines to its harmonic curve 𝒞𝒬\mathcal{C}_{\mathcal{Q}} at its vertices. b) Generic point Z𝒞𝒬Z\in\mathcal{C}_{\mathcal{Q}}, where A,X,B,YA,X,B,Y is a harmonic set in ABA\vee B.

Consider a quadrangle 𝒬\mathcal{Q} with vertices A,C,B,DA,C,B,D. First observe that the vertices are points of its harmonic curve 𝒞𝒬\mathcal{C}_{\mathcal{Q}}. Indeed, for each vertex, the harmonic conjugate of its diagonal with respect to its sides completes a harmonic pencil centered at it which is transversal to 𝒬\mathcal{Q}, see Figure 4.a. These new lines are the tangent lines to 𝒞𝒬\mathcal{C}_{\mathcal{Q}} at the vertices and will be denoted by the corresponding lower case letter. The harmonic bundle of the quadrilateral a,c,b,da,c,b,d is called the tangent bundle of 𝒞𝒬\mathcal{C}_{\mathcal{Q}} and will be denoted 𝒞𝒬\mathcal{C}_{\mathcal{Q}}^{*}.

Now consider a point Z𝒞𝒬Z\in\mathcal{C}_{\mathcal{Q}} different from the vertices, we call it generic, see Figure 4.b. By definition, the four lines from ZZ to the vertices are a harmonic pencil centered at ZZ. Let X=(AB)(CZ)X=(A\vee B)\wedge(C\vee Z) and Y=(AB)(DZ)Y=(A\vee B)\wedge(D\vee Z). Then A,X,B,YA,X,B,Y is a harmonic set. Therefore, we can recover ZZ from XABX\in A\vee B by defining

Y=XρA,BandZ=(CX)(DY).Y=X\cdot\rho_{A,B}\quad\text{and}\quad Z=(C\vee X)\wedge(D\vee Y)\,. (1)

But this makes sense for XX ranging over all of ABA\vee B and gives the four vertices (at a harmonic set), so that 𝒞𝒬\mathcal{C}_{\mathcal{Q}} is parametrized by X(AB)X\in(A\vee B) via this construction. We call this the HC-construction.

Lemma 2 (Duality lemma).

Points in the harmonic curve 𝒞𝒬\mathcal{C}_{\mathcal{Q}} are paired (i.e., in bijective correspondence) by incidence with lines in its tangent bundle 𝒞𝒬\mathcal{C}_{\mathcal{Q}}^{*}.

Proof.

Let us continue with the notation above, so that a,c,b,da,c,b,d, is the quadrilateral whose harmonic bundle is 𝒞𝒬\mathcal{C}_{\mathcal{Q}}^{*}. As before, these four generating lines belong to the bundle because the vertex to which they are tangent (called their contact point) can be obtained as the harmonic fourth of their intersection to the other three lines (see Figure 4.a). Going further on the HC-construction (1), and dualizing it (see Figure 5): let Q=abQ=a\wedge b, x=QYx=Q\vee Y and y=QXy=Q\vee X, so that a,x,b,ya,x,b,y is generically a harmonic pencil centered at QQ. Then, z=(cx)(dy)z=(c\wedge x)\vee(d\wedge y) is a line of the bundle 𝒞𝒬\mathcal{C}_{\mathcal{Q}}^{*}, and any such line is uniquely expressed in this way.

Refer to caption

Figure 5: Incidence of points in a harmonic curve and lines in its tangent bundle.

To prove that ZzZ\in z for XX different from AA and BB, define q=ABq=A\vee B and consider the triangle QXYQXY with respective opposite sides qxyqxy. By the definitions, we have D=CρQ,qD=C\cdot\rho_{Q,q} (d=cρQ,qd=c\cdot\rho_{Q,q}), and by Klein’s Triangle Lemma, ρX,x=ρQ,qρY,y\rho_{X,x}=\rho_{Q,q}\cdot\rho_{Y,y}, then CρX,x=DρY,yC\cdot\rho_{X,x}=D\cdot\rho_{Y,y} (cρX,x=dρY,yc\cdot\rho_{X,x}=d\cdot\rho_{Y,y}). But CρX,xCXC\cdot\rho_{X,x}\in C\vee X and DρY,yDYD\cdot\rho_{Y,y}\in D\vee Y, so that CρX,x=(CX)(DY)=ZC\cdot\rho_{X,x}=(C\vee X)\wedge(D\vee Y)=Z (dually, cρX,x=zc\cdot\rho_{X,x}=z). Hence, the fact that CcC\in c, implies that ZzZ\in z as we wished. ZZ is called the contact point of z𝒞𝒬z\in\mathcal{C}_{\mathcal{Q}}^{*} which is the tangent line to 𝒞𝒬\mathcal{C}_{\mathcal{Q}} at ZZ. ∎

As a corollary, we can express the harmonic curve 𝒞𝒬\mathcal{C}_{\mathcal{Q}} as a family of harmonic reflections applied to a single point

𝒞𝒬={CρX,x|X(AB){A,B}}{A,B},\mathcal{C}_{\mathcal{Q}}=\{\,C\cdot\rho_{X,x}\,|\,X\in(A\vee B)\setminus\{A,B\}\,\}\cup\{A,B\}\,, (2)

where x=(XρA,B)(ab)x=(X\cdot\rho_{A,B})\vee(a\wedge b), which only depends on three points A,C,BA,C,B and the two tangent lines a,ba,b incident to A,BA,B, respectively; we will call this, the A-construction.

Clearly, harmonic curves are sent to harmonic curves under projections because projections preserve harmonicity. So that the fact that the classic conic sections are harmonic curves follows from the fact that a circle is a harmonic curve. Indeed, consider an inscribed square to a circle as a quadrangle. Use the inscribed angle theorem to see that each point in the circle is the center of a transversal pencil to the quadrangle with consecutive lines at angles π4{\pi}\over{4}, which is a harmonic pencil.

4 Polarities and hyperbolic geometry

A polarity in the plane (in space) is a bijective correspondence between points and lines (planes) that preserves incidence; the terms polar of a point, pole of a line (plane) or a polar pair are used666An extra hypothesis is required in [4]. Namely, that for some line, the map to the line pencil of its pole be a projectivity. But we do not need to stress this issue..

Theorem 2 (Polarity).

A harmonic curve 𝒞\mathcal{C} induces a polarity (expressed by upper and lower case of the same letter) satisfying:

  • i)

    P𝒞Pp.P\in\mathcal{C}\Leftrightarrow P\in p\,.

  • ii)

    If P𝒞P\not\in\mathcal{C} then the harmonic reflection ρP,p\rho_{P,p}, with PP as center and its non-incident polar line pp as mirror, leaves 𝒞\mathcal{C} invariant.

We have already seen a part of item (i) as Lemma 2 because tangent lines to points in a harmonic curve are defined as their polar lines. The rest of the proof will be given in the next section as a consequence of an analogue in 3D, Theorem 4. For the moment, let us make two remarks about this theorem and, assuming it is true, explore some of its profound consequences.

The two mathematicians that father this theorem are Jean-Victor Poncelet (1788-1867) and Karl G. C. von Staudt (1798-1867). Poncelet proved the relation of poles and polars for conic sections using harmonicity (in its metric version), and soon after, von Staudt developed polarities as a general concept and used it as an alternative way to define conic curves within projective geometry with no metric or algebraic considerations, [13]. This definition via polarities is the one Coxeter uses in his influential book [4], and calls it “extraordinarily natural and symmetrical” because it has duality built into it. In general, there are two types of polarities: euclidian in which no point is incident with its polar line, and hyperbolic when there exist pole and polar incident pairs. The terms used are related to the groups generated by harmonic reflections of non-incident polar pairs. So that von Staudt’s definition of a conic curve is equivalent to item (i) of the theorem for a hyperbolic polarity, while Poncelet’s results can be rephrased as item (ii).

As examples of polar pairs, we have named lines and points in Figure 5 according to the upper and lower case rule for poles and polars with respect to the displayed harmonic curve 𝒞𝒬\mathcal{C}_{\mathcal{Q}}. Indeed, a point Z𝒞𝒬Z\in\mathcal{C}_{\mathcal{Q}} and the corresponding line in z𝒞𝒬z\in\mathcal{C}_{\mathcal{Q}}^{*} described in Lemma 2 constitute a polar pair satisfying (i).

We now prove that von Staudt’s definition of conic curves with mild extra hypothesis gives harmonic curves.

Lemma 3.

Given a polarity in the plane, let 𝒞\mathcal{C} be the set of points that are incident to their polar line and suppose item (ii) of Theorem 2 holds. If every line meets 𝒞\mathcal{C} in at most two points and 𝒞\mathcal{C} contains at least three points, then 𝒞\mathcal{C} is a harmonic curve.

Proof.

Let A,B,C𝒞A,B,C\in\mathcal{C} be three points. By the hypothesis on the lines, they are not collinear. Let a,ba,b be the respective polar lines of A,BA,B, so that AaA\in a and BbB\in b. Let Q=abQ=a\wedge b; it is the pole of q=ABq=A\vee B because polarities preserve incidence, which also implies that QqQ\not\in q. Finally, let 𝒬\mathcal{Q} be the quadrangle A,C,B,D=CρQ,qA,C,B,D=C\cdot\rho_{Q,q}. To conclude the proof we show that 𝒞=𝒞𝒬\mathcal{C}=\mathcal{C}_{\mathcal{Q}}.

Given Xq{A,B}X\in q\setminus\{\,A,B\,\}, its polar, xx, is a line through QQ different from aa and bb. Let Y=xqY=x\wedge q. Then, since ρX,x\rho_{X,x} leaves qq and 𝒞\mathcal{C} invariant and q𝒞={A,B}q\cap\mathcal{C}=\{\,A,B\,\}, it transposes AA and BB, so that X,A,Y,BX,A,Y,B is a harmonic set. Since the polarity satisfies (ii) of Theorem 2, CρX,x𝒞C\cdot\rho_{X,x}\in\mathcal{C}, so that the A-construction (2) for 𝒞𝒬\mathcal{C}_{\mathcal{Q}} implies that 𝒞Q𝒞\mathcal{C}_{Q}\subset\mathcal{C}. Finally, given Z𝒞Z\in\mathcal{C} different from A,B,CA,B,C, let X=(ZC)qX=(Z\vee C)\wedge q, then Z=CρX,xZ=C\cdot\rho_{X,x} because the line ZCZ\vee C has no point in 𝒞\mathcal{C} other than ZZ and CC by hypothesis. Therefore, 𝒞Q=𝒞\mathcal{C}_{Q}=\mathcal{C}. ∎

As a corollary to the proof of this lemma (and assuming the Polarity Theorem) we can now say which quadrangles 𝒬\mathcal{Q} inscribed in a harmonic curve 𝒞\mathcal{C} generate it as its harmonic curve, that is, are such that 𝒞𝒬=𝒞\mathcal{C}_{\mathcal{Q}}=\mathcal{C}. Precisely the ones in which the pole of one diagonal line lies in the other diagonal. And moreover, for any triplet of points A,C,BA,C,B (with CC distinguished) in 𝒞\mathcal{C}, we have such a quadrangle A,C,B,D=Cρ(ab),(AB)A,C,B,D=C\cdot\rho_{(a\wedge b),(A\vee B)}.

The abstract resemblance of these facts to the harmonic fourth construction and the existence of harmonic sets in the projective line lead to the theorem stated and proved bellow. But we must also remark that it is deeply related to the projective model of the hyperbolic plane due to Beltrami and Klein, which he used as an important example for his Erlangen Program, [9].

If we fix a harmonic curve 𝒞\mathcal{C}, any two points A,BA,B in 𝒞\mathcal{C} define a hyperbolic line q=ABq=A\vee B and a hyperbolic reflection ηq=ρQ,q\eta_{q}=\rho_{Q,q} where QQ is the pole of qq.

Then we have a subgroup yp(2)\mathcal{H}yp(2) of ar(2)\mathcal{H}ar(2), called the hyperbolic group, which is generated by all the hyperbolic reflections ηq\eta_{q} on hyperbolic lines. This group acts on the inside of the harmonic curve 𝒞\mathcal{C} which is taken as the hyperbolic plane for the Beltrami-Klein model, and hyperbolic geometry can be built from there, but we have no space here to follow it through; for such treatments see, e.g., [3, 10, 2] . However, we should remark that the generating quadrangles of 𝒞\mathcal{C} have as diagonals the pairs of perpendicular hyperbolic lines.

The usual way to state the following theorem is in the context of the upper half plane model of the hyperbolic plane and referring to matrix groups.

Theorem 3.

yp(2)ar(1)\,\,\mathcal{H}yp(2)\cong\mathcal{H}ar(1).

Proof.

First, we define the tangential map from 𝒞\mathcal{C} to a tangent line, Figure 6.a. Let TT be a point in 𝒞\mathcal{C} and let tt be its tangent (or polar) line. For every X𝒞X\in\mathcal{C} other than TT, let X=txX^{\prime}=t\wedge x, where xx is the tangent line to 𝒞\mathcal{C} at XX. Taking T=TT=T^{\prime}, this gives a bijective map XXX\leftrightarrow X^{\prime} between 𝒞\mathcal{C} and tt, because xx^{\prime} (the polar of XtX^{\prime}\in t) cuts 𝒞\mathcal{C} in TT and XX for XTX^{\prime}\neq T, see Figure 6.a.

\begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{tangential_map.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf a)}} \end{overpic}    \begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{generating_quadrangle.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf b)}} \end{overpic}

Figure 6: a) Tangential map. b) A generating quadrangle in 𝒞\mathcal{C} and its corresponding harmonic set in tt.

Considering tt as 1\mathbb{P}^{1}, the theorem follows from the fact that generating quadrangles of 𝒞\mathcal{C} and harmonic sets of tt correspond to each other, because then harmonic reflections and hyperbolic reflections (the generators of the groups) correspond under the tangential map.

Let A,C,B,DA,C,B,D be a generating quadrangle of 𝒞\mathcal{C}, and let a,c,b,da,c,b,d be their respective tangent lines. By Lemma 2, the harmonic bundle of this quadrilateral is the tangent bundle of 𝒞\mathcal{C} and it contains tt. Therefore, by the definition of harmonic bundles, we have that A,C,B,DA^{\prime},C^{\prime},B^{\prime},D^{\prime} is a harmonic set, see Figure 6.b. ∎

This proof was the primal motivation for our definition of harmonic curves.

5 Doubly ruled surfaces

The following proof of the Polarity Theorem (2) is inspired by Dandelin’s proof of Pascal’s Hexagonal Theorem. Given a conic curve, Dandelin constructs, in [5], a hyperboloid of revolution that has it as a plane section; then, using the fact that this surface is doubly-ruled, he obtains a configuration of 6 lines in three dimensional space associated to the six points of the hexagon in the conic, and argues with the geometric-combinatorial properties of the configuration to conclude the proof. We use the same general idea and get to the same configuration of 6 lines, but instead of hyperboloids of revolution we can now use general ruled surfaces following Hilbert and Cohn-Vossen’s construction of ruled surfaces in [7], which appeared in print almost a century after Dandelin’s proof, and made clear that they can be constructed by simple incidence arguments.

Consider two lines aa and bb in three dimensional projective space. They touch if and only if they are coplanar. If this is not the case, they can be called a generating pair because for any point XX not in them, there exists a unique line through XX transversal (i.e., with a common point) to aa and bb; namely:

(Xa)(Xb).(X\vee a)\wedge(X\vee b)\,.

Now consider three lines aa, bb, cc in general position (i.e., each pair is generating, or equivalently, no pair of them is coplanar). The transversal ruling to a,b,ca,b,c, denoted (a,b,c)\mathcal{R}(a,b,c), is the set of lines that are transversal to them (i.e., that touch all three); any such set of lines will be called a ruling and its elements are called its rules, see Figure 8.a. If we denote =(a,b,c)\mathcal{R}=\mathcal{R}(a,b,c), the above observation implies that \mathcal{R} is parametrized by incidence with the points in any of the three generating lines (through any point in them there passes a unique rule). It will be important to note that, dually, \mathcal{R} is also parametrized by planes containing one of the lines; if we denote planes by greek letters (points and lines are, respectivelly, upper and lower case latin) we have, for example, that

(a,b,c)={(bα)(cα)|aα}.\mathcal{R}(a,b,c)=\{\,(b\wedge\alpha)\vee(c\wedge\alpha)\,|\,a\subset\alpha\,\}\,. (3)

\begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{blue_ruling.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf a)}} \end{overpic}    \begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{red_ruling.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf b)}} \end{overpic}

Figure 7: a) The transversal ruling by blue lines to three red lines. b) The transversal ruling to any three blue rules contains the three original red lines.

Every pair of rules in \mathcal{R} is generating, otherwise, their three transversal lines a,b,ca,b,c would be coplanar. Thus, for any triplet a,b,ca^{\prime},b^{\prime},c^{\prime}\in\mathcal{R} we get a transversal rulling (a,b,c)\mathcal{R}(a^{\prime},b^{\prime},c^{\prime}) that contains the original three lines, a,b,ca,b,c; this ruling is an extension of a,b,ca,b,c, see Figure 8.b. In real projective space there is only one extension to a ruling of three lines in general position, but this is not true in all projectives spaces. In what follows we will assume that our projective space does have this property, that is, we will assume it as an axiom:

Equipal Axiom.777Equipal is a classic mexican style of furniture that uses double rulings for bases, [2]. Three lines in general position belong to a unique ruling.

Later on we will prove it is equivalent to Pappus’ Theorem and thus to other classic statements that are commonly adopted as axioms in projective geometry. Another name for it could be the “Double-ruling Axiom” because it immediately implies that rulings are matched or paired: any ruling has an opposite ruling which is the transversal ruling to any three of its rules. The doubly-ruled surface (we also refer to it simply as a ruled surface) obtained as the union of the rules in any such ruling is also the union of the rules in its opposite ruling.

Hence, every point on a ruled surface has a tangent plane, the one generated by the unique rules through the point in the opposite rulings of the surface.

Theorem 4 (Polarity of ruled surfaces).

The pairing of points in a ruled surface 𝒮\mathcal{S} with their tangent planes extends to a polarity of projective space. Furthermore, if P𝒮P\not\in\mathcal{S} then PP is not incident with its polar plane π\pi and the harmonic reflection ρP,π\rho_{P,\pi}, with PP as center and π\pi as mirror, leaves 𝒮\mathcal{S} invariant.

Proof.

The ruled surface 𝒮\mathcal{S} has two opposite rulings \mathcal{R} and \mathcal{R}^{\prime} such that

𝒮=xx=yy.\mathcal{S}=\bigcup_{x\in\mathcal{R}}x=\bigcup_{y\in\mathcal{R}^{\prime}}y\,.

To define the polarity induced by 𝒮\mathcal{S} in its complement, fix three rules a,b,ca,b,c in the ruling \mathcal{R}, and beware that we have inverted the notational use of primes: their transversal ruling is now =(a,b,c)\mathcal{R}^{\prime}=\mathcal{R}(a,b,c).

Consider a point P𝒮P\not\in\mathcal{S}; dually, we could start with a non-tangent plane.

Let α=aP\alpha=a\vee P. There is a well defined rule aa^{\prime}\in\mathcal{R}^{\prime} for which Paa=αP\in a\vee a^{\prime}=\alpha (namely, a=(bα)(cα)a^{\prime}=(b\wedge\alpha)\vee(c\wedge\alpha), as in (3)). Let A=aa𝒮A=a\wedge a^{\prime}\in\mathcal{S}. Observe that AA must be in the polar plane of PP because polarities preserve incidence and PP is in the polar plane of AA.

Analougously, we obtain b,cb^{\prime},c^{\prime}\in\mathcal{R}^{\prime}, for which Pbb=βP\in b\vee b^{\prime}=\beta and Pcc=γP\in c\vee c^{\prime}=\gamma. Let B=bbB=b\wedge b^{\prime} and C=ccC=c\wedge c^{\prime}, so that the polar plane to PP has to be

π=ABC.\pi=A\vee B\vee C\,.

\begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{polar_plane_of_point_with_respect_to_ruled_surface.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf a)}} \end{overpic}    \begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{dandelin_configuration_from_ruled_surface.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf b)}} \end{overpic}

Figure 8: a) Polar plane π\pi of a point P𝒮P\not\in\mathcal{S} with respect to a ruled surface 𝒮\mathcal{S}. b) Dandelin configuration.

If we had started, dually, with a non tangent plane π\pi we would have found PP as the intersection of the three tangent planes at A=aπA=a\wedge\pi, B=bπB=b\wedge\pi, C=cπC=c\wedge\pi; and a,b,ca^{\prime},b^{\prime},c^{\prime} would be the rules in \mathcal{R}^{\prime} passing through A,B,CA,B,C respectively. So that the pairing of points and planes is now well defined.

We have distinguished what we will call a Dandelin configuration: six lines of two types or colors, three of each, a,b,ca,b,c and a,b,ca^{\prime},b^{\prime},c^{\prime}—unprimed and primed in the text, red and blue in the pictures as in Figure 8.b— such that a pair of them touch if and only if they have opposite types. This produces nine basic points and nine tangent planes by the “meet” (\wedge) or “join” (\vee) of lines of different colors; but it also comes with a derived configuration of other lines and planes that naturally arise from them. The geometric richness of this configuration, closely related to the combinatorics of 3×33\times 3 determinants, is what Dandelin exploited in [5]; and we follow suit.

Now, we will prove that the harmonic reflection, ρP,π\rho_{P,\pi}, with center PP and mirror π\pi interchanges the lines a,b,ca,b,c respectively with a,b,ca^{\prime},b^{\prime},c^{\prime} in the opposite ruling. By the triangular symmetry of the construction, it will sufffice to prove that:

\bullet in the tangent plane to AA, α=aa{\alpha=a\vee a^{\prime}}, the lines a,AP,a,απa,A\vee P,a^{\prime},\alpha\wedge\pi are a harmonic pencil centered at AA.

Because this happens if and only if ρP,π\rho_{P,\pi} interchanges the lines aa and aa^{\prime}.

Refer to caption

Figure 9: The Dandelin configuration given by the point P𝒮P\not\in\mathcal{S} with the harmonic pencil a,AP,a,AR=απa,A\vee P,a^{\prime},A\vee R=\alpha\wedge\pi in the plane α=aa\alpha=a\vee a^{\prime}.

The tangent plane α=aa\alpha=a\vee a^{\prime} contains five of the nine basic points of our Dandelin configuration. Namely, the α\alpha-quadrangle:

ab,ba,ac,ca,a\wedge b^{\prime},b\wedge a^{\prime},a\wedge c^{\prime},c\wedge a^{\prime}\,,

with its center AA and its diagonals are aa and aa^{\prime}. The remaining four basic points outside of α\alpha, break naturally into two pairs whose generated lines are incident with the two diagonal points of the α\alpha-quadrangle. This follows because these diagonal points can be seen as the intersection of three tangent planes. Namely, P=αβγ{P=\alpha\wedge\beta\wedge\gamma} and R=α(bc)(cb)=α(BC)απR=\alpha\wedge(b\vee c^{\prime})\wedge(c\vee b^{\prime})=\alpha\wedge(B\vee C)\in\alpha\wedge\pi (see Figure 9).

Thus, ρP,π\rho_{P,\pi} interchanges the rules aa and aa^{\prime}. Analogously, it interchanges bb with bb^{\prime} and cc with cc^{\prime}. Then, it gives a bijection between the transversal rulings of a,b,ca,b,c and a,b,ca^{\prime},b^{\prime},c^{\prime}, which are \mathcal{R}^{\prime} and \mathcal{R} respectively, because a line transversal to a,b,ca,b,c is sent by ρP,π\rho_{P,\pi} to a line transversal to a,b,ca^{\prime},b^{\prime},c^{\prime} and viceversa. Therefore, ρP,π\rho_{P,\pi} leaves 𝒮\mathcal{S} invariant, as we wished to prove.

In particular, since a harmonic reflection sends a line to a line concurrent with the mirror and coplanar with the center, our definition of the polarity does not depend on the choice of generating rules a,b,ca,b,c.

Finally, the proof that the polarity we have defined preserves incidence follows in cases, but in a straightforward manner from the fact that if the tangent plane to a point in 𝒮\mathcal{S}, say AA as above, contains a point not in 𝒮\mathcal{S}, say PP, then the polar plane of PP contains AA. ∎

Observe that, because of the incidence invariance, the polarity extends naturally to a pairing of lines. The polar of a line \ell is the intersection of all the polar planes of its points, or of any two of them.

This polarity theorem asserts that what one sees as the contour of a ruled surface is exactly its section with the polar plane of the viewpoint. Sections and the contour of projections coincide. We now prove that sections of ruled surfaces are harmonic curves, and that the corresponding harmonic bundle is the projection from the pole of any one of the two rulings.

Proof of Theorem 2. Consider a harmonic curve, 𝒞\mathcal{C}, in a plane π\pi. Our basic aim is to prove that

\bullet there exists a ruled surface 𝒮\mathcal{S} that has 𝒞\mathcal{C} as a section,

that is, such that 𝒞=𝒮π\mathcal{C}=\mathcal{S}\cap\pi. This will induce the desired polarity in π\pi to complete the proof of the theorem.

By definition, 𝒞\mathcal{C} is the harmonic curve of a quadrangle A,C,B,DA,C,B,D. Let aa and bb be the tangents at AA and BB, respectively; and let Q=abQ=a\wedge b, q=ABq=A\vee B. We know that D=CρQ,qD=C\cdot\rho_{Q,q} and that 𝒞\mathcal{C} is obtained by the A-construction (2).

Choose two points PP and SS not in π\pi and colinear with QQ (see Figure 10.a).

Let S=SρP,QS^{\prime}=S\cdot\rho_{P,Q}. Since SSS\neq S^{\prime}, the four lines from SS and SS^{\prime} to AA and BB can be colored red and blue so that only lines of opposite colors touch. Finally, consider the red (blue) line through CC transversal to the two blue (red) lines. We now have a Dandelin configuration of six lines colored red and blue: let 𝒮\mathcal{S} be the doubly ruled surface it defines (Figure 10.b). By construction, PP and π\pi are a polar pair with respect to 𝒮\mathcal{S}.

\begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{A_Dandelin_conf_from_A_constr_of_harm_curve.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf a)}} \end{overpic}    \begin{overpic}[abs,width=173.56198pt]{Ruled_surface_from_A_constr_of_harm_curve.png} \put(-5.0,0.0){\hbox{\pagecolor{white}\small\bf b)}} \end{overpic}

Figure 10: a) A Dandelin configuration arising from the input of the A-construction of 𝒞\mathcal{C} in a plane π\pi. b) The corresponding ruled surface that intersects π\pi in 𝒞\mathcal{C}.

The polarity induced by 𝒮\mathcal{S} restricts naturally to a polarity in the plane π\pi as follows. The polar line of a point in π\pi is the intersection of its polar plane with π\pi, and the pole of a line in π\pi is the pole of the plane it generates with PP —or the intersection with π\pi of its polar line. In particular, item (i) of Theorem 2 follows for 𝒮π\mathcal{S}\cap\pi.

Since harmonic reflections preserve the planes through their center, those for non-incident polar pairs with pole in π\pi, restrict to harmonic reflections of π\pi that leave 𝒮π\mathcal{S}\cap\pi invariant. Therefore, item (ii) of Theorem 2 follows for 𝒮π\mathcal{S}\cap\pi.

That 𝒞=𝒮π\mathcal{C}=\mathcal{S}\cap\pi now follows from Lemma 3 and its proof (identifying A,B,CA,B,C in both settings) because a line that intersects 𝒮\mathcal{S} in three different points is easily seen to be a rule of 𝒮\mathcal{S} and π\pi contains no such rules. ∎

Observe that, within the above framework, for any point in 𝒮π\mathcal{S}\cap\pi the intersection with π\pi of its tangent plane to 𝒮\mathcal{S} is the projection to π\pi from PP of any of its two rules. So that we may state the following theorem as a corollary to the preceding proofs.

Theorem 5.

Harmonic curves are the sections of ruled surfaces with non-tangent planes. Moreover, harmonic bundles are the projection of rulings from external points, and the tangent bundle of a section of a ruled surface is the projection from the corresponding pole of any of its two rulings. ∎

Finally, we prove the following theorem, making the appropriate remarks to acknowledge Dandelin’s original proof of Pascal’s Hexagon Theorem that inspired our treatment.

Theorem 6.

The Equipal Axiom is equivalent to Pappus’ Theorem.

Proof.

First, we must state Pappus’ Theorem:

\bullet The opposite sides of a planar hexagon whose vertices lie alternatively in two lines, meet in three collinear points.

Let a0a_{0} and b0b_{0} be coplanar lines with points B1,B2,B3a0B_{1},B_{2},B_{3}\in a_{0} and A1,A2,A3b0A_{1},A_{2},A_{3}\in b_{0}, so that the hexagon of Pappus’ hypothesis is A1,B2,A3,B1,A2,B3A_{1},B_{2},A_{3},B_{1},A_{2},B_{3} considered cyclically, and the theorem asserts that the three “Pappus’ points

Pi=(AjBk)(AkBj),P_{i}=(A_{j}\vee B_{k})\wedge(A_{k}\vee B_{j})\,,

where {i,j,k}={1,2,3}\{i,j,k\}=\{1,2,3\}, are collinear.

The hypothesis of Pascal’s Theorem is that the six points named above lie not on two lines, but on a harmonic curve and the conclusion is exactly the same. Dandelin’s proof considers rules (aia_{i} and bib_{i}, i=1,2,3i=1,2,3) through the vertices alternatively in the two rulings of a ruled surface. For the case of Pascal, this would now follow immediately from Theorem 5; for Pappus, we need to work a little more because the plane π=a0b0\pi=a_{0}\vee b_{0} will turn out to be a tangent one.

Let a1,a2a_{1},a_{2} be a pair of generating lines that meet π\pi in A1,A2A_{1},A_{2} respectively. Let =(a0,a1,a2)\mathcal{R}^{\prime}=\mathcal{R}(a_{0},a_{1},a_{2}) so that b0b_{0}\in\mathcal{R}^{\prime} and let b1,b2,b3b_{1},b_{2},b_{3}\in\mathcal{R}^{\prime} be the rules through B1,B2,B3B_{1},B_{2},B_{3} respectively. Now, let =(b0,b1,b2)\mathcal{R}=\mathcal{R}(b_{0},b_{1},b_{2}) so that a0,a1,a2a_{0},a_{1},a_{2}\in\mathcal{R} and finally, let a3a_{3}\in\mathcal{R} be the rule through A3b0A_{3}\in b_{0}.

We have defined eight lines of two types or colors, aia_{i} and bjb_{j} with 0i,j30\leq i,j\leq 3, such that all pairs of different color except one do meet, namely, aia_{i} meets bjb_{j} for all i3ji\neq 3\neq j. The Equipal Axiom implies that =(b0,b1,b3)\mathcal{R}=\mathcal{R}(b_{0},b_{1},b_{3}) and thus, that a3a_{3}\in\mathcal{R} meets b3b_{3}. But moreover, the Equipal Axiom follows if this is always true for this general setting of eight lines, because it implies =(b0,b1,b3)\mathcal{R}=\mathcal{R}(b_{0},b_{1},b_{3}) letting a3a_{3} run in all of \mathcal{R}; and then moving the bjb_{j}’s around \mathcal{R}^{\prime}, this implies that a0,a1,a2a_{0},a_{1},a_{2} extend to the unique ruling \mathcal{R}.

Refer to caption

Figure 11: A Dandelin configuration over a plane with a Pappus configuration.

So, we are left to prove that the Pappus’s points P1,P2,P3P_{1},P_{2},P_{3} are collinear if and only if a3a_{3} and b3b_{3} meet, see Figure 11.

Suppose that a3a_{3} and b3b_{3} meet. Then aia_{i} and bjb_{j}, with i,j{1,2,3}i,j\in\{1,2,3\} form a Dandelin configuration. For any such i,ji,j we have that

AiBj=(aibj)π.A_{i}\vee B_{j}=(a_{i}\vee b_{j})\wedge\pi\,.

So that the Pappus’ points may be seen as lines intersecting π\pi:

Pi=((ajbk)(akbj))π=((ajbj)(akbk))π,P_{i}=((a_{j}\vee b_{k})\wedge(a_{k}\vee b_{j}))\wedge\pi=((a_{j}\wedge b_{j})\vee(a_{k}\wedge b_{k}))\wedge\pi\,, (4)

for {i,j,k}={1,2,3}\{i,j,k\}=\{1,2,3\}. But these three lines meet pairwise, therefore they lie in a plane that defines the Pappus’ line:

p=((a1b1)(a2b2)(a3b3))π,p=((a_{1}\wedge b_{1})\vee(a_{2}\wedge b_{2})\vee(a_{3}\wedge b_{3}))\wedge\pi\,,

which proves Pappus’ Theorem and, for non-tangent planes π\pi constitutes Dandelin’s proof of Pascal’s Theorem.

We are left to prove that Pappus implies the Equipal Axiom which, as we have seen, follows from proving that a3a_{3} meets b3b_{3} assuming that P1,P2,P3P_{1},P_{2},P_{3} lie in a line pπp\subset\pi. Observe that (4) still holds for i=3i=3 (and {j,k}={1,2}\{j,k\}=\{1,2\}), so that

δ=p((a1b1)(a2b2))\delta=p\vee((a_{1}\wedge b_{1})\vee(a_{2}\wedge b_{2}))\,

is a plane because the two lines meet at P3P_{3}. It contains the lines

1=P1(a2b2)and2=P2(a1b1),\ell_{1}=P_{1}\vee(a_{2}\wedge b_{2})\quad\text{and}\quad\ell_{2}=P_{2}\vee(a_{1}\wedge b_{1})\,,

which give us a point W=12W=\ell_{1}\wedge\ell_{2}. To see that Wa3W\in a_{3} and Wb3W\in b_{3} to conclude the proof, observe that WW can be seen as the intersection of three planes in two ways; namely, of δ,(a3b1),(a3b2)\delta,(a_{3}\vee b_{1}),(a_{3}\vee b_{2}) and δ,(a1b3),(a2b3)\delta,(a_{1}\vee b_{3}),(a_{2}\vee b_{3}). ∎

6 Loose ends on axioms and projectivities.

What we have done in this paper works verbatim in the abstract setting of projective geometry. The included images, which are designed to help the reader to understand intuitively the abstract arguments are, of course, drawn in euclidean 2 and 3 dimensional spaces. However no euclidean arguments are used except for a few statements, e.g., when showing that harmonic curves are conic sections and for the model of the hyperbolic plane (the plane not the group!). Since Projective Geometry has always been ground for considerations about math foundations, we think it is appropriate to close with a few remarks concerning axiomatics and the rigorous mathematical content of our proofs.

The axioms on which our presentation is based and all its theorems are proved are the following. A projective space consists of a ground set, or space, of points with a well defined family of subsets called lines, satisfying:

  1. 1.

    Any two distinct points AA and BB lie on a unique line ABA\vee B.

  2. 2.

    If A,B,C,DA,B,C,D are four distinct points and lines ABA\vee B and CDC\vee D meet, then the lines ACA\vee C and BDB\vee D also meet.

  3. 3.

    There are two lines that do not meet.

  4. 4.

    Lines have more than two points.

  5. 5.

    The harmonic fourth of three collinear points is neither of them.

  6. 6.

    The Equipal Axiom.

These axioms are a variation of those commonly used (e.g., the ones suggested by Stillwell in [11]). The main difference being the replacement of Pappus’s Theorem by the Equipal (or Double-rulings) Axiom. Axioms 1 and 2 are the fundamental incidence axioms. The statement of Axiom 2 is attributed to Pash and Veblen; it cleverly says that two lines meet if and only if they are coplanar without the need of having planes previously defined. Axiom 3 means the space is at least three dimensional (more than a plane), and it is known to be equivalent to Desargues’ Theorem. Axiom 4 is required for geometry to become interesting and not simply some trivialized set theory.

The two final axioms depend on some further development of the theory; they are not primitive. Axiom 5 guarantees that the ground field is of characteristic different from 22 or, equivalently, that the geometry does not contain the Fano Plane. The characteristic of a projective space can be defined geometrically using the harmonic fourth construction; essentially from how far can one go in a harmonic sequence without returning. It is needed here to make sense of harmonic curves (and that harmonic reflections are not the identity) because it implies that harmonic sets that have exactly four points do exist. Axiom 6 is a required additional principle for geometry to be rich enough to have a deep relation to other classic branches of mathematics like analysis and topology; bellow, we will discuss the several versions it may adopt.

From the first 4 axioms, flats can be defined as the closed subsets under the operation of taking lines, and then, the dimension of a flat is obtained as one less than the number of points needed to generate it; so that planes are defined as flats of dimension 2, [12]. The incidence properties of planes and lines in a space of dimension 3 are obtained from this; and the Hilbert-Cohn Vossen construction of ruled surfaces follows, making sense of the statement of the Equipal Axiom.

Since the Equipal Axiom is equivalent to Pappus’ Theorem, the arithmetization of projective space yields as ground field a commutative one. In [11] commutativity is proved from Pappus’ Theorem and the ground field is described from scratch. The necessity of the axiom is proved by constructing a projective space over a non-commutative field like the quaternions.

Another widely used version of Axiom 6 is as the uniqueness part of the Fundamental Theorem of Projective Geometry. It is usually stated in the context of planar geometry where Axioms 1 and 2 become appealingly dual (and Axiom 3 is false but replaced by Desargues’ Theorem). A projectivity is defined as the composition of projections between (points in) lines or (lines in) concurrent pencils; they are always bijections. It is not hard to construct a projectivity determined by it’s (arbitrary) effect on (any) three elements of it’s domain. This is the existence part of the Fundamental Theorem. However, the uniqueness is proved to be equivalent to Pappus’ Theorem, so one must be assumed to prove the other, see [4], [12].

We think that Axiom 3 is natural because, among other things, it responds and gives credit to the original motivation for the creation of Projective Geometry which is renaissance perspective, for which dimension 3 is quintessential. But then, if one thinks about projectivities between non coplanar lines in a three dimensional projective space, one is naturally lead to consider ruled surfaces. Indeed, given a projectivity from a line aa to a non coplanar line bb, the set of lines joining a point in aa to its image in bb turns out to be a ruling. So, the Equipal Axiom is intimately related to the uniqueness of projectivities given by three arbitrary values (the projectivity is determined by the extended ruling of three lines). Moreover, this association of a set of lines to a map between lines is also a classic idea. It is the dual of how Jakob Steiner (1796–1863) defined conic curves in a purely projective manner; and is a natural, visual way of presenting them, see e.g., [12].

Projective geometry is remarkable in many ways. One of them is the importance of some mathematical notions that were worked and experimented within it long before their abstract general acknowledgement. For example, projectivities were masterly used almost one century before the notion of sets and the language of abstract functions was stablished; moreover, together they constitute what we now call a groupoid (defined in the mid XX century within category theory). And of course, there is the leading role it played in broadening our notion of geometry and its influence on the dawn of topology. There are many ways to approach it and present it. We hope this paper contributes to the awareness of its cultural significance and the convenience and possibility of finding “its way down into secondary schools”, [8], or at least into early undergraduate courses.

\bmhead

Acknowledgments J. Bracho acknowledges support from PAPIIT-UNAM Project IN109023.

Declarations

The authors declare that there is no conflict of interest.

References

  • [1] J. L. Abreu, J. Bracho, ProGeo3D; a dynamic geometry system. (2016-2023). https://descartes.matem.unam.mx/ejemplos/pg3d/index.html
    Links to the interactive scenes for figures in this article:
    https://arquimedes.matem.unam.mx/harmonic_curves/scenes.html
  • [2] J. L. Abreu, J. Bracho, Geometría Visual; las matemáticas que surgen de cómo vemos el mundo (preliminary version). (2023).
    https://arquimedes.matem.unam.mx/roli/GeometriaVisual/
  • [3] H. S. M. Coxeter, Non-Euclidean Geometry; Toronto University Press (1947).
  • [4] H. S. M. Coxeter, Projective Geometry; 2nd Edition; Springer Verlag (1987) and Toronto University Press (1974). First Edition (1964).
  • [5] G. P. Dandelin, Memoire sur l’hyperboloïde de révolution, et sur les hexagones de Pascal et de M. Brianchon, Nouveau memoires de l’Académie Royale de Sciences et Belles-Lettres de Bruxelles, T II, p. 3-16, (1826).
  • [6] G. Desargues, N. G. Poudra (ed.) Oeuvres de Desargues. Cambridge University Press. (2011).
  • [7] D. Hilbert, S. Cohn-Vossen, Geometry and the Imagination, AMS Chelsea Publishing (1952, 1983, 1990). First Edition (1932).
  • [8] D. N. Lehmer, An Elementary Course in Synthetic Projective Geometry, CRC Press (2018).
  • [9] F. Klein, Erlangen Program: A Comparative review of resent researches in geometry; Translated by Dr. M. W. Haskell. Published in Bull. New York Math. Soc. 2, 215-249, (1892-1893). First published (1872).
  • [10] L. A. Santaló, Geometrías no Euclidianas; Editorial Universitaria de Buenos Aires, (1961).
  • [11] J. Stillwell, Yearning for the impossible: the surprising truths of mathematics, AK Peters (2006); CRC Press (2018).
  • [12] O. Veblen and J. W. Young, Projective Geometry; Ginn and Company, (1910).
  • [13] K. G. C. von Staudt, Geometrie der Lage, Vernag der Fr. Korn’schen Buchhandlung, Nürnberg (1847).