Galois representations, -modules and prismatic F-crystals
Abstract.
We prove that both local Galois representations and -modules can be recovered from prismatic F-crystals, from which we obtain a new proof of the equivalence of Galois representations and -modules.
1. Introduction
The theory of -modules was developed by Fontaine ([1]) to study local Galois representations. It plays an important role in the study of families of Galois representations and -adic Langlands correspondence.
The main result of the theory is that -modules are equivalent to Galois representations. The rough idea is to encode the difficult deeply ramified part of Galois theory into complicated rings. In other words, representations of complicated groups with simple coefficients are traded with representations of simple groups but with complicated coefficients.
The key part of the theory is then the construction of these complicated coefficient rings. It is based on the theory of fields of norms, which is a machine to switch between characteristic 0 and characteristic worlds. There is another, probably more well-known, theory that serves the same purpose, namely perfectoid fields. Indeed, theory of fields of norms can be viewed as a deperfection of perfectoid fields. The coefficient rings appearing in -modules are certain infinitesimal lifting of fields of norms along the -direction, in technical terms, they are Cohen rings of fields of norms.
The insight of this work is to put these rings in a world in which they naturally live, namely the framework of prisms as developed by Bhatt and Scholze ([2]). More precisely, these mysterious rings have natural integral structures which can be viewed as prisms, and the rings themselves are viewed as a structure sheaf on the prismatic site. Then -modules are vector bundles (with extra structures) on the prismatic site. This perspective is useful since prismatic sites are very rich. In particular, we can encode infinitesimal lifting of perfectoid fields into the prismatic world as well, which links with Galois representations. We can deduce the classical equivalence of Galois representations and -modules from this perspective, namely they are both equivalent to a third, arguably more fundamental object, the prismatic F-crystals. In summary, we have
Theorem 1.1.
Let be a perfect field of characteristic , and be a finite extension of . Then -modules over are equivalent to prismatic F-crystals in -modules over .
Moreover, continuous finite free -representations of the absolute Galois group are also equivalent to prismatic F-crystals in -modules over .
Corollary 1.2.
The category of continuous finite free -representations of the absolute Galois group is equivalent to the category of -modules over .
See the main text for explanations of the notation.
The equivalence of Galois representations and prismatic F-crystals in -modules is also contained in the work of Bhatt and Scholze [3]. The proof for -modules follows the same line as the proof for Galois representations.
Acknowledgments
I would like to thank Peter Scholze for helpful discussions and encouragement. I would like to thank Heng Du, Koji Shimiz, Yu Min and Liang Xiao for discussions on the initial draft. I would like to thank Tong Liu for pointing out a mistake in the early version of the paper. I would also like to thank the anonymous referee for many suggestions any corrections. I am grateful to Max Planck Institute for Mathematics in Bonn for its hospitality and financial support.
Convention
We follow the notation of [2]. Fixing a prime , a -ring is a -algebra equipped with a map such that satisfying
for any . We write
which is a ring homomorphism lifting the Frobenius. An element of a -ring is called distinguished if is a unit.
Following the notation of Scholze, for an integral perfectoid ring , we denote by the tilt of . We can also identify with as a multiplicative monoid, then there exists a natural monoid map given by
where , so represents an element of . As a standard notation in -adic Hodge theory, we denote
There exists a canonical surjection of rings
characterized by . Moreover, we know that is principal and is generated by any distinguished element in the kernel, see [2] lemma 3.8, lemma 2.33 and lemma 2.24 for example. In particular, if contains a compatible system of -power roots of unit , then
and generates .
We will use the theory of diamonds as developed in [4] and [5] in a rudimentary way. Recall that a diamond is a sheaf on the pro-étale site of characteristic perfectoid spaces which can be written as the quotient of a representable sheaf by a pro-étale equivalence relation. There is a functor from analytic adic spaces over into diamonds, which sends
where is the sheaf whose value on a characteristic perfectoid space is the set of untilts of together with a map of adic spaces. When is affinoid, we sometimes denote
When and is an -module, we will write
when is viewed as an -algebra with respect to the first factor, i.e. the -algebra structure is is . Similarly, we write
when is equipped with the -algebra structure with respect to the second factor. The convention applies also to other situations when has two structure maps, such as .
2. Prisms
We recall the basic theory of prisms as developed in [2], and introduce the primary examples that will be relevant to us.
2.1. Definitions and Examples
Definition 2.1.
A prism is a pair , where is a -ring, and is an ideal of such that is derived -complete, defines a Cartier divisor on , and . The category of prisms has objects the prisms, and the arrows are -ring maps preserving the given ideals.
A prism is called bounded if for some .
Definition 2.2.
Let be a -adic formal scheme, then the (absolute) prismatic site of has objects bounded prisms together with a map of formal schemes . The arrows are morphisms of prisms preserving the structure map to . An arrow is a cover if is -completely flat over .
When is affine, we simplify the notation by writing .
Example 2.3.
Let be a perfect field of characteristic , then
is a prism in , where , and the -structure is given by the usual -structure on and . It is clearly -complete, which is equivalent to being -complete as and . Moreover, from we have
for some . Applying to both sides, we have
proving .
Example 2.4.
Let be the completion of algebraic closure of , and its ring of integers. Then is a prism, where is the canonical map characterized by . We choose a compatible system of -power roots in , and let
then it is well-known that generates , and we have a map of -rings
by sending to , then is mapped to , and the condition follows from the same condition for the prism .
Moreover, is obviously -complete, where is any nonzero topologically nilpotent element of . This implies -completeness since is such a .
We made use of an embedding sending to in the previous example. This is not standard, and from now on we view as embedded into using the embedding
which sends to . It is the -twist of the previous embedding.
We now recall the theory of fields of norms, see [6] for details. Let be a finite totally ramified extension of contained in a fixed completed algebraically closure of , then we can associate the cyclotomic tower
the field of norms , whose ring of integers can be characterized as a subring of , namely
Then is a complete discrete valuation ring of characteristic , which by construction contains . Moreover, we know that is a finite separable extension of .
We can compute explicitly as
We observe that
is a Cohen ring of . By the henselian property of , the extension
lifts canonically to
for a Cohen ring of . Then as is invariant under the lift of Frobenius on , so is by naturality of being extension of inside .
Let be the integral closure of in , and
i.e. the -adic completion of . We know that is invariant under the Frobenius, so is 111For satisfying with a monic polynomial with coefficients, satisfies .. Passing to the -adic completion, this equips with a -ring structure such that the embedding is a -ring map. The inclusion enables us to view as elements of . We have the following lemmas.
Lemma 2.5.
The inclusion induces an isomorphism
Proof.
First we show that the natural map is an inclusion. Suppose that is in the kernel, then for some . If satisfies the minimal ploynomial equation with , then we have that satisfies the minimal polynomial equation with coefficients in the fraction field of the complete discrete valuation ring , but is integral over as it is an extension of complete DVRs, which tells us that . Further, forces us that , so proving the injectivity.
Next we note that by definition is integral over , so
If , and is the minimal monic polynomial of , then is separable as is a separable extension of . We choose a monic lift of , then Hensel’s lemma tells us that has a root in that reduces to , which means that is a lift of , so . ∎
Corollary 2.6.
is a Noetherian ring.
Proof.
This follows immediately from [7] tag 05GH. ∎
Lemma 2.7.
For every , is a prism.
Proof.
Being a subring of , is an integral domain, so is a non-zero divisor. Since is a prism, we have for some . Applying to it, we have , proving . Lastly, is -complete by construction and , which is a complete DVR. We have , which is a pseudouniformizer in , hence a pseudouniformizer in . This proves that is -complete, by [7] tag 0DYC. ∎
We record some simple algebraic properties of the prism .
Lemma 2.8.
The canonical inclusion is faithfully flat.
Proof.
By remark 4.31 of [8], it is enough to prove flatness of the maps after reduction mod , which is . This is an injective map from a DVR to an integral domain, hence flat.
To show it is faithfully flat, it is enough to show that for any finitely generated -module such that , then . We have
but is faithfully flat as it is a local flat map between DVRs. Thus we have , which implies that by Nakayama. ∎
Corollary 2.9.
is -torsionfree, so the prism is bounded.
Proof.
We have that
is flat since it is the base change of . We observe that
which is -torsionfree. Then the flatness tells us that is also -torsionfree. ∎
Lemma 2.10.
The map is faithfully flat.
Proof.
Again by remark 4.31 of [8], it is enough to show the flatness mod , which is the Frobenius . It is an injective map of DVRs, so flat.
To show it is faithfully flat, it is enough to show that for any finitely generated -module such that , then . We have , but is faithfully flat as it is a local flat map between DVRs. Thus we have , which implies that by Nakayama. ∎
2.2. Perfect prisms and perfectoid rings
There is an important class of prisms that has close connection with perfectoid rings.
Definition 2.11.
A prism is called perfect if is an automorphism of .
We have a natural perfection functor for prisms.
Proposition 2.12.
([2] lemma 3.8) Let be a prism, and
then is a perfect prism. Moreover, it is the universal perfect prism over .
Perfect prisms are canonically equivalent to integral perfectoid rings as defined in [8]. We recall the definition of integral perfectoid rings first.
Definition 2.13.
A ring is integral perfectoid if it is -adically complete for some such that divides , the Frobenius on is surjective, and the canonical map has principal kernel.
The desired equivalence with perfect prisms is the following theorem.
Theorem 2.14.
([2] theorem 3.9) The category of perfect prisms is equivalent to the category of integral perfectoid rings. The equivalence functors are , and .
There is another notion of perfectoid rings used in the theory of perfectoid spaces. We recall the definition and compare it with integral perfectoid rings. Recall that a complete Tate ring is a complete Huber ring that contains a topological nilpotent unit. In more concrete terms, it is a complete topological ring which contains an open subring whose topology is -adic for some element , and . For any Huber ring , we denote by the subring of power bounded elements.
Definition 2.15.
A perfectoid Tate ring is a uniform complete Tate ring , i.e. is bounded, such that there exists a topological nilpotent unit such that divides , and Frobenius is surjective on .
We have the following comparison between the two notions of perfectoid rings. Recall that a ring of integral elements of a Huber ring is an open and integrally closed subring of .
Proposition 2.16.
([8] lemma 3.20) Let be a complete Tate ring, and be a ring of integral elements. Then is a perfectoid Tate ring if and only if is bounded in and integral perfectoid.
The proposition characterizes integral perfectoid subrings of a perfectoid Tate ring. We can also build a perfectoid Tate ring from a integral perfectoid ring as in the following proposition.
Proposition 2.17.
Let be an integral perfectoid ring and be an element such that is -adically complete and divides , then is integral perfectoid, and is a perfectoid Tate ring with ring of definition .
Similarly, for integral perfectoid, then is integral perfectoid and is a perfectoid Tate ring with ring of definition .
Proof.
By [8] lemma 3.9, there are units of such that both and has compatible systems of -power roots in . Then by [9] 16.3.69, , resp. , is integral perfectoid without -, resp. -, torsion (the definition of perfectoid in [9] is the same as being integral perfectoid, as [8] remark 3.8 shows). Now , resp. , is a perfectoid Tate ring with ring of definition , resp. , by [8] lemma 3.21. ∎
Remark 2.18.
We have not excluded the zero ring in the proposition. For example, any perfect ring of characteristic is integral perfectoid with , then the rings produced in the proposition are all zero. This tells us that in some sense the integral perfectoid rings are more general than being perfectoid Tate. For example, finite fields are integral perfectoid, but can not be nonzero (ring of integers of) perfectoid Tate in any way.
We can compute the perfection of the prism .
Lemma 2.19.
We have
Proof.
Let . By [2] corollary 2.31, we have
where we use lemma 10.96.1 (1) of Stacks project, and commutation of colimit with tensoring with , in the third equality. From the theory of fields of norms, we know that
where the completion is with respect to the natural valuation. We know that is a pseudouniformizer in , hence the completion is the same as completion with respect to . Then we have
as desired. ∎
Corollary 2.20.
The automorphism group of in the category is .
Proof.
Let be an automorphism of , then by definition is a -ring morphism, and is continuous with respect to -topology, hence extends to an automorphism of . By theorem 3.10 of [2], the automorphism group of as an abstract prism is the same as the automorphism group of the corresponding integral perfectoid ring, which is by the proposition. The automorphism of as objects of is then the -algebra automorphism of , so
But we observe that already acts on . The action on is clear from its construction, and we need to check that it preserves the ideal .
First,
for some , where . This follows from the definition , and is the value at of the cyclotomic character. Then
and we claim that is a unit, which is what we want to prove. This follows from the computation
which are units in as
Now the corollary follows from the fact that is injective ( is injective as is a -subring of the perfect -ring ). ∎
Moreover, we have the following proposition.
Proposition 2.21.
There exists such that
i.e. there exists a map .
Remark 2.22.
depends only on . In other words, cannot see the difference between and , and this is taken care by the choice of .
Proof.
Let , we have by lemma 2.19
where the last isomorphism follows from and being an automorphism and , for . On the other hand, we also have
by definition of , hence
and we claim that this implies that
(1) |
Observe that is integral over , so is also integral over . Since there is no non-trivial integral extension of in its completion , , being integral over a subring of , has to be contained in . We look at the short exact sequence of -modules
From
and Stacks project lemma 10.96.1, we have . The identification after completion also implies that and have the same fraction field, in other words, is -torsion. Further, we observe that contains
over which is finite. This implies that is a finitely generated -module, which, together with being -torsion, tells us that is killed by for some , so is -adically complete. Then we have , proving the claim.
Now as is finite over , (1) implies that factorizes through for some . Indeed, let for some polymonial with coefficients in . Then , as an element of , lifts to an element for some , and the relation in the colimit forces that in the ring for some , which implies that . Note that we have used the fact that , where the first isomorphism follows from the perfectness of . ∎
Remark 2.23.
We have used freely in the above proof the fact that there is no algebraic extension of nonarchimedean fields in their completion. More precisely, let be an algebraic extension of , then there is no nontrivial algebraic extension in its completion . Equivalently, completion induces an equivalence between algebraic extensions of and algebraic extension of . This follows immediately from the fact that , where is a completed algebraic closure of .
We extract the following lemma from the proof, which will be useful later.
Lemma 2.24.
The map is flat.
Proof.
Since is a valuation ring, it is enough to show that every non-zero element of is not a zero-divisor of . We observe that
is flat, so if satisfies for some , then defines a zero-divisor of in the colimit, which has to be by the flatness of over . Thus for some , which implies that by the faithfully flatness of established in lemma 2.10. ∎
3. Prismatic F-crystals
We recall the definition of prismatic F-crystals and make explicit an example that is relevant for us. Recall that we have a natural structure sheaf of -rings on , together with an ideal sheaf .
Definition 3.1.
Let be a -adic formal scheme, and be , the -adic completion of the structure sheaf with (locally) a generator of inverted. A prismatic -crystal on in -modules is a finite locally free -module over such that
for any arrow in , together with an isomorphism
of -modules.
A concrete way to work with prismatic F-crystals in -modules is to choose a cover of the final object of the topos , suppose that is representable, and
then a prismatic F-crystal in -modules is a finite projective --module together with an isomorphism
of --modules satisfying cocycle conditions. Indeed, it is obvious that we can obtain such an object from a prismatic -crystal. Conversely, if we are given such data, we can build a prismatic -crystal as follows. Given a prism , since covers the final object, there exists a cover of , which also lies over . Then we can define
where which lives over , and the two arrows comes from the base change descent data . Now by the next proposition, the descent data is effective on finite projective modules, so is a finite projective module over .
Proposition 3.2.
Let be a cover in the category of bounded prisms, and be the corresponding Čech nerve, then we have an equivalence of categories
where Vect(R) denotes the category of finite projective modules over the ring .
Proof.
Since (resp. ) is -complete, by [7] tag 0D4B, (resp. )) is equivalent to (resp. ). Thus it suffices to prove the equivalence
(2) |
We know from the proof of [2] corollary 3.12 that is the derived -completion of , which is proved in to be discrete and classically -complete. Then lemma 3.3 shows that
i.e. it is the classical -completion of , and similarly for . Indeed, by the discreteness and classical -completeness of , the derived -completion of , we have
where the third equality follows from lemma 3.3. Then we have
and similarly for . Since is assumed to be -completely faithfully flat, is -completely faithfully flat, and (2) follows from [10] theorem 7.8. ∎
Lemma 3.3.
Let be a ring and be a finitely generated ideal of . Let be a complex of -modules with zero cohomology in positive degrees, and its derived -completion, then we have a canonical identification
in other words, the classical -completion of is the same as the classical -completion of .
Proof.
For any -module , we denote its derived -completion by viewing as a complex concentrated in zero degree. Recall that there is a natural map which is initial among maps with a derived -complete -module, see [10] definition 2.27 for example. By the spectral sequence in [7] tag 0BKE, we have
so we see that
is the initial map among with a derived -complete -module. We now claim that the composite map
is initial among where is classical -complete. This is exactly the universal property of the classical -completion of , whence .
We now prove the claim. Let where be as given, since classical -completeness implies derived -completeness ([7] tag 091T), we have a unique factorization
which further factors as
by the universal property of . ∎
Example 3.4.
Let be a perfect field of characteristic , be a finite totally ramified extension of , and . Let be chosen as in proposition 2.21 such that
then it is a cover of the final object by the following lemma 3.5. Moreover, we have by lemma 3.6
where is -completion of , which is freely adjoining and to as -rings, and .
Thus a prismatic F-crystal in -modules over is a -module together with an isomorphism
satisfying cocycle conditions. The ring is difficult to understand explicitly, we will see below how we can bypass this difficulty by passing to perfections.
Lemma 3.5.
Let be a finite totally ramified extension of , , and be chosen as in proposition 2.21 such that
then it covers the final object in .
Proof.
Let be an object of , then is a -algebra. We have a quasisyntomic cover of , hence
is a quasisyntomic cover of . By [2] proposition 7.11, we can find a prism that covers such that there is a morphism
Now as is integral perfectoid, the composition
lifts to a map of prisms
by [2] lemma 4.7. We have that
by lemma 2.19, so we have a map
of prisms. As covers , we have finished the proof. ∎
Lemma 3.6.
Let be a perfect field of characteristic , be a finite totally ramified extension of , and be an element which modulo becomes a uniformizer of under the inclusion . Then as objects of , we have
where
The ring displayed is -completion of , which is freely adjoining and to as -rings.
Proof.
By definition, an object of is a prism equipped with a morphism . The -algebra structure does not necessarily lift to , but the corresponding -algebra structure does. Indeed, by deformation theory of perfect rings, lifts canonically to a morphism , hence objects of are naturally equipped with -algebra structures, and all arrows in are -algebra morphisms.
Now given such an , together with two arrows in , they give rise canonically to a -ring morphism
We know from properties of prisms that . Moreover, being arrows in , the two arrows are -algebra morphisms , which means that maps to 0 in . Thus factors through .
It remains to show that is a prism. First we observe that is a unit in , whence . This follows from the equation
and [2] lemma 2.24.
We now claim that is a regular sequence of . Viewing as a -algebra along the first factor, then it follows from [2] proposition 3.13 that is a prism. It remains to prove the claim, which puts us into the setting of [2] proposition 3.13.
Observe that is regular since is regular in (being an integral domain), and is flat over . We want to show that is regular in
We note that
by definition of . By our assumption on , is totally ramified over , so for an Eisenstein polynomial . Then
and by Eisenstein criterion, is irreducible in . Note that is a regular local ring, whence a UFD by Auslander–Buchsbaum theorem. Then Gauss’s lemma tells us is a UFD as well, so irreducible polynomials are prime. Then is an integral domain, and is regular in . We know from lemma 2.24 that is flat, so is regular in . ∎
4. étale -modules
In this section, we prove that étale -modules on prisms does not change by passing to perfections. We first recall the definition of étale -modules.
Definition 4.1.
Let be a ring equipped with a ring morphism , an étale -modules over is a finite projective -module equipped with an -module isomorphism
The morphisms between étale -modules are -module morphisms preserving . We denote by the category of étale -modules over .
First, we observe that by passing to naive perfections, the category does not change.
Proposition 4.2.
There is an equivalence of categories
induced by base changing to .
Proof.
For notational convenience, we index the rings in the relevant system by , i.e. the ring is the colimit of the cofiltered system
with each . As the data of an étale -module is finite in nature, an étale -module over comes via base change from an étale -module over for some . We need to show that it has further descent to . Now let be an étale -module over . Since , we can view as an étale -module over , and we claim that is isomorphic to as étale -modules over . Iterate the -module structure , we obtain an -module isomorphism
we need to check that this is an étale -module isomorphism, i.e. , but this is clear. This proves essential surjectivity.
For fully faithfullness, we need to show that for , an arrow in comes uniquely from an arrow in via base change. The arrow comes from an arrow in for some by standard finiteness argument, and we are reduced to showing that any arrow
in has a unique descent to . We show that it descends uniquely to , which proves the claim by iteration. Now we can assume , the previous paragraph shows that
are isomorphisms as étale -modules over (being denoted by in the previous paragraph). Let
then is an arrow in , and we claim that . Since is an arrow in , we have
and then
proving the existence of the descent. It is unique since any descent of satisfies the relation by definition, and satisfies the relation as it is in , combining the two we have
proving
∎
Next we show that -adic completion of the perfection does not lose information of étale -modules over -complete rings.
Lemma 4.3.
Let be a -adically complete ring equipped with a ring morphism , then base change induces an equivalence of categories
Proof.
By -completeness of , we have
where we use the commutativity of colimit with tensoring with in the third equality, proposition 4.2 in the fourth equality and -completeness in the last one. ∎
We now specialize to the case of prisms and closely related rings. Let be a bounded prism, we want to study étale -modules over . There are two natural ways to form a perfection of the ring. The first is take the perfection directly and then -complete it, namely
while the second is to take the perfection of the prism first, then inverting and -complete, i.e.
It is the second one that will ultimately help us, and we want to understand étale -modules over it. Note that we have already understand étale -modules over the first ring, namely lemma 4.3 tells us that étale -modules over is the same as étale -modules over . Observe that we have a natural morphism
and we have the following theorem characterizing étale -modules over .
Theorem 4.4.
Let be a bounded prism such that is generated by a non-zero divisor in , then we have an equivalence of categories
induced by base change.
Proof.
We compute first. Being a -complete perfect -ring, we know from [2] corollary 2.31 that
where we use again the commutation of colimit with tensoring with . is -complete as is a bounded prism, so is -adically complete. By [2] lemma 3.6, is principal, so is principal which is generated by a non-zero divisor by assumption. It follows that is a Tate ring with ring of definition .
We know that étale -modules over are equivalent to lisse sheaves on for a perfect ring by [11] proposition 3.2.7, hence it is enough to compare the finite étale sites of and .
We note that is the completed perfection of the Tate ring , and by the following lemma the finite étale site of is the same as that of . But perfection also does not change finite étale site (see [11] theorem 3.1.15(a)), hence finite étale site of is also identified with . This proves that the finite étale sites of and are equivalent via base change (as all intermediate equivalences here are through base change). ∎
Lemma 4.5.
Let be a Banach ring of characteristic (in the sense of [11] definition 2.2.1), then the finite étale site of is equivalent to that of via base change.
Proof.
Let be the uniformization of as defined in [11] definition 2.8.13, then by [11] proposition 2.8.16, the finite étale site of is equivalent to that of under base change. Moreover, by [11] theorem 3.1.15 (b), the finite étale sites of and are equivalent, so we have the comparison between finite étale sites of and . We claim that . By [11] lemma 2.6.2, there exists an affionid system (see [11] definition 2.6.1 for definition) such that , then by [11] corollary 2.5.6. Let , then
where we use that for any ring of characteristic , which can be checked directly. ∎
Combining all the equivalences we have established, we have the following theorem.
Theorem 4.6.
5. -modules and prismatic -crystals
In this section, we interpret -modules in terms of prismatic -crystals. We recover the equivalence between Galois representations and -modules using the new interpretation.
Let us first recall the definition of -modules. Let be a finite totally ramified extension of , and be as in section 2. Recall that is stable by the canonical Frobenius lifting and the action of the Galois group Gal() on . Moreover, the action factorizes through
Definition 5.1.
A -module over is an étale -module over (with respect to the -structure on ), i.e. a finite projective -module equipped with an isomorphism
together with an action of on that commutes with , and semilinear with respect to the action of on .
We have the following theorem.
Theorem 5.2.
The category of prismatic F-crystals in -modules over is equivalent to the category of -modules over .
Proof.
By example 3.4, we see that a prismatic F-crystal in -modules over is an étale -module over together with an isomorphism
of étale -modules over satisfying cocycle conditions, with
as in example 3.4. Then theorem 4.6 implies that this is equivalent (via base change) to an étale -module over
together with an isomorphism
as étale -modules over , where . Then the lemma below tells us that the descent data is equivalent to an action of on that is semilinear with respect to the action of on . As the action of is already defined on , theorem 4.6 tells us that this is equivalent to an action of on that is semilinear with respect to the action of on , which is exactly a -module over . ∎
Lemma 5.3.
Let be the perfection of the prism in lemma 3.6, then
where is the ring of continuous functions on with values in . Moreover, the two structure maps from to are the obvious constant function map, and the one sending to .
Proof.
Let
By lemma 3.6, is the initial perfect prism in equipped with two arrows from into it. This is the same as the initial perfect prism in with two arrows from
where we use lemma 2.19. Since perfect prisms are equivalent to integral perfectoid rings, we see that is the initial integral perfectoid -algebra with two maps (as -algebras) from . We claim that is the initial perfectoid Tate -algebra with two maps from . This follows immediately form proposition 2.17 and proposition 2.16.
Now for any perfectoid Tate -algebra with two maps from , we obtain two maps from to , as perfectoid spaces over . We view them as diamonds over . Since diamonds is determined by their values on (affinoid) perfectoid test objects, the previous paragraph shows that
for some ring of definition , which can be identified as the image of in , providing we know the right hand side is affinoid perfectoid. But it is well-known that
see [5] lemma 10.1.7 for example, so
where , resp. , is the ring of continuous functions on with values in , resp. , see [4] example 11.12 for the last isomorphism. We then have
as the functor from perfectoid spaces over to diamonds over is fully faithful. The two structure maps from to is then the constant function map, and the one sending to , which is easy to see by chasing through the above canonical isomorphisms. Now
for a uniformizer which we can choose so that divides in . Thus
where the second isomorphism follows directly from the description , and the same descrition for . The last isomorphism follows from the concrete description of the Witt vector, namely . This clearly commutes with taking continuous functions. Moreover, the ring structure is defined by polynomial equations that is independent of the input ring, whence the last isomorphism. The description of the two structure maps is straightforward by chasing through the various canonical isomorphisms. ∎
Remark 5.4.
The action of can be directly detected as follows. For a prismatic F-crystal over , and . The action of on is induced by the base change isomorphism (the crystal structure)
corresponding to the arrow
in as described in the proof of corollary 2.20.
Remark 5.5.
The proof also shows that prismatic -crystals in -modules over are equivalent to -crystals in -modules over , i.e. the site of perfect prisms over , and the equivalence is induced by the obvious restriction functor. Indeed, prismatic -crystals in -modules over (resp. ) are equivalent to -modules over together with descent data over (resp. -modules over together with descent data over ), and the proof shows that the latter objects are equivalent.
With exactly the same idea, we can recover Galois representations from prismatic F-crystals in -modules. As it is along the same reasoning as above, we only sketch the argument.
Theorem 5.6.
The category of prismatic F-crystals in -modules over is equivalent to the category of finite free continuous -representations of .
Proof.
Let and be the ring of integers of it. By remark 5.5, it enough to work in . We can evaluate a prismatic F-crystal at . Let be the product
in , and we need to compute
We know that is a perfectoid Tate -algebra and can be interpreted as
We know that
so
With the help of theorem 4.6, this proves that a prismatic F-crystal is the same as an étale -module over together with a -action which is semilinear with respect to the action of on . Now as is algebraically closed, it is well-known that the category of étale -modules over is equivalent to the category of finite free -modules via taking -invariants, see [11] proposition 3.2.7 for example. This shows that the prismatic F-crystals are equivalent to finite free -representations of . ∎
Remark 5.7.
Similarly as before, for a prismatic F-crystal , the -action on is induced by the base change isomorphism (the crystal structure)
with respect to the arrow
in .
Corollary 5.8.
The category of -modules over is equivalent to the category of finite free -representations of . The equivalence functors are
where is a -module over , is a finite free -representation of , and
The action of is diagonal on both and , where acts on through the canonical quotient . The -structure on is defined by on the second factor. Moreover, the deperfection functor is the equivalence from the category of -modules over to the category of -modules over , as induced from theorem 4.6.
Proof.
Both categories are equivalent to prismatic F-crystals in -modules. We check the equivalence functors are given by the stated ones. Given a prismatic F-crystal , the associated -module is , while the associated Galois representation is . being a crystal, we have a canonical identification
(3) |
using the arrow
in . We have seen in the proof of proposition 4.2 that the base change along does not affect étale -modules, namely for any étale -module over with respect to , there is a canonical identification of étale -modules over . Hence we have a canonical idenfication
(4) |
of étale -modules over . Thus the functor from -modules to Galois representations is of the expected form, we still need to identify the Galois action. This follows easily from remarks 5.7 and 5.4, as the Galois action on both sides of (3) are induced by base change, while the identification (3) itself is also induced by base change. An easy base change computation together with the observation that the action of on through the inclusion is via the quotient proves the compatibility of Galois action in (3). Then the naturality of the identification gives us the desired description of Galois action on both sides of (4).
On the other hand, we have a canonical map
in the site , which is not necessarily an isomorphism, but becomes so on the structure sheaf . Indeed, this follows from that has (continuous) Galois group over and the tilting equivalence of perfectoid fields. This tells us that
Moreover, by looking at the descent data of the -crystal, the -action on the right hand side is carried to the descent data of the left hand side. Then theorem 4.6 applied to gives the other direction. Note that the categorical equivalence in theorem 4.6 implies that base change preserves not only the -structure, but also -action, thereby inducing an equivalence of -modules. ∎
Remark 5.9.
The fact that twist by does not change étale -modules and has all the expected functoriality is used secretly throughout the above proof. For example, it is needed in checking the two functors are quasi-inverse to each other. All that says is that we can ignore the issue caused by twisting by .
The equivalence functors in the above corollary may look different from the treatment one usually finds in the literature. We now check that they are equivalent.
Let be the -adic completion of the maximal unramified extension of inside , i.e. is the Cohen ring of , the separable closure of , which lies inside and extends . It is stable by and the action of the Galois group . If we can write as for some prism , then we can repeat the above argument with replaced by , and deduce the usual description of equivalence functors between Galois representations and -modules. However, this is not possible since is not complete. Instead, we proceed with the following lemma.
Lemma 5.10.
There is an equivalence of categories
induced by base change.
Proof.
Theorem 5.11.
The category of -modules over is equivalent to the category of finite free -representations of . The equivalence functors are
where is a -module over , is a finite free -representation of , and
The action of is diagonal on both and , where acts on through the canonical quotient . The -structure on is defined by on the second factor.
Proof.
By lemma 5.10, the functor
in corollary 5.8 is the same as
Indeed, as étale -modules over are all isomorphic to the trivial ones , lemma 5.10 tells us that étale -modules over are also of the form , so taking -invariants produces the same finite free -modules, namely
for any étale -module over . This gives the identification of the -modules, the identification of Galois actions also follows since the equivalence in lemma 5.10 is a categorical one, so arrows corresponding to Galois action are also preserved.
References
- [1] Jean-Marc Fontaine. Représentations p-adiques des corps locaux (1ère partie), pages 249–309. Birkhäuser Boston, Boston, MA, 2007.
- [2] Bhargav Bhatt and Peter Scholze. Prisms and Prismatic Cohomology. arXiv e-prints, page arXiv:1905.08229, May 2019.
- [3] Bhargav Bhatt and Peter Scholze. Prismatic f-crystals and crystalline galois representations, 2021.
- [4] Peter Scholze. Etale cohomology of diamonds. arXiv e-prints, page arXiv:1709.07343, September 2017.
- [5] Peter Scholze and Jared Weinstein. Berkeley lectures on p-adic geometry. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 2020.
- [6] Jean-Pierre Wintenberger. Le corps des normes de certaines extensions infinies de corps locaux ; applications. Annales scientifiques de l’École Normale Supérieure, 4e série, 16(1):59–89, 1983.
- [7] The Stacks project authors. The stacks project. https://stacks.math.columbia.edu, 2021.
- [8] Bhargav Bhatt, Matthew Morrow, and Peter Scholze. Integral p-adic hodge theory. Publications mathématiques de l'IHÉS, 128(1):219–397, November 2018.
- [9] Ofer Gabber and Lorenzo Ramero. Foundations for almost ring theory – Release 7.5. arXiv Mathematics e-prints, page math/0409584, September 2004.
- [10] Akhil Mathew. Faithfully flat descent of almost perfect complexes in rigid geometry. arXiv e-prints, page arXiv:1912.10968, December 2019.
- [11] Kiran Kedlaya and Ruochuan Liu. Relative p-adic Hodge theory : foundations. Société mathématique de France, Paris, 2015.