This paper was converted on www.awesomepapers.org from LaTeX by an anonymous user.
Want to know more? Visit the Converter page.

finite normal subgroups of strongly verbally closed groups

Filipp D. Denissov
Faculty of Mathematics and Mechanics of Moscow State University
Moscow 119991, Leninskie gory, MSU.
Moscow center for Fundamental and Applied Mathematics.
[email protected]

In the recent paper by A. A. Klyachko, V. Yu. Miroshnichenko, and A. Yu. Olshanskii, it is proven that the center of any finite strongly verbally closed group is its direct factor. One of the results of the current paper is the generalization of this nontrivial fact to the case of finite normal subgroups of any strongly verbally closed groups. It follows from this generalization that finitely generated nilpotent groups with nonabelian torsion subgroups are not strongly verbally closed.

1. Introduction

A subgroup HH of a group GG is called verbally closed [MR14] if any equation of the form

w(x1,x2,,xn)=h, where w is an element of the free group F(x1,,xn) and hH,w(x_{1},x_{2},\dots,x_{n})=h,\text{ where }w\text{ is an element of the free group }F(x_{1},\dots,x_{n})\text{ and }h\in H,

having solutions in GG has a solution in HH. If each system of equations with coefficients from H

{w1(x1,)=1,,wm(x1,)=1}, where wiHF(x1,,xn) (and  means the free product),\{w_{1}(x_{1},\dots)=1,\dots,w_{m}(x_{1},\dots)=1\},\text{ where }w_{i}\in H\ *\ F(x_{1},\dots,x_{n})\text{ (and }*\text{ means the free product),}

having solutions in GG has a solution in HH, then the subgroup HH is called algebraically closed in GG. Note that if the subgroup HH is algebraically closed in the group GG, then it is verbally closed in GG.

A group GG is called strongly verbally closed if it is algebraically closed in any group containing GG as a verbally closed subgroup. Thus, the verbal closedness (as well as the algebraic closedness) is a property of a subgroup, while the strong verbal closedness is a property of an abstract group. The class of strongly verbally closed groups is fairly wide. For example, it includes

  • all abelian groups [Maz18],

  • all free groups [KM18],

  • all virtually free groups containing no nontrivial finite normal subgroups [KM18], [KMM18],

  • all groups decomposing nontrivially into a free product [Maz19],

  • fundamental groups of all connected surfaces except the Klein bottle [Maz18], [Kly21],

  • all finite groups with nonabelian monolith [KMO21],

  • inifinite dihedral group [KMM18] and any finite dihedral group whose order is not divisible by 88 [KMO21],

  • all acylindrically hyperbolic groups with no nontrivial finite normal subgroups [Bog22].

The class of non-strongly-verbally-closed groups is fairly wide too. Among such groups are the following:

  • the already mentioned fundamental group of the Klein bottle [Kly21],

  • the discrete Heisenberg group [KMO21],

  • any finite group, whose center is not its direct factor (in particular, any finite nonabelian nilpotent group) [KMO21], [RKK17], [KM18].

Proving the strong verbal closedness (as well as its absence) of a group is not easy. In [KMO21], for example, a question is raised:

Question 1.

Does there exist a finitely generated nilpotent nonabelian strongly verbally closed group?

A negative answer to this question would yield a broad generalization of the last two examples of non-strongly-verbally-closed groups mentioned above. So far, we managed to give a partial answer to this question. More precisely, we proved the absence of strong verbal closedness of finitely generated nilpotent groups with nonabelian torsion subgroups and of some finitely generated nilpotent nonabelian groups with abelian torsion subgroups.

A property that is stronger than the strong verbal closedness is the property of being a strong retract [KMO21]. A group HH is called a strong retract if it is a retract of any group GHG\geqslant H from the variety generated by the group HH.

Let us recall some terminology [Neu67]:

  • the variety generated by a class of groups 𝒦\mathcal{K} is the class of all groups satisfying all identities that hold in all groups from 𝒦\mathcal{K},

  • the variety generated by a group GG is designated by 𝐯𝐚𝐫G\operatorname{\mathbf{var}}G.

This gives rise to the following question from [KMO21]:

Question 2.

What is an arbitrary finite strong retract?

In [KMO21] some examples of strong retracts are provided. In the next section, we describe all the nilpotent strong retracts.

Below we provide a brief list of notation we use.

If x,yx,y are elements of some group, then the symbol [x,y][x,y] denotes their commutator x1y1xyx^{-1}y^{-1}xy. The symbol ord(x)\operatorname{ord}(x) denotes the order of an element xx of a group GG. The center of a group GG is denoted by Z(G)Z(G), and its commutator subgroup is denoted by GG^{\prime}. The centralizer of a subset XX of a group GG is denoted by C(X)C(X). The symbol X\langle\langle X\rangle\rangle stands for the normal closure of a subset XX of a group GG (that is the intersection of all normal subgroups of GG containing XX). The free group with a basis XX is denoted as F(X)F(X) or FnF_{n} in case XX has nn\in\mathbb{N} elements. Identical mapping from XX to itself is denoted by idid. We use the symbol HGH\cong G to express the fact that groups HH and GG are isomorphic. Finally, the symbol HGH\leqslant G denotes the fact that a group HH is a subgroup of GG. The symbol HGH\unlhd G denotes the fact that HH is a normal subgroup of GG.

The author is grateful to his supervisor Anton Alexandrovich Klyachko for formulation of the problem and for valuable remarks during the work.

2. Nilpotent strong retracts

Note that in case when GG is an abelian group, HGH\leqslant G is its retract if and only if HH is a direct summand of GG. It means that the property of being a strong retract for the abelian group GG is equivalent to the property of GG being a direct summand of any group H𝐯𝐚𝐫GH\in\operatorname{\mathbf{var}}G containing GG. For the further discussion, we need the description of all varieties of abelian groups (see [Fuc70], paragpaph 1818, exercise 77):

Varieties of abelian groups are precisely the following classes of groups: 1) the class of all abelian groups; 2) the class of all abelian groups of a period divising nn\in\mathbb{N}.

Recall that the period of a group GG is the least number nn\in\mathbb{N}, such that xn=1x^{n}=1 for any xGx\in G. If such a number exists, then GG is a group of bounded period.

To begin with, consider the case, when GG is not a group of bounded period. Then, according to the description, 𝐯𝐚𝐫G\operatorname{\mathbf{var}}G is the class of all abelian groups. The following is true of divisible abelian groups (see, for example, [Kur60]):

If GG is a divisible abelian group, and HH is an abelian group such that GHG\leqslant H, then GG is a direct summand of HH.

Let us remind that a group GG is called divisible if for any gGg\in G and nn\in\mathbb{N}, the equation xn=gx^{n}=g has a solution in GG.

Proposition 1.

An abelian group GG of unbounded period is a strong retract if and only if it is divisible.

Proof.

Sufficiency follows from the fact provided above. Let GG be an abelian group of unbounded period. Then, as it was noted earlier, 𝐯𝐚𝐫G\operatorname{\mathbf{var}}G is the class of all abelian groups. In particular, 𝐯𝐚𝐫G\operatorname{\mathbf{var}}G contains a divisible group HH containing GG [Kur60]. Though, if GG is not divisible itself, it is not a direct summand of HH (as direct summands of a divisible group are divisible themselves [Kur60]), so GG is not a strong retract. ∎

Let us move on to abelian groups of bounded period. The first Prüfer theorem provides a complete description of these groups [Kur60]:

An abelian group GG of bounded period dd is a direct sum of primary cyclic groups, i.e. GiIpikiG\cong\bigoplus_{i\in I}\mathbb{Z}_{p_{i}^{k_{i}}}, where pip_{i} are prime numbers and kik_{i} are natural numbers such that piki|dp_{i}^{k_{i}}|d, iIi\in I (II is an index set).

We need the following variation of the Zorn’s lemma [Fuc70]:

Let MM\neq\varnothing be a partially ordered set. Suppose that every chain in MM (a totally ordered subset of MM) has an upper bound. Then MM contains a maximal element.

Now, we are ready to proceed with our description:

Proposition 2.

An abelian group GG of bounded period is a strong retract if and only if in its decomposition into the direct sum of primary cyclic groups, orders of any distinct direct summands are either equal or coprime:

Gi=1mCpiki(ni), where Cpiki(ni) is equal to the direct sum of ni copies of the group piki,G\cong\bigoplus_{i=1}^{m}C_{p_{i}^{k_{i}}}(n_{i}),\text{ where }C_{p_{i}^{k_{i}}}(n_{i})\text{ is equal to the direct sum of }n_{i}\text{ copies of the group }\mathbb{Z}_{p_{i}^{k_{i}}},

where all prime numbers pip_{i} are distinct, m,kim,k_{i}\in\mathbb{N}, and nin_{i} are some cardinal numbers.

Proof.

Suppose that GG cannot be decomposed into such a direct sum. We may assume that

G=i=1mjIipikj,G=\bigoplus_{i=1}^{m}\bigoplus_{j\in I_{i}}\mathbb{Z}_{p_{i}^{k_{j}}}, (1)

where mm\in\mathbb{N}, |Ii|=ni|I_{i}|=n_{i} and among kjk_{j}, jIij\in I_{i} there are only finitely many different ones (because GG is a group of bounded period) but there exists i{1,,m}i\in\{1,\dots,m\} such that for some j1,j2Ii,j_{1},j_{2}\in I_{i}, kj1kj2k_{j_{1}}\neq k_{j_{2}}.

Consider the group: H=i=1mCpisi(ni)\displaystyle H=\bigoplus_{i=1}^{m}C_{p_{i}^{s_{i}}}(n_{i}), where

si=max{kj|pikj is a direct summand in the decomposition (1)},i=1,2,,m.s_{i}=\max\{k_{j}\ |\ \mathbb{Z}_{p_{i}^{k_{j}}}\text{ is a direct summand in the decomposition (1)}\},\ i=1,2,\dots,m.

Since both GG and HH are of the same period i=1msi\prod_{i=1}^{m}s_{i}, it follows from the description of abelian varieties that H𝐯𝐚𝐫GH\in\operatorname{\mathbf{var}}G .

Consider the injection f:GHf:G\to H, which works on each direct summand from (1)(1) as follows: let i{1,,m}i\in\{1,\dots,m\}, jIij\in I_{i}, f:pikjpisif:\mathbb{Z}_{p_{i}^{k_{j}}}\hookrightarrow\mathbb{Z}_{p_{i}^{s_{i}}}, where pisi\mathbb{Z}_{p_{i}^{s_{i}}} is the jjth summand from the decomposition of Cpisi(ni)C_{p_{i}^{s_{i}}}(n_{i}) into the direct sum. Every direct summand from (1)(1) is mapped into the corresponding direct summand of the decomposition of HH, so that the restriction of ff to pikj\mathbb{Z}_{p_{i}^{k_{j}}} is a natural injection: if kj=sik_{j}=s_{i}, then it is the identical map; otherwise it is a mapping to the subgroup of pisi\mathbb{Z}_{p_{i}^{s_{i}}} of the order pikjp_{i}^{k_{j}}. From the uniqueness of the decomposition of an abelian group of bounded period into the direct sum of primary cyclic groups [Fuc70], it follows that f(G)f(G) is not a direct summand of HH. Thus, GG is not a strong retract.

Now, suppose that GG has the decomposition from the statement of the theorem. Let H𝐯𝐚𝐫GH\in\operatorname{\mathbf{var}}G and let f:GHf:G\hookrightarrow H be a monomorphism. As any monomorphism preserves the order of an element, the pip_{i}th component of GG is mapped into the pip_{i}th component of HH under ff, so it suffices to prove the theorem only for the case G=Cpk(n)G=C_{p^{k}}(n), where pp is prime, kk\in\mathbb{N}, and nn is some cardinal number.

Let us show that there exists such XHX\leqslant H that H=f(G)XH=f(G)\oplus X. In Zorn’s lemma, take the set of all subgroups of HH having trivial intersection with f(G)f(G) as MM:

M={YH|Yf(G)={0}}.M=\{Y\leqslant H\ |\ Y\cap f(G)=\{0\}\}.

Order on MM is introduced as follows: for X,YMX,Y\in M, XYX\leqslant Y if XX is a subgroup of YY. It can be verified directly that this is an order on MM. Set MM is nonempty: {0}M\{0\}\in M. Any chain {Yα}M\{Y_{\alpha}\}\subseteq M of subgroups having trivial intersection with f(G)f(G) is bounded by an element YMY\in M, where Y=αYαY=\cup_{\alpha}Y_{\alpha}. Consequently, Zorn’s lemma is applicable, and MM contains a maximal element XX: XHX\leqslant H, Xf(G)={0}X\cap f(G)=\{0\}, and XX is not a subgroup of any bigger (relatively to the order we introduced) subgroup satisfying this property.

From Xf(G)={0}X\cap f(G)=\{0\} it follows that f(G)+X=f(G)Xf(G)+X=f(G)\oplus X. It remains to prove that H=f(G)+XH=f(G)+X. Let hHh\in H. There exists such kk\in\mathbb{N} that khf(G)+Xkh\in f(G)+X. Indeed, otherwise h(f(G)+X)={0}\langle h\rangle\cap(f(G)+X)=\{0\}, which means that (h+X)f(G)={0}(\langle h\rangle+X)\cap f(G)=\{0\}, leading to a contradiction with the maximality of XX.

Let ss be the least of such numbers kk. Without loss of generality, assume that ss is prime or that s=1s=1 (otherwise, take a power of hh instead of hh). Two cases are possible:

1) s=ps=p. Then, ph=f(g)+xph=f(g)+x for some gGg\in G, xXx\in X. If g=pg1g=pg_{1}, g1Gg_{1}\in G (g1g_{1} may be equal to zero), then phf(pg1)=xph-f(pg_{1})=x. However, from hf(g1)Xh-f(g_{1})\not\in X (as hf(G)+Xh\not\in f(G)+X) it can be obtained that (X+hf(g1))f(G)={0}(X+\langle h-f(g_{1})\rangle)\cap f(G)=\{0\}, which leads to a contradiction with the maximality of XX. Consequently, gpg1g\neq pg_{1} for any g1Gg_{1}\in G. As g0g\neq 0, ord(g)=pk\operatorname{ord}(g)=p^{k}. Though, ord(ph)=pr<pk\operatorname{ord}(ph)=p^{r}<p^{k}, so pr(ph)=0=pr(f(g))+prxp^{r}(ph)=0=p^{r}(f(g))+p^{r}x. As the sum f(G)+Xf(G)+X is direct, prf(g)=prx=0p^{r}f(g)=p^{r}x=0, which means that prg=0p^{r}g=0, which is impossible.

2) sps\neq p. For abelian groups of period pp, the mapping gsgg\mapsto sg is an automorphism, so, as sh=f(g)+xsh=f(g)+x for some gGg\in G, xXx\in X, there exist such g1Gg_{1}\in G, x1Xx_{1}\in X that g=sg1g=sg_{1}, x=sx1x=sx_{1}. Thus, s(hf(g1)x1)=0s(h-f(g_{1})-x_{1})=0. No nontrivial element of HH has the order of ss, so h=f(g1)+x1h=f(g_{1})+x_{1}.

As a result, H=f(G)XH=f(G)\oplus X, and GG is a strong retract. ∎

Proposition 3.

The center of a strong retract is its direct factor.

Proof.

Let GG be a strong retract. The center of any group is a normal subgroup, so it suffices to prove that Z(G)Z(G) is a retract of GG. Consider the central product of GG with its copy G~\widetilde{G} with joined center:

K=G×Z(G)=Z(G~)G~=(G×G~)/{(g,g1)|gZ(G)}𝐯𝐚𝐫G.K=G\underset{Z(G)=Z(\tilde{G})}{\times}\tilde{G}=(G\times\tilde{G})/\{(g,g^{-1})|g\in Z(G)\}\in\operatorname{\mathbf{var}}G.

The group G~\tilde{G} is isomorphic to the group GG, so it is a strong retract too. Let ρ\rho be a retraction of KK to its subgroup G~\tilde{G}. From the fact that in the group KK, the group GG commutes with the group G~\tilde{G}, we obtain ρ(G)Z(G)\rho(G)\leqslant Z(G). By definition of the retraction, ρ(g)=g\rho(g)=g is true for any element gZ(G)g\in Z(G). Thus, the restriction of ρ\rho to the subgroup GG of the group KK is the desired retraction to Z(G)Z(G). ∎

The following simple proposition shows that consideration of nilpotent groups does not yield any new strong retracts:

Proposition 4.

Nilpotent strong retract is an abelian group.

Proof.

Any nontrivial normal subgroup of a nilpotent group intersects the center of this group nontrivially (see [KM79]). From this fact and from the proposition 33, we obtain that any nilpotent strong retract is equal to its center. ∎

As a result, we proved the following theorem:

Nilpotent-strong-retract theorem.

Nilpotent strong retracts are precisely divisible abelian groups and abelian groups of bounded period in whose decomposition into the direct sum of primary cyclic groups, orders of any distinct direct summands are either equal or coprime.

In the next paragraph we show that many nilpotent groups are not even strongly verbally closed.

3. Finite normal subgroups of strongly verbally closed groups

We say that a group presentation X|R\langle X\ |\ R\rangle is finitely presented over a group presentation Y|S\langle Y\ |\ S\rangle, if there exist such finite sets AA and BB that X|RX|R\langle X\ |\ R\rangle\cong\langle X^{\prime}\ |\ R^{\prime}\rangle, where X=YAX^{\prime}=Y\cup A, R=SBR^{\prime}=S\cup B.

The following lemma reveals that this definition is, in fact, a group property (which means it does not depend on the choice of a group presentation), so it makes sense to speak about the finite presentability of one group over the other group:

Lemma 1.

Suppose that a group presentation X|R\langle X\ |\ R\rangle is finitely presented over a group presentation Y|S\langle Y\ |\ S\rangle and Y|SY|S\langle Y\ |\ S\rangle\cong\langle Y^{\prime}\ |\ S^{\prime}\rangle. Then X|R\langle X\ |\ R\rangle is finitely presented over Y|S\langle Y^{\prime}\ |\ S^{\prime}\rangle.

Proof.

We may assume that X=YAX=Y\cup A and R=SBR=S\cup B for some finite sets AA and BB. It is known (see, for example, [LS15]) that groups defined by group presentations Y|S\langle Y\ |\ S\rangle and Y|S\langle Y^{\prime}\ |\ S^{\prime}\rangle are isomorphic if and only if presentation Y|S\langle Y^{\prime}\ |\ S^{\prime}\rangle is obtained from presentation Y|S\langle Y\ |\ S\rangle by applying a finite number of Tietze transformations:

  • adding to the set SS an arbitrary set TSF(Y)T\subseteq\langle\langle S\rangle\rangle\unlhd F(Y) of its consequences,

  • adding to the set YY an arbitrary set Y~\widetilde{Y} while ading to SS a set {y~=wy~|y~Y~,wy~F(Y)}\{\widetilde{y}=w_{\widetilde{y}}\ |\ \widetilde{y}\in\widetilde{Y},w_{\widetilde{y}}\in F(Y)\},

and their inverses. It is sufficient to prove the lemma only for the case, when Y|S\langle Y^{\prime}\ |\ S^{\prime}\rangle is obtained from Y|S\langle Y\ |\ S\rangle by applying one Tietze transformation. One can easily verify that in case of the first transformation, X=XX^{\prime}=X and R=RTR^{\prime}=R\cup T, while in case of the second transformation, X=XY~X^{\prime}=X\cup\widetilde{Y} and R=R{y~=wy~|y~Y~,wy~F(Y)}R^{\prime}=R\cup\{\widetilde{y}=w_{\widetilde{y}}\ |\ \widetilde{y}\in\widetilde{Y},w_{\widetilde{y}}\in F(Y)\} provide the desired group presentation. ∎

By virtue of Lemma 11, the following definition may be introduced:

A group GG is finitely presented over a group HH, if there exists such a presentation of GG that it is finitely presented over any presentation of HH.

Lemma 2.

Suppose that GG contains a subgroup HH and a finite normal subgroup NN such that G/NG/N is finitely presented over H/(HN)H/(H\cap N). Then GG is finitely presented over HH.

Proof (with minor changes) replicates the proof of the Hall theorem [Hal54] about preservation of finite presentability of a group under extensions (see also [Rob82]).

Let GG be a group, H=X|RGH=\langle X\ |\ R\rangle\leqslant G, and N=Y|SGN=\langle Y\ |\ S\rangle\ \unlhd\ G be its finite subgroup, where YY and SS are finite sets. By condition of the lemma, the group G/NG/N is finitely presented over H/(HN)=X|RCH/(H\cap N)=\langle X\ |\ R\cup C\rangle, where C=HN\langle\langle C\rangle\rangle=H\cap N and the set CC is finite. Consequently

G/NXA|RCB,G/N\cong\langle X\cup A\ |\ R\cup C\cup B\rangle,

where sets AA and BB are finite.

Let us construct a presentation of the group GG. As the set of generators, take X¯A¯Y¯\overline{X}\cup\overline{A}\cup\overline{Y}, where sets X¯\overline{X}, A¯\overline{A}, Y¯\overline{Y} are in one-to-one correspondence with sets XX, AA, YY respectively. The sets RR, SS, CC, and BB are in correspondence with the sets R¯\overline{R}, S¯\overline{S}, C¯\overline{C}, and B¯\overline{B} respectively. As the set of defining relations, take the union of the following sets: R¯\overline{R}, S¯\overline{S}, C¯1={cwc1|cC¯,wcF(Y¯)}\overline{C}_{1}=\{cw_{c}^{-1}\ |\ c\in\overline{C},w_{c}\in F(\overline{Y})\}, B¯1={bwb1|bB¯,wbF(Y¯)}\overline{B}_{1}=\{bw_{b}^{-1}\ |\ b\in\overline{B},w_{b}\in F(\overline{Y})\} (cC¯c\in\overline{C} and bB¯b\in\overline{B} are considered as words from F(X¯)F(\overline{X}) and from F(X¯A¯)F(\overline{X}\cup\overline{A}) respectively), T¯={a1yawa,y1,aya1va,y1|aA¯,yY¯,wa,y,va,yF(Y¯)}\overline{T}=\{a^{-1}yaw_{a,y}^{-1},\ aya^{-1}v_{a,y}^{-1}\ |\ a\in\overline{A},y\in\overline{Y},\ w_{a,y},v_{a,y}\in F(\overline{Y})\}:

G~=X¯A¯Y¯|R¯S¯C¯1B¯1T¯.\widetilde{G}=\langle\overline{X}\cup\overline{A}\cup\overline{Y}\ |\ \overline{R}\cup\overline{S}\cup\overline{C}_{1}\cup\overline{B}_{1}\cup\overline{T}\rangle.

Consider a surjective homomorphism θ:G~G\theta:\widetilde{G}\to G, defined with the following bijections X¯X\overline{X}\to X, A¯A\overline{A}\to A, Y¯Y\overline{Y}\to Y on the generators (defining relations are mapped into true identities under such a map on generators, so such a homomorphism exists). The restriction θ|K:KN\theta|_{K}:K\to N on the subgroup K=Y¯G~K=\langle\overline{Y}\rangle\leqslant\widetilde{G} is an isomorphism as all the relations in the alphabet Y¯\overline{Y} in G~\widetilde{G} are consequences of the defining relations S¯\overline{S}. Besides, KG~K\unlhd\widetilde{G}.

Homomorphism θ~:G~/KG/N\widetilde{\theta}:\widetilde{G}/K\to G/N generated by θ\theta, is an isomorphism too. Now, let gkerθg\in\ker\theta. Then gKkerθ~gK\in\ker\widetilde{\theta}, but θ~\widetilde{\theta} is an isomorphism, so gKg\in K. Finally, θ|K\theta|_{K} is an isomorphism, so g=1g=1. ∎

The following lemma provides a criterion for algebraic closedness of a subgroup HH of a group GG in case, when GG is finitely presented over HH (for similar propositions, refer to [MR14]):

Lemma 3.

Suppose that H=X|RH=\langle X\ |\ R\rangle is a subgroup of GG and GG is finitely presented over HH. The subgroup HH is algebraically closed in GG if and only if HH is a retract of GG.

Proof.

Suppose HH is algebraically closed in GG and A={a1,,am}A=\{a_{1},\dots,a_{m}\}, B={s1,,sn}B=\{s_{1},\dots,s_{n}\} are the sets from the definition of finite presentability of GG over HH. The relations si(a1,,am,X)=1s_{i}(a_{1},\dots,a_{m},X)=1, i=1,,ni=1,\dots,n are corresponded to a system of equations with coefficients from HH:

{s1(t1,,tm,X)=1sn(t1,,tm,X)=1\begin{cases}s_{1}(t_{1},\dots,t_{m},X)=1\\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \dots\\ s_{n}(t_{1},\dots,t_{m},X)=1\\ \end{cases}

which, by condition, has a solution t1=a1,,tm=amt_{1}=a_{1},\dots,t_{m}=a_{m}. By virtue of algebraic closedness of HH in GG, this system has a solution t1=h1,,tm=hmt_{1}=h_{1},\dots,t_{m}=h_{m} in HH. Mapping X{a1,,am}H,X\sqcup\{a_{1},\dots,a_{m}\}\to H, xXxx\in X\mapsto x, aihia_{i}\mapsto h_{i} extends to a surjective homomorphism φ:GH\varphi:G\to H, as defining relations of GG are mapped into true identities under such a mapping of generators (note that RR is the set of words in the alphabet XX).

This homomorphism is the desired retraction: let hHh\in H,  h=v(x1,,xr)h=v(x_{1},\dots,x_{r}), xiXx_{i}\in X. Applying to this word the homomorphism φ\varphi, we get: φ(h)=v(φ(x1),,φ(xr))=h\varphi(h)=v(\varphi(x_{1}),\dots,\varphi(x_{r}))=h.

Algebraic closedness of a subgroup HH of a group GG follows from retractness of HH in GG for every group GG [MR14]. ∎

Approximation lemma.

Let CC be a finite elementary abelian pp-group (where pp is a prime number). For any kk\in\mathbb{N}, there exists tkt\geqslant k such that the direct product P=×i=1tCiP=\mbox{\Large$\times$}_{i=1}^{t}C_{i} of copies CiC_{i} of CC contains a subgroup RR invariant with respect to the diagonal action on PP of the endomorphism algebra EndC\operatorname{End}C with the following properties:

  1. 1)

    RkerρjR\subseteq\bigcup\ker\rho_{j}, where ρj:PCj\rho_{j}:P\to C_{j}, j=1,,tj=1,\dots,t are the natural projections,

  2. 2)

    But R×jJCj=PR\cdot\mbox{\Large$\times$}_{j\not\in J}C_{j}=P for any subset J{1,,t}J\subseteq\{1,\dots,t\} of cardinality |J|=k|J|=k,

  3. 3)

    Moreover, each such JJ is contained in a set JJJ^{\prime}\supseteq J such that P=R×(×jJCj)P=R\times(\mbox{\Large$\times$}_{j\not\in J^{\prime}}C_{j}); and there exist integers nijn_{ij}\in\mathbb{Z} such that the projection π:P×jJCj\pi:P\to\mbox{\Large$\times$}_{j\not\in J^{\prime}}C_{j} with the kernel RR acts as: CicijJcjnijC_{i}\ni c_{i}\mapsto\prod_{j\not\in J^{\prime}}c_{j}^{n_{ij}}, where cjCjc_{j}\in C_{j} is the element corresponding to cic_{i} under the isomorphism CiCCjC_{i}\cong C\cong C_{j}.

The following theorem provides a generalization of the result from [KMO21] about the center of a finite strongly verbally closed group. The proof is also analogical to the proof of that theorem, with the exception of some nuances.

Finite-normal-subgroup theorem.

Let HH be a strongly verbally closed group. For any finite normal subgroup TT of HH, for any abelian subgroup AA of TT, normal in HH, it is true that Z(CT(A))Z(C_{T}(A)) is a direct factor of CT(A)C_{T}(A), and some complement is normal in HH. Here CT(X)=C(X)TC_{T}(X)=C(X)\cap T.

Proof.

Let HH be such a group, and let L=CT(A)L=C_{T}(A). It suffices, for each prime pp, to find a homomorphism ψp:LZ(L)\psi_{p}:L\to Z(L) commuting with the action HLH\curvearrowright L by conjugations (this action is well-defined as LHL\unlhd H) and injective on the pp-component of the center Zp(L)Z_{p}(L) of LL. Then the homomorphism ψ:LZ(L),\psi:L\to Z(L), xpπp(ψp(x))x\mapsto\displaystyle\prod_{p}\pi_{p}(\psi_{p}(x)), where πp:Z(L)Zp(L)\pi_{p}:Z(L)\to Z_{p}(L) is the projection on the pp-component, is injective on Z(L)Z(L), so its kernel is the desired complement DD (normality of DD in HH follows from the fact that ψ\psi commutes with HLH\curvearrowright L).

Suppose that there are no such homomorphisms for some prime number pp, i.e. every homomorphism f:LZ(L)f:L\to Z(L) commuting with the action HLH\curvearrowright L is not injective on Zp(L)Z_{p}(L). Then it is not injective on the maximal elementary abelian pp-subgroup CZp(L)C\leqslant Z_{p}(L) (it is finite as LL is finite). Indeed, if x1Zp(L)x\neq 1\in Z_{p}(L) is an element such that f(x)=1f(x)=1, then, raising it to the appropriate power dd, we get f(xd)=1f(x^{d})=1 and xdCx^{d}\in C, xd1x^{d}\neq 1.

Choose tt by the approximation lemma applied to CC (for some kk to be specified later) and consider the fibered product of tt copies of the group HH:

Q={(h1,,ht)|h1L==htL}Ht.Q=\{(h_{1},\dots,h_{t})\ |\ h_{1}L=\dots=h_{t}L\}\leqslant H^{t}.

First of all, let us show that the subgroup RCtQR\leqslant C^{t}\leqslant Q from the approximation lemma is normal in QQ. Subgroup RR is invariant under the diagonal action of automorphisms AutCEndC\operatorname{Aut}C\leqslant\operatorname{End}C. It remains to show that QQ acts by conjugations on P=CtP=C^{t} diagonally. It follows from the lemma:

Lemma 4.

Let GG be a group, and NGN\unlhd G. If xC(N)=yC(N)xC(N)=yC(N) for some x,yGx,y\in G, then xx and yy act on NN (by conjugations) identically.

Proof.

From xC(N)=yC(N)xC(N)=yC(N) it follows that for some cC(N)c\in C(N), x=ycx=yc. Then for nNn\in N, we have:

x1nx=c1(y1ny)c=y1ny.x^{-1}nx=c^{-1}(y^{-1}ny)c=y^{-1}ny.

The last identity is true, as (due to normality) y1nyNy^{-1}ny\in N and cC(N)c\in C(N). ∎

Let q=(q1,,qt)Qq=(q_{1},\dots,q_{t})\in Q, p=(p1,,pt)Pp=(p_{1},\dots,p_{t})\in P. As q1L=q_{1}L= q2L=q_{2}L= =qtL\dots=q_{t}L, then (according to Lemma 44) q1pq=q^{-1}pq= q~1pq~\tilde{q}^{-1}p\tilde{q}, where q~=(q1,,q1)\tilde{q}=(q_{1},\dots,q_{1}). It means that the conjugation action of QQ on PP is diagonal. On the other hand, diagonal action by conjugations induces an endomorphism of CtC^{t} (due to normality of CHC\unlhd H), and RR is invariant with respect to the diagonal action of such endomorphisms, leading to normality of RR in QQ.

Put G=Q/RG=Q/R. First, let us show that HH embeds into GG. The group HH embeds into QQ diagonally: h(h,,h)h\mapsto(h,\dots,h), hHh\in H. This homomorphism serves as embedding into GG as well, as all projections of any nontrivial diagonal element of QQ are nontrivial (and RR is contained in the union of the kernels of these projections).

Now, let us prove the verbal closedness of this diagonal subgroup (denote it as HH too) in GG. Consider an equation

w(x1,,xn)=(h,,h)w(x_{1},\dots,x_{n})=(h,\dots,h)

having a solution in GG and let x~1,,x~n\tilde{x}_{1},\dots,\tilde{x}_{n} be a preimage (in QQ) of a solution x1,,xnx_{1},\dots,x_{n}. Then (in QQ):

w(x~1,,x~n)=(hc1,,hct),w(\tilde{x}_{1},\dots,\tilde{x}_{n})=(hc_{1},\dots,hc_{t}),

where (c1,,ct)R(c_{1},\dots,c_{t})\in R. By the property 1)1) of the approximation lemma, ci=1c_{i}=1 for some ii. It means that in HH (the group itself) w(x~1i,,x~ni)=hw(\tilde{x}_{1}^{i},\dots,\tilde{x}_{n}^{i})=h, where x~ji\tilde{x}_{j}^{i} is the iith coordinate of the vector x~j\tilde{x}_{j}, j=1,,nj=1,\dots,n.

Let us take yj=(x~ji,,x~ji)y_{j}=(\tilde{x}_{j}^{i},\dots,\tilde{x}_{j}^{i}), j=1,,nj=1,\dots,n. Then in HGH\leqslant G the following is true:

w(y1,,yn)=(h,,h),w(y_{1},\dots,y_{n})=(h,\dots,h),

which proves the verbal closedness of HH in GG.

Let ULU\leqslant L. We use the following denotion:

Ui:={(1,,1,u,1,,1)|uU}Q,i=1,,t (coordinate u stands on the ith place).U_{i}:=\{(1,\dots,1,u,1,\dots,1)\ |\ u\in U\}\leqslant Q,\ i=1,\dots,t\text{ (coordinate }u\text{ stands on the }i\text{th place)}.

It remains to prove that HH is not algebraically closed in GG.

Lemma 5.

The group QQ is finitely presented over its subgroup HH.

Proof.

According to Lemma 22, it is sufficient to show that Q/(L1××Lt)Q/(L_{1}\times\dots\times L_{t}) is finitely presented over H/L~H/\tilde{L}, where L~={(l,,l)|lL}\tilde{L}=\{(l,\dots,l)\ |\ l\in L\}. However, Q=H(L1××Lt)Q=H\cdot(L_{1}\times\dots\times L_{t}), so the statement we prove follows from this fact (see [KM79], theorem 4.2.44.2.4):

Suppose that GG is a group, FF is its subgroup, and KK is its normal subgroup. Then (KF)/KF/(FK)(K\cdot F)/K\cong F/(F\cap K).

Thus, the group Q/(L1××Lt)Q/(L_{1}\times\dots\times L_{t}) is not just finitely presented over H/L~H/\tilde{L} but is isomorphic to it. ∎

From Lemma 33 and Lemma 55, it follows that it suffices to show that HH is not a retract of GG. Let ρ:GH\rho:G\to H be a hypothetical retraction, and let ρ^:QH\hat{\rho}:Q\to H be its composition with the natural epimorphism QQ/R=GQ\to Q/R=G. Henceforth, all subgroups and centralizers we refer to relate to QQ.

Let us verify that ρ^(Li)CT(CT(L))L\hat{\rho}(L_{i})\leqslant C_{T}(C_{T}(L))\leqslant L for every ii. First, prove the left inclusion. Let hCT(L)h\in C_{T}(L). Then, hh commutes with every element from LL; consequently, hh, as an element of QQ, commutes with LiL_{i}. Applying the retraction ρ^\hat{\rho} to this identity, we get that ρ^(h)\hat{\rho}(h) (=h)(=h) commutes with the subgroup ρ^(Li)\hat{\rho}(L_{i}), which (by definition of the centralizer) proves the inclusion. The second inclusion follows from the fact that L=CT(A)=L=C_{T}(A)= C(A)TC(A)\cap T, which means that

CT(CT(L))CT(AT)=CT(A)=L.C_{T}(C_{T}(L))\leqslant C_{T}(A\cap T)=C_{T}(A)=L.

The first inclusion here is true as C(L)AC(L)\geqslant A. The following equality is true as ATA\leqslant T.

On the other hand, for iji\neq j, the mutual commutator subgroup [Li,Lj][L_{i},L_{j}] is trivial (as in case ii and jj are different, LiL_{i} and LjL_{j} are contained in different components of the fibered product). It means that the image of this mutual commutator subgroup is trivial too: [ρ^(Li),ρ^(Lj)]={1}[\hat{\rho}(L_{i}),\hat{\rho}(L_{j})]=\{1\}. Consequently, [Li,jiLj]={1}[L_{i},\prod_{j\neq i}L_{j}]=\{1\} and [ρ^(Li),jiρ^(Lj)]={1}[\hat{\rho}(L_{i}),\prod_{j\neq i}\hat{\rho}(L_{j})]=\{1\}. If ρ^(Li)=ρ^(Ll)\hat{\rho}(L_{i})=\hat{\rho}(L_{l}) for some ili\neq l, then (by the virtue of well-known commutator identities) [ρ^(Li),jρ^(Lj)]={1}[\hat{\rho}(L_{i}),\prod_{j}\hat{\rho}(L_{j})]=\{1\}, which means that ρ^(Li)CT(L)\hat{\rho}(L_{i})\leqslant C_{T}(L) (as L=ρ^(L)jρ^(Lj)L=\hat{\rho}(L)\leqslant\prod_{j}\hat{\rho}(L_{j})).

Thereby, if for some different ii and jj, ρ^(Li)=ρ^(Lj)\hat{\rho}(L_{i})=\hat{\rho}(L_{j}), then ρ^(Li)CT(L)\hat{\rho}(L_{i})\leqslant C_{T}(L). From here and from the inclusion we proved earlier, we get ρ^(Li)LCT(L)=\hat{\rho}(L_{i})\leqslant L\cap C_{T}(L)= Z(L)Z(L).

Let us take kk in the approximation lemma to be the number of all subgroups of TT, and let JJ be the set of all exclusive numbers ii, namely such that for any lil\neq i, ρ^(Li)ρ^(Ll)\hat{\rho}(L_{i})\neq\hat{\rho}(L_{l}). Since among ρ^(Li)T\hat{\rho}(L_{i})\leqslant T there are no more than kk different subgroups, |J|k|J|\leqslant k. Thus, from the property 3)3) of the approximation lemma, we have a decomposition:

×i=1tCi=R×(×iICi),\mbox{\Large$\times$}_{i=1}^{t}C_{i}=R\times(\mbox{\Large$\times$}_{i\in I}C_{i}),

where I{1,,t}JI\subseteq\{1,\dots,t\}\setminus J is some set of non-exclusive elements. Again, according to the property 3)3) of the approximation lemma, the projection π:×i=1tCi×iICi\pi:\mbox{\Large$\times$}_{i=1}^{t}C_{i}\to\mbox{\Large$\times$}_{i\in I}C_{i} onto the second factor of this decomposition is defined by an integer matrix (nij)(n_{ij}), namely, for ciCic_{i}\in C_{i}, π:cijIcjnij\pi:c_{i}\mapsto\prod_{j\in I}c_{j}^{n_{ij}}, where cjc_{j} are elements corresponding to cic_{i} under the isomorphism CiCCjC_{i}\cong C\cong C_{j}.

This means that the restriction of π\pi to C={(c,,c)|cCH}C=\{(c,\dots,c)\ |\ c\in C\leqslant H\} is defined by formula:

π^:(c,,c)jIcjmj,mj=inij.\hat{\pi}:(c,\dots,c)\mapsto\prod_{j\in I}c_{j}^{m_{j}},\ m_{j}=\sum_{i}n_{ij}.

Here cjc_{j} are elements corresponding to cc under the isomorphism CCjC\cong C_{j}.

Then (as iIi\in I are non-exclusive, we have ρ^(Li)Z(L)\hat{\rho}(L_{i})\leqslant Z(L)), consider the composition:

Ψ:CQZ(L),c𝜋jIcjmjρ^jIρ^(cjmj).\Psi:C\leqslant Q\to Z(L),\ c\overset{\pi}{\mapsto}\prod_{j\in I}c_{j}^{m_{j}}\overset{\hat{\rho}}{\mapsto}\prod_{j\in I}\hat{\rho}(c_{j}^{m_{j}}).

It extends to a homomorphism Φ:LZ(L)\Phi:L\to Z(L) defined by the similar formula:

Φ:gjIρ^(gjmj),\Phi:g\mapsto\prod_{j\in I}\hat{\rho}(g_{j}^{m_{j}}),

where gLg\in L and gjLjg_{j}\in L_{j} are elements corresponding to gLg\in L. Obviously, it is an extension of Ψ\Psi and a homomorphism, as for jIj\in I, ρ^(Lj)Z(L)\hat{\rho}(L_{j})\leqslant Z(L) and the group Z(L)Z(L) is abelian. This homomorphism commutes with the conjugation action of HH on LL. Indeed, let gHg\in H and let 𝔤\mathfrak{g} be the action of gg on LL by conjugation, namely, for xLx\in L, 𝔤(x)=g1xg\mathfrak{g}(x)=g^{-1}xg. Let us show that Φ𝔤=𝔤Φ\Phi\circ\mathfrak{g}=\mathfrak{g}\circ\Phi. Let hLh\in L. Then Φ(𝔤(h))=\Phi(\mathfrak{g}(h))= jIρ^(g1hjmjg)=\prod_{j\in I}\hat{\rho}(g^{-1}h_{j}^{m_{j}}g)= jIg1ρ^(hjmj)g=\prod_{j\in I}g^{-1}\hat{\rho}(h_{j}^{m_{j}})g= 𝔤(Φ(h))\mathfrak{g}(\Phi(h)). Penult identity is true, as ρ^\hat{\rho} is a retraction on HH, so it acts identically on HH itself. By assumption we made in the beginning, the kernel of this homomorphism has nontrivial intersection with CC: kerΦC{1}\ker\Phi\cap C\neq\{1\}, so the restriction Ψ=Φ|C\Psi=\Phi|_{C} has a nontrivial kernel too.

On the other hand, Ψ\Psi is the identical mapping, since Ψ=ρ^|Cπ|C=\Psi=\hat{\rho}|_{C}\circ\pi|_{C}= ρ^|Cπ^=\hat{\rho}|_{C}\circ\hat{\pi}= ρ^|C\hat{\rho}|_{C} (the last identity is true as π^\hat{\pi} is a projection <<forgetting>> the RR coordinate, and ρ^(R)={1}\hat{\rho}(R)=\{1\} is a composition of the natural homomorphism to the quotient group and of the retraction to HH) and ρ^|C=id\hat{\rho}|_{C}=id, as ρ^\hat{\rho} is the retraction from QQ to HH, so it acts trivially on CC. The obtained contradiction completes the proof. ∎

Let us provide some corollaries of this theorem:

Corollary 1.

Finitely generated nilpotent groups with nonabelian torsion subgroups are not strongly verbally closed.

Proof.

Let us take the torsion subgroup of such group as TT from the theorem, and the center of this torsion subgroup as A{1}A\neq\{1\}. Since TT is nilpotent and nonabelian, every nontrivial normal subgroup of TT has a nontrivial intersection with AA [KM79], so AA is not a direct factor of TT. ∎

Corollary 2 [KMO21].

A finite group, whose center is not a direct factor is not strongly verbally closed.

This theorem does not cover the case of finitely generated nilpotent nonabelian groups with abelian torsion subgroups, and it is still unknown whether there are strongly verbally closed groups among such groups. So far, we can provide only a partial answer to this question (see the first proposition of the following paragraph).

4. Nilpotent non-strongly-verbally-closed groups

Let us remind that the discrete Heisenberg group is the free nilpotent group of the nilpotency class two with two free generators. It can be easily verified that this group admits a faithful representation in the group of upper triangular matrices of size 33 by 33.

Proposition 5.

Let HH be the discrete Heisenberg group with aa and bb being its free generators and NN being its subgroup:

N=aα,[a,b]n,α,n0.N=\langle\langle a^{\alpha},[a,b]^{n}\rangle\rangle,\ \alpha,n\geqslant 0.

The group G=H/NG=H/N is strongly verbally closed if and only if gcd(α,n)=1\text{gcd}(\alpha,n)=1.

Proof.

Let T(G)T(G) be the torsion subgroup of GG. The center of the group HH is equal to its commutator subgroup, and it is isomorphic to the infinite cyclic group. As it was said earlier (refer to the proof of the Proposition 44), any nontrivial normal subgroup of a nilpotent group intersects its center nontrivially. Thus, if T(G)={1}T(G)=\{1\}, then either G=HG=H is the discrete Heisenberg group, or GG is abelian. Non-strong-verbal-closedness of HH was proved in [KMO21], and the strong verbal closedness of abelian groups was proved in [Maz18]. The case of T(G)={1}T(G)=\{1\} corresponds to the case of α=0\alpha=0, n=0n=0 and α=0\alpha=0, n=1n=1.

If gcd(α,n)=1\text{gcd}(\alpha,n)=1, then, once again, GG is abelian, since [a,b]α=[aα,b]N[a,b]^{\alpha}=[a^{\alpha},b]\in N; consequently, it is strongly verbally closed.

Consider the case, when gcd(α,n)=d1\text{gcd}(\alpha,n)=d\neq 1. Without loss of generality, we may assume that α\alpha and nn are the least of non-negative numbers such that aαNa^{\alpha}\in N, [a,b]nN[a,b]^{n}\in N. Consider the central product of GG with its copy G~\tilde{G} with joined commutator subgroup:

K=G×G=G~G~=(G×G~)/{(c,c1)|cG}.K=G\underset{G^{\prime}=\tilde{G}^{\prime}}{\times}\tilde{G}=(G\times\tilde{G})/\{(c,c^{-1})|c\in G^{\prime}\}.

The group GG is not algebraically closed in KK, since GG is not a retract of KK. Indeed, let ρ\rho be a hypothetical retraction. The group GG commutes with G~\tilde{G} in KK, so ρ(G~)Z(G)\rho(\tilde{G})\leqslant Z(G) and ρ(G~)={1}\rho(\tilde{G}^{\prime})=\{1\}, which leads to a contradiction with the definition of retraction. However, GG is verbally closed in KK. Let wF(t1,,ts)w\in F(t_{1},\dots,t_{s}) be some word and

w((h1N,h1N),,(hsN,hsN))=(hN,N)w((h_{1}N,h_{1}^{\prime}N),\dots,(h_{s}N,h_{s}^{\prime}N))=(hN,N)

for some hN,hiNGhN,h_{i}N\in G, hiNG~h_{i}^{\prime}N\in\tilde{G}. Then, for some cNGcN\in G^{\prime}, the following holds:

{w(h1,,hs)N=cNw(h1,,hs)N=hc1N\begin{cases}w(h_{1}^{\prime},\dots,h_{s}^{\prime})N=cN\\ w(h_{1},\dots,h_{s})N=hc^{-1}N\\ \end{cases}

By an automorphism of the free group, the word ww can be reduced to a normal form [KMO21]: w(t1,,ts)=t1mw(t1,,ts)w(t_{1},\dots,t_{s})=t_{1}^{m}w^{\prime}(t_{1},\dots,t_{s}), where mm\in\mathbb{N}, wFsw^{\prime}\in F_{s}^{\prime}. From the first equation, we get cNGφ(Gs)cN\in G^{\prime}\ \cap\ \varphi(G^{s}), where φ:GsG,\varphi:G^{s}\to G, (g1,,gs)(g_{1},\dots,g_{s}) w(g1,,gs)\mapsto w(g_{1},\dots,g_{s}) is a verbal mapping. This means that for some w1,w2Nw_{1},w_{2}\in N, in HH it is true that:

{w(h1,,hs)=cw1w(h1,,hs)=hc1w2\begin{cases}w(h_{1}^{\prime},\dots,h_{s}^{\prime})=cw_{1}\\ w(h_{1},\dots,h_{s})=hc^{-1}w_{2}\\ \end{cases}

Let us show that in GG the identity (aN)x=[aN,bN]z(aN)^{x}=[aN,bN]^{z} doesn’t hold for xαx\not\in\alpha\mathbb{Z}. Converse would mean that in the discrete Heisenberg group the following holds:

ax[a,b]z=bkalaαt[a,b]nsalbka^{x}[a,b]^{-z}=b^{-k}a^{-l}a^{\alpha t}[a,b]^{ns}a^{l}b^{k}

for some k,l,t,sk,l,t,s\in\mathbb{Z}. After some reductions, we get: axαt=[a,b]ns+z+αtka^{x-\alpha t}=[a,b]^{ns+z+\alpha tk}. In HH it is possible only if x=αtαx=\alpha t\in\alpha\mathbb{Z}. We obtained a contradiction. Thus, h1=[a,b]γh_{1}^{\prime}=[a,b]^{\gamma} for some γ\gamma\in\mathbb{Z}, and, consequently, cw1Hcw_{1}\in H^{\prime}. Since for any verbal mapping φ\varphi in the discrete Heisenberg group (see [KMO21])

for any gφ(Hs), it is true that g(φ(Hs)H)φ(Hs),\text{for any }g\in\varphi(H^{s}),\text{ it is true that }g(\varphi(H^{s})\cap H^{\prime})\subseteq\varphi(H^{s}),

for some g1,,gsHg_{1},\dots,g_{s}\in H, w(g1,,gs)=w(g_{1},\dots,g_{s})= w(h1,,hs)cw1w(h_{1},\dots,h_{s})cw_{1}. It means that:

w(g1,,gs)=hw3w(g_{1},\dots,g_{s})=hw_{3}

for some w3Ww_{3}\in W, and in GG:

w(g1,,gs)N=hN,w(g_{1},\dots,g_{s})N=hN,

which proves verbal closedness of GG in KK. ∎

At last, let us prove that the higher dimensional Heisenberg groups over any field are not strongly verbally closed:

The Heisenberg group of dimension 2n+12n+1 over a field KK, where nn\in\mathbb{N} is the group of upper triangular matrices of the kind

Hn(K)={T(a¯,b¯,c)=(1a¯c0Inb¯001)|a¯,(b¯)Kn,cK},H_{n}(K)=\Bigg{\{}T(\bar{a},\bar{b},c)=\begin{pmatrix}1&\bar{a}&c\\ 0&I_{n}&\bar{b}\\ 0&0&1\\ \end{pmatrix}\Bigg{|}\bar{a},(\bar{b})^{\intercal}\in K^{n},c\in K\Bigg{\}},

where InI_{n} is the identity matrix of size nn.

Proposition 6.

The group Hn(K)H_{n}(K) is not strongly verbally closed.

Proof.

Consider the central product of Hn(K)H_{n}(K) with its copy H~n(K)\tilde{H}_{n}(K) with joined commutator subgroup:

G=Hn(K)×Hn(K)=H~n(K)H~n(K).G=H_{n}(K)\underset{H_{n}(K)^{\prime}=\tilde{H}_{n}(K)^{\prime}}{\times}\tilde{H}_{n}(K).

Denote with the symbol HH the first factor of this central product. Let us show that HH is not algebraically closed in GG. The group HH is linear, and, consequently, it is equationally noetherian [BMR99], so it is algebraically closed in GG if and only if it is a retract of every finitely generated over HH subgroup of GG [KMM18]. In particular, of such a subgroup of GG:

H¯=H,(1,h1),,(1,hn),(1,g1),,(1,gn), where hi=(1a¯i00In0001),gi=(1000Inb¯i001),\bar{H}=\langle H,(1,h_{1}),\dots,(1,h_{n}),(1,g_{1}),\dots,(1,g_{n})\rangle\text{, where }h_{i}=\begin{pmatrix}1&\bar{a}_{i}&0\\ 0&I_{n}&0\\ 0&0&1\\ \end{pmatrix},g_{i}=\begin{pmatrix}1&0&0\\ 0&I_{n}&\bar{b}_{i}\\ 0&0&1\\ \end{pmatrix},

where a¯i=(0,,1,,0)=(b¯i)\bar{a}_{i}=(0,\dots,1,\dots,0)=(\bar{b}_{i})^{\intercal}, (unit is on the iith place). Thus, N=h1,,hn,g1,,gnN=\langle h_{1},\dots,h_{n},g_{1},\dots,g_{n}\rangle is a subgroup of H~n(K)\widetilde{H}_{n}(K), isomorphic to the discrete Heisenberg group of the dimension (2n+1)(2n+1). Let ρ\rho be a hypothetical retraction. Since in GG the group HH commutes with NN, we get that ρ(N)={1}\rho(N^{\prime})=\{1\}, which leads to a contradiction with the definition of retraction.

Nevertheless, subgroup HH is verbally closed in GG: let wFsw\in F_{s} be some word (without loss of generality, this word is in the normal form we established earlier), and let φ:HsH\varphi:H^{s}\to H be the verbal mapping associated with this word. Suppose that for some hi,hHh_{i},h\in H, hiH~h_{i}^{\prime}\in\tilde{H}, cHc\in H^{\prime}:

{w(h1,,hs)=cw(h1,,hs)=hc1\begin{cases}w(h_{1}^{\prime},\dots,h_{s}^{\prime})=c\\ w(h_{1},\dots,h_{s})=hc^{-1}\\ \end{cases}

In general, on matrices gi=T(a¯i,b¯i,ci)g_{i}=T(\bar{a}_{i},\bar{b}_{i},c_{i}), i=1,,si=1,\dots,s, the mapping φ\varphi acts like that:

φ(g1,,gs)=(1ma¯1mc1+f(a¯1,,a¯s;b¯1,,b¯s)0Inmb¯1001),\varphi(g_{1},\dots,g_{s})=\begin{pmatrix}1&m\bar{a}_{1}&mc_{1}+f(\bar{a}_{1},\dots,\bar{a}_{s};\bar{b}_{1},\dots,\bar{b}_{s})\\ 0&I_{n}&m\bar{b}_{1}\\ 0&0&1\\ \end{pmatrix},

where f:(Kn)s×(Kn)sKf:(K^{n})^{s}\times(K^{n})^{s}\to K is some function linear in every argument. The image of ff is either trivial or is equal to KK, which leads to:

φ(Hn(K)s)={{1}, if m=0 and the image of f is trivial(Hn(K)), if m=0 and the image of f equals KHn(K), if m0\varphi(H_{n}(K)^{s})=\begin{cases}\{1\},&\text{ if }m=0\text{ and the image of }f\text{ is trivial}\\ (H_{n}(K))^{\prime},&\text{ if }m=0\text{ and the image of }f\text{ equals }K\\ H_{n}(K),&\text{ if }m\neq 0\end{cases}

Then φ(Hn(K)s)(Hn(K))Hn(K)\varphi(H_{n}(K)^{s})\cap(H_{n}(K))^{\prime}\leqslant H_{n}(K) and for every element hφ(Hn(K)s)h\in\varphi(H_{n}(K)^{s}) it is true that

h(φ(Hn(K)s)(Hn(K)))φ(Hn(K)s),h(\varphi(H_{n}(K)^{s})\cap(H_{n}(K))^{\prime})\subseteq\varphi(H_{n}(K)^{s}),

whence verbal closedness follows. ∎

References

  • [BMR99] G. Baumslag, A. Myasnikov and V. Remeslennikov ‘‘Algebraic geometry over groups I. Algebraic sets and ideal theory’’ J. Algebra, 219:1, 1999, pp. 16–79
  • [Bog22] O. Bogopolski ‘‘Equations in acylindrically hyperbolic groups and verbal closedness’’ Groups Geom. Dyn., 16:2, 2022, pp. 613–682
  • [Fuc70] L. Fuchs ‘‘Infinite Abelian Groups, v. 1’’ Academic Press, 1970
  • [Hal54] P. Hall ‘‘Finiteness conditions for soluble groups’’ Proc. Lond. Math. Soc., 4:1, 1954, pp. 419–436
  • [Kly21] A.. Klyachko ‘‘The Klein bottle group is not strongly verbally closed, though awfully close to being so’’ Canad. Math. Bull., 64:2, 2021, pp. 491–497
  • [KM18] A.. Klyachko and A.. Mazhuga ‘‘Verbally closed virtually free subgroups’’ Sb. Math., 209:6, 2018, pp. 850–856
  • [KM79] M.. Kargapolov and Ju.. Merzljakov ‘‘Fundamentals of the theory of groups’’ Graduate Texts in Mathematics, 62, Springer, 1979
  • [KMM18] A.. Klyachko, A.. Mazhuga and V.. Miroshnichenko ‘‘Virtually free finite-normal-subgroup-free groups are strongly verbally closed’’ J. Algebra, 510, 2018, pp. 319–330
  • [KMO21] A.. Klyachko, V.. Miroshnichenko and A.. Olshanskii ‘‘Finite and nilpotent strongly verbally closed groups’’ J. Algebra Appl. (to appear), 2021
  • [Kur60] A.. Kurosh ‘‘The theory of groups’’ Chelsea Publishing Company, 1960
  • [LS15] R. Lyndon and P. Schupp ‘‘Combinatorial group theory’’ Springer, 2015
  • [Maz18] A.. Mazhuga ‘‘Strongly verbally closed groups’’ J. Algebra, 493, 2018, pp. 171–184
  • [Maz19] A.. Mazhuga ‘‘Free products of groups are strongly verbally closed’’ Sb. Math., 210:10, 2019, pp. 1456–1492
  • [MR14] A. Myasnikov and V. Roman’kov ‘‘Verbally closed subgroups of free groups’’ J. Group Theory, 17:1, 2014, pp. 29–40
  • [Neu67] H. Neumann ‘‘Varieties of groups’’ Springer-Verlag, Berlin-Heidelberg-New York, 1967
  • [RKK17] V.. Roman’kov, N.. Khisamiev and A.. Konyrkhanova ‘‘Algebraically and verbally closed subgroups and retracts of finitely generated nilpotent groups’’ Siberian Math. J., 58:3, 2017, pp. 536–545
  • [Rob82] D… Robinson ‘‘A course in the theory of groups’’ Springer-Verlag, 1982