Deterministic all-versus-nothing proofs of Bell nonlocality based on non-stabilizer states
Abstract
The all-versus-nothing proof of Bell nonlocality is a kind of mainstream demonstration of Bell’s theorem without inequalities. Two kinds of such proofs, called the deterministic all-versus-nothing proof and the probabilistic all-versus-nothing proof, are both widely investigated. So far, all previous deterministic all-versus-nothing proofs of Bell nonlocality are constructed based on stabilizer states. To break with this tradition, some deterministic all-versus-nothing proofs induced from non-stabilizer states are firstly presented in this work. These results not only can greatly enrich the family of the demonstration of Bell nonlocality without inequalities, but also may provide us some useful resources in certain quantum information processing.
Keywords: Bell nonlocality, deterministic all-versus-nothing proof, Hardy-like quantum pigeonhole paradox, non-stabilizer States
1 Introduction
As one of the most striking features of quantum mechanics and a very important quantum resource of quantum information processing, nonlocality plays a significant role in quantum communication and computation. Among various kinds of nonlocality, the most common one is the Bell nonlocality[1, 2], which states that any local realistic model[1, 3] is incompatible with quantum mechanics. To show this quantum feature, a common approach is to test various of Bell inequalities[1, 3], but this approach can only reveal Bell nonlocality in a probabilistic manner. By contrast, another significant approach of demonstrating Bell nonlocality is to construct some logical contradictions. The corresponding proofs are usually called “Bell’s theorem without inequalities”[4, 5] or “nonlocality without inequalities”[6, 7], which can either be deterministic or probabilistic. The Greenberger-Horne-Zeilinger(GHZ) paradox[4, 5] and the Hardy’s paradox[6, 7] are two typical examples, which belong to two different kinds of all-versus-nothing(AVN) proofs[8] for Bell nonlocality, respectively. Precisely, the former provides a deterministic (or “always-type”) all-versus-nothing (DAVN) proof (which can rule out local realism with a success probability of , i.e., it works for each run of the experiment, and thus sometimes also referred to as “Bell nonlocality without probabilities”[9]), while the latter provides a probabilistic (or “sometimes-type”) AVN proof (in which the contradiction can only be obtained for some runs of the experiment, and thus the success probability of ruling out local realism is less than )[10]. Apart from the GHZ paradox and the Hardy’s paradox, many generalized versions from them also provide us very wonderful AVN proofs of Bell nonlocality, such as Cabello’s four-qubit AVN proof based on two maximally entangled states[11], the GHZ-type AVN proofs for mixed states[12, 13], and the multisetting GHZ-type AVN proofs[14]. Moreover, some of them have even been tested experimentally[15, 16, 17, 18].
It is noted that the quantum states in the DAVN proofs of Bell nonlocality are far more demanding than those in the probabilistic ones. Various GHZ paradoxes are the most common DAVN proofs, and the involved states are entangled stabilizer states (e.g. GHZ states). In such paradoxes, the systems are usually assumed to be described by local hidden variable (LHV) models, so that value assignments to the local observables (within the involved stabilizers) can be applied. Then one can always obtained a group of value assignment relations which cannot hold simultaneously, giving rise to a contradiction. Another representative DAVN proof is Cabello’s four-qubit AVN proof[11], wherein the system consisting of two Bell states (note that the whole system is still a stabilizer state) can induce a total of eight independent Hardy-like proofs of Bell nonlocality (each of them can rule out the LHV model with a probability of 12.5). Combining them together, one can get the desired DAVN proof. In fact, all of the reported DAVN proofs of Bell nonlocality so far are constructed based on stabilizer states. Then a natural question is: can one construct DAVN proofs of Bell nonlocality based on non-stabilizer states? Since the answer of this question may bring us some new understandings for more refined structures of multi-partite Bell non-locality, to address that is necessary.
On the other hand, it is known that DAVN proofs of Bell nonlocality (e.g. the GHZ paradox) have many important applications in quantum information processing, such as reducing communication complexity[19, 20], multiparty quantum key distribution[21], and quantum games[22]. It is also known that every property of quantum mechanics not present in classical physics could give rise to an operational advantage[23, 24, 25]. Therefore, if DAVN proofs derived from non-stabilizer states exist, they can provide us some useful resources in certain quantum information processing as well. In view of this, the exploration on such unconventional DAVN proofs is of great value.
2 A useful tool: the Hardy-like quantum pigeonhole paradox
To construct a DAVN proof of Bell nonlocality, one should first choose a suitable quantum state. It is worthy to notice that some quantum states can induce more than one probabilistic AVN proof (Hardy-like proof). Also note that combining all such probabilistic AVN proofs (induced from the same quantum state) together may greatly improve the success probability of ruling out local realism[11, 26]. As long as this success probability can be improved to , a DAVN proof can be produced. In view of this, the projected-coloring graph(PCG) state proposed very recently[26] seems be a suitable candidate. More precisely, if enough probabilistic AVN proofs can be induced from a PCG state, combining them together will give rise to a DAVN proof. Clearly, whether the DAVN proof is an unconventional or a conventional one relies on whether the given PCG state is a non-stabilizer state or a stabilizer state.
First, let us give the definition of a PCG state. For convenience, here we slightly generalize the -qubit PCG state referred to in [26] to the following form:
(1) |
where , , , (), and the coefficients . Besides, , and . Moreover, is the index set used for describing a group of specific subsets of . Note that the original PCG state needs to contain the component , while for the generalized one, such a requirement is not necessary.
The PCG state plays a central role in the construction of a kind of probabilistic AVN proof called the Hardy-like quantum pigeonhole (HLQP) paradox[26], which can rule out the LHV model[1, 3] by a logical contradiction from classical pigeonhole principle. Here we shall briefly show this quantum effect by resorting to a simple example.
Let us consider the three-qubit PCG state
(2) |
One can also check that it is essentially a GHZ state[26]. Let and be two “boxes” and each qubit be a “pigeon”. Equivalently, if the qubit stays in box , then ; otherwise . Then one can get the following properties (sometimes also referred to as Hardy-like conditions):
(3a) | |||||
(3b) | |||||
(3c) | |||||
(3d) |
Here , for example, stands for the conditional probability that , are measured and their outcomes satisfy given that the result of . Besides, is the joint probability of obtaining the results , and .
By invoking the properties of (3a) to (3d), one can construct a three-qubit HLQP paradox. To be specific, let three qubits of be distributed in different places (hereafter all the measurements are limited to spacelike separated measurements). Consider a run of the experiment that and are measured and the results and are obtained. Assume that can be modeled by a LHV theory, namely, for example, the outcome (a predefined value) of measuring is independent of the choice of the measurements performed on the other qubits. As a consequence, if and were measured in this run, their outcomes should satisfy (pigeon 2 and pigeon 3 are in different boxes). Likewise, similar constraints and must be satisfied in the same run as well. It follows that any pair of the “pigeons” are staying in different “boxes”, a contradiction by classical pigeonhole principle. Then one can get a three-qubit HLQP paradox. This paradox shows that any realistic interpretation of quantum mechanics must be nonlocal. For more complicated examples, see [26].
It is noted that only one type of HLQP paradox (associated with the measurement results ) was discussed in [26]. In fact, other different types of HLQP paradoxes may also be induced from a given PCG state. For example, apart from the group of Hardy-like conditions referred to in equation (3), different results given by the measurements of and can induce another three groups of Hardy-like conditions, and besides, each of them can produce a HLQP paradox. In other words, can induce a total of four probabilistic AVN proofs (HLQP paradoxes). Moreover, one can give a DAVN proof by combining these four HLQP paradoxes together. However, such a DAVN proof is still induced from a stabilizer state rather than from a non-stabilizer one, which is similar to the DAVN proof of Bell’s theorem proposed in [11]. For detailed discussion, see A.
3 The pictorial representation of a group of Hardy-like conditions
Since a HLQP paradox is associated with a group of Hardy-like conditions, as long as a graphical structure can faithfully represent this group of Hardy-like conditions, it can give a pictorial representation for the HLQP paradox. Based on this thought, any original HLQP paradox can be pictorially represented by a mathematical structure called the PCG[26]. Technically, similar representations can also be generalized other types of HLQP paradoxes, and for simplicity, such generalized representations are still referred to as PCGs. Next we will show how to use a PCG to represent a group of Hardy-like conditions.
Consider the following group of constraints induced from the aforementioned -qubit PCG state ,
(3d) | |||||
(3e) | |||||
(3f) | |||||
(3g) | |||||
(3h) |
where and . Besides, stands for , where , and . For convenience, we would still call these constraints a group of Hardy-like conditions regardless of whether they can induce a HLQP paradox or not. Then the PCG corresponding to this group of Hardy-like conditions can be defined as follows:
(i) Each vertex is represented either by or by . To be specific, if , we choose to represent the -th vertex; otherwise, we use to represent this vertex.
(ii)Each edge is represented by a closed green or red curve circulating at least two vertices. Note that the -th edge is used for describing the (conditional) constraint associated with the -th conditional probability relation in equation (3d). To be specific, if , the edge is represented by a closed red curve which circulates all the vertices in ; otherwise, is represented by a closed green curve.

Example 1. Consider the PCG state . It can induce a group of Hardy-like conditions: . As , and , Both of the vertices 1 and 2 in the PCG should be represented by , and besides, the vertex 3 should be represented by . Moreover, from the relation , one can conclude that the edge should be colored with green. Likewise, indicates that the edge is colored with red. Then the final PCG can be obtained, see figure 1(a).
Example 2. The PCG state is , and the Hardy-like conditions are . From , we know that the vertices 1 and 2 are represented by , and the vertices 3 and 4 are represented by . Moreover, the relation gives rise to a red edge , while indicates that the edge is green. For the final PCG, see figure 1(b).
Clearly, the Hardy-like conditions in the above two examples cannot give rise to HLQP paradoxes. This also indicates that not all the PCGs can be associated to HLQP paradoxes. Similar to the discussion in [26], to determine whether a given PCG is a pictorial representation of a HLQP paradox, one can consider such an equivalent vertex-coloring problem: For an -qubit PCG with vertex-set and edge set , check whether there exists a consistent coloring scheme for all the vertices, wherein the vertex-coloring rules are described as follows.
(a) Each vertex can be colored with either green or red. If the -th vertex is colored with red, its coloring value is defined as ; otherwise .
(b) If the -th edge is red, the corresponding weight is defined as ; otherwise .
(c) If there exist at least one coloring scheme such that holds for any , the PCG is colorable; otherwise, is un-colorable.
Note that the color of the edge is determined by the constraint . Besides, it is known that if the group of the constraints , , , cannot hold simultaneously, a HLQP paradox can be constructed. Then according to the above vertex-coloring rules, only un-colorable PCGs can be associated to HLQP paradoxes.
Furthermore, if all of the PCGs induced from the PCG state are un-colorable PCGs, a DAVN proof can be derived, see a minimal example in B. Note that sometimes pictorial representations (by PCGs) can be used for quick identification of the desired DAVN proofs. For example, a loop PCG (in which each edge only connects two vertices and each vertex is shared by two adjacent edges) with an odd number of edges colored with red is an un-colorable PCG. In fact, figure 1(c) shows us one of the simplest un-colorable loop PCGs, wherein only one edge is colored with red. One can also check that as long as the PCG contains a loop substructure in which there is an odd number of red edges, it is an un-colorable PCG. Apart from that, it is obvious that similar techniques apply to the PCGs containing other un-colorable substructures as well.
4 Main results
In this section, we shall construct some typical DAVN proofs of Bell nonlocality based on non-stabilizer states.

Our first DAVN of Bell nonlocality from non-stabilizer states is induced from the following symmetric four-qubit PCG state
(3i) |
where is the sum of all permutations of , i.e., .
One can check whether is a stabilizer state by calculating the reduced density operator on each qubit. In fact, as long as there exists at least one reduced density operator on single qubit not equal to , the state is a non-stabilizer state.
To see that, let us consider the stabilizer states which are fully entangled (since correlations between disentangled subsystems cannot reveal Bell nonlocality). Assume that is such an -qubit stabilizer state, and the independent stabilizers are . Then one have . Note that each is a tensor product of Pauli operators and a variable number of identity operators (up to a local unitary transformation), and such a tensor product requires at least two Pauli operators from different qubits (otherwise it would contradict with the fact that the stabilizer state is fully entangled). Moreover, the product of () different stabilizers is still a stabilizer, and in final form the this product at least two Pauli operators from different qubits are included. Thus, one can get a set of constraints for the partial traces: , where , , and . Then the reduced density operator on the -th qubit is . This also indicates that if a reduced density operator on single qubit of a fully entangled state is not equal to , this entangled state state must be a non-stabilizer state.
A straightforward calculation shows that the reduced density operator (), indicating that is a non-stabilizer state.
It turns out that seven groups of Hardy-like conditions can be derived from .
(I) The first group of Hardy-like conditions can be written as
(3j) |
and
(3k) |
where . Note that equation (3k) contains 6 conditional probability relations.
To construct a HLQP paradox, let us consider a run of the experiment that and are measured and the results and are obtained (happens with a probability of . Assume that admits a LHV model. Similar to the argument in the aforementioned three-qubit HLQP paradox, since one have , one can infer from equation (3k) that if were measured, their results must satisfy . Likewise, five other constraints can be obtained as well. Precisely, according to the LHV model, if and were measured in this run, one would get . This indicates that when four pigeons are put into two boxes in this run, any pair of the pigeons cannot stay in the same box, a contradiction by classical pigeonhole principle. Then a HLQP paradox can be obtained.
(II) The other six groups of Hardy-like conditions have the same structure (up to a permutation): For any given ,
(3l) |
and
(3ma) | |||
(3mb) | |||
(3mc) | |||
(3md) | |||
(3me) |
Consider a run of the experiment that and are measured and the results and (associated with one of the components in ) are obtained. As long as the quantum state admits a LHV model, one can always conclude that if and were measured in this run, their values must satisfy , which also violate the pigeonhole counting principle. Then one can get six such HLQP paradoxes.
To sum up, (I) and (II) can give a total of seven HLQP paradoxes.
Since in any run of the experiment, the measurements of and can only give seven groups of results, and for every group of the results, one can always invoke one of the proofs of seven HLQP paradoxes referred in (I) and (II) to exclude the local realistic description of the quantum system. To be specific, seven groups of results and () can give rise to seven value assignment contradictions, i.e., one is and the other six can be described by (). Therefore, combining the seven HLQP paradoxes together, one can get a DAVN proof (from a non-stabilizer state). For its pictorial representation, see figure 2(a).
Inspired by this example, a family of DAVN proofs based on -qubit () non-stabilizer states can be analytically constructed. Detailed discussion is shown in C.
In addition, another four-qubit example of DAVN proof for Bell nonlocality can be constructed base on the four-qubit non-stabilizer state . One can check that by figure 2(b). Moreover, some states which are locally unitary equivalent to can also induce similar DAVN proofs. A typical example is shown in D.
Next, we shall present a five-qubit DAVN proof of Bell nonlocality based on the following following PCG state
(3mn) |
where .
Notice that the reduced density operator on the -th qubit is (), and thus is also a non-stabilizer state. One can check that can induce six groups of Hardy-like conditions.
(I′) The first group of Hardy-like conditions can be described as follows:
(3mo) |
and
(3mp) |
where . Note that equation (3mp) contains five conditional probability relations.
Consider a run of the experiment that are measured and their outcomes are obtained (with a probability of ). Assume that admits a LHV model. According to equation (3mp), since we have , if were measured in this run, one can infer that their results need to satisfy . Similarly, other four constraints can be derived as well, i.e., . According to classical pigeonhole principle, all the five constraints cannot hold simultaneously. Then one can get a HLQP paradox.
(II′) The other five Hardy-like conditions belong to the same type (up to a permutation), and each of them can be specified as
(3mq) |
and
(3mra) | |||
(3mrb) | |||
(3mrc) | |||
(3mrd) | |||
(3mre) |
where .
Likewise, once are obtained in some run of the experiment, one can infer that if were measured in this run, their results must satisfy according to local realism. Clearly, such constraints also contradict with classical pigeonhole Principle. Therefore, five HLQP paradoxes can be constructed from this type of Hardy-like conditions.
Notice that measuring of can only give six groups of results, and according to (I′) and (II′), any of them can induce a HLQP paradox. Then combining them together will give rise to a DAVN proof, also see figure 2(c) for its pictorial representation.
Moreover, by using a analytical construction technique, one can generalize this example to a family of -qubit () DAVN proofs. For more details, see E.
In the end, some remarks are in order. First, notice that sometimes permutation symmetries can greatly simplify the description of the involved HLQP paradoxes (some of them belong to the same class). Therefore, choosing a permutation symmetrical system or a roughly permutation symmetrical system (one or a few components removed away from a permutation symmetrical state) may simplify the construction of the DAVN proof. Second, note that some quantum systems in aforementioned DAVN proofs seem to be “very close” to stabilizer states. For example, is very close to the fully entangled stabilizer state (a four-qubit GHZ state) . This is not curious. In fact, the -qubit stabilizer state can induce a GHZ paradox, but this paradox is not a genuine -partite GHZ paradox but only a genuine -partite one[27]. Also note that this GHZ paradox can be converted to a combination of eight HLQP paradoxes, and moreover, for each HLQP paradox, the corresponding Hardy-like conditions can provides far more relations than it really needs. Thus even if one of the terms in were missing, each group of new Hardy-like conditions induced from the remaining ones (e.g. the remaining terms form the state ) may still give rise to a HLQP paradox. In view of these, in a practical construction of the unconventional DAVN proof, we prefer to choose the non-stabilizer state which has permutation symmetries (or roughly permutation symmetries) and is very close to some stabilizer state.
5 Conclusion
To summarize, some four- and five-qubit DAVN proofs of Bell nonlocality based on non-stabilizer states have been presented, opening a new chapter in the study of DAVN proofs of Bell nonlocality, as previous ones were always induced from stabilizer states. Besides, such unconventional proofs can also be generalized to the scenarios with more qubits analytically, and as a consequence, one can get several families of scalable DAVN proofs of Bell nonlocality. Our results can not only add many new members to the family of AVN proofs, but also help us to get a better understanding of more refined structures for multi-party Bell nonlocality. However, due to the dramatic growth of calculation, how to derive the DAVN proof of Bell nonlocality from a qudit non-stabilizer state would be a huge challenge. Until very recently, we found a non-trivial example with , which was reported in another work.
Appendix A A DAVN proof for Bell nonlocality from the three-qubit GHZ state
In fact, the three qubit GHZ state can give a total of four groups of Hardy-like conditions, See table 1-(I-IV). Clearly, each of them can produce a HLQP paradox. Then can induce a total of four HLQP paradoxes.
I | , , | , |
---|---|---|
II | , , | , |
III | , , | , |
IV | , , | , |
Combining these HLQP paradoxes together, one can get a DAVN proof for Bell nonlocality. To show that, consider any run of the experiment that and are measured. According to table 1, only four groups of results are possible (each occurs with a probability of ). If the quantum state admits a LHV model, a contradiction can be obtained from any group of the results. Precisely, and will give rise to and , respectively. Clearly, all these relations violate classical pigeonhole principle.
Note that the GHZ state is a stabilizer state, this DAVN proof is still a conventional demonstration of Bell nonlocality without inequalities.
Appendix B Pictorial representation for a three-qubit DAVN proof for Bell nonlocality
Notice that the PCG can give an intuitive pictorial representation for the HLQP paradox. Combining the associated PCGs together, one can get the pictorial representation for the DAVN proof, see figure 3.

Appendix C An example for () qubits
Consider the following -qubit () projected-coloring graph state
(3mrs) |
where is the sum of all permutations of , namely, .
Since is a fully entangled state, and a straightforward calculation shows that the reduced density operator on the -th qubit is (), one can conclude that is a non-stabilizer state.
We can get groups of Hardy-like conditions (which belongs to two classes) from .
The first class (contains only one group):
(3mrt) |
and
(3mru) |
where . Note that equation (3mru) contains such relations.
The second class (contains groups, only one of them is listed in the following): For any given ,
(3mrv) |
and
(3mrwa) | |||
(3mrwb) | |||
(3mrwc) | |||
Here . Note that both of equation (3mrwa) and equation (3mrwb) contain relations. |
Assume that the quantum system admits a LHV model, then one can prove that each group of these Hardy-like conditions conflicts with classical pigeonhole principle. As a consequence, a total of HLQP paradoxes can be obtained. Combining them together will produce an -qubit() DAVN proof of Bell nonlocality.
Appendix D Another four-qubit unconventional DAVN proof
Consider the state . Similarly, combining the six HLQP paradoxes (associated with all possible measurement results of and ) together, we can construct a DAVN proof of Bell nonlocality. For the pictorial representation, see figure 4.

Appendix E An example for () qubits
Consider the following -qubit PCG state
(3mrwda) |
where is the sum of all permutations of , namely, .
Note that is a fully entangled state, and one can check that the reduced density operator on the -th qubit is (). Therefore, is a non-stabilizer state.
Here we can get groups of Hardy-like conditions (which belong to two classes).
The first class (contains only one group):
(3mrwdb) |
and
(3mrwdc) |
where . Note that equation (3mrwdc) contains such relations.
The second class (contains groups, and only one of them is listed in the following): The -th group of such Hardy-like conditions () are
(3mrwdd) |
and
(3mrwdea) | |||
(3mrwdeb) |
where and . Note that equation (3mrwdeb) contains similar relations.
One can check that a total of HLQP paradoxes can be induced. Combining them together will give rise to a DAVN proof of Bell nonlocality.
References
References
- [1] Bell J S 1964 On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen paradox Physics Physique Fizika 1 195
- [2] Brunner N, Cavalcanti D, Pironio S, Scarani V, and Wehner S 2014 Bell nonlocality Rev. Mod. Phys. 86 419
- [3] Clauser J F, Horne M A, Shimony A, and Holt R A 1969 Proposed experiment to test local hidden-variable theories Phys. Rev. Lett. 23 880
- [4] Greenberger D M, Horne M A, and Zeilinger A 1989 Going beyond Bell’s theorem Bell’s theorem, quantum theory and conceptions of the universe ed Kafatos M (Springer) p 69
- [5] Greenberger D M, Horne M A, Shimony A, and Zeilinger A 1990 Bell’s theorem without inequalities American Journal of Physics 58 1131
- [6] Hardy L 1992 Quantum mechanics, local realistic theories, and Lorentz-invariant realistic theories Phys. Rev. Lett. 68 2981
- [7] Hardy L 1993 Nonlocality for two particles without inequalities for almost all entangled states Phys. Rev. Lett. 71 1665
- [8] Mermin N D 1990 Extreme quantum entanglement in a superposition of macroscopically distinct states Phys. Rev. Lett. 65 1838
- [9] Mermin N D 1994 Quantum mysteries refined American Journal of Physics 62 880
- [10] Cabello A 2002 Bell’s theorem with and without inequalities for the three-qubit Greenberger-Horne-Zeilinger and W states Phys. Rev. A 65 032108
- [11] Cabello A 2001 Bell’s theorem without inequalities and without probabilities for two observers Phys. Rev. Lett. 86 1911
- [12] Ghirardi G and Marinatto L 2006 Greenberger-Horne-Zeilinger argument of nonlocality without inequalities for mixed states Phys. Rev. A 74 022101
- [13] Ren C, Su H-Y, Xu Z-P, Wu C and Chen J-L 2015 Optimal GHZ paradox for three qubits Sci. Rep. 5 13080
- [14] Tang W, Yu S and Oh C H 2017 Multisetting Greenberger-Horne-Zeilinger paradoxes Phys. Rev. A 95 012131
- [15] Bouwmeester D, Pan J-W, Daniell M, Weinfurter H and Zeilinger A 1999 Observation of three-photon Greenberger-Horne-Zeilinger entanglement Phys. Rev. Lett. 82 1345
- [16] Pan J-W, Bouwmeester D, Daniell M, Weinfurter H and Zeilinger A 2000 Experimental test of quantum nonlocality in three-photon Greenberger-Horne-Zeilinger entanglement Nature 403 515
- [17] Cinelli C, Barbieri M, Perris R, Mataloni P and De Martini F 2005 All-versus-nothing nonlocality test of quantum mechanics by two-photon hyperentanglement Phys. Rev. Lett. 95 240405
- [18] Su Z-E, Tang W-D, Wu D, Cai X-D, Yang T, Li L, Liu N-L, Lu C-Y, Żukowski M and Pan J-W 2017 Experimental test of the irreducible four-qubit Greenberger-Horne-Zeilinger paradox Phys. Rev. A 95 030103R
- [19] Cleve R and Buhrman H 1997 Substituting quantum entanglement for communication Phys. Rev. A 56 1201
- [20] Buhrman H, Cleve R, Massar S and de Wolf R 2010 Nonlocality and communication complexity Rev. Mod. Phys. 82 665
- [21] Fu Y, Yin H-L, Chen T-Y and Chen Z-B 2015 Long-distance measurement-device-independent multiparty quantum communication Phys. Rev. Lett. 114 090501
- [22] Almeida M L, Bancal J-D, Brunner N, Acín A, Gisin N and Pironio S 2010 Guess your neighbor’s input: A multipartite nonlocal game with no quantum advantage Phys. Rev. Lett. 104 230404
- [23] Matera J M, Egloff D, Killoran N and Plenio M B 2016 Coherent control of quantum systems as a resource theory Quantum Sci. Technol. 1 01LT01
- [24] Hillery M 2016 Coherence as a resource in decision problems: The Deutsch-Jozsa algorithm and a variation Phys. Rev. A 93 012111
- [25] Theurer T, Killoran N, Egloff D and Plenio M B 2017 Resource theory of superposition Phys. Rev. Lett. 119 230401
- [26] Tang W 2022 Hardy-like quantum pigeonhole paradox and the projected-coloring graph state Phys. Rev. A 105 032457
- [27] Cerf N J, Massar S and Pironio S 2002 Greenberger-Horne-Zeilinger paradoxes for many qudits Phys. Rev. Lett. 89 080402