This paper was converted on www.awesomepapers.org from LaTeX by an anonymous user.
Want to know more? Visit the Converter page.

Combinatorial proofs and refinements of three partition theorems of Andrews

Shishuo Fu College of Mathematics and Statistics, Chongqing University, Chongqing 401331, P.R. China [email protected]
Abstract.

In his recent work, Andrews revisited two-color partitions with certain restrictions on the differences between consecutive parts, and he established three theorems linking these two-color partitions with more familiar kinds of partitions. In this note, we provide bijective proofs as well as refinements of those three theorems of Andrews. Our refinements take into account the numbers of parts in each of the two colors.

1. Introduction

In his recent paper [7] published in the Hardy-Ramanujan Journal, Andrews revisited two-color partitions and obtained three new partition theorems that are reminiscent of the two theorems on two-color partitions proved in his 1987 paper [5]. In order to state these new theorems, we first recall some definitions in the theory of partitions.

Given a non-negative integer nn, a partition, say λ\lambda, of nn is a non-increasing list of positive integers that sum up to nn. We shall write λ=λ1+λ2+\lambda=\lambda_{1}+\lambda_{2}+\cdots with λ1λ2\lambda_{1}\geq\lambda_{2}\geq\cdots, where |λ|=n|\lambda|=n might also be referred to as the weight of λ\lambda. In particular, we view the empty partition, denoted as ϵ\epsilon, as the one and only partition of n=0n=0. Denote by 𝒫\mathcal{P} and 𝒫(n)\mathcal{P}(n) the set of all partitions and the set of all partitions of nn, respectively. For example, we have

𝒫(4)={4,3+1,2+2,2+1+1,1+1+1+1},\mathcal{P}(4)=\{4,~{}3+1,~{}2+2,~{}2+1+1,~{}1+1+1+1\},

and 2+1+12+1+1 is said to be a partition of 44 with one part of 22 and two parts of 11. A standard way of representing partitions pictorially is to use the so-called Ferrers graph [4, p. 7]. For a partition λ=λ1+λ2+\lambda=\lambda_{1}+\lambda_{2}+\cdots, we draw a left-justified array of cells, so that a top-down counting reveals λi\lambda_{i} cells in the ii-th row; see Fig 1 for an example111This way of drawing Ferrers graphs is usually called the “English notation”.. Using Ferrers graph, the conjugate partition of λ\lambda, usually denoted as λ\lambda^{\prime}, is defined to be the partition rendered from counting cells in the Ferrers graph of λ\lambda by columns in stead of rows. So for instance, the conjugate of 2+1+12+1+1 is 3+13+1.

Two-color partitions, on the other hand, are those in which each part may come in two colors, say red and green. We indicate the color of any given part by assigning a subindex rr (for red) or gg (for green) to that part. For instance, there are ten two-color partitions of 33, as listed below.

3r,3g,2r+1r,2r+1g,2g+1r,2g+1g,\displaystyle 3_{r},3_{g},2_{r}+1_{r},2_{r}+1_{g},2_{g}+1_{r},2_{g}+1_{g},
1r+1r+1r,1r+1r+1g,1r+1g+1g,1g+1g+1g.\displaystyle 1_{r}+1_{r}+1_{r},1_{r}+1_{r}+1_{g},1_{r}+1_{g}+1_{g},1_{g}+1_{g}+1_{g}.

Given a two-color partition, we shall say that two parts are distinct if they are of different colors or different numerical values or both. We shall say that two parts are numerically distinct if they have different numercial values. As noted by Lovejoy [22, p. 395], if we require in addition that all green parts are distinct, we essentially recover overpartitions [12], a well-studied variant that usually enjoys parallel results to those known ones for ordinary partitions.

Suppose n0n\geq 0 and d1d\geq 1 are integers. Following Andrews [7], we define d(n)\mathcal{L}_{d}(n) to be the set of two-color partitions of nn into numerically distinct parts such that the following three conditions are satisfied:

  1. (1)

    each red part is at least dd larger than the next largest part;

  2. (2)

    each green part is at least d+1d+1 larger than the next largest part;

  3. (3)

    neither 1g1_{g} nor (d1)g(d-1)_{g} is allowed as a part.

We use Ld(n)L_{d}(n) to denote the cardinality of d(n)\mathcal{L}_{d}(n).

The three theorems on two-color partitions proved in [7] are these:

Theorem 1.1.

L1(n)L_{1}(n) equals the number of two-color partitions of nn in which parts with the same color are distinct and green parts are all even numbers.

Theorem 1.2.

L2(n)L_{2}(n) equals the number of basis partitions of nn.

Theorem 1.3.

L3(n)L_{3}(n) equals the number of partitions of nn into distinct parts.

Remark 1.4.

To be precise, the original statements of Theorems 1.1 and 1.3 in Andrews’s paper [7] are different from what we give here, but it suffices to use Euler’s celebrated “Odd-distinct Theorem” to bridge the gap. The definition of basis partition is a bit involved so we decide to postpone it to section 3 (see Definition 3.1).

Andrews [7] proved the above theorems in a uniform way by manipulating generating functions and he requested for bijective proofs. The main purpose of this paper is to prove all three theorems bijectively. Indeed, our bijective approach makes it effortless to keep track of various partition statistics and consequently leads us to the following three refinements. We begin with two definitions.

Definition 1.5.

Let d(n,k,)\mathcal{L}_{d}(n,k,\ell) (resp. Ld(n,k,)L_{d}(n,k,\ell)) denote the set (resp. the number) of two-color partitions in d(n)\mathcal{L}_{d}(n) with kk red parts and \ell green parts.

Clearly, Ld(n)=k,0Ld(n,k,)L_{d}(n)=\sum_{k,\ell\geq 0}L_{d}(n,k,\ell), hence the following three results are indeed refinements of Theorems 1.1, 1.2, and 1.3, respectively.

Definition 1.6.

Let 𝒜(n,k,)\mathcal{A}(n,k,\ell) (resp. A(n,k,)A(n,k,\ell)) be the set (resp. the number) of two-color partitions of nn, each of which is consisted of k+jk+j distinct red parts and \ell distinct even green parts for a certain non-negative integer jj, wherein exactly kk red parts are larger than \ell.

Theorem 1.7.

For non-negative integers n,k,n,k,\ell, we have L1(n,k,)=A(n,k,)L_{1}(n,k,\ell)=A(n,k,\ell).

Example 1.8.

Taking (n,k,)=(7,1,1)(n,k,\ell)=(7,1,1), we see that

1(7,1,1)={6g+1r,5g+2r,5r+2g,4r+3g}.\mathcal{L}_{1}(7,1,1)=\{6_{g}+1_{r},~{}5_{g}+2_{r},~{}5_{r}+2_{g},~{}4_{r}+3_{g}\}.

On the other hand, there are also four two-color partitions in 𝒜(7,1,1)\mathcal{A}(7,1,1), namely,

𝒜(7,1,1)={4g+2r+1r,4r+2g+1r,4g+3r,5r+2g}.\mathcal{A}(7,1,1)=\{4_{g}+2_{r}+1_{r},~{}4_{r}+2_{g}+1_{r},~{}4_{g}+3_{r},~{}5_{r}+2_{g}\}.
Theorem 1.9.

The number of basis partitions λ=(k+,π,σ)\lambda=(k+\ell,\pi,\sigma) of nn such that π\pi has exactly \ell distinct parts, is given by L2(n,k,)L_{2}(n,k,\ell).

Example 1.10.

For (n,k,)=(15,1,2)(n,k,\ell)=(15,1,2), there are six basis partitions meeting the requirements, namely (in terms of the triple expression (d,π,σ)(d,\pi,\sigma); see Sect. 3),

(3,3+1+1+1,ϵ),(3,2+2+1+1,ϵ),(3,2+1+1+1+1,ϵ),(3,3+2,1),(3,3+1,2),(3,2+1,3).(3,3+1+1+1,\epsilon),(3,2+2+1+1,\epsilon),(3,2+1+1+1+1,\epsilon),(3,3+2,1),(3,3+1,2),(3,2+1,3).

On the other hand, one checks that

2(15,1,2)={10g+4g+1r,9g+5g+1r,8g+5g+2r,9g+4r+2g,8g+5r+2g,8r+5g+2g},\mathcal{L}_{2}(15,1,2)=\{10_{g}+4_{g}+1_{r},9_{g}+5_{g}+1_{r},8_{g}+5_{g}+2_{r},9_{g}+4_{r}+2_{g},8_{g}+5_{r}+2_{g},8_{r}+5_{g}+2_{g}\},

which also contains six partitions.

Theorem 1.11.

L3(n,k,)L_{3}(n,k,\ell) equals the number of partitions of nn into k+2k+2\ell distinct parts such that the Durfee square is of side k+k+\ell.

The definition of the Durfee square of a partition will be given in section 3.

Example 1.12.

For (n,k,)=(18,2,1)(n,k,\ell)=(18,2,1), the following are the ten strict partitions meeting the requirements,

10+4+3+1,9+5+3+1,8+6+3+1,8+5+4+1,7+6+4+1,\displaystyle 10+4+3+1,~{}9+5+3+1,~{}8+6+3+1,~{}8+5+4+1,~{}7+6+4+1,
9+4+3+2,8+5+3+2,7+6+3+2,7+5+4+2,6+5+4+3.\displaystyle 9+4+3+2,~{}8+5+3+2,~{}7+6+3+2,~{}7+5+4+2,~{}6+5+4+3.

On the other hand, one checks that

3(18,2,1)\displaystyle\mathcal{L}_{3}(18,2,1) ={13g+4r+1r,12g+5r+1r,12r+5g+1r,11g+6r+1r,11r+6g+1r,\displaystyle=\{13_{g}+4_{r}+1_{r},~{}12_{g}+5_{r}+1_{r},~{}12_{r}+5_{g}+1_{r},~{}11_{g}+6_{r}+1_{r},~{}11_{r}+6_{g}+1_{r},
10r+7g+1r,11g+5r+2r,10g+6r+2r,10r+6g+2r,9r+6r+3g},\displaystyle\qquad 10_{r}+7_{g}+1_{r},~{}11_{g}+5_{r}+2_{r},~{}10_{g}+6_{r}+2_{r},~{}10_{r}+6_{g}+2_{r},~{}9_{r}+6_{r}+3_{g}\},

which contains ten partitions as well.

We will prove one refinement in each of the ensuing sections, and we conclude the paper with some outlook for future research.

2. Two proofs of Theorem 1.7

We present in this section two proofs of Theorem 1.7. The first proof is via generating functions and requires the following qq-binomial theorem [4, p. 17, Thm. 2.1]. For |q|<1|q|<1, |t|<1|t|<1, we have

n=0(a)ntn(q)n=(at)(t).\displaystyle\sum_{n=0}^{\infty}\frac{(a)_{n}t^{n}}{(q)_{n}}=\frac{(at)_{\infty}}{(t)_{\infty}}. (2.1)

Here and in the sequel, we use the standard qq-series notations

(a)n=(a;q)n=(1a)(1aq)(1aqn1),\displaystyle(a)_{n}=(a;q)_{n}=(1-a)(1-aq)\cdots(1-aq^{n-1}),
(a)=(a;q)=limn(a;q)n, and (a)0=1.\displaystyle(a)_{\infty}=(a;q)_{\infty}=\lim_{n\to\infty}(a;q)_{n},\text{ and }(a)_{0}=1.

We claim the following two generating functions for L1(n,k,)L_{1}(n,k,\ell) and A(n,k,)A(n,k,\ell), respectively.

n,k,0L1(n,k,)xkyqn\displaystyle\sum_{n,k,\ell\geq 0}L_{1}(n,k,\ell)x^{k}y^{\ell}q^{n} =m0(yq/x)mxmq(m+12)(q)m,\displaystyle=\sum_{m\geq 0}\frac{(-yq/x)_{m}x^{m}q^{\binom{m+1}{2}}}{(q)_{m}}, (2.2)
n,k,0A(n,k,)xkyqn\displaystyle\sum_{n,k,\ell\geq 0}A(n,k,\ell)x^{k}y^{\ell}q^{n} =k,0xkyq(k++12)+(+12)(q)k(q).\displaystyle=\sum_{k,\ell\geq 0}\frac{x^{k}y^{\ell}q^{\binom{k+\ell+1}{2}+\binom{\ell+1}{2}}}{(q)_{k}(q)_{\ell}}. (2.3)

Indeed, given a partition λ1(n,k,)\lambda\in\mathcal{L}_{1}(n,k,\ell), suppose it has mm (=k+=k+\ell) parts in total (regardless of the colors). These mm parts must all be distinct so at least they should contribute 1+2++m=m(m+1)/21+2+\cdots+m=m(m+1)/2 to the weight of λ\lambda. But the difference λiλi+1\lambda_{i}-\lambda_{i+1} might as well be larger than 11, and this “widening of gaps”, if any, is accounted for by the factor

1(q)m=11q11q211qm,\frac{1}{(q)_{m}}=\frac{1}{1-q}\frac{1}{1-q^{2}}\cdots\frac{1}{1-q^{m}},

where 1/(1q)1/(1-q) dictates the widening between λ1\lambda_{1} and λ2\lambda_{2}, 1/(1q2)1/(1-q^{2}) determines the extra gap between λ2\lambda_{2} and λ3\lambda_{3}, and so on and so forth. Finally, to assign the color for part, say λi\lambda_{i}, we make a decision between red (contributing xx), and green (contributing yqiyq^{i}, since each green part is at least 22 larger than the next part). Collectively, this yields the factor

(x+yq)(x+yq2)(x+yqm),(x+yq)(x+yq^{2})\cdots(x+yq^{m}),

and we arrive at the right hand side of (2.2) after pulling out xx from each factor (x+yqi)(x+yq^{i}), 1im1\leq i\leq m.

Next, to verify (2.3), we see that for a given partition μ𝒜(n,k,)\mu\in\mathcal{A}(n,k,\ell), its kk red parts larger than \ell are generated by

xkq(+1)+(+2)++(+k)(q)k=xkqk+(k+12)(q)k.\frac{x^{k}q^{(\ell+1)+(\ell+2)+\cdots+(\ell+k)}}{(q)_{k}}=\frac{x^{k}q^{k\ell+\binom{k+1}{2}}}{(q)_{k}}.

The remaining red parts, if any, must be no greater than \ell and are generated by (q)(-q)_{\ell}, while the \ell green even parts of μ\mu are generated by

yq2+4++2(q2;q2)=yq(+1)(q)(q).\frac{y^{\ell}q^{2+4+\cdots+2\ell}}{(q^{2};q^{2})_{\ell}}=\frac{y^{\ell}q^{\ell(\ell+1)}}{(q)_{\ell}(-q)_{\ell}}.

Cancelling out (q)(-q)_{\ell}, we arrive at the right hand side of (2.3).

Analytic proof of Theorem 1.7.

It suffices to show that the right hand sides of (2.2) and (2.3) are the same. Starting from the right hand side of (2.3) and substituting mm for k+k+\ell, we deduce that

k,0xkyq(k++12)+(+12)(q)k(q)\displaystyle\sum_{k,\ell\geq 0}\frac{x^{k}y^{\ell}q^{\binom{k+\ell+1}{2}+\binom{\ell+1}{2}}}{(q)_{k}(q)_{\ell}} =m0xmq(m+12)(q)m=0m(qm+1)(q)(yx)q(+12)\displaystyle=\sum_{m\geq 0}\frac{x^{m}q^{\binom{m+1}{2}}}{(q)_{m}}\sum_{\ell=0}^{m}\frac{(q^{m-\ell+1})_{\ell}}{(q)_{\ell}}\left(\frac{y}{x}\right)^{\ell}q^{\binom{\ell+1}{2}}
=m0xmq(m+12)(q)m=0m(qm)(q)(yqm+1x)\displaystyle=\sum_{m\geq 0}\frac{x^{m}q^{\binom{m+1}{2}}}{(q)_{m}}\sum_{\ell=0}^{m}\frac{(q^{-m})_{\ell}}{(q)_{\ell}}\left(-\frac{yq^{m+1}}{x}\right)^{\ell}
=m0xmq(m+12)(q)m(yq/x)(yqm+1/x)(by (2.1) with a=qmt=yqm+1x)\displaystyle=\sum_{m\geq 0}\frac{x^{m}q^{\binom{m+1}{2}}}{(q)_{m}}\frac{(-yq/x)_{\infty}}{(-yq^{m+1}/x)_{\infty}}\quad\text{(by \eqref{id:q-bin} with $a=q^{-m}$, $t=-\frac{yq^{m+1}}{x}$)}
=m0xmq(m+12)(q)m(yq/x)m,\displaystyle=\sum_{m\geq 0}\frac{x^{m}q^{\binom{m+1}{2}}}{(q)_{m}}(-yq/x)_{m},

which is the right hand side of (2.2), as desired. ∎

It is worth noting that there is an auxiliary parameter jj222This parameter jj appeared implicitly in the bijection of Alladi and Gordon; see [24, p. 26, Sect. 4.4]. in the definition of 𝒜(n,k,)\mathcal{A}(n,k,\ell) (see Definition 1.6), so one may ask what is the corresponding parameter for those two-color partitions in 1(n,k,)\mathcal{L}_{1}(n,k,\ell). Our second proof of Theorem 1.7, which is to construct a bijection between 1(n,k,)\mathcal{L}_{1}(n,k,\ell) and 𝒜(n,k,)\mathcal{A}(n,k,\ell), answers this question completely.

Andrews’s original proof of Theorem 1.1 relies on the following identity of Lebesgue [18]:

n0(zq;q)n(q;q)nq(n+12)=(q;q)(zq2;q2).\displaystyle\sum_{n\geq 0}\frac{(-zq;q)_{n}}{(q;q)_{n}}q^{\binom{n+1}{2}}=(-q;q)_{\infty}(-zq^{2};q^{2})_{\infty}. (2.4)

In view of this, the first step towards proving the refinement Theorem 1.7 bijectively, is to interprete the Lebesgue identity combinatorially. This has been done several times via different approaches; see for example the works of Alladi-Gordon [3], and Bessenrodt [9], see also Pak’s survey [24] where both proofs were nicely summarized. Later proofs, refinements, and polynomial analogues of Lebesgue identity include Alladi-Berkovich [2], Little-Sellers [20], Rowell [25], Chen-Hou-Sun [10], and Dousse-Kim [13]. Our bijection, when interpreted in terms of tilings, is equivalent to Little and Sellers’s construction [20], which itself has its roots in Alladi and Gordon’s work [3].

Little and Sellers’s approach via tilings [20] is intuitive and lends itself to further applications [21]. However, for our convenience, we use words made of three letters x,yx,y, and zz, which correspond to black squares, white squares, and dominoes, respectively.

The profile of an integer partition is the south-west to north-east border path in its Ferrers graph. This notion seems to be first introduced by Keith and Nath [17]; see also [14] and [19], where this way of representing integer partitions proved to be useful. For our purpose here, we write the profiles of partitions in 1(n)\mathcal{L}_{1}(n) not as words composed of two letters (NN for north and EE for east) as it was done in [14], but rather as words composed of three letters x,yx,y, and zz, so that we can tell red parts from green parts. More precisely, as we trace out the profile, we label the steps according to the following rules.

  1. (1)

    the two consecutive steps ENEN forming the corner cell of a certain red part are labeled together as xx;

  2. (2)

    the three consecutive steps EENEEN forming the last two cells of a certain green part are labeled together as zz;

  3. (3)

    all remaining east steps are labeled as yy.

It should be clear from the definition that the profile in terms of the xx-yy-zz word as described above is uniquely determined by the partition and vice versa. The readers are invited to use the example in Fig. 1 to make sure they understand this correspondence. Let A={x,y,z}A=\{x,y,z\} be our alphabet, and AA^{*} stands for the free monoid generated by the letters from AA. We denote 𝒲\mathcal{W} the set of words in AA^{*} that are either empty or end with xx or zz. For each word u=u1u2um𝒲u=u_{1}u_{2}\cdots u_{m}\in\mathcal{W}, we define its weight to be

ω(u):=i=1mχ(uiy)(i+|{ji:uj=z}|),\displaystyle\omega(u):=\sum_{i=1}^{m}\chi(u_{i}\neq y)\cdot(i+|\{j\leq i:u_{j}=z\}|), (2.5)

where χ(S)=1\chi(S)=1 if the statement SS is true and χ(S)=0\chi(S)=0 otherwise. For the word u=xzxyxzyyzu=xzxyxzyyz in Fig. 1, one checks that ω(u)=34\omega(u)=34. We denote 𝒲(n,k,)\mathcal{W}(n,k,\ell) the set of words in AA^{*} having weight nn, wherein the letter xx appears kk times and the letter zz appears \ell times.

Proposition 2.1.

The mapping, say ϕ\phi, that sends each partition to its profile written as a word in x,yx,y, and zz, is a bijection from 1(n,k,)\mathcal{L}_{1}(n,k,\ell) to 𝒲(n,k,)\mathcal{W}(n,k,\ell).

ϕ\phixzxyxzyyzx~{}z~{}x~{}y~{}x~{}z~{}y~{}y~{}z
Figure 1. the profile of partition λ=12g+8g+6r+4r+3g+1r\lambda=12_{g}+8_{g}+6_{r}+4_{r}+3_{g}+1_{r}.

Now to prove Theorem 1.7, it remains to construct a bijection, say ψ\psi, from the set of words 𝒲(n,k,)\mathcal{W}(n,k,\ell), to the set of two-color partitions 𝒜(n,k,)\mathcal{A}(n,k,\ell). As alluded to earlier, we can decompose 𝒜(n,k,)\mathcal{A}(n,k,\ell) further into subsets 𝒜(n,k,,j)\mathcal{A}(n,k,\ell,j), 0j0\leq j\leq\ell, i.e., the set of partitions in 𝒜(n,k,)\mathcal{A}(n,k,\ell) with precisely jj red parts no greater than \ell. Again, we use A(n,k,,j)A(n,k,\ell,j) to denote its cardinality. On the other hand for the profile words, we further distinguish two types of letter zz to account for the extra parameter jj.

Definition 2.2.

For a word u=u1u2umAu=u_{1}u_{2}\cdots u_{m}\in A^{*}, we say a letter ui=zu_{i}=z is odd (resp. even) if for all 1j<i1\leq j<i, there is an odd (resp. even) number of uju_{j} being a yy or an odd zz. For each 0j0\leq j\leq\ell, we denote 𝒲(n,k,,j)\mathcal{W}(n,k,\ell,j) the set of words in 𝒲(n,k,)\mathcal{W}(n,k,\ell) that contain jj odd zz’s.

Take the word u=xzxyxzyyzu=xzxyxzyyz in Fig. 1 for example, from left to right, the first and the last zz are even while the middle zz is odd, hence u𝒲(34,3,3,1)u\in\mathcal{W}(34,3,3,1). Now we are ready to construct the aforementioned bijection ψ\psi. Then Theorem 1.7 follows immediately as a direct corollary of Proposition 2.1 and Theorem 2.3.

Theorem 2.3.

There exists a bijection ψ:𝒲(n,k,,j)𝒜(n,k,,j)\psi:\mathcal{W}(n,k,\ell,j)\to\mathcal{A}(n,k,\ell,j).

Corollary 2.4.

The composition ψϕ\psi\circ\phi is a bijection from 1(n,k,)\mathcal{L}_{1}(n,k,\ell) to 𝒜(n,k,)\mathcal{A}(n,k,\ell). In particular, Theorem 1.7 holds true.

Proof of Theorem 2.3.

Take any word u=u1u2um𝒲(n,k,,j)u=u_{1}u_{2}\cdots u_{m}\in\mathcal{W}(n,k,\ell,j), we aim to derive a partition pair ψ(u):=(π,σ)\psi(u):=(\pi,\sigma), where π\pi is a distinct partition into k+jk+j parts while σ\sigma is a distinct partition into \ell even parts.

First off, we screen the word uu from right to left looking for letter zz, and suppose they are us1,us2,,usu_{s_{1}},u_{s_{2}},\ldots,u_{s_{\ell}} in uu with s1>s2>>ss_{1}>s_{2}>\cdots>s_{\ell}. Next, for each i=1,2,,i=1,2,\ldots,\ell, we set

σi\displaystyle\sigma_{i} :=si|{tsi:ut=x}|+|{tsi:ut is an even z}|, and\displaystyle:=s_{i}-|\{t\leq s_{i}:u_{t}=x\}|+|\{t\leq s_{i}:\text{$u_{t}$ is an even $z$}\}|,\text{ and}
vi\displaystyle v_{i} :={x,if usi is an odd z,y,if usi is an even z.\displaystyle:=\begin{cases}x,&\text{if $u_{s_{i}}$ is an odd $z$},\\ y,&\text{if $u_{s_{i}}$ is an even $z$}.\end{cases}

We further let uu^{\prime} be the word obtained from uu by replacing all letter zz by letter yy, and let

u^:=v1v2vu.\hat{u}:=v_{1}v_{2}\cdots v_{\ell}u^{\prime}.

Finally, we take π:=ϕ1(u^)\pi:=\phi^{-1}(\hat{u})333Strictly speaking, the images under the mapping ϕ\phi should be words ending with xx or zz. So, when u^\hat{u} ends with yy, we simply ignore all its ending yy’s (doing this will not change the weight of u^\hat{u}), and then apply ϕ1\phi^{-1}. and σ:=σ1+σ2++σ\sigma:=\sigma_{1}+\sigma_{2}+\cdots+\sigma_{\ell}, i.e., σ\sigma is the partition with parts σ1,σ2,,σ\sigma_{1},\sigma_{2},\ldots,\sigma_{\ell}. With the following claims, we see that ψ(u)=(π,σ)\psi(u)=(\pi,\sigma) is indeed a two-color partition in 𝒜(n,k,,j)\mathcal{A}(n,k,\ell,j).

  1. (1)

    all σi\sigma_{i} are even integers and σi>σi+1\sigma_{i}>\sigma_{i+1}.

  2. (2)

    u^\hat{u} is an xx-yy word containing k+jk+j copies of letter xx, jj of which occur in the prefix v1v2vv_{1}v_{2}\cdots v_{\ell}.

  3. (3)

    ω(u)=ω(u^)+|σ|\omega(u)=\omega(\hat{u})+|\sigma|.

The proofs of the claims above are straightforward verifications. We give some details on the proof of claim (3) here and leave the rest to the interested readers. For the trivial case =0\ell=0, clearly u^=u=u\hat{u}=u^{\prime}=u, and σ=ϵ\sigma=\epsilon, so (3) holds true. In general for >0\ell>0, we make a letter-by-letter comparison between uu and u^\hat{u}. For a certain letter utu_{t} in uu, if ut=yu_{t}=y, then according to (2.5) it contributes nothing in either ω(u)\omega(u) or ω(u^)\omega(\hat{u}). Otherwise utyu_{t}\neq y, we go through various ranges for the index tt and list in Table 1 the corresponding increments in utu_{t}’s contributions to the weights going from uu to u^\hat{u}.

t>s1t>s_{1} t=s1t=s_{1} s2<t<s1s_{2}<t<s_{1} t=s2t=s_{2} s3<t<s2s_{3}<t<s_{2} \cdots t=st=s_{\ell} 1t<s1\leq t<s_{\ell}
0 (s1+)-(s_{1}+\ell) 11 (s2+1)-(s_{2}+\ell-1) 22 \cdots (s+1)-(s_{\ell}+1) \ell
Table 1. Letterwise increments in weights from uu to u^\hat{u}.

In addition, for the prefix v1v2vv_{1}v_{2}\cdots v_{\ell} of u^\hat{u}, each viv_{i} would incur an increment of ii in weight, if and only if usiu_{s_{i}} is an odd zz in uu. Summing up all these changes, we have

ω(u^)ω(u)\displaystyle\omega(\hat{u})-\omega(u) =i=1(si++1i)+|{tsi:ut=x}|+1iusi is oddi\displaystyle=\sum_{i=1}^{\ell}-(s_{i}+\ell+1-i)+|\{t\leq s_{i}:u_{t}=x\}|+\sum_{\begin{subarray}{c}1\leq i\leq\ell\\ \text{$u_{s_{i}}$ is odd}\end{subarray}}i
=i=1si+|{tsi:ut=x}|1iusi is eveni=i=1σi,\displaystyle=\sum_{i=1}^{\ell}-s_{i}+|\{t\leq s_{i}:u_{t}=x\}|-\sum_{\begin{subarray}{c}1\leq i\leq\ell\\ \text{$u_{s_{i}}$ is even}\end{subarray}}i=-\sum_{i=1}^{\ell}\sigma_{i},

which yields claim (3).

Lastly, it should be clear from our construction (especially the definitions of σi\sigma_{i} and viv_{i}), that the mapping ψ\psi is invertible, thus a bijection between 𝒲(n,k,,j)\mathcal{W}(n,k,\ell,j) and 𝒜(n,k,,j)\mathcal{A}(n,k,\ell,j). ∎

For our running example u=xzxyxzyyzu=xzxyxzyyz from Fig. 1, one checks that π=8+6+4+2\pi=8+6+4+2 and σ=8+4+2\sigma=8+4+2, therefore ψ(u)=(π,σ)𝒜(34,3,3,1)\psi(u)=(\pi,\sigma)\in\mathcal{A}(34,3,3,1).

Problem 2.5.

Recall our first proof of Theorem 1.7, where we have derived the generating function (2.3) for A(n,k,)A(n,k,\ell). The same analysis readily gives us the following generating function for the refined A(n,k,,j)A(n,k,\ell,j):

n,k,,j0A(n,k,,j)xkyzjqn\displaystyle\sum_{n,k,\ell,j\geq 0}A(n,k,\ell,j)x^{k}y^{\ell}z^{j}q^{n} =k,0(zq;q)(q;q)k(q2;q2)xkyq(k++12)+(+12).\displaystyle=\sum_{k,\ell\geq 0}\frac{(-zq;q)_{\ell}}{(q;q)_{k}(q^{2};q^{2})_{\ell}}x^{k}y^{\ell}q^{\binom{k+\ell+1}{2}+\binom{\ell+1}{2}}.

Therefore, it might be interesting to find the generating function for |𝒲(n,k,,j)||\mathcal{W}(n,k,\ell,j)|, so as to give an analytic counterpart of Theorem 2.3.

3. Proof of Theorem 1.9

We begin this section by introducing the Durfee square, which is an important conjugation invariant for integer partition. Suppose λ=λ1+λ2+\lambda=\lambda_{1}+\lambda_{2}+\cdots is a partition, then the Durfee square of λ\lambda is the largest square that could fit in its Ferrers graph. Alternatively, λ\lambda has a Durfee square of side dd, if and only if dd is the largest integer ii, such that λii\lambda_{i}\geq i. For example, the partition in Fig. 1 (ignoring its colors) has a Durfee square of side 44.

Now each partition λ\lambda can be written as a triple (d,π,σ)(d,\pi,\sigma), where dd is the Durfee side of λ\lambda, and π=λd+1+λd+2+\pi=\lambda_{d+1}+\lambda_{d+2}+\cdots (resp. σ=λd+1+λd+2+\sigma=\lambda^{\prime}_{d+1}+\lambda^{\prime}_{d+2}+\cdots) is the subpartition below the Durfee square of λ\lambda (resp. the conjugate partition λ\lambda^{\prime}). The following two facts are immediate from the definition.

  • |λ|=d2+|π|+|σ||\lambda|=d^{2}+|\pi|+|\sigma|;

  • both π\pi and σ\sigma are partitions with parts no greater than dd.

As our running example, the (uncolored) partition λ=12+8+6+4+3+1\lambda=12+8+6+4+3+1 can be represented as (4,3+1,3+3+2+2+1+1+1+1)(4,~{}3+1,~{}3+3+2+2+1+1+1+1).

Basis partitions were first introduced by Gupta [15] and his definition involves the notion of successive ranks [4, Sect. 9.3]. All we need here is the following alternative definition due to Nolan, Savage, and Wilf [23]. See also [16] and [6] for other works related to basis partitions.

Definition 3.1.

[23, Thm. 3] A partition λ=(d,π,σ)\lambda=(d,\pi,\sigma) is said to be a basis partition, if and only if π\pi and σ\sigma do not have parts in common.

For a partition λ=λ1+λ2++λm2(n)\lambda=\lambda_{1}+\lambda_{2}+\cdots+\lambda_{m}\in\mathcal{L}_{2}(n), in addition to the standard Ferrers graph, we can also represent λ\lambda via the 22-indented Ferrers graph; see Fig. 2. We denote λ~\tilde{\lambda} the partition obtained from λ\lambda by setting

λ~i:=λi2m+2i1, for 1im.\tilde{\lambda}_{i}:=\lambda_{i}-2m+2i-1,\text{ for $1\leq i\leq m$}.

Graphically, the 22-indented Ferrers graph of λ\lambda is the ordinary Ferrers graph of λ~\tilde{\lambda} with the staircase (2m1)+(2m3)++3+1(2m-1)+(2m-3)+\cdots+3+1 attached to its left.

Next, we prove Theorem 1.9 by constructing a direct bijection η\eta between 2(n,k,)\mathcal{L}_{2}(n,k,\ell) and (n,k,)\mathcal{B}(n,k,\ell), i.e., the set of basis partitions λ=(k+,π,σ)\lambda=(k+\ell,\pi,\sigma) of nn, wherein π\pi has \ell distinct parts.

Proof of Theorem 1.9.

Given a partition λ=λ1+λ2++λm\lambda=\lambda_{1}+\lambda_{2}+\cdots+\lambda_{m} in 2(n,k,)\mathcal{L}_{2}(n,k,\ell) (here m=k+m=k+\ell), we proceed to construct its image η(λ)\eta(\lambda). First we isolate λ~\tilde{\lambda} from its 22-indented Ferrers graph, then we decompose its conjugate λ~\tilde{\lambda}^{\prime} into two partitions, π\pi and σ\sigma. π\pi is consisted of all those parts in λ~\tilde{\lambda}^{\prime} having the same length as a certain part containing a green cell (i.e., the last cell of a green part in λ\lambda), while the remaining parts of λ~\tilde{\lambda}^{\prime} constitute σ\sigma. A moment of reflection should reveal that the above way of decomposition guarantees that π\pi and σ\sigma do not have parts in common, and that π\pi has \ell distinct parts. Therefore, η(λ):=(m,π,σ)\eta(\lambda):=(m,\pi,\sigma) is indeed a basis partition in (n,k,)\mathcal{B}(n,k,\ell). The whole process is clearly invertible so we see η\eta is a bijection. ∎

η\eta
Figure 2. the 22-indented Ferrers graph of λ=14r+12g+8g+5r+2g\lambda=14_{r}+12_{g}+8_{g}+5_{r}+2_{g} and its image η(λ)\eta(\lambda).

We should point out that it is also not difficult to give a generating function proof of Theorem 1.9. The idea is to show that both types of partitions have the same generating function as follows:

n,k,02(n,k,)xkyqn\displaystyle\sum_{n,k,\ell\geq 0}\mathcal{L}_{2}(n,k,\ell)x^{k}y^{\ell}q^{n} =n,k,0(n,k,)xkyqn=m0(yq/x;q)mxmqm2(q;q)m.\displaystyle=\sum_{n,k,\ell\geq 0}\mathcal{B}(n,k,\ell)x^{k}y^{\ell}q^{n}=\sum_{m\geq 0}\frac{(-yq/x;q)_{m}x^{m}q^{m^{2}}}{(q;q)_{m}}. (3.1)

Setting x=y=1x=y=1 in (3.1) recovers the generating function of basis partitions, which was first derived by Nolan-Savage-Wilf [23, Coro. 2].

4. Proof of Theorem 1.11

Let 𝒟(n,k,)\mathcal{D}(n,k,\ell) denote the set of those partitions as described in Theorem 1.11, i.e., strict partitions of nn into k+2k+2\ell parts such that the Durfee square is of side k+k+\ell. Our goal in this section is to construct a direct bijection θ:3(n,k,)𝒟(n,k,)\theta:\mathcal{L}_{3}(n,k,\ell)\to\mathcal{D}(n,k,\ell).

The first thing to notice is that 3(n,k,)2(n,k,)\mathcal{L}_{3}(n,k,\ell)\subset\mathcal{L}_{2}(n,k,\ell) from their definitions, but partitions in 𝒟(n,k,)\mathcal{D}(n,k,\ell) might not be basis partitions so in general 𝒟(n,k,)(n,k,)\mathcal{D}(n,k,\ell)\not\subset\mathcal{B}(n,k,\ell). Consequently, restricting the bijection η\eta onto 3(n,k,)\mathcal{L}_{3}(n,k,\ell) is not sufficient. Nonetheless, the main ingredient in the construction of θ\theta is analogous to that of η\eta.

Proof of Theorem 1.11.

Given a non-empty partition λ=λ1++λm3(n,k,)\lambda=\lambda_{1}+\cdots+\lambda_{m}\in\mathcal{L}_{3}(n,k,\ell) with m=k+m=k+\ell, we explain how to derive its image θ(λ)\theta(\lambda). The first step is the same as that of η\eta. Namely, we display λ\lambda using its 22-indented Ferrers graph and peel off the partition λ~\tilde{\lambda} with

λ~i:=λi2m+2i1, for 1im.\tilde{\lambda}_{i}:=\lambda_{i}-2m+2i-1,\text{ for }1\leq i\leq m.

Note that λ~\tilde{\lambda} is a strict (λ~i>λ~i+1\tilde{\lambda}_{i}>\tilde{\lambda}_{i+1}) partition with either m1m-1 (when λ~m=0\tilde{\lambda}_{m}=0) or mm (when λ~m0\tilde{\lambda}_{m}\neq 0) parts. Moreover, if λi\lambda_{i} is a green part in λ\lambda, then λ~iλ~i+12\tilde{\lambda}_{i}-\tilde{\lambda}_{i+1}\geq 2.

Next, we decompose λ~\tilde{\lambda}^{\prime} into two subpartitions π\pi and σ\sigma, where π\pi is a strict partition consisted of all those parts in λ~\tilde{\lambda}^{\prime} containing a green cell, in other words, when λi\lambda_{i} is a green part in λ\lambda, then λλi\lambda^{\prime}_{\lambda_{i}} is a part assigned to π\pi. The remaining parts of λ~\tilde{\lambda} form σ\sigma. It is not hard to verify the following facts.

  • π\pi is a strict partition with \ell parts, all of which are no greater than mm.

  • If λm=1\lambda_{m}=1, then the largest part of π\pi is less than mm.

  • σ\sigma^{\prime} is a strict partition into m1m-1 or mm parts, depending on whether λm=1\lambda_{m}=1 or not.

  • |λ|=m2+|π|+|σ||\lambda|=m^{2}+|\pi|+|\sigma|.

These facts guarantee that θ(λ):=(m,π,σ)\theta(\lambda):=(m,\pi,\sigma) is indeed a partition in 𝒟(n,k,)\mathcal{D}(n,k,\ell), expressed using the triple notation (see section 3). It should also be clear how to reverse the above process, so θ\theta is bijective and the proof is now completed. ∎

We note that in [7], Andrews’s first proof of Theorem 1.3 utilized Sylvester’s 1882 identity [4, Thm. 9.2]:

(aq;q)\displaystyle(-aq;q)_{\infty} =1+k=1akq(3k2k)/2(aq;q)k1(1+aq2k)(q;q)k.\displaystyle=1+\sum_{k=1}^{\infty}\frac{a^{k}q^{(3k^{2}-k)/2}(-aq;q)_{k-1}(1+aq^{2k})}{(q;q)_{k}}. (4.1)

Here the parameter aa keeps track of the number of parts in each strict partition. Seeing that 𝒟(n,k,)\mathcal{D}(n,k,\ell) actually refines the set of strict partitions further by the size of the Durfee square, one can view our Theorem 1.11 as a combinatorial refinement of (4.1). On the other hand, (4.1) has seen multi-dimensional extensions recently, first by Alladi [1], then by Chern-Fu-Tang [11]. With this in mind, it seems plausible that we try to adapt our combinatorial approach to the multi-colored partition case, so as to give new partition-theoretical interpretations of those extended qq-summations derived in [1] and [11].

Another possible line of investigation, is to restrict d(n,k,)\mathcal{L}_{d}(n,k,\ell) further, by bounding the largest part of each two-color partition. This so-called “finitization” would presumably provide us with new polynomial analogues of the corresponding qq-series identities, such as it has been done in [8] and [26].

Acknowledgement

The author was partly supported by the National Natural Science Foundation of China grant 12171059 and the Natural Science Foundation Project of Chongqing (No. cstc2021jcyj-msxmX0693).

References

  • [1] K. Alladi, A multi-dimensional extension of Sylvester’s identity, Int. J. Number Theory 13 (2017), 2487–2504.
  • [2] K. Alladi and A. Berkovich, New polynomial analogues of Jacobi’s triple product and Lebesgue’s identities, Adv. in Appl. Math. 32 (2004), 801–824.
  • [3] K. Alladi and B. Gordon, Partition identities and a continued fraction of Ramanujan, J. Combin. Theory Ser. A 63 (1993), 275–300.
  • [4] G. E. Andrews, The Theory of Partitions, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1998).
  • [5] G. E. Andrews, Rogers-Ramanujan identities for two-color partitions, Indian J. Math. 29 (1987), 117–125.
  • [6] G. E. Andrews, Basis partition polynomials, overpartitions and the Rogers-Ramanujan identities, J. Approx. Theory 197 (2015), 62–68.
  • [7] G. E. Andrews, Partition identities for two-color partitions, Hardy-Ramanujan Journal 44 (2021), 74–80.
  • [8] A. Berkovich and A. K. Uncu, Elementary polynomial identities involving qq-trinomial coefficients, Ann. Comb. 23 (3-4) (2019), 549–560.
  • [9] C. Bessenrodt, A bijection for Lebesgue’s partition identity in the spirit of Sylvester, Discrete Math. 132 (1994), 1–10.
  • [10] W. Y. C. Chen, Q.-H. Hou, and L. H. Sun, An iterated map for the Lebesgue identity, arXiv:1002.0135v2.
  • [11] S. Chern, S. Fu, and D. Tang, Multi-dimensional qq-summations and multi-colored partitions, Ramanujan J. 51 (2020), 297–306.
  • [12] S. Corteel and J. Lovejoy, Overpartitions, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 356 (2004), 1623–1635.
  • [13] J. Dousse and B. Kim, An overpartition analogue of qq-binomial coefficients, II: Combinatorial proofs and (q,t)(q,t)-log concavity, J. Combin. Theory Ser. A 158 (2018), 228–253.
  • [14] S. Fu and D. Tang, Partitions with fixed largest hook length, Ramanujan J. 45 (2018), 375–390.
  • [15] H. Gupta, The rank-vector of a partition, Fibonacci Quart. 16 (1978), 548–552.
  • [16] M. D. Hirschhorn, Basis partitions and Rogers-Ramanujan partitions, Discrete Math. 205 (1999), 241–243.
  • [17] W. J. Keith and R. Nath, Partitions with prescribed hooksets, J. Comb. Number Theory 3(1) (2011), 39–50.
  • [18] V. A. Lebesgue, Sommation de quelques séries, J. Math. Pures Appl. 5 (1840), 42–71.
  • [19] Z. Lin, H. Xiong, and S. H. F. Yan, Combinatorics of integer partitions with prescribed perimeter, preprint.
  • [20] D. P. Little and J. A. Sellers, New proofs of identities of Lebesgue and Göllnitz via tilings, J. Combin. Theory Ser. A 116 (2009), 223–231.
  • [21] D. P. Little and J. A. Sellers, A tiling approach to eight identities of Rogers, European J. Combin. 31 (2010), 694–709.
  • [22] J. Lovejoy, Gordon’s theorem for overpartitions, J. Combin. Theory Ser. A 103 (2003), 393–401.
  • [23] J. M. Nolan, C. D. Savage and H. S. Wilf, Basis partitions, Discrete Math. 179 (1998), 277–283.
  • [24] I. Pak, Partition bijections, a survey, Ramanujan J. 12 (2006), 5–75.
  • [25] M. Rowell, A new exploration of the Lebesgue identity, Int. J. Number Theory 6 (2010), 785–798.
  • [26] A. K. Uncu, On double sum generating functions in connection with some classical partition theorems, Discrete Math. 344 (2021) 112562.