Combinatorial proofs and refinements of three partition theorems of Andrews
Abstract.
In his recent work, Andrews revisited two-color partitions with certain restrictions on the differences between consecutive parts, and he established three theorems linking these two-color partitions with more familiar kinds of partitions. In this note, we provide bijective proofs as well as refinements of those three theorems of Andrews. Our refinements take into account the numbers of parts in each of the two colors.
1. Introduction
In his recent paper [7] published in the Hardy-Ramanujan Journal, Andrews revisited two-color partitions and obtained three new partition theorems that are reminiscent of the two theorems on two-color partitions proved in his 1987 paper [5]. In order to state these new theorems, we first recall some definitions in the theory of partitions.
Given a non-negative integer , a partition, say , of is a non-increasing list of positive integers that sum up to . We shall write with , where might also be referred to as the weight of . In particular, we view the empty partition, denoted as , as the one and only partition of . Denote by and the set of all partitions and the set of all partitions of , respectively. For example, we have
and is said to be a partition of with one part of and two parts of . A standard way of representing partitions pictorially is to use the so-called Ferrers graph [4, p. 7]. For a partition , we draw a left-justified array of cells, so that a top-down counting reveals cells in the -th row; see Fig 1 for an example111This way of drawing Ferrers graphs is usually called the “English notation”.. Using Ferrers graph, the conjugate partition of , usually denoted as , is defined to be the partition rendered from counting cells in the Ferrers graph of by columns in stead of rows. So for instance, the conjugate of is .
Two-color partitions, on the other hand, are those in which each part may come in two colors, say red and green. We indicate the color of any given part by assigning a subindex (for red) or (for green) to that part. For instance, there are ten two-color partitions of , as listed below.
Given a two-color partition, we shall say that two parts are distinct if they are of different colors or different numerical values or both. We shall say that two parts are numerically distinct if they have different numercial values. As noted by Lovejoy [22, p. 395], if we require in addition that all green parts are distinct, we essentially recover overpartitions [12], a well-studied variant that usually enjoys parallel results to those known ones for ordinary partitions.
Suppose and are integers. Following Andrews [7], we define to be the set of two-color partitions of into numerically distinct parts such that the following three conditions are satisfied:
-
(1)
each red part is at least larger than the next largest part;
-
(2)
each green part is at least larger than the next largest part;
-
(3)
neither nor is allowed as a part.
We use to denote the cardinality of .
The three theorems on two-color partitions proved in [7] are these:
Theorem 1.1.
equals the number of two-color partitions of in which parts with the same color are distinct and green parts are all even numbers.
Theorem 1.2.
equals the number of basis partitions of .
Theorem 1.3.
equals the number of partitions of into distinct parts.
Remark 1.4.
To be precise, the original statements of Theorems 1.1 and 1.3 in Andrews’s paper [7] are different from what we give here, but it suffices to use Euler’s celebrated “Odd-distinct Theorem” to bridge the gap. The definition of basis partition is a bit involved so we decide to postpone it to section 3 (see Definition 3.1).
Andrews [7] proved the above theorems in a uniform way by manipulating generating functions and he requested for bijective proofs. The main purpose of this paper is to prove all three theorems bijectively. Indeed, our bijective approach makes it effortless to keep track of various partition statistics and consequently leads us to the following three refinements. We begin with two definitions.
Definition 1.5.
Let (resp. ) denote the set (resp. the number) of two-color partitions in with red parts and green parts.
Clearly, , hence the following three results are indeed refinements of Theorems 1.1, 1.2, and 1.3, respectively.
Definition 1.6.
Let (resp. ) be the set (resp. the number) of two-color partitions of , each of which is consisted of distinct red parts and distinct even green parts for a certain non-negative integer , wherein exactly red parts are larger than .
Theorem 1.7.
For non-negative integers , we have .
Example 1.8.
Taking , we see that
On the other hand, there are also four two-color partitions in , namely,
Theorem 1.9.
The number of basis partitions of such that has exactly distinct parts, is given by .
Example 1.10.
For , there are six basis partitions meeting the requirements, namely (in terms of the triple expression ; see Sect. 3),
On the other hand, one checks that
which also contains six partitions.
Theorem 1.11.
equals the number of partitions of into distinct parts such that the Durfee square is of side .
The definition of the Durfee square of a partition will be given in section 3.
Example 1.12.
For , the following are the ten strict partitions meeting the requirements,
On the other hand, one checks that
which contains ten partitions as well.
We will prove one refinement in each of the ensuing sections, and we conclude the paper with some outlook for future research.
2. Two proofs of Theorem 1.7
We present in this section two proofs of Theorem 1.7. The first proof is via generating functions and requires the following -binomial theorem [4, p. 17, Thm. 2.1]. For , , we have
(2.1) |
Here and in the sequel, we use the standard -series notations
We claim the following two generating functions for and , respectively.
(2.2) | ||||
(2.3) |
Indeed, given a partition , suppose it has () parts in total (regardless of the colors). These parts must all be distinct so at least they should contribute to the weight of . But the difference might as well be larger than , and this “widening of gaps”, if any, is accounted for by the factor
where dictates the widening between and , determines the extra gap between and , and so on and so forth. Finally, to assign the color for part, say , we make a decision between red (contributing ), and green (contributing , since each green part is at least larger than the next part). Collectively, this yields the factor
and we arrive at the right hand side of (2.2) after pulling out from each factor , .
Next, to verify (2.3), we see that for a given partition , its red parts larger than are generated by
The remaining red parts, if any, must be no greater than and are generated by , while the green even parts of are generated by
Cancelling out , we arrive at the right hand side of (2.3).
Analytic proof of Theorem 1.7.
It is worth noting that there is an auxiliary parameter 222This parameter appeared implicitly in the bijection of Alladi and Gordon; see [24, p. 26, Sect. 4.4]. in the definition of (see Definition 1.6), so one may ask what is the corresponding parameter for those two-color partitions in . Our second proof of Theorem 1.7, which is to construct a bijection between and , answers this question completely.
Andrews’s original proof of Theorem 1.1 relies on the following identity of Lebesgue [18]:
(2.4) |
In view of this, the first step towards proving the refinement Theorem 1.7 bijectively, is to interprete the Lebesgue identity combinatorially. This has been done several times via different approaches; see for example the works of Alladi-Gordon [3], and Bessenrodt [9], see also Pak’s survey [24] where both proofs were nicely summarized. Later proofs, refinements, and polynomial analogues of Lebesgue identity include Alladi-Berkovich [2], Little-Sellers [20], Rowell [25], Chen-Hou-Sun [10], and Dousse-Kim [13]. Our bijection, when interpreted in terms of tilings, is equivalent to Little and Sellers’s construction [20], which itself has its roots in Alladi and Gordon’s work [3].
Little and Sellers’s approach via tilings [20] is intuitive and lends itself to further applications [21]. However, for our convenience, we use words made of three letters , and , which correspond to black squares, white squares, and dominoes, respectively.
The profile of an integer partition is the south-west to north-east border path in its Ferrers graph. This notion seems to be first introduced by Keith and Nath [17]; see also [14] and [19], where this way of representing integer partitions proved to be useful. For our purpose here, we write the profiles of partitions in not as words composed of two letters ( for north and for east) as it was done in [14], but rather as words composed of three letters , and , so that we can tell red parts from green parts. More precisely, as we trace out the profile, we label the steps according to the following rules.
-
(1)
the two consecutive steps forming the corner cell of a certain red part are labeled together as ;
-
(2)
the three consecutive steps forming the last two cells of a certain green part are labeled together as ;
-
(3)
all remaining east steps are labeled as .
It should be clear from the definition that the profile in terms of the -- word as described above is uniquely determined by the partition and vice versa. The readers are invited to use the example in Fig. 1 to make sure they understand this correspondence. Let be our alphabet, and stands for the free monoid generated by the letters from . We denote the set of words in that are either empty or end with or . For each word , we define its weight to be
(2.5) |
where if the statement is true and otherwise. For the word in Fig. 1, one checks that . We denote the set of words in having weight , wherein the letter appears times and the letter appears times.
Proposition 2.1.
The mapping, say , that sends each partition to its profile written as a word in , and , is a bijection from to .
Now to prove Theorem 1.7, it remains to construct a bijection, say , from the set of words , to the set of two-color partitions . As alluded to earlier, we can decompose further into subsets , , i.e., the set of partitions in with precisely red parts no greater than . Again, we use to denote its cardinality. On the other hand for the profile words, we further distinguish two types of letter to account for the extra parameter .
Definition 2.2.
For a word , we say a letter is odd (resp. even) if for all , there is an odd (resp. even) number of being a or an odd . For each , we denote the set of words in that contain odd ’s.
Take the word in Fig. 1 for example, from left to right, the first and the last are even while the middle is odd, hence . Now we are ready to construct the aforementioned bijection . Then Theorem 1.7 follows immediately as a direct corollary of Proposition 2.1 and Theorem 2.3.
Theorem 2.3.
There exists a bijection .
Corollary 2.4.
The composition is a bijection from to . In particular, Theorem 1.7 holds true.
Proof of Theorem 2.3.
Take any word , we aim to derive a partition pair , where is a distinct partition into parts while is a distinct partition into even parts.
First off, we screen the word from right to left looking for letter , and suppose they are in with . Next, for each , we set
We further let be the word obtained from by replacing all letter by letter , and let
Finally, we take 333Strictly speaking, the images under the mapping should be words ending with or . So, when ends with , we simply ignore all its ending ’s (doing this will not change the weight of ), and then apply . and , i.e., is the partition with parts . With the following claims, we see that is indeed a two-color partition in .
-
(1)
all are even integers and .
-
(2)
is an - word containing copies of letter , of which occur in the prefix .
-
(3)
.
The proofs of the claims above are straightforward verifications. We give some details on the proof of claim (3) here and leave the rest to the interested readers. For the trivial case , clearly , and , so (3) holds true. In general for , we make a letter-by-letter comparison between and . For a certain letter in , if , then according to (2.5) it contributes nothing in either or . Otherwise , we go through various ranges for the index and list in Table 1 the corresponding increments in ’s contributions to the weights going from to .
In addition, for the prefix of , each would incur an increment of in weight, if and only if is an odd in . Summing up all these changes, we have
which yields claim (3).
Lastly, it should be clear from our construction (especially the definitions of and ), that the mapping is invertible, thus a bijection between and . ∎
For our running example from Fig. 1, one checks that and , therefore .
Problem 2.5.
Recall our first proof of Theorem 1.7, where we have derived the generating function (2.3) for . The same analysis readily gives us the following generating function for the refined :
Therefore, it might be interesting to find the generating function for , so as to give an analytic counterpart of Theorem 2.3.
3. Proof of Theorem 1.9
We begin this section by introducing the Durfee square, which is an important conjugation invariant for integer partition. Suppose is a partition, then the Durfee square of is the largest square that could fit in its Ferrers graph. Alternatively, has a Durfee square of side , if and only if is the largest integer , such that . For example, the partition in Fig. 1 (ignoring its colors) has a Durfee square of side .
Now each partition can be written as a triple , where is the Durfee side of , and (resp. ) is the subpartition below the Durfee square of (resp. the conjugate partition ). The following two facts are immediate from the definition.
-
•
;
-
•
both and are partitions with parts no greater than .
As our running example, the (uncolored) partition can be represented as .
Basis partitions were first introduced by Gupta [15] and his definition involves the notion of successive ranks [4, Sect. 9.3]. All we need here is the following alternative definition due to Nolan, Savage, and Wilf [23]. See also [16] and [6] for other works related to basis partitions.
Definition 3.1.
[23, Thm. 3] A partition is said to be a basis partition, if and only if and do not have parts in common.
For a partition , in addition to the standard Ferrers graph, we can also represent via the -indented Ferrers graph; see Fig. 2. We denote the partition obtained from by setting
Graphically, the -indented Ferrers graph of is the ordinary Ferrers graph of with the staircase attached to its left.
Next, we prove Theorem 1.9 by constructing a direct bijection between and , i.e., the set of basis partitions of , wherein has distinct parts.
Proof of Theorem 1.9.
Given a partition in (here ), we proceed to construct its image . First we isolate from its -indented Ferrers graph, then we decompose its conjugate into two partitions, and . is consisted of all those parts in having the same length as a certain part containing a green cell (i.e., the last cell of a green part in ), while the remaining parts of constitute . A moment of reflection should reveal that the above way of decomposition guarantees that and do not have parts in common, and that has distinct parts. Therefore, is indeed a basis partition in . The whole process is clearly invertible so we see is a bijection. ∎
We should point out that it is also not difficult to give a generating function proof of Theorem 1.9. The idea is to show that both types of partitions have the same generating function as follows:
(3.1) |
Setting in (3.1) recovers the generating function of basis partitions, which was first derived by Nolan-Savage-Wilf [23, Coro. 2].
4. Proof of Theorem 1.11
Let denote the set of those partitions as described in Theorem 1.11, i.e., strict partitions of into parts such that the Durfee square is of side . Our goal in this section is to construct a direct bijection .
The first thing to notice is that from their definitions, but partitions in might not be basis partitions so in general . Consequently, restricting the bijection onto is not sufficient. Nonetheless, the main ingredient in the construction of is analogous to that of .
Proof of Theorem 1.11.
Given a non-empty partition with , we explain how to derive its image . The first step is the same as that of . Namely, we display using its -indented Ferrers graph and peel off the partition with
Note that is a strict () partition with either (when ) or (when ) parts. Moreover, if is a green part in , then .
Next, we decompose into two subpartitions and , where is a strict partition consisted of all those parts in containing a green cell, in other words, when is a green part in , then is a part assigned to . The remaining parts of form . It is not hard to verify the following facts.
-
•
is a strict partition with parts, all of which are no greater than .
-
•
If , then the largest part of is less than .
-
•
is a strict partition into or parts, depending on whether or not.
-
•
.
These facts guarantee that is indeed a partition in , expressed using the triple notation (see section 3). It should also be clear how to reverse the above process, so is bijective and the proof is now completed. ∎
We note that in [7], Andrews’s first proof of Theorem 1.3 utilized Sylvester’s 1882 identity [4, Thm. 9.2]:
(4.1) |
Here the parameter keeps track of the number of parts in each strict partition. Seeing that actually refines the set of strict partitions further by the size of the Durfee square, one can view our Theorem 1.11 as a combinatorial refinement of (4.1). On the other hand, (4.1) has seen multi-dimensional extensions recently, first by Alladi [1], then by Chern-Fu-Tang [11]. With this in mind, it seems plausible that we try to adapt our combinatorial approach to the multi-colored partition case, so as to give new partition-theoretical interpretations of those extended -summations derived in [1] and [11].
Acknowledgement
The author was partly supported by the National Natural Science Foundation of China grant 12171059 and the Natural Science Foundation Project of Chongqing (No. cstc2021jcyj-msxmX0693).
References
- [1] K. Alladi, A multi-dimensional extension of Sylvester’s identity, Int. J. Number Theory 13 (2017), 2487–2504.
- [2] K. Alladi and A. Berkovich, New polynomial analogues of Jacobi’s triple product and Lebesgue’s identities, Adv. in Appl. Math. 32 (2004), 801–824.
- [3] K. Alladi and B. Gordon, Partition identities and a continued fraction of Ramanujan, J. Combin. Theory Ser. A 63 (1993), 275–300.
- [4] G. E. Andrews, The Theory of Partitions, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1998).
- [5] G. E. Andrews, Rogers-Ramanujan identities for two-color partitions, Indian J. Math. 29 (1987), 117–125.
- [6] G. E. Andrews, Basis partition polynomials, overpartitions and the Rogers-Ramanujan identities, J. Approx. Theory 197 (2015), 62–68.
- [7] G. E. Andrews, Partition identities for two-color partitions, Hardy-Ramanujan Journal 44 (2021), 74–80.
- [8] A. Berkovich and A. K. Uncu, Elementary polynomial identities involving -trinomial coefficients, Ann. Comb. 23 (3-4) (2019), 549–560.
- [9] C. Bessenrodt, A bijection for Lebesgue’s partition identity in the spirit of Sylvester, Discrete Math. 132 (1994), 1–10.
- [10] W. Y. C. Chen, Q.-H. Hou, and L. H. Sun, An iterated map for the Lebesgue identity, arXiv:1002.0135v2.
- [11] S. Chern, S. Fu, and D. Tang, Multi-dimensional -summations and multi-colored partitions, Ramanujan J. 51 (2020), 297–306.
- [12] S. Corteel and J. Lovejoy, Overpartitions, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 356 (2004), 1623–1635.
- [13] J. Dousse and B. Kim, An overpartition analogue of -binomial coefficients, II: Combinatorial proofs and -log concavity, J. Combin. Theory Ser. A 158 (2018), 228–253.
- [14] S. Fu and D. Tang, Partitions with fixed largest hook length, Ramanujan J. 45 (2018), 375–390.
- [15] H. Gupta, The rank-vector of a partition, Fibonacci Quart. 16 (1978), 548–552.
- [16] M. D. Hirschhorn, Basis partitions and Rogers-Ramanujan partitions, Discrete Math. 205 (1999), 241–243.
- [17] W. J. Keith and R. Nath, Partitions with prescribed hooksets, J. Comb. Number Theory 3(1) (2011), 39–50.
- [18] V. A. Lebesgue, Sommation de quelques séries, J. Math. Pures Appl. 5 (1840), 42–71.
- [19] Z. Lin, H. Xiong, and S. H. F. Yan, Combinatorics of integer partitions with prescribed perimeter, preprint.
- [20] D. P. Little and J. A. Sellers, New proofs of identities of Lebesgue and Göllnitz via tilings, J. Combin. Theory Ser. A 116 (2009), 223–231.
- [21] D. P. Little and J. A. Sellers, A tiling approach to eight identities of Rogers, European J. Combin. 31 (2010), 694–709.
- [22] J. Lovejoy, Gordon’s theorem for overpartitions, J. Combin. Theory Ser. A 103 (2003), 393–401.
- [23] J. M. Nolan, C. D. Savage and H. S. Wilf, Basis partitions, Discrete Math. 179 (1998), 277–283.
- [24] I. Pak, Partition bijections, a survey, Ramanujan J. 12 (2006), 5–75.
- [25] M. Rowell, A new exploration of the Lebesgue identity, Int. J. Number Theory 6 (2010), 785–798.
- [26] A. K. Uncu, On double sum generating functions in connection with some classical partition theorems, Discrete Math. 344 (2021) 112562.