Categorical representation of DRC-semigroups
Abstract
DRC-semigroups model associative systems with domain and range operations, and contain many important classes, such as inverse, restriction, Ehresmann, regular -, and -regular semigroups. In this paper we show that the category of DRC-semigroups is isomorphic to a category of certain biordered categories whose object sets are projection algebras in the sense of Jones. This extends the recent groupoid approach to regular -semigroups of the first and third authors. We also establish the existence of free DRC-semigroups by constructing a left adjoint to the forgetful functor into the category of projection algebras.
Keywords: DRC-semigroup, biordered category, projection algebra.
MSC: 20M50, 20M10, 18B40, 20M05.
James East,111Centre for Research in Mathematics and Data Science, Western Sydney University, Locked Bag 1797, Penrith NSW 2751, Australia. Emails: [email protected], [email protected], [email protected]. Matthias Fresacher,1 P.A. Azeef Muhammed,1 Timothy Stokes222Department of Mathematics, University of Waikato, Hamilton 3216, New Zealand. Email: [email protected].
1 Introduction
DRC-semigroups were introduced in [33], and first studied systematically in [50] where they were used to model associative systems with domain and range operations.333DRC-semigroups were referred to in [33] as reduced -semiabundant semigroups satisfying the congruence conditions. The current terminology stems from usage in [50, 30]. Such a semigroup has additional unary operations and satisfying the laws
DRC-semigroups contain many important classes, such as inverse [34], restriction [19], Ehresmann [33], regular - [43], and -regular semigroups [12]. For example, any inverse semigroup is a DRC-semigroup under the operations and , or more generally any -regular semigroup under and , in terms of the Moore–Penrose inverse. Prototypical examples of -regular semigroups are the multiplicative monoids and of real or complex matrices [46]. The above classes are shown in Figure 1; we refer to [50, 8] for more on these and other classes, as well as more examples and historical background.
One of the strong motivations for studying classes of semigroups such as those above stems from the fact that they can be understood categorically, going back to the celebrated Ehresmann–Nambooripad–Schein (ESN) Theorem, as formulated by Lawson in [34]. This result states that the category of inverse semigroups is isomorphic to the category of inductive groupoids, i.e. the ordered groupoids whose object sets are semilattices. The main significance of this result is that one can capture the entire semigroup by limited knowledge of the product (the groupoid only ‘remembers’ when ) and the natural partial order (). The ESN Theorem has far-reaching consequences and applications, for example to representation theory [47, 49, 48] and C*-algebras [36, 45, 31].
One of the first generalisations of the ESN Theorem, to the important class of Ehresmann semigroups and categories, was due to Lawson himself [33]. These include many non-inverse semigroups, such as monoids of binary relations (which are not even regular) and partition monoids [14, 39]. See also [37] for a recent alternative approach, and [58, 35, 7, 17, 22, 16, 1, 56, 55, 41, 26, 21, 20, 25, 13, 57, 18, 51, 53, 52] for other generalisations. Of course the main challenge in obtaining an ‘ESN-type’ theorem for a class of semigroups is to identify and axiomatise the appropriate categorical structures used in the representation. A major part of this is to ascertain the precise structure to place on the object sets, which play the role of the semilattices of Lawson’s inductive groupoids. Typically these are (proper) subsets of the idempotents of the semigroup in question, but they need not be commutative or even closed under multiplication, and in particular they need not be semilattices.
Recent work of the first and third authors [13] represents regular -semigroups by certain ordered groupoids whose object sets are the projection algebras of Imaoka [28]. These are special cases of Jones’ projection algebras, defined in [30] to obtain transformation representations of fundamental DRC-semigroups. These were subsequently used by Wang in [57] to obtain an ESN-type theorem for DRC-semigroups, although he did not use categories for his representation, but rather generalisations in which many more products/compositions are required to exist.
The main purpose of the current work is to extend the approaches of [13] and [33] to obtain a purely categorical representation for the class of DRC-semigroups. Our main result, Theorem 7.1, obtains an isomorphism between the category of DRC-semigroups and what we call chained projection categories. These are natural biordered categories whose object sets form projection algebras in the sense of Jones [30]. As an application, we establish the existence of free DRC-semigroups, thereby also extending the results of [15]. We note that special cases of these results, on so-called DRC-restriction semigroups, have been independently obtained by Die and Wang [8]. This is the class of DRC-semigroups for which our biordered categories have only a single order, and represents the limit to which the techniques of [13] generalise without significant modification.
The paper is organised as follows.
-
•
We begin in Section 2 with the preliminary definitions and results we need on biordered categories.
- •
-
•
We then turn to projection algebras in Section 4. After establishing several preliminary facts, we construct a forgetful functor (in Proposition 4.19) into the category of projection algebras. At the object level, this maps a DRC-semigroup to its underlying projection algebra , as defined by Jones [30]. We also define the chain category associated to a projection algebra (see Definition 4.28), which will play an important role in subsequent constructions.
-
•
In Section 5 we introduce the chained projection categories, and the category formed by them. Such a category is in fact a triple , where is a biordered category whose object set is a projection algebra (with close structural ties to ), and where is a certain functor from the chain category of . The main result here is Theorem 5.20, which constructs a functor .
- •
- •
-
•
In Section 8, we construct a left adjoint to the forgetful functor from Section 4, thereby establishing the existence of free projection-generated DRC-semigroups. These free semigroups are defined by presentations in terms of generators and defining relations. Among other things, this has the consequence that every (abstract) projection algebra is the algebra of projections of some DRC-semigroup, a fact that was first established by Jones in [30] by entirely different methods. Along the way, we also construct the unique (up to isomorphism) fundamental projection-generated DRC-semigroup with projection algebra .
- •
2 Preliminaries on biordered categories
Throughout the paper, we identify a small category with its morphism set, and identify the objects of with the identities, the set of which is denoted . Thus, we have domain and range maps , for which the following hold, for all :
-
•
exists if and only if , in which case and . (So we are composing morphisms ‘left to right’.)
-
•
.
-
•
If and exist, then .
-
•
for all .
A left-ordered category is a pair , where is a small category and a partial order on satisfying the following, for all :
-
•
If , then and .
-
•
If and , and if and , then .
-
•
For any with , there exists a unique with . This element is denoted , and called the left restriction of to .
(These are the -structured categories with restrictions, in the terminology of [33].) Right-ordered categories are defined analogously, where the third item above is replaced by:
-
•
For any with , there exists a unique with . This element is denoted , and called the right restriction of to .
A biordered category is a triple , where:
-
•
is a left-ordered category, and a right-ordered category, and
-
•
and restrict to the same order on , meaning that for all .
(The Ehresmann categories considered in [33] are certainly biordered categories in the above sense.) Unless there is a chance of confusion, we typically speak of ‘a biordered category ’, and assume the orders are named and . It is important to note that left and right restrictions in a biordered category are quite independent of each other. For example, if , then we need not have ; in fact, need not even have domain . (Some concrete examples are discussed in Section 9.)
We write for the (large) category of biordered categories. Morphisms in are the biordered morphisms. Such a morphism is a functor preserving both orders, in the sense that
(2.1) |
Although a biordered category need not be particularly symmetric in its own right, there is a certain symmetry/duality in the category itself. Specifically, we have an isomorphism , given at the object level by . Here denotes the opposite category to , in which domains and codomains are swapped, and composition is reversed. (At the morphism level we simply have .)
Throughout the paper, we will typically construct biordered categories by first defining an ordering on objects, and then defining suitable restrictions, as formalised in the next result. We omit the proof, as it is directly analogous to that of [13, Lemma 2.3].
Lemma 2.2.
Suppose is a small category for which the following two conditions hold:
-
(i)
There is a partial order on the object set .
-
(ii)
For all , and for all and , there exist morphisms and in such that the following hold, for all and :
-
(O1)
If , then and .
-
If , then and .
-
(O2)
.
-
(O3)
If , then .
-
If , then .
-
(O4)
If and , and if , then .
-
If and , and if , then .
-
(O1)
Then is a biordered category with orders given by
(2.3) |
Moreover, any biordered category has the above form. ∎
For biordered categories and , it is easy to check that a functor is a biordered morphism, i.e. satisfies (2.1), if and only if it satisfies
(2.4) |
Here, and henceforth, we denote by the common restriction of and to .
Consider a biordered category , and let . We then have two maps
given by
(2.5) |
Here for a partially ordered set , we write for the down-set of . It follows quickly from (ii)(O3) that
(2.6) |
A -congruence on a small category is an equivalence relation on satisfying the following, for all :
-
•
and ,
-
•
, whenever the stated compositions are defined,
-
•
, whenever the stated compositions are defined.
If is a biordered category, we say that the -congruence is a biordered congruence if it additionally satisfies the following, for all :
-
•
and ] for all and .
In this case the quotient is a biordered category with orders given by
3 DRC-semigroups
We now come to the main object of our study, the class of DRC-semigroups. We begin in Section 3.1 by recalling the definitions, and listing some basic properties; while many of these preliminary lemmas exist in the literature (see for example [30, 57, 50]), we give brief proofs to keep the paper self-contained. In Section 3.2 we show how to construct a biordered category from a DRC-semigroup, leading to a functor .
3.1 Definitions and basic properties
Definition 3.1.
A DRC-semigroup is an algebra , where is a semigroup, and where and are unary operations satisfying the following laws, for all :
-
(DRC1)
,
-
(DRC2)
,
-
(DRC3)
,
-
(DRC4)
,
-
,
-
,
-
,
-
.
Throughout the article, we will almost always identify an algebra with its underlying set, including for a DRC-semigroup . Thus, we typically speak of ‘a DRC-semigroup ’, write multiplication as juxtaposition, and assume the unary operations are denoted and .
We denote by the category of all DRC-semigroups, with DRC-morphisms. Such a morphism in is a function preserving all the operations, meaning that
As noted in the introduction, Lawson first introduced DRC-semigroups in [33], where he referred to them as reduced -semiabundant semigroups satisfying the congruence conditions. (The laws in axiom (DRC2) are typically called the congruence conditions as, for example, the identity is equivalent, in the presence of the other laws, to the relation being a left congruence on .) Lawson was mainly interested in Ehresmann semigroups, which additionally satisfy the law , and hence also , which makes (DRC3) redundant in the presence of the other laws.
As with , the category posesses a natural symmetry/duality. Specifically, if is a DRC-semigroup, and if is the opposite semigroup of , where for , then is a DRC-semigroup. Thus, any equality that holds in can be converted to a dual equality by reversing the order of all products, and interchanging and .
Remark 3.2.
Note that (DRC4) says and . It follows from these that
That is, we have the following consequence of (DRC1)–(DRC4):
-
(DRC5)
,
-
.
In calculations to follow, we use to indicate equality in a DRC-semigroup by one or more applications of (DRC1), and similarly for (DRC2)–(DRC5).
It follows from (DRC4) that . We denote this common image by , so
The elements of are called projections. We will typically use the next result without explicit reference.
Lemma 3.3 (cf. [50, Proposition 1.2]).
We have .
Proof.
Certainly every element of the stated set belongs to . Conversely, let , so that for some . Then , and similarly . From , it also follows that . ∎
Since every projection is an idempotent, it follows that (DRC3) is equivalent (in the presence of the other axioms) to:
-
(DRC3)′
, .
Lemma 3.4.
For any and we have
Proof.
The first follows from (DRC3)′ and ; the second is dual. ∎
Since projections are idempotents, the natural partial order on idempotents restricts to a partial order on :
(3.5) |
The next result shows that this is equivalent to either of or . This is referred to as the reduced property in the literature [50].
Corollary 3.6.
For , we have .
Proof.
Remark 3.7.
An equivalent definition of DRC-semigroups stems from this order-theoretic perspective. Thus, a DR-semigroup is defined in [50] to be a semigroup in which a (sub)set of idempotents is distinguished such that for each there exist smallest under the natural partial order for which , called and . This defines unary operations and on such (both with image ), and it follows that DRC-semigroups are precisely the DR-semigroups satisfying the congruence conditions (DRC2).
The set can be given the structure of a projection algebra, as defined by Jones in [30]. We will recall the formal definition in Section 4, but the next result will be used to verify the axioms. For we define the functions by
Lemma 3.8 (cf. [30, Proposition 7.2]).
For any , we have
-
(i)
, , , , ,
-
(ii)
, , , , .
Proof.
We just prove (i), as (ii) is dual. In what follows, we write to indicate an application of Lemma 3.4 (and continue to use , , etc.). For the first item we have , and for the second,
For the remaining three items, fix , and first note that . The third and fifth items follow by combining this with
and
For the fourth we have . ∎
3.2 From DRC-semigroups to biordered categories
We now wish to show that a DRC-semigroup naturally induces a biordered category with morphism set , and object/identity set . For this we need the following.
Lemma 3.9.
If is a DRC-semigroup, and if are such that , then and .
Proof.
We have ; the other is dual. ∎
As a consequence, we can make the following definition.
Definition 3.10.
Given a DRC-semigroup , we define the (small) category as follows:
-
•
The underlying (morphism) set of is .
-
•
The object/identity set is .
-
•
For we have and .
-
•
For with we have .
For , and for and we define and . (Here is the partial order on in (3.5).)
Proposition 3.11.
For any DRC-semigroup , the category is biordered, with and as in (2.3).
Proof.
We just need to check conditions (ii)(O1)–(ii)(O4) from Lemma 2.2. By symmetry, we just need to check the properties of left restrictions.
(ii)(O2). We have .
(ii)(O3). From we have , and so .
(ii)(O4). Here we have , and also , so
Remark 3.12.
Note that our orders and were denoted and (the other way round) by Lawson in the context of Ehresmann semigroups [33]. We have chosen the current terminology, as our is contained in Green’s preorder, which is defined by . An analogous statement applies to and . These containments are strict in general. For example, if is a DRC-monoid with identity , then every element is and below , but only the projections are or below .
The construction of from is an object map from to . For a DRC-morphism , we define . (Since the underlying set of is just , this is well defined.)
Proposition 3.13.
is a functor .
Proof.
It remains to check that any DRC-morphism is a biordered morphism , where and . This amounts to checking (cf. (2.4)) that
-
(i)
for all with ,
-
(ii)
for all and , and
-
(iii)
for all and .
Here, we use dashes to distinguish the parameters and operations associated to and . We will, however, denote multiplication in both and by juxtaposition. Next we note that for any ,
(i). If , then , and so
(ii). If , where for simplicity we write , then , and so . This gives , and it follows that .
4 Projection algebras
The set of projections of a DRC-semigroup need not be a subsemigroup of . Nevertheless, it can be given the structure of a projection algebra, as axiomatised by Jones [30]. These algebras will play a crucial role in all that follows, and here we gather the information we need. In Section 4.1 we recall Jones’ definition, albeit in an alternative format, and prove some preliminary results (some of which can again be found in the existing literature). In Section 4.2 we consider the category of projection algebras, and show how the construction of from a DRC-semigroup leads to a functor . In Section 4.3 we show how a projection algebra induces two biordered categories, the path category and the chain category . These will be crucial ingredients in constructions of subsequent sections.
4.1 Definitions and basic properties
Definition 4.1.
A projection algebra is an algebra , where and are families of unary operations satisfying the following laws, for all :
-
(P1)
,
-
(P2)
,
-
(P3)
,
-
(P4)
,
-
(P5)
,
-
,
-
,
-
,
-
,
-
.
The elements of a projection algebra are called projections. We typically speak of ‘a projection algebra ’, and assume that its operations are denoted and .
Again there is a natural symmetry/duality, as whenever is a projection algebra, so too is . As usual, this allows us to shorten proofs, by omitting the proof of any statement whose dual has already been proved. This will often be done without explicit comment.
Remark 4.2.
Jones’ original formulation of projection algebras in [30] utilised two binary operations, denoted and , which are related to our unary operations by:
Jones’ axioms (with his labelling) are as follows:
-
(LP1)
,
-
(LP2)
,
-
(LP3)
,
-
(LP4)
,
-
(RP1)
,
-
(RP2)
,
-
(RP3)
,
-
(RP4)
,
-
(PA1)
and ,
-
(PA2)
and .
Our axioms (P1)–(P3) correspond to Jones’ (LP1)–(LP3) and (RP1)–(RP3), and our (P4)–(P5) are Jones’ (PA1)–(PA2). For example, directly translating (RP3) to the unary setting yields , which is equivalent to the equality of maps, (requiring one less parameter), the first part of our (P3).
Jones’ (LP4) and (RP4) are absent from our list, as they are consequences of the other axioms; see Lemma 4.5 and Remark 4.6. The reason Jones included those axioms is that (LP1)–(LP4) are axioms for ‘left projection algebras’, which are used to model projections of ‘DC-semigroups’, and (LP4) cannot be deduced from (LP1)–(LP3), as can be shown for example with Mace4 [40]. Similar comments apply to (RP1)–(RP4).
One reason we have opted for the unary approach is due to associativity of function composition, meaning that bracketing becomes unnecessary for complex projection algebra terms. Another is to emphasise the connection with certain natural mappings , , and on associated categories, which will be introduced below. For a more detailed comparison of the binary and unary approaches, we refer to [13, Remark 4.2].
Here then is the connection between DRC-semigroups and projection algebras. The following is well defined because of Lemma 3.8.
Definition 4.3 (cf. [30, Proposition 7.2]).
The projection algebra of a DRC-semigroup has
-
•
underlying set , and
-
•
and operations defined by
For the rest of this section, we fix a projection algebra . In calculations to follow, we use to indicate equality by one or more applications of (P1), and similarly for the other axioms.
Lemma 4.4.
For any we have
Proof.
For the first implication (the second is dual), suppose . Then
The next lemma gathers some fundamental consequences of (P1)–(P5), which will be used so frequently as to warrant naming them (P6)–(P10).
Lemma 4.5.
For any we have
-
(P6)
,
-
(P7)
,
-
(P8)
,
-
(P9)
,
-
(P10)
,
-
,
-
,
-
,
-
,
-
.
Proof.
(P6). We have .
Lemma 4.7.
For , the following are equivalent:
-
(i)
,
-
(ii)
for some , i.e. ,
-
(iii)
,
-
(iv)
for some , i.e. ,
-
(v)
.
Proof.
The following implications are clear:
We will show that , and then will follow by duality.
. If for some , then .
. If , then . Lemma 4.4 then gives . ∎
Definition 4.8.
Proposition 4.10 (cf. [30, Lemma 5.2]).
is a partial order.
Proof.
Reflexivity follows from (P1). For anti-symmetry, suppose and , so that and . Then . For transitivity, suppose and , so that and . Then , which gives . ∎
Lemma 4.11.
If , then and .
Proof.
If , then , and so . Essentially the same calculation gives . ∎
In addition to the partial order , a crucial role in all that follows will be played by the following relation.
Definition 4.12.
We define the relation on a projection algebra by
Note that is reflexive by (P1), but need not be symmetric or transitive.
In the next sequence of results we gather some basic facts about the relation , and its interaction with the partial order .
Lemma 4.13.
Let , and put and . Then:
-
(i)
, and ,
-
(ii)
and ,
-
(iii)
if for some , then ,
-
(iv)
if for some , then .
Proof.
(ii). We have .
Corollary 4.14.
If , then for any and we have and .
Proof.
Lemma 4.15.
If are such that and , then
Proof.
For the first (the second is dual), we have
The case of the previous result has the following simple consequence.
Corollary 4.16.
For , we have . ∎
It will be convenient to record a result concerning products of projections in a DRC-semigroup.
Lemma 4.17.
If for a DRC-semigroup , then
-
(i)
and ,
-
(ii)
and if
4.2 The category of projection algebras
Definition 4.18.
We write for the category of projection algebras. A projection algebra morphism in is a map such that
In Definition 4.3 (cf. Lemma 3.8) we saw that a DRC-semigroup gives rise to a projection algebra . In this way, can be thought of as an object map . Since a DRC-morphism maps projections to projections (by the law ), it follows that we can define
to be the (set-theoretic) restriction of to .
Proposition 4.19.
is a functor .
Proof.
It only remains to show that is a projection algebra morphism for any DRC-morphism . But for any we have
4.3 The chain category of a projection algebra
Definition 4.20.
Let be a projection algebra. A (-)path is a non-empty tuple where and . We write and . The set of all such paths is the path category of , under the composition defined by
For , we identify the path with itself, and in this way we have .
We now wish to give the path category the structure of a biordered category. To this end, consider a path , and let and . We then define the restrictions
where | for each , | (4.21) | ||||||
and | ||||||||
where | for each . | (4.22) |
Note here that and , since and , so in particular we have and . We now prove a sequence of results that show these restrictions satisfy conditions (ii)(O1)–(ii)(O4) from Lemma 2.2.
Lemma 4.23.
If , and if , then , and we have and .
Proof.
Let , and write as in (4.21). Since we have
To show that , we must show that for all , i.e. that and . By definition, we note that . We then have
Since , we have , and also by Lemma 4.11, so
By definition, we have , and . ∎
Lemma 4.24.
If , and if , then .
Proof.
Let , and write as in (4.21). We need to show that for all . This is true for , as . If , then by induction, and since , we have . ∎
Lemma 4.25.
If , and if , then .
Proof.
Lemma 4.27.
If with , and if , then with we have
Proof.
Write and , noting that . Then
It follows that | ||||
Lemmas 4.23–4.27 and their duals show that the restrictions given in (4.21) and (4.22) satisfy the conditions of Lemma 2.2. It follows that is a biordered category, under the orders and defined, for , by
Definition 4.28.
Let be a projection algebra, and let be the path category. We let be the congruence on generated by the relations for all . Since
it follows that is a biordered congruence. Consequently, the quotient
is a biordered category under the induced and orders. We call the chain category of . An element of is called a (-)chain, and is an -class of a path. For a path , we write for the corresponding chain, so that . We again identify a projection with the chain , so that . Restrictions in are given by
5 Chained projection categories
In Proposition 3.11 we saw that a DRC-semigroup gives rise to a biordered category whose object set is the projection algebra . It turns out that the category carries rather a lot more information, and has the structure of what we will call a chained projection category. In this section we introduce this class of categories, and the category formed by them. We do so sequentially, by first defining weak projection categories (Section 5.1), projection categories (Section 5.2), weak chained projection categories (Section 5.3), and finally chained projection categories (Section 5.4). At each step of the way we will show that a DRC-semigroup gives rise to a structure of the relevant kind, ultimately leading to a functor ; see Theorem 5.20. We will eventually see in Section 7 that is an isomorphism.
5.1 Weak projection categories
Definition 5.1.
A weak projection category is a pair , consisting of a biordered category and a projection algebra , for which the restriction of both orders and to is the order from (4.9).
Let be a weak projection category, and let . As in (2.5), we have the two maps
given by and , for and . Since and , we can also define the maps
(5.2) |
Lemma 5.3.
If is a weak projection category, and if , then
-
(i)
and ,
-
(ii)
and ,
-
(iii)
and for any and ,
-
(iv)
and .
Proof.
(i). For any , we have , and so .
Lemma 5.4.
If is a DRC-semigroup, then is a weak projection category.
Proof.
Write and . By Lemma 3.8 and Proposition 3.11, is a projection algebra and a biordered category, and by construction we have . It remains to check that:
As ever, it is enough to establish the equivalence involving and . For this, first suppose , so that for some . It follows that , so that (cf. (3.5)). Conversely, if , then the restriction exists, and ; it follows that . ∎
In what follows, we will need to understand the and maps associated to the weak projection category arising from a DRC-semigroup . For this, consider a morphism . For we have
It follows that for arbitrary we have
Similar calculations apply to the and maps, and in summary we have:
(5.5) |
5.2 Projection categories
We saw in Lemma 5.3(iii) that the and maps in a weak projection category behave well with regard to left and right restrictions, respectively, in the sense that and for any and . We are particularly interested in the situation in which the analogous statements hold for the other restrictions.
Definition 5.6.
A projection category is a weak projection category satisfying:
-
(C1)
For every , and every and , we have
We write for the category of projection categories. A morphism in is a biordered morphism whose object map is a projection algebra morphism.
Proposition 5.7.
The assignment is the object part of a functor .
5.3 Weak chained projection categories
We now bring in an extra layer of structure.
Definition 5.8.
Given a projection category , an evaluation map is a biordered -functor , where is the chain category of , and where -functor means that for all . (We write evaluation maps to the left of their arguments.) It quickly follows that and for all .
Within the image of , we will mainly be interested in elements of the form , for . The next lemma gathers some simple properties of these elements, all of which follow quickly from the definitions.
Lemma 5.9.
Let be a projection category, and an evaluation map.
-
(i)
For all we have .
-
(ii)
For all we have and ,
-
(iii)
For all , and for all and , we have
Definition 5.10.
A weak chained projection category is a triple , where is a projection category, and is an evaluation map. We write for the category of weak chained projection categories. A morphism in is called a chained projection functor, and is a projection category morphism that respects the evaluation maps, in the sense that
Consider a DRC-semigroup , and write . Since projections are idempotents, there is a well-defined map
where the latter product is taken in .
Lemma 5.11.
is an evaluation map.
Proof.
We first claim that for we have
i.e. that
(5.12) |
By symmetry it suffices to prove the first. The case being clear, we assume that . We then use (DRC2), induction and to calculate
Next we check that is a -functor. Certainly for all . Now consider composable chains and in . We then have
Note that the final product is a composition in since by (5.12).
Finally, we need to check that is biordered, i.e. that
For the first (the second is dual), write , so that , where each . Noting that and , we need to show that
When we have (as ), so now suppose . We then have by induction, so it remains to show that . For this we use Lemma 3.4 to calculate
Proposition 5.13.
The assignment is the object part of a functor .
Proof.
It follows from Proposition 5.7 and Lemma 5.11 that is a weak chained projection category for any DRC-semigroup . It remains to check that any DRC-morphism is a chained projection functor . We already know from Proposition 5.7 that is a projection category morphism , so it remains to check that preserves the evaluation maps. But for with we have
5.4 Chained projection categories
We have almost achieved the main objective of this section, defining chained projection categories. These will be the weak chained projection categories satisfying a natural coherence condition stating that certain diagrams in commute. A diagrammatic representation of this condition can be seen in Figure 2. To see that the relevant morphisms are well defined requires a preliminary definition and lemma.
In what follows, for a small category , and objects , it will be convenient to write
for the set of all morphisms .
Definition 5.14.
Let be a projection category, let , and let . We define the projections
(5.15) |
When no confusion arises, we will abbreviate these to , , and so on.
Lemma 5.16.
Let be a projection category, and let and . Then the projections in (5.15) satisfy the following:
-
(i)
and ,
-
(ii)
,
-
(iii)
exists, and has domain ,
-
(iv)
and ,
-
(v)
,
-
(vi)
exists, and has range .
Proof.
(i). We have
(ii). For , we have
and
For , let and , so that by Lemma 4.13(i). Since , it then follows from Corollary 4.14 that , so we can complete the proof of this part by showing that . For this we use Lemmas 4.13(ii) and 5.3(ii) to calculate
(iii). As in the previous part we write , noting that . This means that exists, and we denote this by . Note that
Since , it follows that exists, and it remains to show that this has domain . For this we have
as | ||||
by (C1), as . |
Definition 5.17.
Here then is the main definition of this section:
Definition 5.19.
A chained projection category is a weak chained projection category satisfying the following coherence condition:
-
(C2)
For every , and for every , we have , where these morphisms are as in (5.18).
We denote by the full subcategory of consisting of all chained projection categories, and all chained projection functors between them.
For a DRC-semigroup we write for the weak chained projection category from Proposition 5.13.
Theorem 5.20.
is a functor .
Proof.
During the proof, we use (5.5) freely.
Given Proposition 5.13, we just need to check that satisfies (C2) for any DRC-semigroup . So fix and , let be as in (5.15), and write
By Lemma 5.16(iii) we have , and of course , so it follows from (DRC1) that , and so
It therefore remains to show that , and we claim that
(5.21) |
It suffices by symmetry to prove the first. For this we first note that , and we have
since by Lemma 5.16(i); cf. (3.5) | |||||
by Lemma 3.4 | |||||
by (DRC1) | |||||
by (DRC1), since . | (5.22) | ||||
Next we note that | |||||
since by Lemma 5.16(iv); cf. (3.5) | |||||
by the definition of | |||||
by Lemma 3.4 | |||||
by (DRC1) | |||||
using again. | (5.23) | ||||
Putting everything together, it follows that | |||||
by (5.22) | |||||
by (5.23) | |||||
by (DRC1) | |||||
as . |
This completes the proof of (5.21), and hence of the theorem. ∎
6 From chained projection categories to DRC-semigroups
In Section 5 we defined the category of chained projection categories, and constructed a functor . We will see in Section 7 that is an isomorphism. The proof involves constructing an inverse functor in the opposite direction, and that is the purpose of this section. The main part of the work is undertaken in Section 6.1, where we show how to construct a DRC semigroup from a chained projection category; see Definition 6.1 and Theorem 6.5. We then construct the functor in Section 6.2; see Theorem 6.7.
6.1 The DRC-semigroup associated to a chained projection category
Definition 6.1.
Given a chained projection category , we define to be the -algebra with:
-
•
underlying set ,
-
•
unary operations and given by and for , and
- •
For the remainder of this section we fix a chained projection category . In Theorem 6.5 we will show that is indeed a DRC-semigroup. Our first task in this direction is to show that is associative, the proof of which requires the following lemma.
Lemma 6.2.
For any we have
Proof.
For the first (the second is dual), we keep the notation of Definition 6.1, and we have . ∎
Lemma 6.3.
For any we have .
Proof.
During the proof, we write
We also denote the projections from Definition 5.14 by , , and so on. Given (C2), we can prove the lemma by showing that
where and are as in Definition 5.17. We just do the first, as the second follows by duality.
Writing and , we first note that
and we also let (cf. Lemma 6.2). Then
We also use (ii)(O4) to calculate
where and . Next we note that
Since , we also have
using (C1) in the second-last step. Combining this with Lemma 5.9(iii) it follows that
We then have
as shown above | ||||
by Lemma 4.13(ii) | ||||
by Lemma 5.3(ii), noting that . |
Putting everything together, we have
as required. ∎
Lemma 6.4.
-
(i)
If are such that , then .
-
(ii)
If , then , where and .
-
(iii)
If , and if and , then and .
Proof.
Theorem 6.5.
If is a chained projection category, then is a DRC-semigroup.
Proof.
Given Lemma 6.3, it remains to verify (DRC1)–(DRC4). By symmetry, only the first part of each needs to be treated.
(DRC2). Writing , we use Lemma 6.2 to calculate
(DRC3). Write and . We must show that . By Lemma 6.4(ii), we have
By Lemma 6.2, and since , we have , so in fact . Thus,
Essentially the same argument gives .
(DRC4). This follows from . ∎
We will also need the following information concerning the projections of .
Proposition 6.6.
Let be a chained projection category, and let . Then
-
(i)
,
-
(ii)
and for all .
6.2 A functor
We can think of the construction of the DRC-semigroup from the chained projection category as an object map . At the level of morphisms, any chained projection functor is a map . Since the underlying sets of the semigroups and are and , respectively, we can think of as a map . We now show that , interpreted in this way, is a functor.
Theorem 6.7.
is a functor .
Proof.
It remains only to check that a morphism in is also a morphism in , where and . For simplicity, we will write for . We also use dashes to distinguish between the various parameters and operations on and , and on and .
If , then writing , we have
It therefore remains to show that for all . So fix some such , and let
As shown above, we have , and similarly . It follows that
where and . Since is a projection algebra morphism, we have
Since respects evaluation maps, we have
Since is a biordered functor, we have
Putting everything together, we have
7 The category isomorphism
In this section we will show that the functors
from Theorems 5.20 and 6.7 are mutually inverse isomorphisms, thereby proving the main result of the paper:
Theorem 7.1.
The category of DRC-semigroups (with DRC-morphisms) is isomorphic to the category of chained projection categories (with chained projection functors).
Proof.
Proposition 7.2.
For any chained projection category we have .
Proof.
Throughout the proof we will write
To prove the result we need to show that:
-
(i)
as projection algebras,
-
(ii)
as biordered categories, and
-
(iii)
as maps.
As usual we use dashes in what follows to denote the various parameters and operations on .
(ii). By construction, the underlying set of is the same as that of and . We also have , and
It follows that for any with , we have , and Lemma 6.4(i) then gives
It remains to check that the orders on and coincide, and for this it suffices to show that
Here we write and for restrictions in , and and for restrictions in . For this we use Lemma 6.4(iii) to calculate
(iii). We must show that for any chain . So fix some such . First observe that for any , Lemma 6.4(ii) gives
We then have
by definition | ||||
as each is an idempotent of | ||||
as just observed | ||||
by Lemma 6.4(i) | ||||
as is a functor. |
This completes the proof. ∎
Proposition 7.3.
For any DRC-semigroup we have .
8 Free and fundamental projection-generated DRC-semigroups
Theorem 7.1 shows that the categories and are isomorphic. It also follows from the definition of the functors and that the algebras of projections of DRC-semigroups are precisely the same as the (structured) object sets of chained projection categories. But the theorem does not answer the following:
Question 8.1.
Given an abstract projection algebra , as in Definition 4.1, does there exist a DRC-semigroup with ? Or equivalently, does there exist a chained projection category ?
The semigroup version of this question was answered in the affirmative by Jones in his study of fundamental DRC-semigroups [30], i.e. the DRC-semigroups with no non-trivial projection-separating congruences. In [30, Section 9], Jones constructed a DRC-semigroup, denoted , from a projection algebra , and showed it to be the maximum fundamental DRC-semigroup with projection algebra , meaning that:
-
•
is fundamental, and has projection algebra , and
-
•
any fundamental DRC-semigroup with projection algebra embeds canonically into .
In a sense, one of the purposes of the current section is to provide another way to answer Question 8.1, in that we construct two different DRC-semigroups, denoted and , both with projection algebra . However, we have a deeper purpose than this (as did Jones), and our main objective here is to demonstrate the existence of free (projection-generated) DRC-semigroups. Specifically, we show that the assignment is the object part of a functor , and that this is in fact a left adjoint to the forgetful functor from Proposition 4.19, which maps a DRC-semigroup to its underlying projection algebra . It follows that is the free (projection-generated) DRC-semigroup with projection algebra .
The semigroup is defined abstractly in terms of a presentation by generators and relations. By contrast, the semigroup is a concrete semigroup consisting of pairs of self-maps of , built from the underlying and operations of . The main initial purpose of is to provide a concrete homomorphic image of , which will be useful in certain proofs concerning the latter. But we will also see that is very special in its own right, in that it is the unique projection-generated fundamental DRC-semigroup with projection algebra .
The definitions of and are given in Section 8.1, and their key properties are established in Theorem 8.11. Categorical freeness of is established in Section 8.2; see Theorem 8.17. The unique fundamentality properties of are established in Section 8.3; see Theorem 8.25.
Before we begin, we briefly revise our notation for semigroup presentations. Let be an alphabet, and write for the free semigroup over , which is the semigroup of all non-empty words over , under concatenation. Also let be a set of pairs of words over , and write for the congruence on generated by . We then write
and call this the semigroup defined by the presentation . Elements of are called letters or generators, and elements of are called relations. A relation is often written as an equality, .
8.1 Definition of and
Fix a projection algebra for the duration of this section. Also fix an alphabet
in one-one correspondence with , and let be the set of relations, quantified over all :
-
(R1)
,
-
(R2)
,
-
(R3)
.
Write for the congruence on generated by the relations (R1)–(R3), and denote by the -class of a word . We then take to be the semigroup defined by the presentation
We will soon see that is a DRC-semigroup with projection algebra (isomorphic to) .
We also define a second semigroup associated to . First, we denote by the full transformation semigroup over , i.e. the semigroup of all maps under composition. As before, we also write for the opposite semigroup. Our second semigroup will be a subsemigroup of the direct product , in which the operation is given by . For each , we define the pair
and the semigroup
A typical element of has the form
Define the (surjective) semigroup homomorphism
Lemma 8.2.
We have .
Proof.
It follows that induces a well-defined (surjective) semigroup homomorphism
Note in particular that for .
In what follows, we write to denote -equivalence of words from by one or more applications of relations from (R1), with similar meanings for and .
Lemma 8.3.
If , then , where and .
Proof.
We have , using (P9) in the last step. ∎
For a path from the path category , we define the word
Lemma 8.4.
Any word over is -equivalent to for some .
Proof.
Consider an arbitrary word . We will show by induction on that
The case is trivial, so we now assume that . First, Lemma 8.3 gives
and by Lemma 4.13(i) we have , and . By induction, we have
for some () and , with . We also have
Since , it follows from Corollary 4.14 that . Putting everything together, we have
with all conditions met. (Note that for .) ∎
Lemma 8.5.
If , then
-
(i)
and ,
-
(ii)
and .
Proof.
It follows that we have well-defined maps and given by
for . | (8.6) |
There should be no confusion in using and to denote these operations on both semigroups and , as they take on different kinds of arguments in the two semigroups. Note also that
(8.7) |
Lemma 8.8.
If , and if and , then
Proof.
For the first (the second is dual), write , and fix . We then have
and we must show that
If , then (using in the second step). For , we apply induction to calculate
and we are done, since . ∎
For paths and with , the concatenation of with is a path, which we denote by
Lemma 8.9.
For paths and , we have
Proposition 8.10.
is a DRC-semigroup.
Proof.
We need to check the axioms (DRC1)–(DRC4), and as usual we only have to prove one part of each. To do so, fix paths and .
(DRC1). We have .
(DRC2). Let and , and write and . Lemma 8.9 then gives
Since and , it then follows that
(DRC3). Keeping the notation of the previous part, and keeping in mind , we have
An analogous calculation gives .
(DRC4). We have . ∎
Theorem 8.11.
If is a projection algebra, then and are projection-generated DRC-semigroups, with
Proof.
We saw in Proposition 8.10 that is a DRC-semigroup. It follows that
so we have a surjective map
Combining the definitions with Corollary 4.16 shows that is also injective, as for we have
(8.12) |
So is a bijection, and we now wish to show that it is a projection algebra morphism, meaning that
where here we write and for the projection algebra operations in . For the first (the second is dual), we write and , and use Lemma 8.3 to calculate
By definition, is generated by the projections ().
Remark 8.13.
By identifying each projection with the -class , we can identify itself with the projection algebra . It will be convenient to do so in the next section.
8.2 Free projection-generated DRC-semigroups
Recall that we have a functor , which at the object level maps a DRC-semigroup to its projection algebra
with operations given by
We can think of as a forgetful functor, as when we construct from , we remember only a subset of the elements of , and retain only partial information about their products.
It turns out that has a left adjoint, , which involves the semigroups constructed in Section 8.1. At the object level, we define
To see how acts on a projection algebra morphism , we begin by defining a semigroup morphism
It is easy to see that . For example, if then
as contains the relation | ||||
as is a projection algebra morphism | ||||
which shows that preserves (R2). It follows that induces a well-defined semigroup homomorphism
(8.14) |
We then define . It is essentially trivial to check that preserves the and operations on and , in light of the definitions of these operations in (8.6), meaning that is indeed a well-defined DRC-morphism .
Proposition 8.15.
is a functor , and we have .
Proof.
Proposition 8.16.
For every projection algebra , every DRC-semigroup , and every projection algebra morphism , there exists a unique DRC-morphism such that , i.e. such that the following diagram of maps commutes (with vertical arrows being inclusions):
Proof.
Fix a projection algebra morphism . For convenience we write
We write and for the unary operations on , and and for the projection algebra operations in , and use dashes to distinguish the corresponding operations in and .
We begin by defining
To see that , note for example that if then
by (DRC1) | ||||
by Lemma 3.4 | ||||
by definition | ||||
as is a projection algebra morphism | ||||
showing that preserves (R2). As usual, it follows that induces a well-defined semigroup morphism
To see that preserves ( is dual), consider a typical element of (cf. Lemma 8.4), where . We then have
so we must show that . But this follows from Lemma 4.17(ii), together with the fact that implies (as is a projection algebra morphism).
So is indeed a DRC-morphism . Since maps to , it is clear that . This establishes the existence of . Uniqueness follows from the fact that . ∎
Propositions 8.15 and 8.16 verify the assumptions of [15, Lemma 5.6], which immediately gives the following result. For the definitions of the (standard) categorical terms in the statement see for example [2, 38], and also [15, Section 5].
Theorem 8.17.
The functor is a left adjoint to the forgetful functor , and is coreflective in . ∎
Remark 8.18.
One might wonder if the assignment is also the object part of a functor , but this turns out not to be the case, for exactly the same reason discussed in [13, Remark 4.29].
Remark 8.19.
The study of free idempotent-generated semigroups over biordered sets is a topic of considerable interest in its own right [23, 24, 11, 9, 6, 60, 10, 3], and the corresponding theory for regular -semigroups has been recently initiated in [15]. We hope that the free projection-generated DRC-semigroups introduced here will likewise inspire further studies.
8.3 Fundamental projection-generated DRC-semigroups
Following [30], a (DRC-)congruence on a DRC-semigroup is an equivalence relation on respecting all of the operations, in the sense that
The congruence is projection-separating if for all projections . Among other things, [30, Proposition 2.3] shows that has a maximum projection-separating congruence, denoted ; that is, is projection-separating, and any other projection-separating congruence is contained in . We say is (DRC-)fundamental if is the trivial congruence . In general, is fundamental, the maximum fundamental image of .
Remark 8.20.
Here we follow Jones’ convention in dropping the ‘DRC-’ prefix, and speak simply of ‘fundamental DRC-semigroups’. But the reader should be aware that a ‘fundamental’ (ordinary) semigroup is usually defined as a semigroup with no non-trivial congruence contained in Green’s -relation. For regular semigroups, this is equivalent to having no non-trivial idempotent-separating congruence [32].
Proposition 8.21.
If is a DRC-semigroup, then
Proof.
Writing , Proposition 2.3 of [30] says that for we have if and only if
where is with an adjoined identity element. Keeping (5.5) in mind, this is equivalent to all of the following holding:
Remembering also that and , we can therefore prove the first equality in the current proposition by showing that
(8.22) |
To do so, suppose and . Writing , we have
The proof that is dual.
For the second equality in the proposition, we will show that
(8.23) |
In light of the identities and (the second of which is Lemma 5.3(iv)), and the analogous identities for and , we can prove (8.23) by showing that
The first implication is (8.22), which was proved above. The second follows from the fact that and . ∎
Fundamental DRC-semigroups were classified in [30] by means of a transformation representation. We will not attempt to reprove this here, but instead we prove a result concerning projection-generated fundamental DRC-semigroups (see Theorem 8.25 below), which was not given in [30]. For its proof, we will make use of the following result, which shows that the maps and have very natural forms when is a product of projections.
Lemma 8.24.
If is a DRC-semigroup, and if , then
Proof.
We are now ready to prove our final result of this section:
Theorem 8.25.
For any projection algebra there is a unique (up to isomorphism) projection-generated fundamental DRC-semigroup with projection algebra , namely .
Proof.
By Theorem 8.11, we can identify the projection algebras and with itself, and in this way the semigroups and are both generated by . To avoid confusion, we will denote the products in these semigroups by and , respectively, so that typical elements have the form
for some . In what follows, we use Proposition 8.21 freely.
We have already noted that is a projection-generated DRC-semigroup with projection algebra . To see that it is fundamental, we need to show that is trivial. To do so, suppose ; we must show that . As above, we have
for some . Since , we have and . It then follows from Lemma 8.24 that
But then .
Now let be an arbitrary projection-generated fundamental DRC-semigroup with projection algebra ; we denote the product in simply by juxtaposition. The proof will be complete if we can show that . Applying Proposition 8.16 to the identity morphism , we see that there is a DRC-morphism
Since is projection-generated, is surjective, and so by the fundamental homomorphism theorem. It therefore remains to show that . Since maps identically, is projection-separating, and so . Conversely, let , so that and . Since is projection-generated, we have
But then applying Lemma 8.24 in both and , we have
It follows that , and simlarly , so that . Since is fundamental, it follows that , i.e. that . ∎
9 Regular - and -regular semigroups
As mentioned in Section 1, the current paper extends to DRC-semigroups the groupoid-based approach to regular -semigroups from [13]. In the case of regular -semigroups (whose definition will be recalled below), many of the current categorical constructions simplify, sometimes drammatically. In this section we outline many of these simplifications, and indicate why the more elaborate approach of the current paper is necessary to encompass the full generality of DRC-semigroups. In doing so, we will contrast the situation with Drazin’s broader class of -regular semigroups [12], which induce natural DRC-structures. These are already complex enough to require the more complicated setup, and a ready source of (counter)examples will be provided by the real matrix monoids , which are known to be -regular [46]. (Due to quirks of terminology, -regular and regular -semigroups are distinct classes, though the former contains the latter.) We will also observe in Section 10 that many of the simplifications hold in the DRC-restriction semigroups considered by Die and Wang in [8].
Before we begin, we recall some basic semigroup theoretical background; for more information see for example [27, 4]. Let be a semigroup, and its monoid completion. So if is a monoid, or else , where is a symbol not belonging to , acting as an adjoined identity. Green’s , and equivalences are defined, for , by
From these are defined the further equivalences and , where the latter is the join in the lattice of all equivalences on . We have , and if is finite then .
An element of a semigroup is regular if for some . This is equivalent to having and for some (if , then take ), and such an element is called a (semigroup) inverse of . Note then that and , with and idempotents. In fact, an element of a semigroup is regular if and only if it is -related to an idempotent.
9.1 Matrix monoids
Fix an integer , and let be the monoid of real matrices, under ordinary matrix multiplication. (We consider real matrices merely for convenience, though what we say can be adapted to the complex field.) Denoting the row and column spaces of by and , and writing for the rank of , Green’s relations on are given by
(9.1) |
(See for example [44, Lemma 2.1].) Since idempotents of arbitrary rank clearly exist, is regular.
In fact, any matrix can be assigned a special inverse [46]. Using to denote transpose, there exists a unique matrix satisfying
(9.2) |
This is known as the Moore–Penrose inverse, and is denoted . There is no simple formula for ; its existence is established in [46] by using the linear dependence of the sequence , . Nevertheless, many computational packages exist for working with the Moore–Penrose inverse, e.g. Matlab [54]. For example, with , Matlab tells us that . One can readily check the identities (9.2), and we note that and are symmetric idempotents, with ; cf. (9.1).
9.2 Regular - and -regular semigroups as DRC-semigroups
The defining properties of the Moore–Penrose inverse in led to the introduction in [12] of the class of -regular semigroups, to which we now turn.
First, a -semigroup is an algebra , where is a semigroup, and where ∗ is an involution, i.e. a unary operation satisfying the laws
For example, becomes a -semigroup with involution given by transpose: . The category of -semigroups with -morphisms (i.e. the semigroup morphisms preserving ∗) contains two important (full) subcategories, whose definitions we will shortly recall:
Beginning with the latter, a regular -semigroup is a -semigroup additionally satisfying
It follows from the axioms that also in a regular -semigroup, meaning that is a (semigroup) inverse of .
A -regular semigroup is a -semigroup for which every element has an inverse that is -related to . It follows from basic semigroup-theoretic facts that this inverse is unique; it is denoted by , and called the Moore–Penrose inverse of [46]. The terminology stems from the fact (see [42, Corollary 1.2]) that can also be characterised as the unique element satisfying
In this way, a -regular semigroup can be equivalently defined as an algebra , where is a semigroup, and ∗ and † are unary operations satisfying:
(9.3) |
Various other laws can be deduced as consequences (see for example [42, Theorem 1.3]), including:
(9.4) |
Regular -semigroups are the -regular semigroups in which for all . The matrix monoid is -regular (cf. (9.2)), but it is not a regular -semigroup, as need not be an inverse of , even when .
It is well known (and easy to see) that any -morphism between -regular semigroups preserves Moore–Penrose inverses, meaning that for all . Less obvious is the following:
Theorem 9.5 (Jones [30, Proposition 4.2]).
Any -regular semigroup gives rise to a DRC-semigroup , under the unary operations
Remark 9.5.
We can think of the assignment as an object map from to , and this can be easily extended to a functor . Given a -morphism in , we simply define . Since preserves †, it also preserves and .
The functor is not full (surjective on morphisms), however. Indeed, consider an abelian group with identity , in which at least one element is not its own inverse (e.g. the cyclic group of order ). Then and are both -regular semigroups, where for all . Moreover, we have , since in both semigroups for all . It follows that the identity map is a DRC-morphism , but it is not a -morphism, as for any non-self-inverse .
On the other hand, the restriction of to the subcategory of regular -semigroups is full, as follows from the next result (recall that † coincides with ∗ in a regular -semigroup).
Proposition 9.6.
If is a DRC-morphism, for -regular semigroups and , then for all .
Proof.
Since is a DRC-morphism, we have
Combining these gives
It follows that is (isomorphic to) a full subcategory of , and is hence isomorphic to its image under the isomorphism from Theorem 5.20. One could then go on to show that this image is isomorphic to the category of chained projection groupoids, as defined in [13], thereby proving the main result of that paper. We will not give the full details here, as a similar deduction was considered in [13] itself, where the isomorphism was used to reprove the Ehresmann–Nambooripad–Schein Theorem on inverse semigroups and inductive groupoids.
The situation for the more general -regular semigroups, however, is more complicated. Since the functor is not an isomorphism onto a full subcategory, we are left with what seems to be a very interesting and important open problem:
Problem 9.7.
Obtain an ‘ESN-type’ theorem for the category of -regular semigroups.
9.3 Projection algebras of regular - and -regular semigroups
For the rest of this section we fix a -regular semigroup , and denote the corresponding DRC-semigroup from Theorem 9.5 by . Using (9.3) and (9.4) we see that
(9.8) |
meaning that is an involutory DRC-semigroup in the terminology of Jones [30, Section 4]. Among other things, this leads to a simplification in the structure of the projection algebra . First, we note that
Indeed, the first equality was shown in [30, Proposition 4.2]. For the second, suppose first that . It follows that is an inverse of that is -related (indeed, equal) to , so that . Conversely, if , then . Using (9.8), it then follows that for any we have
In other words, we have for all , meaning that the two families of operations of reduces to one, and is symmetric in the terminology of Jones [30, Section 11].
In fact, not only do the and operations coincide in a -regular semigroup, but they can be defined equationally in terms of the † operation. To describe this, and for later use, we need the following basic result:
Lemma 9.9.
If is a -regular semigroup, then for any and we have
Proof.
Since , it follows that is a right identity for , which gives the first identity. The second is dual. ∎
Proposition 9.10.
If is a -regular semigroup, then for any we have
Proof.
Using Lemma 9.9 we see that . A symmetrical calculation gives , and we have already seen that . ∎
Remark 9.11.
In the case that is a regular -semigroup, we obtain the simpler expression
(9.12) |
This does not hold in -regular semigroups in general, however. For example, with the projections and , both from , the matrix is not an idempotent, and hence not a projection.
The projection algebras of regular -semigroups were axiomatised by Imaoka [28], as the algebras , where is a set of unary operations satisfying
-
(P1)′
,
-
(P2)′
,
-
(P3)′
,
-
(P4)′
,
-
(P5)′
.
It is easy to see that these axioms hold in a regular -semigroup (using (9.12)), and that they imply axioms (P1)–(P5), keeping in mind. Note that (P1)′ and (P2)′ are exactly (P1) and (P6), respectively, while (P3)′ is the version of (P9). In particular, axioms (P1)′–(P3)′ hold in the projection algebra of a -regular semigroup. Axioms (P4)′ and (P5)′ do not, however. For example, in we have
for
(This example was found, and can be checked, with Matlab [54], as with all the examples to come.)
As far as we are aware, there is no known axiomatisation for the projection algebras of -regular semigroups. Obtaining such an axiomatisation is a necessary first step in tackling Problem 9.7. We also believe it is of interest in its own right, as among other things it could also be useful in developing a theory of fundamental -regular semigroups; cf. [28, 30, 29, 59].
Problem 9.13.
Give an (abstract) axiomatisation for the class of projection algebras of -regular semigroups.
9.4 Chained projection categories of regular - and -regular semigroups
We continue to fix the -regular semigroup , and its associated DRC-semigroup from Theorem 9.5. Also let be the chained projection category associated to . In particular, is the projection algebra of . Note that for any we have
Proposition 9.14.
If is a -regular semigroup, then is a groupoid, in which for all .
Proof.
Fix , and first note that (9.4) gives
It follows that the compositions and exist in . Specifically, we have
so that is indeed the inverse of in . ∎
Using (9.3) and (9.4), it is also worth noting that for we have
In what follows, we will typically use the laws and without explicit reference.
A further simplification occurs in the special case that is a regular -semigroup (where we recall that ∗ and † coincide).
Proposition 9.15.
If is a regular -semigroup, then the orders and on coincide.
Proof.
By symmetry it suffices to show that for , so suppose . This means that , where . It follows from the latter that . Write , and note that the biordered category axioms give . It then follows that
so that . ∎
Remark 9.16.
The orders and are generally distinct for -regular semigroups. For example, consider the following matrices from :
Then , and are projections with , and we have , and . We also have , so that . But , since .
Another special property enjoyed by the category has to do with the and maps from (2.5) and (5.2). We summarise this in Proposition 9.18 below, but we first note that for we have
(9.17) |
Indeed, if , then using (5.5) and Lemma 9.9 we have
The other formulae are checked analogously. If is a regular -semigroup, then these reduce further; for example, for and . Such simplifications do not hold in general for -regular semigroups; for example, for the projections from Remark 9.11, we have .
Proposition 9.18.
If is a -regular semigroup, then for any :
-
(i)
and are bijections, and and ,
-
(ii)
and ,
-
(iii)
and .
Proof.
For each item, it suffices by symmetry to prove the first assertion.
(i). It suffices by symmetry to show that , i.e. that for all . To do so, fix some such , and write . We then have
from which it follows that .
Remark 9.19.
Remark 9.20.
Another point of difference concerning the and maps is that these are always projection algebra morphisms when is a regular -semigroup, as shown in the proof [13, Proposition 6.11]. This property was called (G1d) in [13], and was shown to be equivalent to certain other natural conditions in the context of the projection groupoids of [13], including our (C1). However, the maps and need not be projection algebra morphims when is -regular.444This is also the case in general for Ehresmann semigroups; see for example [20, Section 4.2]. For example, we have for , and , all from . It is worth noting that one of the other equivalent conditions in (G1) is:
(9.21) |
This also need not hold for -regular semigroups. For example, for , and from we have and .
The final issue we wish to address concerns axiom (C2), and is somewhat more technical. Recall that this is quantified over all morphisms and all projections , and asserts the equality of the morphisms
(9.22) |
in . These morphisms were defined in terms of the projections , , and given by
(9.23) |
All of the above projections and morphisms are shown in Figure 2. The idea behind axiom (C2) is that if we have three morphisms , with
then
(See the proof of Lemma 6.3.)
In the case of regular -semigroups, the corresponding axiom (G2) from [13] was quantified over all morphisms , and all -linked pairs . Such a pair satisfies
(9.24) |
(In the notation of [13] the latter equation was , which is equivalent to the above since and .) The idea here is that if are arbitrary, then and from (9.23) are -linked, and we have
(9.25) |
which in turn leads to and . For example, using (9.21), (9.23), (9.24) and , we have
In the general case of a -regular semigroup, the equalities involving and in (9.25) need not hold. For example, consider the following matrices from :
(9.26) |
Then and are projections, and we have
(9.27) |
Moreover, we have for . However, although and , we have
(9.28) |
Not only can axiom (C2) be quantified over a smaller set of projections when is a regular -semigroup, but the projections and in (9.23) take on much simpler forms. Specifically, when is -linked (and is a regular -semigroup), we have
(9.29) |
where again and . For example, using , (P4)′, Lemma 5.3(ii) and (9.24), we have
The simplifications in (9.29) do not hold in general DRC-semigroups. Indeed, small counterexamples can be readily constructed using Mace4 [40], although we do not currently know of any -regular counterexamples.
10 Other special cases
In this final section we consider another two important subclasses of DRC-semigroups, specifically the Ehresmann and DRC-restriction semigroups considered by Lawson [33] and Die and Wang [8]. Again, although we could in principle deduce the main results of [33, 8] from ours, we will not give all of the details. Rather, we just outline the ways in which our constructions simplify in these cases.
10.1 Ehresmann semigroups
We noted in Section 3.1 that the Ehresmann semigroups of Lawson [33] are precisely the DRC-semigroups satisfying the additional law
Given (DRC4), either of the above identities implies the other, and of course they say that projections of commute. This is a very strong property, and to unpack it we first prove the following:
Proposition 10.1.
If for a DRC-semigroup , then the following are equivalent:
-
(i)
,
-
(ii)
and ,
-
(iii)
,
-
(iv)
.
Proof.
Corollary 10.2.
If for a DRC-semigroup , and if , then
-
(i)
the meet exists in the poset , and ,
-
(ii)
.
Proof.
Corollary 10.2 has some important simplifying consequences for an Ehresmann semigroup , since all projections commute. First, is a meet semilattice, and hence a subsemigroup of . Second, is the equality relation. Thus, the chain category is simply a copy of , in which the only compositions are (), and in which is the order from (4.9). It follows that the chained projection category of the Ehresmann semigroup carries no more information than the projection category itself. Moreover, since is trivial, axiom (C2) simplifies as well. Indeed, we first note that since and by Lemma 5.16, it follows that and . Thus, (C2) asserts the equality of the double restrictions:
(10.3) |
This can be used to prove the following, which is one of the Ehresmann category axioms from [33].
Proposition 10.4.
In an Ehresmann semigroup , we have .
Proof.
By symmetry, it suffices to prove the inclusion . To do so, suppose are such that for some . This means that
(So here .) We can complete the proof by showing that
(10.5) |
To do so, we now write and , and we work towards interpreting (10.3) in the current context. First note that
which imply that and . We also have
because ; cf. (4.9). Thus, (10.3) gives
where . Since , it follows that , completing the proof of (10.5), and hence of the proposition. ∎
Lawson in [33] denotes by the composition , and we note that the above proof shows that if , then we have
This is [33, Lemma 4.6].
Finally, we note that has the consequence that the product on the category from Definition 6.1 takes on the simpler form
10.2 DRC-restriction semigroups
We conclude the paper by briefly commenting on the DRC-restriction semigroups considered by Die and Wang in [8]. These are the DRC-semigroups satisfying the additional laws
It was observed in [8, Section 1] that these laws need only be quantified over and , given (DRC2). The DRC-restriction laws might seem unwieldy, but it turns out that they are equivalent to the orders and coinciding, as shown in [8, Lemma 5.8].
The full subcategory of consisting of all DRC-restriction semigroups (and DRC-morphisms) is isomorphic to its image under the isomorphism from Theorem 6.7 (cf. Theorem 7.1). One could then use this to deduce the results from [8]. Again we omit the details, but we do note that the constructions and results of [8] involve some (but not all) of the simplifications that we discussed in Section 9 for regular -semigroups. As we have already mentioned, the and orders coincide, so one works with ordered rather than biordered categories. However, the and operations need not be equal, i.e. need not be symmetric. Similarly, the and maps need not be related to each other; for example, () need not be equal to any map (for ). On the other hand, is always a projection algebra morphism , with a similar statement for ; see [8, Lemmas 4.7 and 7.7]. This leads to the various equivalent conditions in the analogue of (C1) in [8], including (9.21); cf. Remark 9.20. Likewise, the simplifications in (C2) discussed at the end of Section 9.4 all hold in DRC-restriction semigroups; specifically, the axiom can be quantified over -linked pairs (cf. (9.24)), and the projections take on the simpler forms in (9.29).
References
- [1] S. Armstrong. Structure of concordant semigroups. J. Algebra, 118(1):205–260, 1988.
- [2] S. Awodey. Category theory, volume 52 of Oxford Logic Guides. Oxford University Press, Oxford, second edition, 2010.
- [3] M. Brittenham, S. W. Margolis, and J. Meakin. Subgroups of the free idempotent generated semigroups need not be free. J. Algebra, 321(10):3026–3042, 2009.
- [4] A. H. Clifford and G. B. Preston. The algebraic theory of semigroups. Vol. I. Mathematical Surveys, No. 7. American Mathematical Society, Providence, R.I., 1961.
- [5] S. Crvenković and I. Dolinka. Congruences on -regular semigroups. Period. Math. Hungar., 45(1-2):1–13, 2002.
- [6] Y. Dandan, I. Dolinka, and V. Gould. A group-theoretical interpretation of the word problem for free idempotent generated semigroups. Adv. Math., 345:998–1041, 2019.
- [7] D. DeWolf and D. Pronk. The Ehresmann-Schein-Nambooripad theorem for inverse categories. Theory Appl. Categ., 33:Paper No. 27, 813–831, 2018.
- [8] Y. Die and S. Wang. Chain projection ordered categories and DRC-restriction semigroups. Preprint, 2024, arXiv:2407.11434.
- [9] I. Dolinka. Free idempotent generated semigroups: the word problem and structure via gain graphs. Israel J. Math., 245(1):347–387, 2021.
- [10] I. Dolinka and R. D. Gray. Maximal subgroups of free idempotent generated semigroups over the full linear monoid. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 366(1):419–455, 2014.
- [11] I. Dolinka, R. D. Gray, and N. Ruškuc. On regularity and the word problem for free idempotent generated semigroups. Proc. Lond. Math. Soc. (3), 114(3):401–432, 2017.
- [12] M. P. Drazin. Regular semigroups with involution. In Symposium on Regular Semigroups, pages 29–46. Northern Illinois University, DeKalb, 1979.
- [13] J. East and P. A. Azeef Muhammed. A groupoid approach to regular -semigroups. Adv. Math., 437:Paper No. 109447, 104 pp., 2024.
- [14] J. East and R. D. Gray. Ehresmann theory and partition monoids. J. Algebra, 579:318–352, 2021.
- [15] J. East, R. D. Gray, P. A. Azeef Muhammed, and N. Ruškuc. Projection algebras and free projection- and idempotent-generated regular -semigroups. Preprint, 2024, arXiv:2406.09109.
- [16] D. G. FitzGerald. Factorizable inverse monoids. Semigroup Forum, 80(3):484–509, 2010.
- [17] D. G. FitzGerald. Groupoids on a skew lattice of objects. Art Discrete Appl. Math., 2(2):Paper No. 2.03, 14, 2019.
- [18] D. G. FitzGerald and M. K. Kinyon. Trace- and pseudo-products: restriction-like semigroups with a band of projections. Semigroup Forum, 103(3):848–866, 2021.
-
[19]
V. Gould.
Notes on restriction semigroups and related structures.
https://www-users.york.ac.uk/~varg1/restriction.pdf, 2010. - [20] V. Gould. Restriction and Ehresmann semigroups. In Proceedings of the International Conference on Algebra 2010, pages 265–288. World Sci. Publ., Hackensack, NJ, 2012.
- [21] V. Gould and C. Hollings. Restriction semigroups and inductive constellations. Comm. Algebra, 38(1):261–287, 2010.
- [22] V. Gould and Y. Wang. Beyond orthodox semigroups. J. Algebra, 368:209–230, 2012.
- [23] R. Gray and N. Ruškuc. On maximal subgroups of free idempotent generated semigroups. Israel J. Math., 189:147–176, 2012.
- [24] R. Gray and N. Ruškuc. Maximal subgroups of free idempotent-generated semigroups over the full transformation monoid. Proc. Lond. Math. Soc. (3), 104(5):997–1018, 2012.
- [25] C. Hollings. Extending the Ehresmann-Schein-Nambooripad theorem. Semigroup Forum, 80(3):453–476, 2010.
- [26] C. Hollings. The Ehresmann-Schein-Nambooripad theorem and its successors. Eur. J. Pure Appl. Math., 5(4):414–450, 2012.
- [27] J. M. Howie. Fundamentals of semigroup theory, volume 12 of London Mathematical Society Monographs. New Series. The Clarendon Press, Oxford University Press, New York, 1995. Oxford Science Publications.
- [28] T. Imaoka. Some remarks on fundamental regular -semigroups. In Recent developments in the algebraic, analytical, and topological theory of semigroups (Oberwolfach, 1981), volume 998 of Lecture Notes in Math., pages 270–280. Springer, Berlin, 1983.
- [29] P. R. Jones. A common framework for restriction semigroups and regular -semigroups. J. Pure Appl. Algebra, 216(3):618–632, 2012.
- [30] P. R. Jones. Generalized Munn representations of DRC-semigroups. Southeast Asian Bull. Math., 45(5):591–619, 2021.
- [31] M. Khoshkam and G. Skandalis. Regular representation of groupoid -algebras and applications to inverse semigroups. J. Reine Angew. Math., 546:47–72, 2002.
- [32] G. Lallement. Demi-groupes réguliers. Ann. Mat. Pura Appl. (4), 77:47–129, 1967.
- [33] M. V. Lawson. Semigroups and ordered categories. I. The reduced case. J. Algebra, 141(2):422–462, 1991.
- [34] M. V. Lawson. Inverse semigroups. World Scientific Publishing Co., Inc., River Edge, NJ, 1998. The theory of partial symmetries.
- [35] M. V. Lawson. Ordered groupoids and left cancellative categories. Semigroup Forum, 68(3):458–476, 2004.
- [36] M. V. Lawson. Recent developments in inverse semigroup theory. Semigroup Forum, 100(1):103–118, 2020.
- [37] M. V. Lawson. On Ehresmann semigroups. Semigroup Forum, 103(3):953–965, 2021.
- [38] S. Mac Lane. Categories for the working mathematician, volume 5 of Graduate Texts in Mathematics. Springer-Verlag, New York, second edition, 1998.
- [39] S. Margolis and I. Stein. Ehresmann semigroups whose categories are EI and their representation theory. J. Algebra, 585:176–206, 2021.
- [40] W. McCune. Prover9 and Mace4. http://www.cs.unm.edu/~mccune/prover9/.
- [41] K. S. S. Nambooripad. Structure of regular semigroups. I. Mem. Amer. Math. Soc., 22(224):vii+119, 1979.
- [42] K. S. S. Nambooripad and F. J. C. M. Pastijn. Regular involution semigroups. In Semigroups (Szeged, 1981), volume 39 of Colloq. Math. Soc. János Bolyai, pages 199–249. North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1985.
- [43] T. E. Nordahl and H. E. Scheiblich. Regular -semigroups. Semigroup Forum, 16(3):369–377, 1978.
- [44] J. Okniński. Semigroups of matrices, volume 6 of Series in Algebra. World Scientific Publishing Co., Inc., River Edge, NJ, 1998.
- [45] A. L. T. Paterson. Groupoids, inverse semigroups, and their operator algebras, volume 170 of Progress in Mathematics. Birkhäuser Boston, Inc., Boston, MA, 1999.
- [46] R. Penrose. A generalized inverse for matrices. Proc. Cambridge Philos. Soc., 51:406–413, 1955.
- [47] B. Steinberg. Möbius functions and semigroup representation theory. J. Combin. Theory Ser. A, 113(5):866–881, 2006.
- [48] B. Steinberg. Möbius functions and semigroup representation theory. II. Character formulas and multiplicities. Adv. Math., 217(4):1521–1557, 2008.
- [49] B. Steinberg. A groupoid approach to discrete inverse semigroup algebras. Adv. Math., 223(2):689–727, 2010.
- [50] T. Stokes. Domain and range operations in semigroups and rings. Comm. Algebra, 43(9):3979–4007, 2015.
- [51] T. Stokes. D-semigroups and constellations. Semigroup Forum, 94(2):442–462, 2017.
- [52] T. Stokes. Left restriction monoids from left -completions. J. Algebra, 608:143–185, 2022.
- [53] T. Stokes. Ordered Ehresmann semigroups and categories. Comm. Algebra, 50(11):4805–4821, 2022.
- [54] The MathWorks Inc., Natick, Massachusetts, United States. MATLAB. https://www.mathworks.com.
- [55] S. Wang. An Ehresmann-Schein-Nambooripad-type theorem for a class of -restriction semigroups. Bull. Malays. Math. Sci. Soc., 42(2):535–568, 2019.
- [56] S. Wang. An Ehresmann-Schein-Nambooripad theorem for locally Ehresmann -Ehresmann semigroups. Period. Math. Hungar., 80(1):108–137, 2020.
- [57] S. Wang. An Ehresmann-Schein-Nambooripad type theorem for DRC-semigroups. Semigroup Forum, 104(3):731–757, 2022.
- [58] Y. Wang. Beyond regular semigroups. Semigroup Forum, 92(2):414–448, 2016.
- [59] M. Yamada. On the structure of fundamental regular -semigroups. Studia Sci. Math. Hungar., 16(3-4):281–288, 1981.
- [60] D. Yang, I. Dolinka, and V. Gould. Free idempotent generated semigroups and endomorphism monoids of free -acts. J. Algebra, 429:133–176, 2015.