Biserial algebras and generic bricks
Abstract.
We consider generic bricks and use them in the study of arbitrary biserial algebras over algebraically closed fields. For a biserial algebra , we show that is brick-infinite if and only if it admits a generic brick, that is, there exists a generic -module with . Furthermore, we give an explicit numerical condition for brick-infiniteness of biserial algebras: If is of rank , then is brick-infinite if and only if there exists an infinite family of bricks of length , for some . This also results in an algebro-geometric realization of -tilting finiteness of this family: is -tilting finite if and only if is brick-discrete, meaning that in every representation variety , there are only finitely many orbits of bricks.
Our results rely on our full classification of minimal brick-infinite biserial algebras in terms of quivers and relations. This is the modern analogue of the recent classification of minimal representation-infinite (special) biserial algebras, given by Ringel. In particular, we show that every minimal brick-infinite biserial algebra is gentle and admits exactly one generic brick. Furthermore, we describe the spectrum of such algebras, which is very similar to that of a tame hereditary algebra. In other words, is the disjoint union of a unique generic brick with a countable infinite set of bricks of finite length, and a family of bricks of the same finite length parametrized by the ground field.
2020 Mathematics Subject Classification:
16G20,16G60,16D80,05E101. Introduction
Throughout, all algebras are assumed to be finite dimensional associative unital over algebraically closed field. By we denote any such algebra and, with no loss of generality, we can further assume every algebra is basic and connected. Hence, has a presentation of the form , for a unique finite and connected quiver and an admissible ideal in the path algebra . Consequently, -modules can be identified with representations of the bound quiver . Unless specified otherwise, we always work with left -modules and consider them up to isomorphism. In particular, denotes the category of all left -modules, whereas denotes the category of all finitely generated left -modules. Moreover, let and respectively denote the collections of (isomorphism classes) of indecomposable modules in and . The standard notations and terminology which are not explicitly defined here can be found in [ASS], or else they will be introduced throughout the text.
1.1. Motivations and background
Recall that in is a brick if is a division algebra. Then, is called brick-finite if it admits only finitely many bricks (up to isomorphism). Each brick is evidently indecomposable and by and we denote the subsets of all bricks, respectively in and . Although each representation-finite (rep-finite, for short) algebra is brick-finite, the converse is not true in general (e.g. any representation-infinite local algebra admits a unique brick). More precisely, the notion of brick-finiteness is of interest only if is a rep-infinite tame algebra, or else when is wild but not strictly wild (a standard argument yields that any strictly wild algebra is brick-infinite).
Bricks and their properties play pivotal roles in different areas and can be studied from various perspectives (see Section 2). As we do here, the notion of brick-finiteness can be viewed as a conceptual counterpart of representation-finiteness. To better highlight this perspective, let us present two analogous characterizations that also motivate our work. Thanks to some classical and recent results, is known to be rep-finite if and only if , whereas it is brick-finite if and only if (for details, see [Se]). Furthermore, through the lens of approximation theory, is shown to be rep-finite if and only if every full subcategory of is functorially finite, whereas it is brick-finite if and only if every torsion class in is functorially finite (for details, see [DIJ]).
Before we recall a powerful tool in the study of rep-infinite algebras, observe that each -module can be viewed as a (right) module over . Then, the endolength of is the length of when considered as an -module. In particular, a -module in is called generic if it is of finite endolength. Generic modules are known to play a significant role in representation theory of algebras. For instance, any generic -module of endolength gives rise to an infinite family of (non-isomorphic) modules of length in (see [CB1] and the references therein). In fact, Crawley-Boevey [CB1] has given an elegant realization of the Tame/Wild dichotomy theorem of Drozd [Dr] in terms of generic modules and their endolength (see Theorem 4.1). Based on his characterization, one can further refine tame algebras and say is -domestic if it admits exactly generic modules (up to isomorphism). In general, is domestic if is -domestic for some .
For an algebra , it is known that is rep-infinite if and only if it admits a generic module ([CB1]). Hence, it is natural to ask for an analogous characterization of brick-infinite algebras. First, observe that if is brick-finite, no generic -module is a brick (see Theorem 2.1). To describe our proposal for a new treatment of brick-infinite case, we introduce some new terminology. In particular, we say is a generic brick of if is a generic module and it belongs to . Furthermore, is called brick-continuous if for a positive integer , there exists an infinite family in consisting of bricks of length . The latter notion is motivated by the algebro-geometric properties of bricks (see Section 4). In particular, is said to be brick-discrete if it is not brick-continuous. We remark that brick-discrete algebras are studied in [CKW], where the authors call them “Schur representation-finite” algebras and view them as a generalization of rep-finite algebras. In [Mo2], it is conjectured that brick-discrete algebras are the same as brick-finite algebras.
1.2. Problem and results
In the rest of this section, we focus on our main problem and present our results. In particular, our conjecture below is primarily inspired by our earlier results in [Mo1, Mo2] on the behavior of bricks, as well as our work on minimal -tilting infinite algebras in [MP] (see also Conjecture 2.1).
Conjecture 1.1 (Conjecture 4.1)
For an algebra , the following are equivalent:
-
(1)
is brick-infinite;
-
(2)
is brick-continuous;
-
(3)
admits a generic brick.
To verify the above conjecture in full generality, one only needs to treat those algebras which are brick-infinite and minimal with respect to this property. In particular, we say is a minimal brick-infinite algebra (min-brick-infinite, for short) if is brick-infinite but all proper quotient algebras of are brick-finite. Thus, a concrete classification of such algebras will be helpful in the study of our conjecture. As discussed in Subsection 2.4, min-brick-infinite algebras are novel counterparts of minimal representation-infinite algebras (min-rep-infinite, for short). This classical family is extensively studied due to their role in several fundamental problems, particularly in the celebrated Brauer-Thrall Conjectures (see [Bo1] and references therein). Note that min-brick-infinite algebras also enjoy some important properties that could be helpful in the study of Conjecture 1.1 (see Theorem 2.4).
It is known that biserial algebras form an important family of tame algebras, among which string, gentle and special biserial algebras have appeared in many areas of research (for definitions and details, see Subsection 2.2). In particular, if is a special biserial algebra, one can combinatorially describe all indecomposable modules in , as well as their Auslander-Reiten translate and morphisms between them (for details, see [BR] and [WW]). However, for arbitrary biserial algebras, there is no full classification of indecomposable modules and their representation theory is more complicated than that of special biserial algebras.
In 2013, Ringel [Ri1] gave an explicit classification of those min-rep-infinite algebras which are special biserial. Thanks to the more recent results of Bongartz [Bo1], one can show that Ringel’s classification is in fact the full list of min-rep-infinite biserial algebras. In particular, any such biserial algebra is a string algebra which is either -domestic or else non-domestic (for more details, see [Ri1] and Subsection 2.4). Here, we obtain an analogue of Ringel’s classification and give a full list of min-brick-infinite biserial algebras in terms of their quivers and relations.
Due to some technical observations that are further explained in Section 4, in this paper, unless stated otherwise, we restrict to tame algebras and verify the above conjecture for all biserial algebras. Before stating our main classification result, let us fix some new terminology. In particular, for an arbitrary algebra , we say is -generic-brick-domestic if it admits exactly (isomorphism classes) of generic bricks. More generally, is generic-brick-domestic if it admits only finitely many generic bricks. For the definition and concrete description of generalized barbell algebras, we refer to Subsection 2.4 and Figure 2. In particular, the following theorem follows from our results in Section 3.
Theorem 1.1
Let be a minimal brick-infinite biserial algebra. Then, is either a hereditary algebra of type or is a generalized barbell algebra. In particular, is a -generic-brick-domestic gentle algebra.
If is an affine Dynkin quiver, the algebra is known to be min-brick-infinite and tame. A classical result of Ringel [Ri2] shows that every such path algebra admits a unique generic brick. Hence, from this point of view, the preceding theorem extends the aforementioned result of Ringel and treats some non-hereditary tame min-brick-infinite algebras (see Theorem 4.4).
We remark that the generalized barbell algebras are never domestic. However, by the above theorem, they are always -generic-brick-domestic. As an interesting consequence of our classification, the following corollary is shown in Section 4. It is known that any string algebra which is not domestic must be of non-polynomial growth. Therefore, such algebras can be seen as -domestic.
Corollary 1.2
For every pair of integers in , there exists a string algebra which is -domestic and -generic-brick domestic.
To prove the above corollary, in Section 4.2 we present several examples and as the result give an explicit algorithm to construct an -generic-brick-domestic algebra for each . Moreover, in Example 4.10, we give a gentle algebra which is not generic-brick-domestic. The above corollary further highlights the fundamental differences between generic modules and generic bricks, as well as the domestic and generic-brick-domestic algebras (for example, see Questions 4.2).
As an important consequence of our classification result, we obtain a useful characterization of brick-finiteness of biserial algebras. Note that the rank of the Grothendieck group of is the number of vertices in , denoted by .
Theorem 1.3
For a biserial algebra , the following are equivalent:
-
(1)
is brick-infinite;
-
(2)
For some , there is an infinite family in with ;
-
(3)
admits a generic brick whose endolength is at most ;
The above theorem asserts a stronger version of Conjecture 1.1 for the family of biserial algebras. Moreover, the numerical condition given in part is similar to that of Bongartz’s for the length of -parameter families of indecomposable modules over rep-inf algebras (for details, see [Bo2]). This opens some new directions in the study of distribution of bricks (for example, see Question 4.1).
As mentioned earlier, any systematic study of bricks and their properties provide new insights into several other domains of research. We end this section by the following corollary which highlight these connections and postpone further applications of our results to our future work. All the undefined terminology and notations used in the next assertion appear in Sections 2 or 3. Moreover, proof of the following corollary follows from Theorem 2.2 and Corollary 4.5.
Corollary 1.4
Let be a biserial algebra. The following are equivalent:
-
(1)
is -tilting infinite;
-
(2)
There is a band component in which contains a rational curve of non-isomorphic bricks such that ;
-
(3)
For some , there exist infinitely many non-isomorphic -modules which are -stable.
2. Preliminaries
In this section we mainly collect some essential tools used in our main arguments. For the well-known results on (special) biserial algebras, tilting and -tilting theory, as well as for the rudiments of representation varieties, we only provide references.
2.1. Notations and conventions
By a quiver we always mean a finite directed graph, formally given by a quadruple , with the vertex set and arrow set , and the functions respectively send each arrow to its start. For and in , by we denote the path of length two which starts at and ends at . Let be the set of formal inverses of arrows of . That is, and .
Following our assumptions in Section 1, every algebra is an admissible quotient of a path algebra for some quiver , up to Morita equivalence. In this case, the pair is called a bound quiver. All quotients of path algebras will be assumed to be admissible quotients. Moreover, modules over can be seen as representations over the bound quiver . Provided we begin from a bound quiver, this dictionary is still available and can be an arbitrary field. In this case, -modules are representations of the corresponding bound quiver. For in , let denote the number of non-isomorphic indecomposable modules that appear in the Krull-Schmidt decomposition of . In particular, for , we have , which is the same as the rank of , where denotes the Grothendieck group of . In particular, this rank is the number of (isomorphism classes of) simple modules in .
For , unless specified otherwise, we consider a minimal set of uniform relations that generate the admissible idea . That is, each generator of is a linear combination of the form , where and , and all are paths of length strictly larger than one in starting at the same vertex and ending at the same vertex . For the most part, we work with monomial and binomial relations, which are respectively when and . In particular, the monomial relations of length , known as quadratic monomial relations, play a crucial role in the study of (special) biserial algebras. A vertex in is a node if it is neither a sink nor a source, and for any arrow incoming to and each arrow outgoing from , we have .
In this paper, all subcategories are assumed to be full and closed under isomorphism classes, direct sum and summands. Moreover, for a given collection , we say a property holds for almost all elements in if it is true for all but at most finitely many elements of .
2.2. Biserial algebras
An algebra is said to be biserial if for each left and right indecomposable projective -module , we have , where and are uniserial modules and is either zero or a simple module. Biserial algebras were formally introduced by Fuller [Fu], as a generalization of uniserial algebras, and Crawley-Boevey [CB2] showed that they are always tame.
Special biserial algebras form a well-known subfamily of biserial algebras and thanks to their rich combinatorics, their representation theory is well-studied. We recall that an algebra is special biserial if it is Morita equivalent to an algebra such that the bound quiver satisfies the following conditions:
-
(B1)
At every vertex in , there are at most two incoming and at most two outgoing arrows.
-
(B2)
For each arrow in , there is at most one arrow such that and at most one arrow such that .
A special biserial algebra with as above is called a string algebra if in can be generated by monomial relations. Over string algebras, all indecomposable modules and morphisms between them are understood (see [BR] and [WW]).
An important subfamily of string algebras consists of gentle algebras. Recall that is gentle if it is a string algebra and can be generated by a set of quadratic monomial relations such that satisfies the following condition:
-
(G)
For each arrow , there is at most one arrow and at most one arrow such that and .
Observe that if is biserial (respectively a string algebra, or gentle algebra), then for every and each the quotient algebras and are again biserial (respectively string, or gentle). Moreover, an arbitrary quotient of a (special) biserial algebra is again (special) biserial. For , a string in is a word with letters in and , for all , such that
-
(S1)
and , for all ;
-
(S2)
Neither , nor , contain a subpath in .
A string in is serial if either or is a direct path in . Namely, or , for some arrows in . For a string , we say it starts at , ends at , and is of length . Moreover, a zero-length string, denoted by , is associated to every . Suppose is the set of all equivalence classes of strings in , where for each string in the equivalence class consists of and (i.e. set ). A string is called a band if and is a string for each , but itself is not a power of a string of strictly smaller length, where each band is considered up to all cyclic permutations of it. For a vertex of , we say in visits if it is supported by . Moreover, passes through provided that there exists a nontrivial factorization of at . That is, there exist with , such that and . For , we say is supported by if the string contains or as a letter.
Let denote the underlying graph of . Then, every string induces a walk in , where a vertex or an edge may occur multiple times. The representation of associated to has an explicit construction as follows: Put a copy of at each vertex of the walk induced by . This step gives the vector spaces , where and is the number of times visits . To specify the linear maps of the representation between the two copies of associated to and , put the identity in the direction of . Namely, this identity map is from the basis vector of to that of if , and it goes from the basis vector of to that of , if . If , the string module associated to is an indecomposable -module given in terms of the representation . Note that for every string , there is an isomorphism of modules (representations) .
To every band , in addition to the string module , there exists another type of indecomposable -modules associated to which are called band modules. For the description of band modules, as well as the morphisms between the string and band modules over string algebras, we refer to [BR], [Kr] and [WW].
2.3. -tilting (in)finiteness
Let be a finitely generated -module. We say that is basic if no indecomposable module appears more than once in the Krull-Schmidt decomposition of . We denote by the number of non-isomorphic indecomposable direct summands of . Also, is rigid if . Let denote the set of isomorphism classes of all basic rigid modules in . Moreover, by we denote the set of indecomposable modules in . Similarly, is said to be -rigid if , where denotes the Auslander-Reiten translation in . Provided there is no confusion, we simply use to denote the Auslander-Reiten translation. By and we respectively denote the set of isomorphism classes of basic -rigid modules and the indecomposable -rigid modules. A rigid module is called tilting if and , where denotes the projective dimension of . Analogously, a -rigid module is -tilting if . More generally, is called support -tilting if is -tilting over , where is an idempotent in . By and we respectively denote the set of all isomorphism classes of basic tilting and -tilting modules in . Moreover, denotes the set of isomorphism classes of all basic support -tilting modules in .
-tilting theory, introduced by Adachi, Iyama and Reiten [AIR], has been a modern setup in representation theory of associative algebras where many rich ideas from cluster algebras and classical tilting theory meet. Through this new setting, the authors address the deficiency of classical tilting theory with respect to the mutation of tilting modules. In [AIR], the notion of mutation of clusters is conceptualized in terms of mutation of (support) -tilting modules.
Given an algebra , it is a priori a hard problem to decide whether or not the set of (support) -tilting modules is finite. Since these modules form the main ingredient of -tilting theory, finding explicit necessary and sufficient conditions such that an algebra has is monumental. This has spurred a lot of research in this direction, among which the elegant “brick--rigid correspondence” appearing in [DIJ] has proved to be very useful. Some important characterizations of -tilting finite algebras are recalled in the rest of this subsection.
Recall that a -module is called a brick if is a division algebra. That is, any nonzero endomorphism of is invertible. As in Section 1, by and we respectively denote the set of isomorphism classes of bricks in and . If the field is algebraically closed, then belongs to if and only if . Such modules are sometimes called Schur representations, particularly when they are studied from the algebro-geometric viewpoint, such as in [CKW]. An algebra is called brick-finite provided . Meanwhile, we warn the reader that those algebras called “Schur representation-finite” in [CKW] are not known to be necessarily brick-finite (for further details on this difference, see Subsection 2.5, as well as [Mo2, Subsection 1.3]).
One of our main goals in this paper is to establish a relationship between certain modules in and those in . In this regard, the following result of Sentieri [Se] is of interest.
Theorem 2.1 ([Se])
An algebra is brick-finite if and only if every brick in is finite dimensional.
We now list some of the fundamental results on -tilting finiteness of algebras. Recall that a subcategory of is a torsion class if it is closed under quotients and extensions. Let denote the set of all torsion classes in . For in , let denote the subcategory of consisting of all those modules that are quotients of some finite direct sum of copies of . It is known that in is functorially finite provided , for some in . By we denote the subset of consisting of functorially finite torsion classes. The following important result relates the finiteness of the notions introduced so far. In particular, it states that an algebra is brick-finite if and only if it is -tilting finite.
2.4. Minimal brick-infinite algebras
Here we collect some of our main results from [Mo1, Mo2], as well as [MP], which are used in this paper. We begin with a useful observation that is freely used in our reductive arguments. In particular, we recall that each epimorphism of algebras induces an exact functorial full embedding . Particularly, we get and also . This implies that if is rep-infinite (respectively, brick-infinite) then so is . Thus, by Theorem 2.2, -tilting finiteness is preserved under taking quotients.
Recall that an algebra is minimal representation-infinite (or min-rep-infinite, for short) if is rep-infinite and any proper quotient of is representation-finite. Following our notations in [Mo2], by we respectively denote the family of min-rep-infinite special biserial algebras and denotes the family of non-distributive min-rep-infinite algebras. Before we summarize the relevant results on the brick (in)finiteness of these algebras, let us recall that in [Mo1], the following bound quivers are called generalized barbell:
where , and are cyclic strings with no common vertex, except for possibly the case where is of zero length (which implies ). Moreover, (respectively and ) can have any length (respectively any positive length) and arbitrary orientation of their arrows, provided is not a uniserial string in . We note that generalized barbell quivers are a slight generalization of “barbell” quivers introduced by Ringel [Ri1], where he always assume the bar is of positive length.
The following theorem summarizes some of our earlier results on the study of -tilting finiteness. To make them more congruent with the scope of this paper, below we state them in terms of bricks.
Theorem 2.3 ([Mo2])
With the same notations as above, the following hold:
-
(1)
If belongs to , then is brick-infinite if and only if is hereditary of type or is generalized barbell.
-
(2)
If belongs to , then is brick-infinite if and only if has a sink.
We remark that and consist of only tame algebras and either of these two families contains both brick-finite and brick-infinite algebras (see [Mo1, Mo2] for full classifications).
We also recall that an algebra is said to be minimal -tilting infinite if is -tilting infinite but every proper quotient of is -tilting finite. From Theorem 2.2, it is immediate that minimal -tilting infinite algebras are the same as minimal brick-infinite algebras. Here we only list some of the main properties of these algebras and for more details we refer to [MP]. Recall that is called central provided its center is the ground field .
Theorem 2.4
Let be a minimal brick-infinite algebra. Then,
-
(1)
is central and admits no projective-injective module. Moreover, has no node.
-
(2)
Almost every -rigid -module is faithful, and therefore is partial tilting.
-
(3)
is minimal tilting infinite (i.e. is an infinite set but is finite, for each nonzero ideal in ).
To highlight some fundamental differences between these modern and classical notions of minimality, we remark that min-rep-infinite algebras are not necessarily central and their bound quivers can have several nodes. Furthermore, note that although -tilting finiteness is preserved under algebraic quotients, there exists tilting-finite algebra such that is tilting-infinite, for an ideal in .
2.5. Schemes and varieties of representations
In this subsection we collect some basic tools used in this paper which allow us to move between the algebraic and geometric sides of our problem. In particular, for algebra and a dimension vector in , let denote the affine (not necessarily irreducible) variety parametrizing the modules in . Here, denotes the subcategory of consisting of all modules of dimension vector .
Under the action of via conjugation, can be viewed as a scheme, as well as an affine variety, where the orbits of this action are in bijection with the isomorphism classes of modules in . Through this conceptual dictionary, we study some geometric properties of representations of the bound quiver , where is an admissible presentation of . For in , by we denote the -orbit of , when it is viewed as a point in . If is viewed as the -points of a corresponding scheme, it is known that is open in this scheme if and only is rigid. However, if we consider as a variety, there could be non-rigid modules such that is open. Although both of these geometric structures are rich and come with powerful tools, we mostly treat as an affine variety. When there is no risk of confusion, is referred to as a variety to reflect the geometric structure that comes from .
Let and respectively denote the set of all indecomposable modules and bricks in . It is known that is an open subset of . Let be the set of all irreducible components of , and by we denote the union of all , where is an arbitrary dimension vector. A component is called indecomposable provided it contains a non-empty open subset which consists of indecomposable representations. In [CBS], the authors prove a geometric analogue of the Krull-Schmidt decomposition for irreducible components, which highlights the role of indecomposable components among all irreducible ones.
For each in , the algebraic properties of the modules in capture important information on the geometry of , and vice versa. Motivated by this interaction, Chindris, Kinser and Weyman [CKW] have recently adopted a geometric approach to generalize the notion of representation-finiteness, primarily based on the properties of irreducible components. In particular, is said to have dense orbit property provided every in contains a dense orbit. By some simple geometric considerations, one can show that every rep-finite algebra has the dense orbit property. In [CKW], the authors show that the new notion is novel and construct explicit rep-infinite algebras which have the dense orbit property. Furthermore, they prove that a string algebra (and more generally, each special biserial algebra) is rep-finite if and only if it has the dense orbit property.
Adopting this algebro-geometric approach, we say that is brick-discrete if for each , there are only finitely many (isomorphism classes of) bricks of dimension . This is equivalent to the fact that for each in , if belongs to , then . Here, denotes the orbit closure of . We remark that brick-discrete algebras have been treated in [CKW], where the authors introduced them under the name “Schur representation-finite” algebras. To avoid confusion between brick-finite and Schur representation-finite algebras, we use our new terminology and call the latter type brick-discrete.
In [CKW], it is shown that if has the dense orbit property, then it is brick-discrete, but the converse does not hold in general. So, brick-discreteness was considered as a generalization of the dense orbit property, and hence a generalization of rep-finiteness. We observe that every brick-finite algebra is brick-discrete. In contrast, in general it is not known whether brick-discrete algebras are necessarily brick-finite. In fact, this is the content of the following conjecture, which is a precursor of Conjecture 1.1.
Conjecture 2.1 ([Mo2])
Let be an algebra over an algebraically closed field . The following are equivalent:
-
(1)
is -tilting finite;
-
(2)
is brick-discrete;
Equivalently, is brick-infinite if and only if there exists a family of bricks of the same length.
The above conjecture first appeared in the arXiv version of [Mo2], where the first-named author proposed an algebro-geoemtric realization of -tilting finiteness. Moreover, it is verified for all algebras treated in that paper. We also remark that the numerical implication of the above conjecture was later stated in [STV].
For a special biserial algebra , an irreducible component in is called a string component if it contains a string module such that is dense in . That being the case, we get , which implies that can be specified by the isomorphism class of the string module . In contrast, is a band component provided contains a family of band modules such that is dense in . In this case, . Hence, a band component is determined by the band that gives rise to the one-parameter family . Provided is a string algebra, consists only of string and band components.
3. Minimal brick-infinite biserial algebras
It is well-known that a minimal representation-infinite algebra which is special biserial must be a string algebra. Recently, Ringel [Ri1] gave a full classification of these algebras and one can observe that in fact every biserial min-rep-infinite algebra falls into Ringel’s classification (for further details, see [Mo2]). In this section, we give an analogous classification result and fully describe the bound quivers of those biserial algebras which are minimal brick-infinite. In particular, we show that any min-brick-infinite biserial algebra is gentle and falls into exactly one of the two types described in Theorem 3.5.
We first recall some notations and results from [CB+]. A quiver is said to be biserial if for any vertex in , there are at most two arrows starting at , and at most arrows ending at . It is clear that the quiver of any biserial algebra has to be biserial. A bisection of a biserial quiver is the data of two functions such that if are two distinct arrows starting (resp. ending) at , then (resp. ). Given a biserial quiver and a bisection of it, a good path is any path such that for , we have that . Trivial paths are declared to be good. A path that is not good is said to be bad. Bad paths of length two will play an important role due to the following result.
Observe that if is such that there exist multiple arrows between two fixed vertices of , then is min-brick-infinite if and only if is the Kronecker quiver and . Hence, for simplicity of the assertions, in the rest of this section we exclude the situation where the quiver of algebra has multiple arrows.
Theorem 3.1 ([CB+])
Let be a biserial algebra with quiver having no multiple arrows. There exists a bisection of such that , and for each bad path of length two contains an element of one of the following types:
-
or
-
there is a path parallel to , which neither starts nor ends with such that is good and such that for some non-zero scalar .
Conversely, if is a biserial quiver with no multiple arrows with a bisection , and is an admissible ideal of that contains all of the above elements , then is biserial.
Since the opposite algebra to a biserial algebra is also biserial, the dual of the above theorem is also valid as follows.
Theorem 3.2
Let be a biserial algebra with quiver having no multiple arrows. There exists a bisection of such that , and for each bad path of length two contains an element of one of the following types:
-
or
-
there is a path parallel to , which neither starts nor ends with such that is good and such that for some non-zero scalar .
Conversely, if is a biserial quiver with no multiple arrows with a bisection , and is an admissible ideal of that contains all of the above elements , then is biserial.
The next result plays an important role in our arguments below. This proposition appears as Lemma 2.3 in [Ku], but it is originally due to Vila-Freyer.
Proposition 3.3 (Vila-Freyer)
It is important to note that in the setting of Theorem 3.1, although we always have , there may exist an arrow such that . A similar observation holds for Theorem 3.2. The following example further explains this phenomenon.
Example 3.4
Let be the following biserial quiver
with bisection such that the values of are always positive, except that . There is a unique bad path of length , namely . The algebra is biserial by Theorem 3.1. However, the bad path is not in . On the other hand, one can change the generator by . Using the same bisection, now we get that the bad path belongs to . Hence, is special biserial. On the other hand, let be the quiver obtained from by adding a vertex and an arrow . Consider the bisection of obtained by extending the bisection of with . Consider the algebra . Then the algebra is biserial but no longer special biserial. With the change of generator as above, the relations and respectively become and . The latter is a relation as in Theorem 3.2.
The rest of this section is dedicated to proving the following theorem.
Theorem 3.5
Let be a minimal brick-infinite biserial algebra. Then, is a generalized barbell algebra, or , for some .
To prove the above theorem, in the remainder of the section we assume is minimal brick-infinite and is not hereditary and show that must be a generalized barbell quiver. Hence, below always denotes a minimal brick-infinite biserial algebra which is not hereditary. In particular, the quiver does not have multiple arrows (between any pair of vertices). We fix a bisection of and assume that where is as Theorem 3.1. We may further assume that the bisection and ideal as in Theorem 3.1 (and similarly, in Theorem 3.2) are chosen in such a way that, up to isomorphism, the number of relations of type in that theorem is minimal.
Lemma 3.6
In the above setting, if is not special biserial, there has to be one relation of type from Theorem 3.1 such that is not a loop.
Proof.
For the sake of contradiction, assume otherwise. That is, for any relation with nonzero , where is a good path and is a bad path of length two passing through , we must have is a loop. Since neither starts nor ends with , there are arrows , different from , such that for some good path . If is a loop, then has a single vertex with two loops, is local and hence brick-finite, a contradiction. Hence, are not loops.
If , we get . In this case, it is clear that and are bad paths and does not appear in any other bad path of length two. By our assumption, we have . We set . Assume first that . Consider the change of generators which changes only to , so that the arrow originally representing now represents . Observe that after this change of generators, the bisection is preserved. Since both bad paths at are now represented by elements in , up to isomorphism, we have that where the number of relations of type in from Theorem 3.1 has decreased by one, contradicting our running minimality assumption on the number of such relations. Hence, we may assume . We see that for and . Therefore, any module not annihilated by has a submodule isomorphic to the simple at . On the other hand, since is bad, any module not annihilated by has a quotient isomorphic to the simple at . Therefore, for any brick , either is annihilated by or by . Since is minimal brick-infinite, at most finitely many bricks are annihilated by each of these elements. This gives our desired contradiction.
Assume now that and are distinct. Therefore, is not a loop and . The bad paths at are and . Because is not a loop and is bad, we get . As in the previous case, we set and make a similar argument. If , then we proceed with a change of generator for the loop (so is replaced by ) and we get another presentation of with a smaller number of relations of type , leading to a contradiction. If is not in , then for and . Now, any module not annihilated by has a submodule isomorphic to the simple at and any module not annihilated by has a quotient isomorphic to the simple at . We get a contradiction as in the previous case. ∎
From the preceding lemma and our assumptions, it follows that if is minimal brick-infinite and not special biserial, then with a bisection of such that there exists a bad path , where is not a loop and where for some non-zero scalar , and a good path . We need the following lemmas.
Lemma 3.7
Assume that where contains the generators from Theorem 3.1. Then, is generated by these relations, plus possibly some other monomial relations.
Proof.
Let be a relation from a vertex to a vertex , where could be equal to . Since contains the generators from Theorem 3.1, we can reduce to a linear combination of good paths from to . If all of these paths start with the same given arrow, then there is a good path such that all paths occurring in starts with . By Nakayama’s lemma, this implies that , so we reduce the relation. Hence, we may assume that the paths occuring in start with two different arrows. Note that could have more than terms. There are paths starting at and starting with different arrows such that where none of is in (otherwise, we can reduce the relation as argued above). This means that the projective module has a radical which is the sum of two uniserial modules which have to intersect, and the intersection has to be at a simple module. This simple module has to be the simple at vertex . Hence, embeds into the injective module at . Using dual argument, we see that the right projective module embeds into the right injective module . By dimension count, that means that is projective-invective, which cannot happen for a minimal brick-infinite algebra (see Theorem 2.4). ∎
In the next lemma, we describe the behaviour of certain parallel paths in the bound quiver of algebras under consideration.
Lemma 3.8
Let be two parallel good paths starting at a vertex and ending at a vertex and such that no arrow on or starts with vertex . Assume that none of lie in . Then, there is an arrow of or ending at .
Proof.
We assume otherwise and claim that the good paths and are linearly independent as elements in the -bimodule . Here, denotes the radical of the bimodule . To verify the claim, note that if and are linearly dependent, there are elements and such that or . Without loss of generality, assume the first case happens. It follows from our presentation that can be taken to be a linear combination of good paths from to . Now, a non-trivial good path starting at and returning to either starts with or with . Therefore, we get an expression where and is in the radical. By Nakayama’s lemma, this implies that where . Now, consider the projective module . Since there are two arrows starting at , it is clear that is a sum of two uniserial modules. The equation given means that these two uniserial modules intersect non-trivially at a simple submodule at . Hence, embeds into the injective module at . Dually, arguing on , we similarly get that where . As above, this yields that embeds into the injective module . By dimension count, that means that is projective-invective, which cannot happen for a minimal brick-infinite algebra (see Theorem 2.4). ∎
Using the same notation and setting as in the paragraph preceding Lemma 3.6 and 3.7, we claim the following.
Claim: must appear in .
Proof of the claim: Assume that does not appear in the good path . Then we take a starting subpath of (thus starting at ) which is minimal with the property of ending at . It follows from Lemma 3.8 that has to be a starting vertex of an arrow in . Since that arrow cannot be , it has to be the first arrow of . This yields that there is no good path starting with ending with . This is a contradiction and proves our claim. ∎
We recall that a generalized barbell algebra whose bar is of positive length is simply called a barbell algebra (see Subsection 2.4). In the next definition, we specify a particular type of barbell algebras which are important in the proof of our main theorem.
Definition 3.9
Consider the quiver with given bisection and ideal as in Theorem 3.1 so that . We say that a subquiver is a good barbell subquiver for if is the quiver of a barbell algebra such that the two defining cycles are oriented cycles and the bar is linear. Moreover, any path which is not going through the “zero relations” of the barbell is a non-zero good path.
Remark 3.10
According to the above arguments, we may assume that the good path contains , and it is neither the first, nor the last arrow of . We remark that one can construct a good barbell subquiver of as follows. First, write the good path as where does not appear in . We further write such that is the ending subpath of and it is minimal with the property of revisiting itself. Thus, we can write as where is a simple oriented cycle from a vertex to itself, while is a path from to (if , then is trivial). Similarly, we write where is the starting subpath of which is minimal with the property of revisiting itself. Therefore, we can write as where is a simple oriented cycle from a vertex to itself while is a path from to (if , then is trivial). This configuration is depicted in Figure 1, where we put , , and . We consider the list
of vertices. If there is repetition in , take the first such repetition in the given order. Then we have the following cases:
Case : This repetition involves for or for . In the first case, contains two parallel paths starting at and ending at some vertex and not sharing any arrows or vertices (other than starting and ending points). Being subpaths of , none of them belong to . But this contradicts Lemma 3.8. In the second case, contains two parallel paths ending at and starting at some vertex and not sharing any arrows or vertices (other than starting and ending points). This leads to a similar contradiction.
Case : The repetition involves vertices in . Assume first that is involved and . By minimality of the repetition, this means that a subpath of appears as an ending subpath of . This either means that appears in , which is a contradiction, or that is the starting vertex of some . In the latter case, again, we get a contradiction to the minimality of the repetition. Similarly, if is involved and , we get a contradiction. If the vertices involved are not , then we may shrink to a smaller good subpath having and which will form a good barbell quiver (but may no longer appear in the bar). If and are involved, then this forces to be a loop, given the assumptions of this case. This is excluded.
Therefore, we know that contains a subpath having which will form a good barbell subquiver.
The construction in the above remark leads to the following proposition, which finishes our argument about the description of those non-hereditary biserial algebras which are minimal brick-infinite.
Proposition 3.11
Let where is biserial, a bisection is given and contains the generators as in theorem 3.1. If A is minimal brick-infinite and contains a good barbell subquiver, then itself is a barbell algebra. In particular, is gentle.
Proof.
By Remark 3.10, there exists a good barbell subquiver in , with a unique maximal good path, say of , which could be seen as a good path of and it is a priori not maximal in . Assume in starts at and ends at . We know that can be taken to be generated by the relations as in Theorem 3.1 for the bad paths of length two, plus possible monomials. We let be the ideal of containing together with the vertices and arrows not in , as well as by all bad paths in . Clearly, is a string algebra. Let be a good path in , where the bisection is inherited from that of .
We claim that is not in . We need to prove that if is a bad path in , then is not parallel to the good path occurring in in . By Proposition 3.3, this is possible only if is an ending subpath of the maximal good path in , as otherwise, , a contradiction. So assume that is an ending subpath of . We have that , where starts with and ends at . But since already has two arrows ending at and since cannot end with , that means that is the arrow on the bar ending at . On the other hand, we know that lies in but since is bad, that means that there has to be two arrows ending at in , which does not happen for a good barbell subquiver. Hence, any good path in is not in , and this proves that , which is a quotient of , is isomorphic to the algebra of a generalized barbell subquiver with a nontrivial bar. ∎
The preceding proposition, along with our assumptions in this section, completes our proof of Theorem 3.5. Consequently, we get the following result which gives a full classification of biserial algebras with respect to brick-finiteness.
Corollary 3.12
A biserial algebra is brick-infinite if and only if it has a gentle quotient algebra such that admits a band.
We note that our results also apply to some other families of algebras which have been studied in the literature, such as the weighted surface algebras introduced in [ES], as well as the stably biserial algebras, studied in [Po]. In particular, in the assertion of the preceding corollary, one can replace biserial algebras with weighted surface algebras or stably biserial algebras. The argument is quite straightforward but requires some considerations, which we leave to the interested reader.
4. Some applications and problems
Here we consider some consequences of our results in the preceding sections and propose a new treatment of brick-infinite algebras. In doing so, we view some classical results through a new lens which better motivates some questions posed below. As before, we work over an algebraically closed field and, unless specified otherwise, denotes a tame algebra. Also, recall that is a generic brick if it is generic and is a division algebra. As in [Ri2], one can treat generic bricks as certain points of the spectrum of . This is a conceptual generalization of spectrum of commutative rings to any arbitrary ring, first introduced by P. Cohn [Co]. However, here we primarily study them from the algebraic and geometric viewpoints. For further details on spectrum of algebra, see [Ri2].
4.1. Generic bricks and generic-brick-domestic algebras
The Tame/Wild dichotomy theorem of Drozd [Dr] plays a decisive role in the study of rep-infinite algebras. The family of tame algebras further refines into three disjoint subfamilies– namely, domestic algebras, algebras of polynomial growth, and algebras of non-polynomial growth (for definitions and background, see [Sk]). To motivate a modern analogue of domestic algebras, we recall a fundamental theorem of Crawley-Boevey which gives a conceptual characterization of tameness, as well as domestic algebras. Following [CB1], we say that is generically tame if for each , there are only finitely many (isomorphism classes) of generic modules of endolength .
Theorem 4.1 ([CB1])
An algebra is tame if and only if it is generically tame. Moreover, is domestic exactly when it admits only finitely many isomorphism classes of generic modules.
As we do henceforth, the characterization of tame and domestic algebras in the above theorem can be adopted as their definition. Moreover, for a , the algebra is -domestic if and only if it admits exactly generic modules (see [CB1, Corollary 5.7]). Analogously, we say is -generic-brick-domestic if it admits exactly (isomorphism classes) of generic bricks. In general, we call generic-brick-domestic if it admits only finitely many generic bricks.
It is known that is rep-finite if and only if (see [Au]). Furthermore, by [CB1] this is equivalent to the existence of a generic module. Hence, the family of -domestic algebras is the same as that of rep-finite algebras. Moreover, Theorem 2.1 implies that any brick-finite algebra is -generic-brick-domestic. However, we do not know whether the converse is true in general. Thanks to our new results, we can affirmatively answer this question for the family of biserial algebras and further conjecture that this holds in general.
Remark 4.2
We note that, in contrast to the notion of generic-brick-domestic algebras defined above, one can call a tame algebra -brick domestic algebra if for any , there are most one-parameter families of bricks of length . We observe that this notion is different from -generic-brick-domestic algebras and further studying of connections between these two notions could be interesting. We do not treat this comparison in this paper.
Before restating our main conjecture for arbitrary algebras, we recall some basic notions and facts on the representation varieties of algebras. Recall from Section 2 that is brick-discrete if for every in , the set contains at most one brick (up to isomorphism). If , then is called a brick component. Because is always an open subset of , each brick component is an indecomposable component. Thus, is brick-discrete exactly when each brick component in is of the form , for some in . As in the Introduction, is called brick-continuous if it is not brick-discrete. That is, there exists and in such that contains infinitely many orbits of bricks. In [Mo2], the first-named author conjectured that an algebra is brick-finite if and only if it is brick-discrete (see also Conjecture 2.1). Below, we propose a stronger version of this conjecture which also implies Theorem 2.1.
Conjecture 4.1
For any algebra , the following are equivalent:
-
(1)
is brick-infinite;
-
(2)
is brick-continuous;
-
(3)
admits a generic brick.
In the preceding conjecture, observe that evidently implies , and from Theorem 2.1 it is immediate that implies . Furthermore, the implication to holds if there exist a generic brick which satisfies the assumption of the next proposition. In particular, this condition always holds for tame algebras.
Proposition 4.3 ([Ri2])
Let be an algebra and be a generic brick such that is finitely generated over its center. Then, gives rise to a one-parameter family of bricks in .
To verify Conjecture 4.1 for the family of tame algebras, it suffices to show the implication and for that one can reduce to minimal brick-infinite tame algebras. In the following theorem, we consider certain families of such algebras and extend a classical result of Ringel on the hereditary case. We remark that if and are two non-isomorphic generic modules in , they induce two distinct -parameter families of indecomposable modules in (see [CB1]). As mentioned earlier, the next theorem can be stated in the language of spectrum of algebras, as in [Ri2].
Theorem 4.4
Let be a minimal brick-infinite tame algebra. If is hereditary or biserial, then
-
•
has a unique generic brick;
-
•
is the disjoint union of an infinite discrete family with , where all are of the same dimension.
In particular, in either of these cases is brick-continuous and -generic-brick-domestic.
Proof.
If is hereditary, it is the path algebra of some or , where and . In this case, the assertions follow from the main result of [Ri2]. If we assume is biserial and non-hereditary, Theorem 3.5 implies that is a generalized barbell algebra. As shown in [Mo1], every generalized barbell algebra admits a unique band for which the band module is a brick, for all . In particular, explicit description of depends on the length and orientation of the bar in the generalized barbell quiver , as depicted in Figure 2. If denotes the length of , we need to consider the two cases and , as discussed below. In the following, by and we denote respectively the left and right cyclic strings in and assume and , with and , for every and .
If , let and , and suppose with , for all . Without loss of generality, we can assume , because the case is similar. Then, by [Mo1, Proposition 5.6], gives us the desired band in , which we use to construct a generic brick over . Starting from , put a copy of at each time passes through . As the result, for each vertex that belongs to we have , whereas at the remaining vertices we get . As for the linear maps, as we go through , for all arrows except for the second occurrence of , we put the identity map between the two copies of and in the direction of , whereas the map from the first copy of at to the second copy of at is given by multiplication by . Then, an argument similar to [Mo1, Proposition 5.6] shows that , and from the construction it is clear is of finite dimension over . Hence, is the desired generic brick.
Note that if , the strings and cannot be serial simultaneously (otherwise will be infinite dimensional). In this case the desired band is given by and an argument similar to the above case gives the explicit construction of the generic brick.
To show the uniqueness of this generic brick , assume otherwise and let be a generic brick in which is not isomorphic to . By Proposition 4.3, both and induce -parameter families of bricks in , say respectively and , where . From [BR], all these bricks are band modules. Moreover, from [CB1], we know that these two -parameter families are distinct, which implies there must come from two distinct bands in , say and , for which and are bricks. This contradicts the uniqueness of , as shown in [Mo1, Proposition 5.6 and Proposition 7.10].
Finally, observe that each in is either a band module of the form , for some , or else is a string module. The former type gives a -parameter family, whereas string bricks form a countable (discrete) infinite family. In particular, if , we note that each string module is a brick, where (for details, see [Mo1]). If , the explicit description of an infinite family of string modules which are bricks is given in [Mo1, Proposition 7.10]. ∎
We remark that (generalized) barbell quivers are of non-polynomial growth (see [Ri1]). That means, roughly speaking, as long as the behavior of all indecomposable modules is concerned, generalized barbell algebras are among the most complicated type of tame algebras. However, the preceding theorem implies they are always -generic-brick-domestic. Hence, with respect to this modern criterion, generalized barbell algebras are among the simplest type of brick-infinite algebras (see also Subsection 4.2).
As a consequence of the preceding theorem, we get the following result. In particular, this proves Corollary 1.4.
Corollary 4.5
Let be a biserial algebra. The following are equivalent:
-
(1)
is brick-infinite;
-
(2)
is brick-continuous;
-
(3)
admits a generic brick;
-
(4)
There is an infinite family of non-isomorphic bricks of length ;
-
(5)
In a brick component in , there a rational curve of non-isomorphic bricks such that ;
-
(6)
For some , there exist infinitely many non-isomorphic -modules which are -stable.
Before we present a proof, note that this corollary gives novel algebro-geometric realizations of -tilting (in)finiteness of biserial algebras (see Theorem 2.2). Viewed from this perspective, these results also extend some earlier work on the family of special biserial algebras (see [STV]).
Proof.
First, we note that a tame algebra is brick-continuous if and only if for some we have , where is a rational curve of bricks in (for details, see [CC2]). This implies the equivalence of . Furthermore, observe that the family of biserial algebras is quotient-closed, meaning that any quotient of a biserial algebra is again biserial. Hence, without loss of generality, we assume is a min-brick-infinite biserial algebra. Then, by Theorem 4.4, implies , from which we conclude the equivalences (see also the paragraph following Conjecture 4.1). Moreover, by the proof of Theorem 4.4, the unique generic brick on is of endolength , which induces an infinite family of band modules of length in . This shows and the reverse implication is immediate from . Hence, the first five parts are equivalent.
It is well-known that if is -stable, for some , then is a brick. Hence, is immediate. To finish the proof, we note that admits an infinite subfamily of consists of band modules (of the same length). These are known to be homogeneous and by a result of Domokos [Do], the are -stable, for some (for explicit description of , also see [CKW, Lemma 2.5]). ∎
4.2. Domestic vs. generic-brick-domestic
In this subsection we highlight some fundamental differences between the two notions of domesticness for tame algebras. In particular, we present several examples to better clarify some important points and motivate some questions which could be further pursued. In doing so, we give specific attention to string algebras, because they provide a more tractable setting.
As remarked earlier, generalized barbell algebras give an explicit family of tame algebras which are not domestic but always -generic-brick-domestic. This naturally raises the question if there are examples of tame algebras which are -domestic and -generic-brick-domestic, for arbitrary and in . Evidently, we need to additionally assume . In the following examples, we give an explicit algorithm for constructing such algebras and prove Corollary 1.2.
Before we give a set of examples, let us fix some notation and terminology that will be handy. We encourage the reader to observe the bound quiver given in Example 4.8 while going through the following definition. Below, by we denote a linearly oriented copy of quiver .
Definition 4.6
Let and be two algebras and suppose and are two minimal sets of generators, respectively, for the ideals and . Let be a sink in and be a source in . Furthermore, assume be the set of all arrows in ending at , and be the set of all arrows in starting at .
For any , the -nody gluing of and from to is the new quiver obtained as follows:
-
•
is the result of connecting to via which begins at and ends at .
-
•
A generating set for the ideal is given by
.
In particular, all vertices of , including those identified with and , are nodes in .
In the previous definition, if , then is obtained by identifying the vertices and and imposing all the monomial quadratic relations at every possible compositions , for all and . Hence, the new vertex is evidently a node in the quiver .
The following lemma is handy in discussing the following examples.
Lemma 4.7
With the same notion and convention as in Definition 4.6, let be the -nody gluing of two string algebras and . Provided , no generic module over is supported on the arrows of . That is, every generic module in belongs to either or .
Before we prove the lemma, let us remark that the assumption is essential (see Example 4.10).
Proof.
From the construction of , it is immediate that is also a string algebra. Furthermore, all vertices of that belong to are nodes in . That is, every composition of arrows in at these vertices falls in . Therefore, if is a generic module over , it induces a -parameter family of band modules. In particular, if is supported on any of the arrows of , so are the induced band modules. This is impossible, because there is no band in which is supported on an arrow of . This completes the proof. ∎
In [Ri1], the author introduced a particular type of string algebras, so-called wind wheel algebras, which played a crucial role in classification of minimal representation-infinite (special) biserial algebras. Since the definition of wind wheel algebras is technical, here we only recall the general configuration of their bound quivers and for their explicit constructions, we refer the reader to [Ri1]. In general, each wind wheel algebra has a bound quiver of the following form:
where the bar is a serial and of length . Moreover, in addition to the monomial quadratic relations and , we only have the monomial relation . Note that the internal orientation of the left and right cycles are arbitrary, and this freedom is depicted by dashed segments. In particular, observe that we may have and similarly .
Example 4.8 (-domestic algebras which are -generic-brick-domestic)
The wind wheel algebras are known to be -domestic (see [Ri1]). Moreover, in [Mo1], it is shown that they are always brick-finite. Hence, wind wheel algebras are -domestic but -generic-brick-domestic string algebras. Let and be any pair of wind wheel algebras such that has a sink and has a source. By description of their bound quivers, such sinks and sources cannot belong to their bars, thus they must be on one of their cycles that connect to vertices of degree .
Then, consider an -nody gluing of and , such as the explicit example illustrated below. Note that, to distinguish the arrows of form those that belong to and , they are depicted by dashed arrows. Moreover, the solid arrows appearing on the left end (respectively, right end) of the large quiver belong to (respectively, ). Moreover, those monomial quadratic relations which do not belong to nor are imposed through the -nody gluing, and they are shown with thicker dotted quadratic relation.
Let the above bound quiver be the -nody gluing of and . Then, is evidently a string algebra and it is easy to check that it is a -domestic and brick-finite. In particular, by Lemma 4.7, every generic module in is a generic module over exactly one of the two wind wheel algebras, whose bound quivers are specified by solid arrows on the left and right ends of the above bound quiver. Moreover, Corollary 3.12 implies that is brick-finite. Hence, is -domestic but -generic-brick-domestic.
Through a recursive argument as above, for every , one can explicitly construct -domestic string algebras which are -generic-brick-domestic.
In the next example, we consider some non-domestic tame algebras. In particular, we look at explicit string algebras that are of non-polynomial growth.
Example 4.9 (-generic-brick-domestic algebras which are not domestic)
One can easily show that every (generalized) barbell algebra is of non-polynomial growth. In particular, it is a string algebra such that each arrow can appear in infinitely many distinct bands (for details, see [Ri1]). Consider a barbell algebra, say , such that has at least one source, say , and at least one sink, say . It is well-known that by gluing these two vertices together, we obtain a new minimal representation-infinite algebra, say . That is, the vertices and are identified and all quadratic monomial relations are imposed at the new vertex (see [Ri1]). In particular, observe that is again a string algebra and of non-polynomial growth. However, the new vertex is a node and the new algebra obtained via gluing vertices and becomes brick-finite (see [Mo2]). In particular, it is -generic-brick-domestic.
Below, we present another useful observation on the behavior of generic-brick-domestic algebras. In particular, the next example shows that there are tame algebras which are not generic-brick-domestic.
Example 4.10 (Gentle but not generic-brick-domestic algebras)
Consider the algebra , where is the following bound quiver, where all relations are quadratic. Note that is a gentle algebra, hence it is tame. We claim that is not generic-brick-domestic.
First observe that admits two distinct quotient algebras which are hereditary, given by and . Each of these quotient algebras is a path of the Kronecker quiver and admits a unique generic brick (see Theorem 4.4). Following the explicit description of morphisms between band modules, as in [Kr], one can show that the the band is a brick band, hence gives rise to a generic brick. More generally, for each , consider the band in , where means the repetition of string for times. Evidently, if and and , the bands and are distinct and the corresponding generic modules are non-isomorphic. Again, using the same argument as above, one can show that each is a brick band, and therefore the corresponding generic module is a generic brick (see [Kr]). Thus, the above gentle algebra is not generic-brick-tame.
We finish this subsection with a proof of Corollary 1.2. In particular, thanks to Theorem 4.4 and the explicit constructions given in the preceding examples, we have the following result. We recall that a string algebra which is not domestic admits infinitely many generic modules, hence it is of non-polynomial growth. We simply call such algebras -domestic. Similarly, by -generic-brick-domestic, we denote those tame algebras which admit infinitely many generic bricks.
Corollary 4.11
For every pair of integers in , there exists a string algebra which is -domestic and -generic-brick domestic.
Proof.
Every rep-finite algebra is tame and -domestic, therefore it is -generic-brick-domestic. This address the case . Furthermore, Example 4.10 gives an explicit example for the case . Moreover, the case and is discussed in Example 4.8. Provided we begin from such an algebra, via an -nody gluing of a copy of (for some ), we can construct a string algebra which is -domestic but -generic-brick-domestic. Using this idea recursively, for every , one can easily construct a string algebra which is -domestic and -generic-brick-domestic. This settles the case and .
Provided , in Example 4.8, we gave a construction for -domestic string algebras which are -generic-brick-domestic. For a given string algebra which is -domestic and -generic-brick-domestic, by an -nody gluing of a wind wheel bound quiver to we obtain a string algebra which is -domestic but remains -generic-brick-domestic (see Lemma 4.7 and Example 4.8). Moreover, via an -nody gluing of a copy of to the bound quiver to , we obtain a string algebra which is -domestic and -generic-brick-domestic. Consequently, for each pair of integers and in with , we can construct a string algebra which is -domestic and -generic-brick-domestic. ∎
4.3. Problems and remarks
The rest of this section consists of some remarks and questions which outline our future work and new directions of research related to the scope of this paper.
Numerical condition for brick-finiteness
To verify whether or not a biserial algebra is brick-infinite, by Theorem 1.3 one only needs to study all indecomposable modules of length no larger than . This, in particular, gives a very small and explicit bound which could be effectively applied to the study of -tilting theory and stability conditions of biserial algebras, as in Corollary 4.5. Meanwhile, for any rep-infinite algebra , in [Bo2, Theorem 26] Bongartz gives an explicit test for rep-finiteness of . Furthermore, [Bo2, Theorem 26] gives a bound for existence of the smallest -parameter family of indecomposable -modules. This, by [Sm], then results in existence of infinitely many -parameter families of indecomposable modules asserted by Second Brauer-Thrall conjecture (now theorem). This observation, along with our result on biserial algebras, naturally yields the following question.
Question 4.1
Let be a -dimensional algebra whose rank of Grothendieck group is . Is there an explicit bound in terms of and such that, to verify the brick finiteness of , it is sufficient to check if there is no infinite family of bricks of length less than ?
Observe that, by definition, every domestic algebra is generic-brick-domestic, but Exmaple 4.9 shows that the latter family is strictly larger. Meanwhile, as shown in Example 4.10, there exist tame algebras which are not generic-brick-domestic. Recently, Bodnarchuk and Drozd [BD] introduced the brick-analogue of the classical notion of tameness, and called them brick-tame algebras. Furthermore, they give a new dichotomy theorem of algebras with respect to this criterion (for further details, see [BD]). This notion is further studied by Carroll and Chindris [CC1]. Note that strictly wild algebras are never brick-tame. It is a folklore open conjecture, attributed to Ringel, that the converse holds in general. Adopting this perspective in the study of bricks, combined with the characterization of tame/wild dichotomy through generic modules in [CB1], naturally raises the question whether there exists an analogue characterization of brick-tame/brick-wild algebras via generic bricks. The notion of brick-tameness allows one to approach brick-infinite algebras from a new perspective, particularly in the treatment of non-domestic tame algebras and those wild algebras which are not strictly wild.
As long as non-domestic tame algebras are concerned, a good knowledge of -generic-brick-domestic algebras, for different , should provide fresh impetus to some classical problems. In that sense, the following question could be of interest and relates to Theorem 4.4.
Question 4.2
Is every tame minimal brick-infinite algebra generic-brick-domestic?
As a question of the same nature, one can ask whether arbitrary minimal brick-infinite algebras always admit only finitely many generic bricks.
Finally, we note that for gentle algebras, recently Geiß, Labardini-Fragoso and Schröer[G+] have extensively studied the string and band components. Such results directly apply to the family of minimal brick-infinite biserial algebras, because they are always gentle (see Theorem 1.1). Hence, it is natural to further investigate that approach and try to extend the setting of [G+].
Acknowledgements. The authors would like to thank William Crawley-Boevey for some helpful discussions related to the scope of this work. We also thank Aaron Chan for some interesting conversations about gentle algebras coming from surfaces.
References
- [Au] M. Auslander, Large modules over artin algebras, Algebra, Topology and Category Theory: a collection of papers in honor of Samuel Eilenberg; Academic Press (1976), 1–17.
- [AIR] T. Adachi, O. Iyama, I. Reiten, -tilting theory, Compos. Math. 150 (2014), 415-452.
- [ASS] I. Assem, D. Simson, A. Skowroński, Elements of the representation theory of associative algebras, Volume 1, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, (2006).
- [Bo1] K. Bongartz, On minimal representation-infinite algebras, arXiv:1705.10858v4.
- [Bo2] K. Bongartz, K.Bongartz: On representation-finite algebras and beyond, Advances in Representation Theory of algebras,65-101, EMS Ser. Congr. Rep., Eur. Math. Soc., Zürich, (2013).
- [BD] L. Bodnarchuk and Yu. Drozd, One class of wild but brick-tame matrix problems. Journal of Algebra (2010), 3004–3019.
- [BR] M. C. R. Butler, C. M. Ringel, Auslander-Reiten sequences with few middle terms, Comm. in Algebra. 15 (1987), 145-179.
- [CB1] W. Crawley-Beovey, Tame algebras and generic modules, Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society (1991), 241–265.
- [CB2] W. Crawley-Boevey, Tameness of biserial algebras, Arch. Math. 65 (1995), 399-407.
- [Co] P. M. Cohn, Progress in free associative algebras, Israel Journal of Mathematics volume 19 (1974), 109–151.
- [CC1] A. Carroll, C. Chindris Moduli spaces of modules of Schur-tame algebras, Algebras and Representation Theory volume 18 (2015), 961–976.
- [CC2] A. Carroll, C. Chindris On the invariant theory for acyclic gentle algebras, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 367 (2015), 3481–3508.
- [CBS] W. Crawley-Boevey, J. Schroër, Irreducible components of varieties of modules, J. Reine Angew. Math. 553 (2002), 201–220.
- [CB+] W. Crawley-Boevey, R. Vila-Freyer, The Structure of Biserial Algebras, Journal of the London Mathematical Society, Volume 57 (1998), 41–54.
- [CKW] C. Chindris, R. Kinser, J. Weyman, Module Varieties and Representation Type of Finite-Dimensional Algebras, International Mathematics Research Notices, Volume 2015 (2015), 631–650.
- [Dr] Y. A. Drozd, Tame and wild matrix problems, Representations and quadratic forms (Institute of Mathematics, Academy of Sciences, Ukrainian SSR, Kiev, 1979), pp. 39-74; Amer. Math. Soc. Transl. 128 (1986), 31-55.
- [DIJ] L. Demonet, O. Iyama, G. Jasso, -tilting finite algebras and -vectors, Int. Math. Res. Not. IMRN (2019), 852–892.
- [Do] M. Domokos, Relative invariants for representations of finite dimensional algebras, Manuscripta Mathematica 108 (2002), 123–33.
- [ES] K. Erdmann, A. Skowronski, Weighted surface algebras, Journal of Algebra 608 (2018), 490-558.
- [Fu] K. R. Fuller, Biserial rings, Ring theory, Lecture Notes in Mathematics 734, Springer, Berlin (1979).
- [G+] F. Geiß, D. Labardini-Fragoso, J. Schröer, Schemes of modules over gentle algebras and laminations of surfaces, arxiv:2005.01073.
- [Kr] H. Krause, Maps between tree and band modules, Journal of Algebras, Volume 137 (1991), 186–194.
- [Ku] J. Külshammer, Biserial algebras via subalgebras and the path algebra of , Journal of Algebras, Volume 331 (2011), 58-67.
- [Mo1] K. Mousavand, -tilting finiteness of biserial algebras, arXiv:1904.11514.
- [Mo2] K. Mousavand, -tilting finiteness of non-distributive algebras and their module varieties, Journal of Algebra 608 (2022), 673-690.
- [MP] K. Mousavand, C. Paquette Minimal -tilting infinite algebras, arXiv:2103.12700 (to appear in Nagoya Mathematical Journal).
- [Po] Z. Pogarzaly, Algebras stably equivalent to selfinjective special biserial algebras, Communications in Algebra 22.4 (1994), 1127–1160.
- [Ri1] C.M. Ringel, The minimal representation-infinite algebras which are special biserial, Representations of Algebras and Related Topics, EMS Series of Congress Reports, European Math. Soc. Publ. House, Zürich (2011).
- [Ri2] C.M. Ringel, The spectrum of a finite dimensional algebra, Proceedings of a conference on Ring Theory, Antwerp 1978 (Dekker, New York, 1979).
- [Se] F. Sentieri, A brick version of a theorem of Auslander, arXiv:2011.09253.
- [Sm] S. O. Smalø, The inductive step of the second Brauer-Thrall conjecture, Canadian J. Math., 32 (1980), 342–349.
- [Sk] A. Skowronski, Algebras of polynomial growth, Banach Center Publications , Volume 26, (1990), 535-568.
- [STV] S. Schroll, H. Treffinger, Y. Valdivieso, On band modules and -tilting finiteness, Mathematische Zeitschrift 299 (2021), 2405–2417.
- [WW] B. Wald, J. Waschbüsch, Tame biserial algebras, Journal of Algebra 95 (1985), 480–500.