58A03, 18B25, 18F10, 03G30 \eaddress[email protected]
Bi-directional models of
‘Radically Synthetic’ Differential Geometry
Abstract
The radically synthetic foundation for smooth geometry formulated in [Law11] postulates a space with the property that it has a unique point and, out of the monoid of endomorphisms, it extracts a submonoid which, in many cases, is the (commutative) multiplication of a rig structure. The rig is said to be bi-directional if its subobject of invertible elements has two connected components. In this case, may be equipped with a pre-order compatible with the rig structure. We adjust the construction of ‘well-adapted’ models of Synthetic Differential Geometry in order to build the first pre-cohesive toposes with a bi-directional . We also show that, in one of these pre-cohesive variants, the pre-order on , derived radically synthetically from bi-directionality, coincides with that defined in the original model.
keywords:
Axiomatic Cohesion, (Radically) Synthetic Differential Geometry1 Introduction
The origin of Synthetic Differential Geometry (SDG) may be traced back to certain 1967 lectures by Lawvere, later summarized in [Law79]. That summary includes, between brackets, some remarks based on developments that occurred since the original lectures. It postulates a locally catesian closed category , a ring therein, and an isomorphism , where denotes the subobject of elements of square . Between brackets, it is observed that such isomorphism could be interpreted to mean that the canonical is invertible, as had been done in several papers by Kock. See [Koc77] where this interpretation is introduced and where rings satisfying the resulting ‘Kock-Lawvere (KL)’ axiom are called of line type.
The summary also sketches the construction of models, including the role of the algebraic theories of real-analytic and of functions. Between brackets, it is mentioned that, in 1978, Dubuc succeeded in constructing a model of the axioms containing the category of real -manifolds. See [Dub79] where -rings play the prominent role.
The first book on SDG appeared in 1981 and it was reprinted as a second edition in [Koc06]. Several other books have appeared since 1990 giving respective accounts of the development of the subject [MR91, Lav96, Bel98, Koc10] and [BGSLF18].
Much can be done with the KL-axiom alone but, for some purposes, (e.g. integration), a pre-order on a ring of line type , compatible with the ring structure, is also postulated. The typical models are ‘gros’ toposes such as those arising in classical Algebraic Geometry [Koc06] and those intentionally built to produce ‘well-adapted’ models embedding the category of manifolds [Dub79, Koc06, MR91]. See also [Men21a] for more recent examples, similar to those in Algebraic Geometry over , but over the simple rig with idempotent addition.
The ‘gros’ vs ‘petit’ distinction among toposes appears already in [AGV72] but the idea to axiomatize toposes ‘of spaces’ is from the early ‘80s [Law05]. See also [Law07] for a more recent formulation and [Men14] or [Men21b] for the definition of pre-cohesive geometric morphism. For instance, the ‘gros’ Zariski topos determined by the field of complex numbers is a well-known model of SDG and the canonical geometric morphism is pre-cohesive. The same holds for some of the models in [Men21a]. On the other hand, the well-adapted models of SDG are intuitively toposes of spaces but, as far as I know, very little work has been done to relate them with Axiomatic Cohesion. Perhaps the only exception are the results in [MR91] noting that the well-adapted models discussed there are local, which is one of the requirements in [Law05] (and also in the definition of pre-cohesive map). Another requirement is that the inverse image of a pre-cohesive geometric morphism must have a finite-product preserving left adjoint which, intuitively, sends a space to the associated set of connected components of . This cannot be true for the canonical geometric morphism from the ‘smooth Zariski topos’ [MR91, VI] to the topos of sets because, in constrast with the classical cases over a field, where every affine scheme is a finite coproduct of connected ones, there are affine -schemes with infinite coproduct decompositions.
The paragraph above does not imply that ‘well-adaptation’ is incompatible with Cohesion. We will show in Sections 2 and 4 how to modify the techniques to construct well-adapted models of SDG so that they produce very simple (presheaf) pre-cohesive toposes (over ) with rings of line type. Moreover, these pre-cohesive toposes also model something more radical.
The radically synthetic foundation for smooth geometry formulated in [Law11] (and briefly recalled in Section 3) postulates a space with the property that it has a unique point and, out of the monoid of endomorphisms of , it extracts a submonoid which, in many cases, is the (commutative) multiplication of a rig structure. The rig is said to be bi-directional if its subgroup of invertible elements is such that the multiplicative group with two elements. In this case, may be equipped with a pre-order compatible with the rig structure. As explained loc.cit., this is ‘radically synthetic’ in the sense that all algebraic structure is derived from constructions on the geometric spaces rather than assumed. (See also [Law] which is unpublished but freely available from Lawvere’s webpage.)
We remark that no explicit models of bi-directional Radical SDG are considered in [Law11]. It is clear that the objects arising in SDG can play the role of and that they will give the expected result, but the issue of bi-directionality is more subtle. On the one hand, is not bidirectional in the models coming from Algebraic Geometry; on the other hand, we don’t know which of the known well-adapted models of SDG have a ‘’ functor. Nevertheless, many well-adapted models at least satisfy that the subobject of invertibles in is not connected; in fact, in these cases, is representable by the -ring of smooth -valued functions on the non-connected manifold so, at least, they are ‘bi-directional’ in this sense. Essentially the same phenomenon implies that, in our pre-cohesive models, bi-directionality holds in the sense of the previous paragraph.
Finally we show in Section 5 that, in one of the pre-cohesive models, the pre-order on , derived radically synthetically from bi-directionality, coincides with the pre-order that is defined in the analogous model of SDG.
2 The coextensive category of -rings
Let be the coextensive category of rings so that the slice is the category of -algebras. We next recall the algebraic theory of -rings [Koc06, III.5]. For any finite set , the -ary operations are the smooth functions . The associated algebraic category of -rings will be denoted by . There is an evident algebraic functor that has the following not quite so evident property.
Lemma 2.1 ([Koc06, Proposition III.5.4]).
Let be a -ring and let be an ideal in the usual ring-theoretic sense. Then the -algebra carries a unique structure of -ring such that the quotient is a morphism of -rings. Hence, as map in , it is the universal map from with kernel .
As an application we prove the following (folk?) basic fact.
Proposition 2.2.
The category is coextensive.
Proof 2.3.
We show that coextensivity lifts from along . It is enough to check that this functor preserves and reflects both finite products and pushouts along product projections. The issue of finite products is easy because any algebraic functor creates limits so it also preserves and reflects them.
Consider now a product projection in . It is well-known that, as a map in , it may be identified with for some idempotent . Then so is the case in by Lemma 2.1. Hence, for any in the square below
is a pushout both in and in . It is then clear that both preserves and reflects these pushouts.
Let be the full subcategory of finitely generated -rings.
Corollary 2.4.
The essentially small category is coextensive and the full inclusion preserves finite products.
Proof 2.5.
It is enough to show that the full subcategory is closed under finite products and direct factors. Closure under direct factors follows from their description in terms of idempotents as in the proof of Proposition 2.2. So it remains to prove that finitely generated -rings are closed under binary product. It is enough to check that is finitely generated for all finite . Using (smooth) Tietze one may show that a simple is surjective.
In contrast with Lemma 2.1 the forgetful does not create the universal solution to inverting an element. This will be of key importance throughout the paper.
Also, in contrast with the case of -algebras for a field : it is not the case that every finitely generated -ring is finitely presentable [Koc06, Example III.5.5], and it is not the case that every finitely generated -ring is a finite direct product of directly indecomposable ones. Moreover, by the Nullstellensatz, every non-final finitely generated -algebra has a (co)point, but see [Koc06, p. 165] for an example of a non-final finitely generated -ring without points.
Let be the (extensive) opposite of the category of finitely generated -rings. Its objects might be called affine -schemes.
3 Radically Synthetic Differential Geometry
Euler’s observation that real numbers are ratios of infinitesimals is the topic of [Law11]. To make that observation rigorous, Lawvere suggests some basic properties of the underlying category of spaces and postulates the existence of an object ‘of infinitesimals’ with the sole property that it has a unique point. Then he shows how some simple axioms of geometric nature allow to construct a pre-ordered ring ‘of Euler reals’. In this section, we briefly recall some of these ideas and relate them to SDG.
Let be an extensive category with finite limits and let be a pointed object in such that is exponentiable. For any object in , is called the tangent bundle of the space , with evaluation at inducing the bundle map .
Definition 3.1.
The subobject of Euler reals is defined by declaring
to be a pullback in .
The exponential carries a canonical monoid structure determined by composition in . This monoid structure restricts to and is called multiplication. The transposition of the evident composite factors as a map followed by the inclusion . In this way, has the intrinsic structure of a monoid with .
We are mainly interested in categories of spaces that are toposes, but some of the ideas may be directly illustrated at the level of sites.
Example 3.2 (Affine -schemes.).
Let be a field and let be the (cartesian and extensive) opposite of the category of finitely presentable -algebras. If is one such then denotes the corresponding object in . In particular, let and let . Clearly has a unique point and a direct calculation shows that and that , the affine line. The subobject corresponds to the unique map that sends to and to . Also, the multiplication morphism in corresponds to the morphism that sends to . It is well-known that this multiplication is the multiplicative structure of a ring of line type.
The preservation properties of the Yoneda functor imply that, in the topos of presheaves on , the monoid of Euler reals determined by the presheaf representable by is representable by . On the other hand, does not preserve finite coproducts.
Example 3.3 (The Gaeta topos determined by field.).
Still assuming that is a field, extensivity of allows us to consider the Gaeta subtopos of finite-product preserving presheaves. The Yoneda embedding factors through this subtopos and that the factorization preserves not only limits but also finite coproducts. As in the presheaf case, the monoid of Euler reals determined by coincides with .
Remark 3.4 (On the complex Gaeta topos.).
Essentially by the Basis Theorem, every object in is a finite coproduct of connected objects. It follows that the Gaeta topos is a equivalent the topos of presheaves on the subcategory of connected objects in . If , every connected object in has a point, so the Gaeta topos of is pre-cohesive over . We make this remark because the experience of the Complex Gaeta topos will lead us to consider other sites of connected objects that have a point.
The similarity between the intuitions about and about the object in SDG is no accident. To give a rigorous comparison we prove the following result which has surely been known since the mid 60’s although I don’t think it appears explicitly in [Law79] or in [Koc06]. An ‘external’ form of the result is mentioned in the paragraph before Section 4 in [Ros84]. The present form is suggested in the last paragraph of p. 250 of [Law11] and it is stated explicitly just before Corollary 5.5 in [CC14].
Proposition 3.5 (KL implies E.).
If is a ring of line type then the multiplicative part of is the monoid of Euler reals determined by .
Proof 3.6.
The map used in KL axiom makes the inner triangle below commute
(where is the obvious product projection) and the supplementary inner polygon is a pullback so the left rectangle above is a pullback. Also, if we let be the evident subobject then the square on the right above commutes where the top map is the transposition of restricted multiplication ; so the rectangle is a pullback. Stacking the pullbacks we obtain that is the inverse image of along . As the square on the left below commutes
and factors through , it follows that the right square above is a pullback.
It remains to check that preserves multiplication, in other words, that the diagram on the left below commutes
but, via transposition, this reduces to the commutativity of the diagram on the right above.
Remark 3.7 (Alternative proof of 3.5.).
For comparison we sketch below a proof using generalized elements suggested by A. Kock (private communication). The KL-axiom implies that maps may be identified with affine endomaps with . If we denote such a map by then it follows that . Such an affine map takes into if and only if for every . This is equivalent to the conjunction of and, for all , ; and we may cancel the universally quantified . So we have identified the monoid of endos of as that of affine maps such that and . Such an affine map preserves if and only if . In other words, the monoid of Euler reals may be identified with that of affine maps of the form with and, clearly, .
In any case, regardless of the preferred style of proof, Proposition 3.5 shows, roughly speaking, that the ‘radical’ and the ‘conservative’ versions of SDG are compatible.
Example 3.8 (Affine -schemes.).
Let be the opposite of the category of finitely generated -rings. As in the case of algebras over a field, for a finitely generated -ring we let be the corresponding object in . It is well-known that is a ring of line type in , so its underlying multiplicative monoid is a monoid of Euler reals by Propostion 3.5.
Recall that, in an extensive category, an object is said to be connected if it has exactly two complemented subobjects. For instance, the rings of line type in Examples 3.2 and 3.8 are connected. On the other hand:
Example 3.9 (Rings of line type need not be connected.).
It is known that the ring of line type in the Weil topos determined by a field is a coproduct indexed by . See [Koc06, Exercise III.11.4] pointing at the existence of non-constant endomorphisms of such that . See also [MM19, Proposition 6.3] where it is evident that, in the complex Weil topos, the set of points of is isomorphic to its set of connected components.
(A different approach to connectedness is that in [MR91, Section III.3] using internal topological spaces in well-adapted models of SDG, but we will not deal with that here.)
Even assuming that is connected, the subobject of invertibles may or may not be connected.
Example 3.10 ( may be connected.).
For any field , in , which is connected. We stress that need not be algebraically closed. In particular, is connected in . This may appear counter-intuitive but, in some sense, Algebraic Geometry over a field is not just about but also about its finite extensions so, intuitively, we might expect that displays some traits of the separable or algebraic closure of .
In contrast, consider the following.
Example 3.11 ( may be disconnected.).
It follows from [Koc06, Proposition III.6.7] that the embedding of manifolds into preserves the pullback
and, since the embedding sends to and to , we may conclude that
which is not connected in the extensive .
In order to continue our discussion it is convenient to recall the following restricted version of [Yet87, Definition 0.2].
Definition 3.12.
An object in is -discrete if is an isomorphism.
To capture the idea of a ‘discrete space of connected components’, the suggestion in [Law11] is to use a full reflective subcategory of of -discrete objects and such that the left adjoint preserves finite products. We will not make emphasis on -discrete objects. We will simply assume that we have a reflective subcategory whose left adjoint preserves finite products. Given such a reflective subcategory we may say that an object in is connected if .
Example 3.13 (Decidable affine -schemes.).
For a fixed base field , the full subcategory of decidable objects has a finite-product preserving left adjoint [DG70, I,§4, n 6]. In terms of algebras, the adjoint sends a finitely generated -algebra to its largest separable subalgebra. It follows that is connected in (i.e. ).
Example 3.13 may be lifted to toposes as in [Men14]. Again, see [Men21a] for analogous examples in the context of algebras with idempotent addition.
To recapitulate, let be an extensive category with finite limits and let be a full subcategory with finite-product preserving left adjoint . Let be a pointed object in with exponentiable and let be the associated monoid of Euler reals.
Proposition 3.14 ([Law11, Proposition 1]).
If is connected then, for every in , is an isomorphism. If is connected and has a retraction, the converse holds.
Proof 3.15.
Internal composition provides with a ‘pointed’ action and it is straightforward to check that it restricts to a pointed action . As preserves finite products it sends pointed actions (of ) in to pointed actions (of ) in . If is connected then in the monoid so the result follows. In more detail, the condition saying that acts as the identity means that the triangle on the right below commutes. ‘Pointedness’ means that the left square below commutes
where is the canonical section of , that is, the transposition of the projection . As preserves finite products, the diagram below
commutes in . If is connected (i.e. ) then the following diagram commutes
so the retraction is an isomorphism.
For the converse we have that by hypothesis. That is, is connected and, since retracts of connected objects are connected, the result follows.
In other words, under mild assumptions, is connected if and only if, for every space , the tangent bundle of has the same connected components as . (Notice that if is a ring of line type then the subobject appearing in the proof of Proposition 3.5 has a retraction needed to define derivatives.)
Rings of line type have always been commutative. Concerning monoids of Euler reals [Law11] says that “To justify that commutativity seems difficult, though intuitively it is related to the tinyness of , in the sense that even for slightly larger infinitesimal spaces, the (pointed) endomorphism monoid is non-commutative”.
Also, [Law11] briefly discusses two ways to insure that monoids of Euler reals have a unique addition. One via Integration, the other via trivial Lie algebras. The first one is to consider the subobject of the functionals such that for every , and then require that , so that addition “emerges as the unique homogeneous map which becomes the identity when restricted to both -induced axes .” The second one is to consider the kernel of which has a binary operation that may be called addition; “the space of endomorphisms of for that operation is a rig that contains (the right action of) as a multiplicative sub-monoid, so that if we postulate that exhausts the whole endomorphism space, then inherits a canonical addition”.
Assuming that the monoid underlies a ring structure, the simple result below is applied to derive, from a subgroup of , a pre-order on , meaning a subrig of ‘non-negative quantities’.
Proposition 3.16 ([Law11, Proposition 2]).
Given a subobject of a rig , let
and .
Then is an additive submonoid and so is a subrig. If then . If is a multiplicative subgroup then .
For example, if is the subobject of invertible elements then and . On the other hand, if then .
Lemma 3.17.
For as in Proposition 3.16 the following hold:
-
1.
If is a ring, and then .
-
2.
If then, the inclusion is an equality of subobjects if and only if is closed under multiplication.
Proof 3.18.
If then by Proposition 3.16 so, if then and hence . One direction of the second item is trivial. For the other, assume that is closed under multiplication. Then, for every , so .
Let be the subobject of invertible elements and let the following square
be a pullback, where is the unit of as a subobject of . Since is a subgroup of , and preserves products, is also a group and is the kernel of the group morphism .
The map may be an isomorphism and, in this case, is also an isomorphism, of course. We are mainly interested in contexts where this is not the case.
Definition 3.19.
The monoid is bi-directional if .
So, assuming that the monoid of Euler reals underlies a ring, we may apply Proposition 3.16 to the subgroup in order to obtain a subrig . The ‘real’ intuition suggests that it is not unnatural to require or expect that ; in other words, . Then the first item of Lemma 3.17 implies that , unless in .
Readers are invited to compare the above with the efforts in [Koc06, MR91] to prove that the pre-orders defined on certain rings of line type there are compatible with the ring operations. We should also remark that some of those efforts will play a role below when the time comes to give a simple description of the subrigs derived radically synthetically.
4 A bi-directional monoid of Euler reals
Let be a geometric morphism. Recall that is hyperconnected if is fully faithful and the counit of is monic. Intuitively, is a category of spaces, is the full subcategory of discrete spaces, and the right adjoint sends a space to the associated discrete space of points. For a space , the monic may be thought of as the discrete subspace of points.
In perspective, we may say that is pre-cohesive if it is hyperconnected, is cartesian closed and preserves coequalizers. It follows [Men21b] that has a (necessarily fully faithful) right adjoint and that has a left adjoint that preserves finite products. Hence, is pre-cohesive if and only if extends to a string of adjoints such that is fully faithful, the counit of is monic and the leftmost adjoint preserves finite products. It follows that the reflector is epic. Sometimes we say that is pre-cohesive over .
For any pre-cohesive , the fact that the canonical is an epimorphism is consistent with the intuition that every connected component has a point. In particular, if then . In other words, if the space has a unique point then it is connected.
The purpose of this section is to build a pre-cohesive topos and a (necessarily connected) object in such that , and such that the resulting monoid of Euler reals is bi-directional. Moreover, it will be evident from the construction that underlies a ring of line-type.
Pre-cohesion will follow from the next result borrowed from [Joh11]. (See also [Men14, Proposition 2.10] for a statement consistent with our terminology.)
Proposition 4.1.
Let be a small category with terminal object. Then is pre-cohesive if and only if every object in has a point.
Now recall Remark 3.4 and let be the full subcategory of connected objects that have a point. The category is essentially small but contains many objects of interest. It certainly has a terminal object. Also, germ-determined -rings have a copoint almost by definition ([Koc06, Exercise III.7.1]), so every non-trivial germ-determined finitely-generated -ring with exactly two idempotents determines an object in .
In particular, for any manifold , is finitely-presentable and germ-determined (in fact, point-determined) by [Koc06, Theorem III.6.6 and Corollary III.5.10]. Moreover, if is connected then has exactly two idempotents by the Intermediate Value Theorem. Altogether, for any connected manifold , determines an object of .
Also, every Weil algebra (over ) is a finitely presentable -ring by [Koc06, Proposition III.5.11] and hence determines an object in .
Let be the object in determined by the Weil algebra . Of course, it has a unique point, and we denote it by .
Lemma 4.2.
For any in , the product in is also in .
Proof 4.3.
The forgetful functor reflects coproducts with Weil algebras by [Koc06, Theorem III.5.3]. More precisely, if is a -ring and is a Weil algebra then there is a unique -ring structure on extending its -algebra structure such that is a coproduct in . In particular, . So, if is finitely generated, or has exactly two idempotents, or has a copoint, then so does . Therefore, if determines an object in then so does the coproduct .
By the remarks above, the object is in the subcategory . The product
is also in , so is a ring object in .
Proposition 4.4.
The canonical is pre-cohesive and the monoid of Euler reals determined by in is bi-directional. Moreover, that monoid coincides with (the multiplicative part of) the ring which is connected and satisfies the KL-axiom.
Proof 4.5.
By definition, the category has a terminal object and every object in it has a point, so is pre-cohesive by Proposition 4.1.
The quotient in determines a monomorphism in . In fact, it is the subobject of elements of square zero. Moreover, by Lemma 4.2 we can repeat the usual proof that the KL-axiom holds. Indeed, for any in ,
as usual. Proposition 3.5 implies that the monoid of Euler reals determined by coincides with the multiplicative part of . Moreover, is connected because it is representable.
As observed in Example 3.11, the subobject of invertibles in coincides with . The domain of this subobject is not an object in , but the summands are. Then
in . So because in is a coproduct of two representables.
It is clear from the proof of Proposition 4.4 that in . Then and so, by the remarks following Lemma 3.17, we obtain a subrig inside the complement of . I have not found an illuminating expression of this subrig though. In the next section we consider a smaller topos, also with a bi-directional , but where has a simple description.
5 W-determination and the Positiv-stellen-satz
In this section we construct another bi-directional ring of line type but in a topos where the induced pre-order is easier to describe explicitly in terms of the site.
A -ring is W-determined if the family of maps in with Weil codomain is jointly monic.
W-determined -rings are called near-point determined in [MR91].
Let be the full subcategory induced by the objects in that are W-determined as -rings. It follows from the discussion following [Koc06, Theorem III.9.4] that every connected manifold with boundary determines an object in . Moreover, this assignment is functorial.
Proposition 5.1.
The canonical is pre-cohesive and the monoid of Euler reals induced by in is bi-directional. Moreover, this monoid coincides with (the multiplicative part of) the ring which is connected and satisfies the KL-axiom.
Proof 5.2.
It is enough to check that has all the properties needed to mimic Proposition 4.4. It certainly contains all the objects induced by connected manifolds and also those induced by Weil algebras. In particular, it contains the object . So the main problem is to extend Lemma 4.2 by showing that is closed under products with , but this follows from [MR91, Proposition I.4.6 and Lemma II.1.15].
Let where is the ideal of functions that vanish on .
Proposition 5.3 (Positiv-Stellen-Satz.).
Let be a finite set and let be a regular epimorphism in with W-determined codomain. If we let be the kernel of then, for any smooth , the following are equivalent:
-
1.
The restriction of the smooth to factors through , where .
-
2.
The composite
factors through .
Proof 5.4.
Use the proof of [Koc06, Lemma III.11.4].
The -ring is W-determined by the remarks in [Koc06, p.185]. The corresponding object in will be denoted by . So the quotient induces a monomorphism in .
Let be the usual ‘points’ functor.
Corollary 5.5.
For every in , factors through the subobject if and only if factors through .
Proof 5.6.
The object equals for some finitely generated and W-determined -ring . So there is a finite set and a regular epimorphism . The map corresponds to a map and, since the domain of this map is projective, there exists a smooth such that the following triangle
commutes in . By Proposition 5.3, factors through if and only if the restriction of to factors through where is the kernel of . But this holds if and only if the left-bottom composite below
factors through the right subobject as depicted above, so the result follows.
For a connected manifold we let . To complete our calculation we need another standard result that we reformulate as follows.
Lemma 5.7.
For any connected manifold , the product of and exists in and it corresponds to where is the ideal of functions that vanish on .
Proof 5.8.
This follows from the proof of [Koc06, Theorem III.9.5] (and the fact that, for connected , has exactly two idempotents).
Recall that is the subobject of invertibles, that is the kernel of and that is the subrig determined by bi-directionality of .
Theorem 5.9.
In the topos , the subrig coincides with .
Proof 5.10.
Consider first . To check that is enough, by Lemma 5.7, to show that the composite
factors through , but this follows from the embedding of connected manifolds with boundary in and the fact that the composite
factors through there.
To prove that let in and let in factor through . It follows that, for every and , the composite
factors through . In other words, the composite
factors through . Then factors through . So factors through by Corollary 5.5. This completes the proof that as subobjects of .
Certainly, factors through so, by Lemma 3.17, it only remains to check that the subobject is closed under multiplication. That is, we need to prove that the composite
factors through . So let in and let in . Then the composite
clearly factors through , because the restricted multiplication does. Hence, for every as above, the composite
factors through in by Corollary 5.5. Therefore the composite
does factor through as we needed to prove.
References
- [AGV72] M. Artin, A. Grothendieck, and J. L. Verdier. Théorie de topos et cohomologie étale des schémas, volume 269-270 of Lecture notes in mathematics. Springer-Verlag, 1972. (SGA4).
- [Bel98] J. L. Bell. A primer of infinitesimal analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
- [BGSLF18] M. Bunge, F. Gago, and A. M. San Luis Fernández. Synthetic differential topology, volume 448 of Lond. Math. Soc. Lect. Note Ser. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2018.
- [CC14] J. R. B. Cockett and G. S. H. Cruttwell. Differential structure, tangent structure, and SDG. Appl. Categ. Struct., 22(2):331–417, 2014.
- [DG70] M. Demazure and P. Gabriel. Groupes algébriques. Tome I: Géométrie algébrique, généralités, groupes commutatifs. Masson & Cie, Éditeur, Paris, 1970. Avec un appendice Corps de classes local par Michiel Hazewinkel.
- [Dub79] E. J. Dubuc. Sur les modeles de la géométrie différentielle synthetique. Cah. Topologie Géom. Différ. Catégoriques, 20:231–279, 1979.
- [Joh11] P. T. Johnstone. Remarks on punctual local connectedness. Theory Appl. Categ., 25:51–63, 2011.
- [Koc77] A. Kock. A simple axiomatics for differentiation. Math. Scand., 40:183–193, 1977.
- [Koc06] A. Kock. Synthetic differential geometry. 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2nd ed. edition, 2006.
- [Koc10] A. Kock. Synthetic geometry of manifolds, volume 180 of Camb. Tracts Math. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010.
- [Lav96] R. Lavendhomme. Basic concepts of synthetic differential geometry. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1996.
- [Law] F. W. Lawvere. Outline of synthetic differential geometry. Notes of the February 1998 talks in the Buffalo Geometry Seminar. With corrections (Nov. 1998). Available from Lawvere’s webpage.
- [Law79] F. W. Lawvere. Categorical dynamics. Var. Publ. Ser., Aarhus Univ., 30:1–28, 1979.
- [Law05] F. W. Lawvere. Categories of spaces may not be generalized spaces as exemplified by directed graphs. Repr. Theory Appl. Categ., 9:1–7, 2005. Reprinted from Rev. Colombiana Mat. 20 (1986), no. 3-4, 179–185.
- [Law07] F. W. Lawvere. Axiomatic cohesion. Theory Appl. Categ., 19:41–49, 2007.
- [Law11] F. W. Lawvere. Euler’s continuum functorially vindicated. In Logic, Mathematics, Philosophy: Vintage Enthusiasms, volume 75 of The Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science, pages 249–254. Springer Science+Bussiness Media B. V., 2011.
- [Men14] M. Menni. Sufficient cohesion over atomic toposes. Cah. Topol. Géom. Différ. Catég., 55(2):113–149, 2014.
- [Men21a] M. Menni. A Basis Theorem for 2-rigs and Rig Geometry. Cah. Topol. Géom. Différ. Catég., 62(4):451–490, 2021.
- [Men21b] M. Menni. The hyperconnected maps that are local. J. Pure Appl. Algebra, 225(5):15, 2021. Id/No 106596.
- [MM19] F. Marmolejo and M. Menni. Level . Cah. Topol. Géom. Différ. Catég., 60(4):450–477, 2019.
- [MR91] I. Moerdijk and G. E. Reyes. Models for smooth infinitesimal analysis. Springer-Verlag, New York, 1991.
- [Ros84] J. Rosický. Abstract tangent functors. Diagrammes 12, 1984.
- [Yet87] D. Yetter. On right adjoints to exponential functors. J. Pure Appl. Algebra, 45:287–304, 1987.