This paper was converted on www.awesomepapers.org from LaTeX by an anonymous user.
Want to know more? Visit the Converter page.

Bad list assignments for non-kk-choosable kk-chromatic graphs with 2k+22k+2-vertices

Jialu Zhu Department of Mathematics, Zhejiang Normal University, Email:[email protected],    Xuding Zhu Department of Mathematics, Zhejiang Normal University, Email: [email protected], Grant numbers: NSFC 11971438,U20A2068, ZJNSFC LD19A010001.
Abstract

It was conjectured by Ohba, and proved by Noel, Reed and Wu that kk-chromatic graphs GG with |V(G)|2k+1|V(G)|\leq 2k+1 are chromatic-choosable. This upper bound on |V(G)||V(G)| is tight: if kk is even, then K3(k/2+1),1(k/21)K_{3\star(k/2+1),1\star(k/2-1)} and K4,2(k1)K_{4,2\star(k-1)} are kk-chromatic graphs with 2k+22k+2 vertices that are not chromatic-choosable. It was proved in [Zhu and Zhu, Minimum Non-chromatic choosable graphs with given chromatic number, arXiv:2201.02060] that these are the only non-kk-choosable complete kk-partite graphs with 2k+22k+2 vertices. For G{K3(k/2+1),1(k/21),K4,2(k1)}G\in\{K_{3\star(k/2+1),1\star(k/2-1)},K_{4,2\star(k-1)}\}, a bad list assignment of GG is a kk-list assignment LL of GG such that GG is not LL-colourable. Bad list assignments for G=K4,2(k1)G=K_{4,2\star(k-1)} were characterized in [Enomoto, Ohba, Ota and Sakamoto, Choice number of some complete multi-partite graphs, Discrete Mathematics 244 (2002) 55–66]. In this paper, we first give a simpler proof of this result, and then we characterize bad list assignments for G=K3(k/2+1),1(k/21)G=K_{3\star(k/2+1),1\star(k/2-1)}. Using these results, we characterize all non-kk-choosable (non-complete) kk-partite graphs with 2k+22k+2 vertices.

Keywords: chromatic-choosable graphs, Ohba conjecture, bad list assignment.

1 Introduction

A proper colouring of a graph GG is a mapping f:V(G)f:V(G)\rightarrow\mathbb{N} such that f(u)f(v)f(u)\neq f(v) for every edge uvuv of E(G)E(G). The chromatic number χ(G)\chi(G) of GG is the minimum kk such that GG has a proper kk-colouring, i.e., a proper colouring ff with |f(V(G))|k|f(V(G))|\leq k. A kk-list assignment of a graph GG is a mapping LL which assigns to each vertex vv a set L(v)L(v) of at least kk permissible colours, i.e., |L(v)|k|L(v)|\geq k. An LL-colouring of GG is a proper colouring of GG which colours each vertex vv with a colour from L(v)L(v). We say that GG is LL-colourable if there exists an LL-colouring of GG, and GG is kk-choosable if GG is LL-colourable for each kk-list assignment LL of GG. More generally, for a function f:V(G)f:V(G)\to\mathbb{N}, an ff-list assignment of GG is a list assignment LL with |L(v)|f(v)|L(v)|\geq f(v) for all vV(G)v\in V(G). We say GG is ff-choosable if GG is LL-colourable for every ff-list assignment LL of GG. The choice number ch(G){\rm ch}(G) of GG is the minimum kk for which GG is kk-choosable. List colouring of graphs was introduced independently by Erdős-Rubin-Taylor [3] and Vizing [16], and has been studied extensively in the literature (cf. [15]).

It follows from the definitions that χ(G)ch(G)\chi(G)\leq ch(G) for any graph GG, and it is well-known [3] that bipartite graphs can have arbitrarily large choice number. A graph GG is called chromatic-choosable if χ(G)=ch(G)\chi(G)=ch(G). Some families of graphs are conjectured or proven to be chromatic-choosable. For example, the list colouring conjecture, proposed independently by Albertson and Collins, Gupta, and Vizing (see [6]), asserts that line graphs are chromatic-choosable. This conjecture was proved for bipartite graphs [4], for complete graphs of odd order [6] and for complete graphs of order p+1p+1 for primes pp [14]. Also it was conjectured by Ohba [12] and proved by Noel, Reed and Wu [11] that kk-chromatic graphs GG with |V(G)|2χ(G)+1|V(G)|\leq 2\chi(G)+1 are chromatic-choosable. We shall refer this result as Noel-Reed-Wu Theorem in the remainder of this paper.

We denote by Kk1n1,k2n2,,kqnqK_{k_{1}\star n_{1},k_{2}\star n_{2},\ldots,k_{q}\star n_{q}} the complete multi-partite graph with nin_{i} partite sets of size kik_{i}, for i=1,2,,qi=1,2,\ldots,q. If nj=1n_{j}=1, then the number njn_{j} is omitted from the notation. For example, K4,2(k1)K_{4,2\star(k-1)} is the complete kk-partite graph with one partite set of size 44, and k1k-1 partite sets of size 22. It was proved in [2] that if kk is an even integer, then K4,2(k1)K_{4,2\star(k-1)} and K3(k/2+1),1(k/21)K_{3\star(k/2+1),1\star(k/2-1)} are not kk-choosable.

So Noel-Reed-Wu Theorem is tight, when χ(G)\chi(G) is even. Noel [9] conjectured that if kk is odd, then the bound is not tight, i.e., all kk-chromatic graphs with 2k+22k+2 vertices are kk-choosable. This conjecture was confirmed in [17], where the following result was proved.

Theorem 1.1

If GG is a complete kk-partite non-kk-choosable graph with 2k+22k+2 vertices, then kk is even and G=K4,2(k1)G=K_{4,2\star(k-1)} or G=K3(k/2+1),1(k/21)G=K_{3\star(k/2+1),1\star(k/2-1)}.

Thus any kk-chromatic non-kk-choosable graph with 2k+22k+2 vertices is a spanning subgraph of G=K4,2(k1)G=K_{4,2\star(k-1)} or G=K3(k/2+1),1(k/21)G=K_{3\star(k/2+1),1\star(k/2-1)}, and kk is an even integer.

For G=K4,2(k1)G=K_{4,2\star(k-1)} or G=K3(k/2+1),1(k/21)G=K_{3\star(k/2+1),1\star(k/2-1)}, a bad list assignment of GG is a kk-list assignment LL of GG such that GG is not LL-colourable. Bad list assignments for G=K4,2(k1)G=K_{4,2\star(k-1)} were characterized in [2]. We shall give a simpler proof of this result. Then we characterize bad list assignments for G=K3(k/2+1),1(k/21)G=K_{3\star(k/2+1),1\star(k/2-1)}: If k4k\geq 4, then a kk-list assignment LL of G=K3(k/2+1),1(k/21)G=K_{3\star(k/2+1),1\star(k/2-1)} is bad if and only if

  • |vV(G)L(v)|=32k|\bigcup_{v\in V(G)}L(v)|=\frac{3}{2}k,

  • for each 33-part PP of GG, vPL(v)=\bigcap_{v\in P}L(v)=\emptyset.

If k=2k=2, then a kk-list assignment LL of K3,3K_{3,3} is bad if and only if it is isomorphic to one of the list assignments in Figure 1.

As a consequence, we characterize all non-kk-choosable kk-chromatic graphs with 2k+22k+2 vertices.

Corollary 1.2

For k3k\geq 3, every kk-chromatic non-kk-choosable graph GG with 2k+22k+2 vertices satisfies K4¯(2kk1)GK4,2(k1)\overline{K_{4}}\vee(2k_{k-1})\subseteq G\subseteq K_{4,2\star(k-1)}, where kk is even, K4¯(2kk1)\overline{K_{4}}\vee(2k_{k-1}) is the join of K4¯\overline{K_{4}}, an independent set of size 44, and 2Kk12K_{k-1}, which is the disjoint union of two copies of Kk1K_{k-1}.

2 Some notation and preliminaries

Assume that G=K4,2(k1)G=K_{4,2\star(k-1)} or G=K3(k/2+1),1(k/21)G=K_{3\star(k/2+1),1\star(k/2-1)}, and LL is a bad kk-list assignment of GG.

For a subset XX of V(G)V(G), let

L(X)=vXL(v).L(X)=\bigcup_{v\in X}L(v).

Let C=L(V(G))C=L(V(G)). It was proved in [7] that if LL is a bad list assignment of GG with |C||C| minimum, then |C|<|V(G)||C|<|V(G)|. We observe that by the same argument, without assuming the minimality of |C||C|, the conclusion still holds for bad list assignments of GG. Indeed, if |C||V(G)||C|\geq|V(G)|, then we let XX be a maximum subset of V(G)V(G) with |X|>|L(X)||X|>|L(X)| (it is possible that X=X=\emptyset). As |V(G)||C||V(G)|\leq|C|, we know that XV(G)X\neq V(G). Thus |X|2k+1|X|\leq 2k+1 and by Noel-Wu-Reed Theorem, we have G[X]G[X] is LL-colourable. The maximality of XX implies that for any YV(G)XY\subseteq V(G)-X, |L(Y)L(X)||Y||L(Y)-L(X)|\geq|Y|. By Hall ’s Theorem, there is an injective colouring ff of GXG-X such that for each vertex vv, f(v)L(v)L(X)f(v)\in L(v)-L(X). Hence GG is LL-colourable.

Each partite set of GG is called a part of GG, and a part of size ii (respectively, at least ii or at most ii) is called a ii-part (respectively,i+i^{+}-part, or ii^{-}-part).

For each 3+3^{+}-part PP of GG, let

tP=max{|L(u)L(v)|:uv,u,vP}.t_{P}=\max\{|L(u)\cap L(v)|:u\neq v,u,v\in P\}.

For cCc\in C and CCC^{\prime}\subseteq C, let

L1(c)={v:cL(v)},L1(C)=cCL1(c).L^{-1}(c)=\{v:c\in L(v)\},\ L^{-1}(C^{\prime})=\bigcup_{c\in C^{\prime}}L^{-1}(c).

For a part PP of GG and integer ii, let

CP,i={cC:|L1(c)P|=i},CP,i+={cC:|L1(c)P|i}.C_{P,i}=\{c\in C:|L^{-1}(c)\cap P|=i\},C_{P,i^{+}}=\{c\in C:|L^{-1}(c)\cap P|\geq i\}.
Definition 1

Assume 𝒮\mathcal{S} is a partition of V(G)V(G), in which each part S𝒮S\in\mathcal{S} is an independent set. We denote by G/𝒮G/\mathcal{S} the graph obtained from GG by identifying each part S𝒮S\in\mathcal{S} into a single vertex vSv_{S}. Let L𝒮L_{\mathcal{S}} be the list assignment of G/𝒮G/\mathcal{S} defined as L𝒮(vS)=vSL(v)L_{\mathcal{S}}(v_{S})=\bigcap_{v\in S}L(v).

If S={v}𝒮S=\{v\}\in\mathcal{S} is a singleton part of 𝒮\mathcal{S}, then we may also denote vSv_{S} by vv. In this case, L𝒮(v)=L(v)L_{\mathcal{S}}(v)=L(v). In the partitions 𝒮\mathcal{S} constructed in this paper, most parts of 𝒮\mathcal{S} are singleton parts. To define 𝒮\mathcal{S}, it suffices to list its non-singleton parts.

Definition 2

Let B𝒮B_{\mathcal{S}} be the bipartite graph with partite sets V(G/𝒮)V(G/\mathcal{S}) and CC, in which {vS,c}\{v_{S},c\} is an edge if and only if cL𝒮(vS)c\in L_{\mathcal{S}}(v_{S}).

It is obvious that a matching MM in B𝒮B_{\mathcal{S}} covering V(G/𝒮)V(G/\mathcal{S}) induces a proper L𝒮L_{\mathcal{S}}-colouring of G/𝒮G/\mathcal{S}, which in turn induces a proper LL-colouring of GG. As GG is not LL-colourable, no such matching MM exists. By Hall’s Theorem, there is a subset X𝒮X_{\mathcal{S}} of V(G/𝒮)V(G/\mathcal{S}) such that |X𝒮|>|NB𝒮(X𝒮)||X_{\mathcal{S}}|>|N_{B_{\mathcal{S}}}(X_{\mathcal{S}})|.

In the remainder of the paper, for a given partition 𝒮\mathcal{S} of V(G)V(G), let X𝒮X_{\mathcal{S}} be a maximum subset of V(G/𝒮)V(G/\mathcal{S}) for which |X𝒮|>|NB𝒮(X𝒮)||X_{\mathcal{S}}|>|N_{B_{\mathcal{S}}}(X_{\mathcal{S}})|. Let

Y𝒮=NB𝒮(X𝒮)=vSX𝒮L𝒮(vS).Y_{\mathcal{S}}=N_{B_{\mathcal{S}}}(X_{\mathcal{S}})=\bigcup_{v_{S}\in X_{\mathcal{S}}}L_{\mathcal{S}}(v_{S}).
Observation 2.1

The following facts will be used often in this paper.

  1. (1)

    No two vertices in the same part of GG have the same list, and no colour is contained only in the lists of vertices in a same part. Thus for any part PP of GG, vV(G)PL(v)=C\bigcup_{v\in V(G)-P}L(v)=C.

  2. (2)

    Each 2+2^{+}-part has no common colour.

Proof. (1) is trivial.

(2) Assume PP is a 2+2^{+}-part of GG with vPL(v)\bigcap_{v\in P}L(v)\neq\emptyset, say cvPL(v)c\in\bigcap_{v\in P}L(v). We colour all vertices of PP by colour cc. Let G=GPG^{\prime}=G-P and L(v)=L(v){c}L^{\prime}(v)=L(v)-\{c\} for any vertex vv of GG^{\prime}. As |V(G)|2χ(G)+2|V(G^{\prime})|\leq 2\chi(G^{\prime})+2 and χ(G)=k1\chi(G^{\prime})=k-1 is odd, it follows from Theorem 1.1 that GG^{\prime} is LL^{\prime}-colourable, and hence GG is LL-colourable, a contradiction.  

The following lemma was proved in [17] and also will be used in this paper.

Lemma 2.2

Let GG be a complete multipartite graph with parts of size at most 33. Let 𝒜,\mathcal{A}, 𝒟\mathcal{D}, \mathcal{B}, 𝒞\mathcal{C} be a partition of the set of parts of GG into classes such that 𝒜\mathcal{A} and 𝒟\mathcal{D} contains only parts of size 11, while \mathcal{B} contains all parts of size 22 and 𝒞\mathcal{C} contains all parts of size 33. Let k1,d,k2,k3k_{1},d,k_{2},k_{3} denote the cardinalities of classes 𝒜\mathcal{A}, 𝒟\mathcal{D}, \mathcal{B}, 𝒞\mathcal{C} respectively. Suppose that classes 𝒜\mathcal{A} and 𝒟\mathcal{D} are ordered, i.e. 𝒜=(A1,,Ak1)\mathcal{A}=(A_{1},\ldots,A_{k_{1}}) and 𝒟=(D1,,Dd)\mathcal{D}=(D_{1},\ldots,D_{d}). If f:V(G)f:V(G)\to\mathbb{N} is a function for which the following conditions hold

f(v)\displaystyle f(v) k2+k3+i,\displaystyle\geq k_{2}+k_{3}+i, for all 1ik11\leq i\leq k_{1} and vAiv\in A_{i} (a-1)
f(v)\displaystyle f(v) 2k3+k2+k1+i,\displaystyle\geq 2k_{3}+k_{2}+k_{1}+i, for all 1id1\leq i\leq d and vDiv\in D_{i} (d-1)
f(v)\displaystyle f(v) k2+k3,\displaystyle\geq k_{2}+k_{3}, for all vBv\in B\in\mathcal{B} (b-1)
f(u)+f(v)\displaystyle f(u)+f(v) 3k3+2k2+k1+d,\displaystyle\geq 3k_{3}+2k_{2}+k_{1}+d, for all u,vBu,v\in B\in\mathcal{B} (b-2)
f(v)\displaystyle f(v) k2+k3,\displaystyle\geq k_{2}+k_{3}, for all vC𝒞v\in C\in\mathcal{C} (c-1)
f(u)+f(v)\displaystyle f(u)+f(v) 2k3+2k2+k1,\displaystyle\geq 2k_{3}+2k_{2}+k_{1}, for all u,vC𝒞u,v\in C\in\mathcal{C} (c-2)
vCf(v)\displaystyle\sum_{v\in C}f(v) 4k3+3k2+2k1+d1,\displaystyle\geq 4k_{3}+3k_{2}+2k_{1}+d-1, for all C𝒞C\in\mathcal{C} (c-3)

then GG is ff-choosable.

3 Bad list assignments for K4,2(k1)K_{4,2\star(k-1)}

The following theorem is the characterization of bad list assignments of K4,2(k1)K_{4,2\star(k-1)} which has been proved in [2]. In this section, we give an alternate (and shorter) proof of this theorem.

Theorem 3.1

Assume LL is a bad kk-list assignment of G=K4,2(k1)G=K_{4,2\star(k-1)}. Assume P1={u1,v1,x1,y1}P_{1}=\{u_{1},v_{1},x_{1},y_{1}\} and Pi={ui,vi}P_{i}=\{u_{i},v_{i}\} for 2ik2\leq i\leq k and C=vV(G)L(v)C=\bigcup_{v\in V(G)}L(v). Then CC can be partitioned into AA and BB with |A|=|B|=k|A|=|B|=k, where AA can be further partitioned into A1,A2,A3,A4A_{1},A_{2},A_{3},A_{4} such that |A1|=|A2||A_{1}|=|A_{2}|, |A3|=|A4||A_{3}|=|A_{4}| (where A3,A4A_{3},A_{4} maybe empty), and BB can be further partitioned into B1,B2B_{1},B_{2} with |B1|=|B2||B_{1}|=|B_{2}|, and the following hold:

  • L(u1)=A1A3B1L(u_{1})=A_{1}\cup A_{3}\cup B_{1}, L(v1)=A1A4B2L(v_{1})=A_{1}\cup A_{4}\cup B_{2}, L(x1)=A2A4B1L(x_{1})=A_{2}\cup A_{4}\cup B_{1}, L(y1)=A2A3B2L(y_{1})=A_{2}\cup A_{3}\cup B_{2}.

  • L(ui)=AL(u_{i})=A, L(vi)=BL(v_{i})=B for 2ik2\leq i\leq k.

Proof. If there is a colour cCc\in C such that |L1(c)P1|3|L^{-1}(c)\cap P_{1}|\geq 3, then we colour vertices L1(c)P1L^{-1}(c)\cap P_{1} by colour cc. Let G=G(L1(c)P1)G^{\prime}=G-(L^{-1}(c)\cap P_{1}) and L(v)=L(v){c}L^{\prime}(v)=L(v)-\{c\} for vV(G)v\in V(G^{\prime}). It is easy to verify that GG^{\prime} and LL^{\prime} satisfy the condition of Lemma 2.2 (here we need to use the fact that any 2-part PP has a vertex vv with cL(v)c\notin L(v), see (2) of Observation 2.1). Therefore GG^{\prime} is LL^{\prime}-colourable, and hence GG is LL-colourable, a contradiction.

Thus |L1(c)P1|2|L^{-1}(c)\cap P_{1}|\leq 2 for any cCc\in C. By (2) of Observation 2.1, we have |C|2k|C|\geq 2k. Recall that |C||V(G)|1=2k+1|C|\leq|V(G)|-1=2k+1. Depending on the size of CC, we consider two cases.

Case 1 |C|=2k+1|C|=2k+1.

Since |C|=2k+1|C|=2k+1 and |L(u1)|+|L(v1)|+|L(x1)|+|L(y1)|4k|L(u_{1})|+|L(v_{1})|+|L(x_{1})|+|L(y_{1})|\geq 4k, we may assume L(u1)L(v1)L(u_{1})\cap L(v_{1})\neq\emptyset. Let 𝒮\mathcal{S} be the partition of V(G)V(G) with one non-singleton part S={u1,v1}S=\{u_{1},v_{1}\}, and consider the graph G/𝒮G/\mathcal{S} and list assignment L𝒮L_{\mathcal{S}}. Let X𝒮X_{\mathcal{S}} and Y𝒮Y_{\mathcal{S}} be as defined in Section 2. We denote by PiP^{\prime}_{i} be the parts of G/𝒮G/\mathcal{S}.

It is obvious that X𝒮{vS}X_{\mathcal{S}}-\{v_{S}\}\neq\emptyset, and hence |Y𝒮||L(v)|k|Y_{\mathcal{S}}|\geq|L(v)|\geq k for vX𝒮{vS}v\in X_{\mathcal{S}}-\{v_{S}\}. Hence |X𝒮|k+1|X_{\mathcal{S}}|\geq k+1. If there is an index i2i\geq 2 such that PiX𝒮P^{\prime}_{i}\subseteq X_{\mathcal{S}}, then |Y𝒮||L(ui)|+|L(vi)|2k|Y_{\mathcal{S}}|\geq|L^{\prime}(u_{i})|+|L^{\prime}(v_{i})|\geq 2k and hence |X𝒮|=|V(G/𝒮)|=2k+1|X_{\mathcal{S}}|=|V(G/\mathcal{S})|=2k+1. But in this case, by Observation 2.1, |Y𝒮|=|C|=2k+1=|X𝒮||Y_{\mathcal{S}}|=|C|=2k+1=|X_{\mathcal{S}}|, a contradiction.

So |PiX|1|P^{\prime}_{i}\cap X|\leq 1 for i2i\geq 2, and hence |X𝒮|k+2|X_{\mathcal{S}}|\leq k+2. Since |X𝒮|k+1|X_{\mathcal{S}}|\geq k+1, |X𝒮P1|2|X_{\mathcal{S}}\cap P^{\prime}_{1}|\geq 2. This implies that |Y𝒮|k+1|Y_{\mathcal{S}}|\geq k+1 and hence |X𝒮|=k+2|X_{\mathcal{S}}|=k+2, i.e., P1XP^{\prime}_{1}\subseteq X. So |Y𝒮||L(vS)|+|L(x1)L(y1)|1+k+1=k+2=|X𝒮||Y_{\mathcal{S}}|\geq|L^{\prime}(v_{S})|+|L^{\prime}(x_{1})\cup L^{\prime}(y_{1})|\geq 1+k+1=k+2=|X_{\mathcal{S}}|, a contradiction.

Case 2 |C|=2k|C|=2k.

As |CP1,1|+2|CP1,2|=vP1|L(v)|=4k|C_{P_{1},1}|+2|C_{P_{1},2}|=\sum_{v\in P_{1}}|L(v)|=4k and |CP1,1|+|CP1,2||C||C_{P_{1},1}|+|C_{P_{1},2}|\leq|C|, we conclude that |CP1,2|=2k|C_{P_{1},2}|=2k, i.e., CP1,2=CC_{P_{1},2}=C.

Claim 3.2

For any 2-subset UU of P1P_{1}, |vUL(v)|=|vP1UL(v)||\bigcap_{v\in U}L(v)|=|\bigcap_{v\in P_{1}-U}L(v)|.

Proof. Assume UU is a 2-subset of P1P_{1}. Then (vUL(v))(vP1UL(v))=(\bigcap_{v\in U}L(v))\cap(\bigcup_{v\in P_{1}-U}L(v))=\emptyset. So

2k=|C||vUL(v)|+|vP1UL(v)|=|vUL(v)|+2k|vP1UL(v)|.2k=|C|\geq|\bigcap_{v\in U}L(v)|+|\bigcup_{v\in P_{1}-U}L(v)|=|\bigcap_{v\in U}L(v)|+2k-|\bigcap_{v\in P_{1}-U}L(v)|.

Hence |vUL(v)||vP1UL(v)||\bigcap_{v\in U}L(v)|\leq|\bigcap_{v\in P_{1}-U}L(v)|. By symmetry, |vP1UL(v)||vUL(v)||\bigcap_{v\in P_{1}-U}L(v)|\leq|\bigcap_{v\in U}L(v)|. So |vUL(v)|=|vP1UL(v)||\bigcap_{v\in U}L(v)|=|\bigcap_{v\in P_{1}-U}L(v)|.  

Claim 3.3

Assume UU is a 2-subset of P1P_{1} with vUL(v)\bigcap_{v\in U}L(v)\neq\emptyset. Then there is a kk-subset YUY_{U} of CC and a (k1)(k-1)-subset SUS_{U} of V(G)V(G) such that for i=2,3,,ki=2,3,\ldots,k, |SUPi|=1|S_{U}\cap P_{i}|=1 and

L(SUPi)=L(SU)(vUL(v))(vP1UL(v))=YU.L(S_{U}\cap P_{i})=L(S_{U})\cup(\bigcap_{v\in U}L(v))\cup(\bigcap_{v\in P_{1}-U}L(v))=Y_{U}.

Proof. Assume U={u1,v1}U=\{u_{1},v_{1}\} and L(u1)L(v1)L(u_{1})\cap L(v_{1})\neq\emptyset. By Claim 3.2, we know that L(x1)L(y1)L(x_{1})\cap L(y_{1})\neq\emptyset. Let 𝒮\mathcal{S} be the partition of V(G)V(G) whose non-singleton parts are S={u1,v1},T={x1,y1}S=\{u_{1},v_{1}\},T=\{x_{1},y_{1}\}.

It is easy to see that X𝒮{vS,vT}X_{\mathcal{S}}-\{v_{S},v_{T}\}\neq\emptyset. Hence |Y𝒮||L(v)|k|Y_{\mathcal{S}}|\geq|L(v)|\geq k for some vX𝒮{vS,vT}v\in X_{\mathcal{S}}-\{v_{S},v_{T}\}. This implies that |X𝒮|k+1|X_{\mathcal{S}}|\geq k+1. If |X𝒮|>k+1|X_{\mathcal{S}}|>k+1, then PiXP_{i}\subseteq X for some 2ik2\leq i\leq k, and hence |Y𝒮|2k=|V(G/𝒮)||X𝒮||Y_{\mathcal{S}}|\geq 2k=|V(G/\mathcal{S})|\geq|X_{\mathcal{S}}|, a contradiction. So |X𝒮|=k+1|X_{\mathcal{S}}|=k+1 and k=|Y𝒮|k=|Y_{\mathcal{S}}|. This implies that P1X𝒮P^{\prime}_{1}\subseteq X_{\mathcal{S}} and |X𝒮Pi|=1|X_{\mathcal{S}}\cap P_{i}|=1 for 2ik2\leq i\leq k. Let SU=X𝒮{vS,vT}S_{U}=X_{\mathcal{S}}-\{v_{S},v_{T}\} and YU=Y𝒮Y_{U}=Y_{\mathcal{S}}. We have L(SU)(vUL(v))(vP1UL(v))=YU.L(S_{U})\cup(\bigcap_{v\in U}L(v))\cup(\bigcap_{v\in P_{1}-U}L(v))=Y_{U}. For i=2,,ki=2,\ldots,k and vSUPiv\in S_{U}\cap P_{i}, since |YU|=k|L(v)||Y_{U}|=k\leq|L(v)|, we have YU=L(v)Y_{U}=L(v).  

Corollary 3.4

For distinct 2-subsets UU and UU^{\prime} of P1P_{1}, either SU=SUS_{U}=S_{U^{\prime}} and YU=YUY_{U}=Y_{U^{\prime}}, or SUSU=S_{U}\cap S_{U^{\prime}}=\emptyset and YUYU=Y_{U}\cap Y_{U^{\prime}}=\emptyset.

By symmetry, we may assume L(u1)L(v1)L(u_{1})\cap L(v_{1})\neq\emptyset, S{u1,v1}={u2,u3,,uk}S_{\{u_{1},v_{1}\}}=\{u_{2},u_{3},\ldots,u_{k}\}.

Since |L(u1)L(v1)|=|L(x1)L(y1)||L(u_{1})\cap L(v_{1})|=|L(x_{1})\cap L(y_{1})| and |L(u1)L(v1)|+|L(x1)L(y1)||Y{u1,v1}|=k|L(u_{1})\cap L(v_{1})|+|L(x_{1})\cap L(y_{1})|\leq|Y_{\{u_{1},v_{1}\}}|=k, we have |L(u1)L(v1)|=|L(x1)L(y1)|k/2|L(u_{1})\cap L(v_{1})|=|L(x_{1})\cap L(y_{1})|\leq k/2.

As CP1,2=CC_{P_{1},2}=C, we may assume that L(u1)L(x1)L(u_{1})\cap L(x_{1})\neq\emptyset. Similarly, we have |L(u1)L(x1)|=|L(v1)L(y1)|k/2|L(u_{1})\cap L(x_{1})|=|L(v_{1})\cap L(y_{1})|\leq k/2.

Case 2(a) L(u1)L(y1)=L(u_{1})\cap L(y_{1})=\emptyset.

Then

CP1,2=C=(L(u1)L(v1))(L(x1)L(y1))(L(u1)L(x1))(L(v1)L(y1)).C_{P_{1},2}=C=(L(u_{1})\cap L(v_{1}))\cup(L(x_{1})\cap L(y_{1}))\cup(L(u_{1})\cap L(x_{1}))\cup(L(v_{1})\cap L(y_{1})).

Hence |L(u1)L(v1)|=|L(x1)L(y1)|=|L(u1)L(x1)|=|L(v1)L(y1)|=k/2|L(u_{1})\cap L(v_{1})|=|L(x_{1})\cap L(y_{1})|=|L(u_{1})\cap L(x_{1})|=|L(v_{1})\cap L(y_{1})|=k/2. Then

(L(u1)L(v1))(L(x1)L(y1))=Y{u1,v1},(L(u_{1})\cap L(v_{1}))\cup(L(x_{1})\cap L(y_{1}))=Y_{\{u_{1},v_{1}\}},
(L(u1)L(x1))(L(v1)L(y1))=Y{u1,x1}.(L(u_{1})\cap L(x_{1}))\cup(L(v_{1})\cap L(y_{1}))=Y_{\{u_{1},x_{1}\}}.

As L(u1)L(v1)L(x1)=L(u_{1})\cap L(v_{1})\cap L(x_{1})=\emptyset, we conclude that Y{u1,v1}Y{u1,x1}=Y_{\{u_{1},v_{1}\}}\cap Y_{\{u_{1},x_{1}\}}=\emptyset and S{u1,v1}S{u1,x1}=S_{\{u_{1},v_{1}\}}\cap S_{\{u_{1},x_{1}\}}=\emptyset.

Thus we have S{u1,x1}={v2,v3,,vk}S_{\{u_{1},x_{1}\}}=\{v_{2},v_{3},\ldots,v_{k}\}. Theorem 3.1 holds with A1=L(u1)L(v1),A2=L(x1)L(y1),A3=A4=A_{1}=L(u_{1})\cap L(v_{1}),A_{2}=L(x_{1})\cap L(y_{1}),A_{3}=A_{4}=\emptyset, B1=L(u1)L(x1),B2=L(v1)L(y1)B_{1}=L(u_{1})\cap L(x_{1}),B_{2}=L(v_{1})\cap L(y_{1}).

Case 2(b) L(u1)L(y1)L(u_{1})\cap L(y_{1})\neq\emptyset.

Since

CP1,2=C\displaystyle C_{P_{1},2}=C =(L(u1)L(v1))(L(x1)L(y1))(L(u1)L(x1))(L(v1)L(y1))\displaystyle=(L(u_{1})\cap L(v_{1}))\cup(L(x_{1})\cap L(y_{1}))\cup(L(u_{1})\cap L(x_{1}))\cup(L(v_{1})\cap L(y_{1}))
(L(u1)L(y1))(L(v1)L(x1)),\displaystyle\cup(L(u_{1})\cap L(y_{1}))\cup(L(v_{1})\cap L(x_{1})),

we may assume that S{u1,v1}=S{u1y1}S_{\{u_{1},v_{1}\}}=S_{\{u_{1}y_{1}\}}, Y{u1,v1}=Y{u1y1}Y_{\{u_{1},v_{1}\}}=Y_{\{u_{1}y_{1}\}}, S{u1,v1}S{u1x1}=S_{\{u_{1},v_{1}\}}\cap S_{\{u_{1}x_{1}\}}=\emptyset and Y{u1,v1}Y{u1x1}=Y_{\{u_{1},v_{1}\}}\cap Y_{\{u_{1}x_{1}\}}=\emptyset. Then Theorem 3.1 holds with A1=L(u1)L(v1),A2=L(x1)L(y1),A3=L(u1)L(y1),A4=L(v1)L(x1)A_{1}=L(u_{1})\cap L(v_{1}),A_{2}=L(x_{1})\cap L(y_{1}),A_{3}=L(u_{1})\cap L(y_{1}),A_{4}=L(v_{1})\cap L(x_{1}), B1=L(u1)L(x1),B2=L(v1)L(y1)B_{1}=L(u_{1})\cap L(x_{1}),B_{2}=L(v_{1})\cap L(y_{1}).

This completes the proof of Theorem 3.1.  

4 Bad list assignments for K3(k/2+1),1(k/21)K_{3\star(k/2+1),1\star(k/2-1)}

Let G=K3(k/2+1),1(k/21)G=K_{3\star(k/2+1),1\star(k/2-1)}. Assume LL is a bad kk-list assignment of GG. By Observation 2.1, for any 3-part PP of GG, vPL(v)=\bigcap_{v\in P}L(v)=\emptyset. Thus 2|C|vP|L(v)|3k2|C|\geq\sum_{v\in P}|L(v)|\geq 3k. Hence |C|3k/2|C|\geq 3k/2. If |C|=3k/2|C|=3k/2, then GG is not LL-colourable, because if ff is a proper LL-colouring of GG, then |f(P)|2|f(P)|\geq 2 for each 3-part PP and |f(P)|=1|f(P)|=1 for each 1-part PP. As f(P)f(P)=f(P)\cap f(P^{\prime})=\emptyset for distinct parts PP and PP^{\prime}, we have |C||f(P)|2×(k/2+1)+(k/21)=3k/2+1|C|\geq\sum|f(P)|\geq 2\times(k/2+1)+(k/2-1)=3k/2+1, a contradiction.

If k=2k=2, then there are some other bad 22-list assignment of K3,3K_{3,3}.

Theorem 4.1

Any bad 22-list assignment of K3,3K_{3,3} is isomorphic to one of the list assignments in Figure 1.

Proof. Assume G=K3,3G=K_{3,3} and LL is a bad 22-list assignment of GG. Assume the two parts of GG are Pi={ui,vi,wi}P_{i}=\{u_{i},v_{i},w_{i}\} for i=1,2i=1,2. By (2) of Observation 2.1, CPi,3=C_{P_{i},3}=\emptyset for i=1,2i=1,2. As |C|5|C|\leq 5, we know that CP1,2C_{P_{1},2}\neq\emptyset. Assume 1L(u1)L(v1)1\in L(u_{1})\cap L(v_{1}). If 1CP2,21\notin C_{P_{2},2}, then we colour u1,v1u_{1},v_{1} by colour 11, which easily extends to an LL-colouring of GG, a contradiction.

Thus we may assume that 1L(u1)L(v1)L(u2)L(v2)1\in L(u_{1})\cap L(v_{1})\cap L(u_{2})\cap L(v_{2}). If L(w1)(L(u2)L(v2))L(w_{1})\not\subseteq(L(u_{2})\cup L(v_{2})), then we colour {u1,v1}\{u_{1},v_{1}\} by colour 11, and colour w1w_{1} by a colour in L(w1)(L(u2)L(v2))L(w_{1})-(L(u_{2})\cup L(v_{2})), which extends to a proper LL-colouring of GG. Thus we must have L(w1)=(L(u2)L(v2)){1}L(w_{1})=(L(u_{2})\cup L(v_{2}))-\{1\}, and by symmetry, L(w2)=(L(u1)L(v1)){1}L(w_{2})=(L(u_{1})\cup L(v_{1}))-\{1\}. Thus L(u1)={1,a},L(v1)={1,b},L(w1)={c,d},L(u2)={1,c},L(v2)={1,d},L(w2)={a,b}L(u_{1})=\{1,a\},L(v_{1})=\{1,b\},L(w_{1})=\{c,d\},L(u_{2})=\{1,c\},L(v_{2})=\{1,d\},L(w_{2})=\{a,b\}, where aba\neq b and cdc\neq d. Depending on |{a,b}{c,d}|=0,1|\{a,b\}\cap\{c,d\}|=0,1 or 22, we have three bad 2-list assignments for K3,3K_{3,3} as depicted in Figure 1.  

Refer to caption
Refer to caption
Refer to caption
Figure 1: all bad 22-list assignments of K3,3K_{3,3}
Theorem 4.2

Suppose k4k\geq 4 is an even integer and LL is the kk-list assignment of GG with |C|>3k/2|C|>3k/2. Then GG is LL-colourable.

Proof. For an ordering π=(P1,P2,,Pk/2+1)\pi=(P_{1},P_{2},\ldots,P_{k/2+1}) of the 3-parts, let

(π)=max{i:tPjj,ji}.\ell(\pi)=\max\{i:t_{P_{j}}\geq j,\forall j\leq i\}.

Let π\pi be an ordering of the 3-parts such that

  • (1)

    (π)\ell(\pi) is maximum.

  • (2)

    Subject to (1), |L(Pk/2+1)||L(P_{k/2+1})| is maximum.

For 1i(π)1\leq i\leq\ell(\pi), choose a 2-subset SiS_{i} of PiP_{i} with vSiL(v)=tPi\bigcap_{v\in S_{i}}L(v)=t_{P_{i}}. Let 𝒮\mathcal{S} be the partition of V(G)V(G) whose non-singleton parts are S1,S2,,S(π)S_{1},S_{2},\ldots,S_{\ell(\pi)}. Let G/𝒮,L𝒮,X𝒮,Y𝒮G/\mathcal{S},L_{\mathcal{S}},X_{\mathcal{S}},Y_{\mathcal{S}} be as defined in Section 2. Similarly, let PiP^{\prime}_{i} be the parts of G/𝒮G/\mathcal{S}.

Let Z={vSi:1i(π)}.Z=\{v_{S_{i}}:1\leq i\leq\ell(\pi)\}. Subject to the condition that vSiL(v)=tPi\bigcap_{v\in S_{i}}L(v)=t_{P_{i}}, we choose SiS_{i} so that |L𝒮(Z)||L_{\mathcal{S}}(Z)| is maximum.

Claim 4.3

X𝒮ZX_{\mathcal{S}}-Z\neq\emptyset, (π)k/2\ell(\pi)\leq k/2 and |X𝒮Pi|2|X_{\mathcal{S}}\cap P_{i}|\geq 2 for some (π)+1ik/2+1\ell(\pi)+1\leq i\leq k/2+1.

Proof. If X𝒮Z=X_{\mathcal{S}}-Z=\emptyset, then let ii be the maximum index such that vSiX𝒮v_{S_{i}}\in X_{\mathcal{S}}, then |Y𝒮|i|X𝒮||Y_{\mathcal{S}}|\geq i\geq|X_{\mathcal{S}}|, a contradiction.

So |Y𝒮||L(v)|=k|Y_{\mathcal{S}}|\geq|L(v)|=k for vX𝒮Zv\in X_{\mathcal{S}}-Z. Hence |X𝒮|k+1|X_{\mathcal{S}}|\geq k+1. Thus for some part PiP^{\prime}_{i} of G/𝒮G/\mathcal{S}, |PiX𝒮|2|P^{\prime}_{i}\cap X_{\mathcal{S}}|\geq 2.

If |X𝒮Pi|1|X_{\mathcal{S}}\cap P_{i}|\leq 1 for each i(π)+1i\geq\ell(\pi)+1, then let ii be the maximum index such that PiX𝒮P^{\prime}_{i}\subseteq X_{\mathcal{S}}. Then |X𝒮|k+i|X_{\mathcal{S}}|\leq k+i. But |Y𝒮||L𝒮(Pi)|k+i|Y_{\mathcal{S}}|\geq|L_{\mathcal{S}}(P^{\prime}_{i})|\geq k+i, a contradiction. Thus (π)k/2\ell(\pi)\leq k/2 and |X𝒮Pi|2|X_{\mathcal{S}}\cap P_{i}|\geq 2 for some (π)+1ik/2+1\ell(\pi)+1\leq i\leq k/2+1.  

Claim 4.4

|Y𝒮|3k/2|Y_{\mathcal{S}}|\geq 3k/2, |V(G/𝒮)X𝒮|1|V(G/\mathcal{S})-X_{\mathcal{S}}|\leq 1 and (π)=tPk/2+1=k/2\ell(\pi)=t_{P_{k/2+1}}=k/2.

Proof. By Claim 4.3, there exists (π)+1ik/2+1\ell(\pi)+1\leq i\leq k/2+1 such that |X𝒮Pi|2|X_{\mathcal{S}}\cap P_{i}|\geq 2. Assume x,yX𝒮Pix,y\in X_{\mathcal{S}}\cap P_{i}. Then

|Y𝒮||L(x)L(y)|2ktPi2k(π)3k/2.|Y_{\mathcal{S}}|\geq|L(x)\cup L(y)|\geq 2k-t_{P_{i}}\geq 2k-\ell(\pi)\geq 3k/2. (1)

Hence

2k+2(π)=|V(G/𝒮)||X𝒮|2k(π)+1.2k+2-\ell(\pi)=|V(G/\mathcal{S})|\geq|X_{\mathcal{S}}|\geq 2k-\ell(\pi)+1.

So |X𝒮|3k/2+1|X_{\mathcal{S}}|\geq 3k/2+1. This implies that either X𝒮=G/𝒮X_{\mathcal{S}}=G/\mathcal{S} or X𝒮=G/𝒮vX_{\mathcal{S}}=G/\mathcal{S}-v^{*} for some vertex vv^{*}.

If (π)k/21\ell(\pi)\leq k/2-1, then X𝒮X_{\mathcal{S}} contains a 3-part PiP_{i}, where i(π)+1i\geq\ell(\pi)+1. By the maximality of (π)\ell(\pi), we have |L(x)L(y)|(π)|L(x)\cap L(y)|\leq\ell(\pi) for any x,yPix,y\in P_{i}. Hence

3(π)|CPi,2|3k|L(Pi)|3k|Y𝒮|k+(π)1,3\ell(\pi)\geq|C_{P_{i},2}|\geq 3k-|L(P_{i})|\geq 3k-|Y_{\mathcal{S}}|\geq k+\ell(\pi)-1,

a contradiction. Hence (π)k/2\ell(\pi)\geq k/2, and by Claim 4.3, we have (π)=k/2\ell(\pi)=k/2.

Now we show that tPk/2+1=k/2t_{P_{k/2+1}}=k/2. It follows from the definition of (π)\ell(\pi) that tPk/2+1k/2t_{P_{k/2+1}}\leq k/2. Assume to the contrary that tPk/2+1k/21t_{P_{k/2+1}}\leq k/2-1. Then |Y𝒮||L(x)L(y)|2ktPk/2+13k/2+1|Y_{\mathcal{S}}|\geq|L(x)\cup L(y)|\geq 2k-t_{P_{k/2+1}}\geq 3k/2+1. Hence |X𝒮|3k/2+2|X_{\mathcal{S}}|\geq 3k/2+2, which implies that X𝒮=V(G/𝒮)X_{\mathcal{S}}=V(G/\mathcal{S}). In particular, Pk/2+1X𝒮P_{k/2+1}\subseteq X_{\mathcal{S}} and hence |Y𝒮||L(Pk/2+1)|3k3tPk/2+13k/2+3>|X𝒮||Y_{\mathcal{S}}|\geq|L(P_{k/2+1})|\geq 3k-3t_{P_{k/2+1}}\geq 3k/2+3>|X_{\mathcal{S}}|, a contradiction.  

Corollary 4.5

For i=1,2,,k/2+1i=1,2,\ldots,k/2+1, tPi=k/2t_{P_{i}}=k/2.

Proof. Interchange the positions of PiP_{i} and Pk/2+1P_{k/2+1}, we obtain an ordering π\pi^{\prime} of the parts of GG with (π)=k/2\ell(\pi^{\prime})=k/2. Apply Claims 4.3 and 4.4 to π\pi^{\prime}, we conclude that tPi=k/2t_{P_{i}}=k/2. (Note that the proofs of these two claims only used the fact that π\pi is an ordering with (π)\ell(\pi) maximum among all orderings of the parts of GG.)  

In the following, we assume that X𝒮=G/𝒮X_{\mathcal{S}}=G/\mathcal{S} or X𝒮=G/𝒮vX_{\mathcal{S}}=G/\mathcal{S}-v^{*} for some vertex vv^{*}. Note that for any ik/2i\leq k/2, if π\pi^{\prime} is the ordering of the parts of GG obtained from π\pi by interchanging the position of PiP_{i} and Pk/2+1P_{k/2+1}, we have (π)=k/2=(π)\ell(\pi^{\prime})=k/2=\ell(\pi). Thus by the choice of π\pi, we have

|L(Pi)||L(Pk/2+1)|,ik/2.|L(P_{i})|\leq|L(P_{k/2+1})|,\forall i\leq k/2. (2)
Claim 4.6

If Pk/2+1X𝒮P_{k/2+1}\subseteq X_{\mathcal{S}}, then |Y𝒮|>3k/2|Y_{\mathcal{S}}|>3k/2

Proof. Assume to the contrary that Pk/2+1X𝒮P_{k/2+1}\subseteq X_{\mathcal{S}} and |Y𝒮|=3k/2|Y_{\mathcal{S}}|=3k/2.

For i=1,2,,k/2+1i=1,2,\ldots,k/2+1,

2|L(Pi)||CPi,1|+2|CPi,2|=vPi|L(v)|3k2|L(P_{i})|\geq|C_{P_{i},1}|+2|C_{P_{i},2}|=\sum_{v\in P_{i}}|L(v)|\geq 3k

and hence |L(Pi)|3k/2|L(P_{i})|\geq 3k/2. Combined with |LPk/2+1||Y𝒮|=3k/2|L_{P_{k/2+1}}|\leq|Y_{\mathcal{S}}|=3k/2, we have |L(Pk/2+1)|=3k/2|L(P_{k/2+1})|=3k/2.

By (2), for any jk/2j\leq k/2, |L(Pj)|=3k/2|L(P_{j})|=3k/2. This implies that L(Pj)=L𝒮(Pj)L(P_{j})=L_{\mathcal{S}}(P^{\prime}_{j}).

Assume vPiv^{*}\in P_{i} (if vv^{*} exists). Then C=vV(G)PiL(v)Y𝒮C=\bigcup_{v\in V(G)-P_{i}}L(v)\subseteq Y_{\mathcal{S}}. This is a contradiction, as |C|>3k/2|C|>3k/2.  

In the remaining part of the proof, we consider two cases.

Case 1: X𝒮=G/𝒮vX_{\mathcal{S}}=G/\mathcal{S}-v^{*}.

In this case, |X𝒮|=3k/2+1|X_{\mathcal{S}}|=3k/2+1 and |Y𝒮|=3k/2|Y_{\mathcal{S}}|=3k/2. By Claim 4.6, we conclude that Pk/2+1X𝒮P_{k/2+1}\not\subseteq X_{\mathcal{S}} and hence vPk/2+1v^{*}\in P_{k/2+1}. By the maximality of X𝒮X_{\mathcal{S}}, we know that

|L(v)Y𝒮|2.|L(v^{*})-Y_{\mathcal{S}}|\geq 2. (3)

Assume Pk/2+1={uk/2+1,vk/2+1,wk/2+1}P_{k/2+1}=\{u_{k/2+1},v_{k/2+1},w_{k/2+1}\} and v=vk/2+1v^{*}=v_{k/2+1}. Since |L(uk/2+1)L(wk/2+1)||Y𝒮|=3k/2|L(u_{k/2+1})\cup L(w_{k/2+1})|\leq|Y_{\mathcal{S}}|=3k/2, we have |L(uk/2+1)L(wk/2+1)|k/2|L(u_{k/2+1})\cap L(w_{k/2+1})|\geq k/2. As (π)=k/2\ell(\pi)=k/2, we have |L(uk/2+1)L(wk/2+1)|=k/2|L(u_{k/2+1})\cap L(w_{k/2+1})|=k/2.

As 2|P1,2|+|P1,1|3k2|P_{1,2}|+|P_{1,1}|\geq 3k and |P1,2|+|P1,1||C|2k+1|P_{1,2}|+|P_{1,1}|\leq|C|\leq 2k+1, we have |P1,2|k1>k/2|P_{1,2}|\geq k-1>k/2. Hence there is a 2-subset S1S^{\prime}_{1} of P1P_{1} such that

vS1L(v)L(uk/2+1)L(wk/2+1).\bigcap_{v\in S^{\prime}_{1}}L(v)\not\subseteq L(u_{k/2+1})\cap L(w_{k/2+1}).

Let Sk/2+1={uk/2+1,wk/2+1}S_{k/2+1}=\{u_{k/2+1},w_{k/2+1}\} and let 𝒮=(𝒮{S1}){S1,Sk/2+1}\mathcal{S}^{\prime}=(\mathcal{S}-\{S_{1}\})\cup\{S^{\prime}_{1},S_{k/2+1}\}.

Let Pi′′P^{\prime\prime}_{i} be the part of G/𝒮G/\mathcal{S}^{\prime} and let Z=(Z{vS1}){vS1,vSk/2+1}Z^{\prime}=(Z-\{v_{S_{1}}\})\cup\{v_{S^{\prime}_{1}},v_{S_{k/2+1}}\}.

We have

X𝒮Z,X_{\mathcal{S^{\prime}}}-Z^{\prime}\neq\emptyset,

for otherwise, if |X𝒮Z|k/2|X_{\mathcal{S^{\prime}}}\cap Z^{\prime}|\leq k/2, then |X𝒮|k/2|Y𝒮||X_{\mathcal{S^{\prime}}}|\leq k/2\leq|Y_{\mathcal{S^{\prime}}}| (as it is obvious that |X𝒮|2|X_{\mathcal{S}}|\geq 2), a contradiction, and if X𝒮=ZX_{\mathcal{S^{\prime}}}=Z^{\prime}, then |X𝒮|=k/2+1|L𝒮(vS1)L𝒮(vSk/2+1)||Y𝒮||X_{\mathcal{S^{\prime}}}|=k/2+1\leq|L_{\mathcal{S^{\prime}}}(v_{S^{\prime}_{1}})\cup L_{\mathcal{S^{\prime}}}(v_{S_{k/2+1}})|\leq|Y_{\mathcal{S^{\prime}}}|, a contradiction.

Hence, there is a vertex vX𝒮v\in X_{\mathcal{S^{\prime}}} such that |L𝒮(v)|k|L_{\mathcal{S^{\prime}}}(v)|\geq k and this implies that |X𝒮|k+1|X_{\mathcal{S^{\prime}}}|\geq k+1. So, we know that there exists an index 1jk/2+11\leq j\leq k/2+1 such that Pj′′X𝒮P^{\prime\prime}_{j}\subseteq X_{\mathcal{S^{\prime}}}.

This implies that |Y𝒮|k+1|Y_{\mathcal{S^{\prime}}}|\geq k+1, and hence |X𝒮|k+2|X_{\mathcal{S^{\prime}}}|\geq k+2. This in turn implies that there exists an index 2jk/2+12\leq j\leq k/2+1 such that Pj′′X𝒮P^{\prime\prime}_{j}\subseteq X_{\mathcal{S^{\prime}}}. This implies that |Y𝒮|3k/2|Y_{\mathcal{S^{\prime}}}|\geq 3k/2. Hence |X𝒮|=3k/2+1|X_{\mathcal{S^{\prime}}}|=3k/2+1, i.e., X𝒮=V(G/𝒮)X_{\mathcal{S^{\prime}}}=V(G/\mathcal{S}^{\prime}) and |Y𝒮|=3k/2|Y_{\mathcal{S^{\prime}}}|=3k/2. But we know that |Y𝒮||Y𝒮L(v)|3k/2+2|Y_{\mathcal{S^{\prime}}}|\geq|Y_{\mathcal{S}}\cup L(v^{*})|\geq 3k/2+2 (by (3)), a contradiction.

Case 2: X𝒮=V(G/𝒮)X_{\mathcal{S}}=V(G/\mathcal{S})

In this case, |X𝒮|=3k/2+2|X_{\mathcal{S}}|=3k/2+2. In particular,

Pk/2+1X𝒮,L(Pk/2+1)Y𝒮.P_{k/2+1}\subseteq X_{\mathcal{S}},L(P_{k/2+1})\subseteq Y_{\mathcal{S}}. (4)

By Claim 4.6, |Y𝒮|=3k/2+1|Y_{\mathcal{S}}|=3k/2+1.

Claim 4.7

|L𝒮(Z)|k/2+1|L_{\mathcal{S}}(Z)|\geq k/2+1 and L(Pi)Y𝒮L(P_{i})\subseteq Y_{\mathcal{S}} for 1ik/2+11\leq i\leq k/2+1.

Proof. By Corollary 4.5, tPi=k/2t_{P_{i}}=k/2 for all 1ik/2+11\leq i\leq k/2+1. As |L(Pk/2+1)||Y𝒮|=3k/2+1|L(P_{k/2+1})|\leq|Y_{\mathcal{S}}|=3k/2+1, we have 3k/2+1|L(Pk/2+1)||L(Pi)|3k/2+1\geq|L(P_{k/2+1})|\geq|L(P_{i})|. This implies that PiP_{i} has at least two 2-subsets SiS_{i} with |vSiL(v)|=k/2|\bigcap_{v\in S_{i}}L(v)|=k/2. As (π)2\ell(\pi)\geq 2, we can make a choice of S2S_{2} so that vS1L(v)vS2L(v)\bigcap_{v\in S_{1}}L(v)\neq\bigcap_{v\in S_{2}}L(v). Hence

|L𝒮(Z)||vS1L(v)vS2L(v)|k/2+1.|L_{\mathcal{S}}(Z)|\geq|\bigcap_{v\in S_{1}}L(v)\cup\bigcap_{v\in S_{2}}L(v)|\geq k/2+1.

If |L(Pk/2+1)|=3k/2|L(P_{k/2+1})|=3k/2, then |L(Pi)|=|L𝒮(Pi)|=3k/2|L(P_{i})|=|L_{\mathcal{S}}(P^{\prime}_{i})|=3k/2 for all 1ik/21\leq i\leq k/2, and hence L(Pi)=L𝒮(Pi)Y𝒮L(P_{i})=L_{\mathcal{S}}(P^{\prime}_{i})\subseteq Y_{\mathcal{S}}, and the claim is true.

Assume |L(Pk/2+1)|=3k/2+1|L(P_{k/2+1})|=3k/2+1. Then Y𝒮=L(Pk/2+1)Y_{\mathcal{S}}=L(P_{k/2+1}).

Assume to the contrary that L(Pi)Y𝒮L(P_{i})\not\subseteq Y_{\mathcal{S}} for some 1ik/21\leq i\leq k/2. Since tPi=k/2t_{P_{i}}=k/2 for 1ik/21\leq i\leq k/2, by a re-ordering of the parts of GG if needed, we may assume that P1={u1,v1,w1}P_{1}=\{u_{1},v_{1},w_{1}\} and L(u1)Y𝒮L(u_{1})-Y_{\mathcal{S}}\neq\emptyset (the resulting ordering π\pi^{\prime} will still have (π)=k/2\ell(\pi^{\prime})=k/2). Let S1={v1,w1}S^{\prime}_{1}=\{v_{1},w_{1}\} and 𝒮=(𝒮{S1}){S1}\mathcal{S}^{\prime}=(\mathcal{S}-\{S_{1}\})\cup\{S^{\prime}_{1}\}. The argument remains valid for X𝒮X_{\mathcal{S}^{\prime}}. Hence |X𝒮|=|V(G/𝒮)|=3k/2+2|X_{\mathcal{S}^{\prime}}|=|V(G/\mathcal{S}^{\prime})|=3k/2+2. However, Y𝒮(L(u1)Y𝒮)Y𝒮Y_{\mathcal{S}}\cup(L(u_{1})-Y_{\mathcal{S}})\subseteq Y_{\mathcal{S}^{\prime}}. Hence |Y𝒮||Y𝒮|+1=3k/2+2|Y_{\mathcal{S}^{\prime}}|\geq|Y_{\mathcal{S}}|+1=3k/2+2, a contradiction.  

By (2) of Observation 2.1, C=i[k]{k/2+1}L(Pi)C=\bigcup_{i\in[k]-\{k/2+1\}}L(P_{i}). By Claim 4.7, i[k]{k/2+1}L(Pi)Y𝒮\bigcup_{i\in[k]-\{k/2+1\}}L(P_{i})\subseteq Y_{\mathcal{S}}.

Let Sk/2+1S_{k/2+1} be a 2-subset of Pk/2+1P_{k/2+1} with vSk/2+1L(v)=k/2\cap_{v\in S_{k/2+1}}L(v)=k/2, and let 𝒮=𝒮{Sk/2+1}\mathcal{S}^{\prime}=\mathcal{S}\cup\{S_{k/2+1}\}. By using the fact that |L𝒮(Z)|=|L𝒮(Z)|k/2+1|L_{\mathcal{S^{\prime}}}(Z)|=|L_{\mathcal{S}}(Z)|\geq k/2+1, it is easy to show that X𝒮=V(G/𝒮)X_{\mathcal{S^{\prime}}}=V(G/\mathcal{S}^{\prime}), and hence |Y𝒮||Y𝒮|=3k/2+1=|X𝒮||Y_{\mathcal{S^{\prime}}}|\leq|Y_{\mathcal{S}}|=3k/2+1=|X_{\mathcal{S^{\prime}}}|, a contradiction.

This completes the proof of Theorem 4.2.

 

5 Characterization of non-kk-choosable kk-chromatic graphs with 2k+22k+2-vertices

This section proves Corollary 1.2. By Theorem 1.1, it suffices to consider proper subgraphs of K3(k/2+1),1(k/21)K_{3\star(k/2+1),1\star(k/2-1)} and K4,2(k1)K_{4,2\star(k-1)}, where kk is an even integer.

Let GG^{*} be the subgraph of K4,2(k1)K_{4,2\star(k-1)} obtained by deleting all the edges {uivj:2i,jk}\{u_{i}v_{j}:2\leq i,j\leq k\}. In other words, G=K4¯(2kk1)G^{*}=\overline{K_{4}}\vee(2k_{k-1}) is the join of K4¯\overline{K_{4}}, an independent set of size 44, and 2Kk12K_{k-1}, which is the disjoint union of two copies of Kk1K_{k-1}. It is easy to verify that GG^{*} is not kk-choosable. Indeed, let LL be the kk-list assignment of GG^{*} as described in Theorem 3.1. Assume ff is a proper LL-colouring of GG^{*}. Then |f({u2,u3,,uk})|=|f({v2,v3,,vk})|=k1|f(\{u_{2},u_{3},\ldots,u_{k}\})|=|f(\{v_{2},v_{3},\ldots,v_{k}\})|=k-1. Hence there is only one colour from AA, and only one colour from BB, that are left for vertices in P1P_{1}. No matter what are the colours from AA and BB are left, the list of one of the vertices of P1P_{1} contains none of these two colours, and hence cannot be properly coloured by a colour from its list.

Thus any subgraph of K4,2(k1)K_{4,2\star(k-1)} containing a copy of GG^{*} is not kk-choosable. The following lemma shows that any other subgraph of K4,2(k1)K_{4,2\star(k-1)} is kk-choosable.

Theorem 5.1

Assume GG is a subgraph of K4,2(k1)K_{4,2\star(k-1)} which does not contain a copy of GG^{*}. Then GG is kk-choosable.

Proof. Assume LL is a kk-list assignment of GG. We may assume LL is the kk-list assignment as described in Theorem 3.1, for otherwise, K4,2(k1)K_{4,2\star(k-1)} is LL-colourable, and hence GG is LL-colourable. If there are 2i<jk2\leq i<j\leq k such that uiuju_{i}u_{j} is not an edge of GG, then since L(ui)=L(uj)L(u_{i})=L(u_{j}), we can identify uiu_{i} and uju_{j} into a single vertex. It follows from Noel-Reed-Wu Theorem that GG is LL-colourable. Thus we may assume that {u2,u3,,uk}\{u_{2},u_{3},\ldots,u_{k}\} induces a clique. Similarly, {v2,v3,,vk}\{v_{2},v_{3},\ldots,v_{k}\} induces a clique.

As GG does not contain GG^{*} as a subgraph, we know that uvE(G)uv\notin E(G) for some uP1u\in P_{1} and vPiv\in P_{i} for some 2ik2\leq i\leq k. By symmetry, assume u1u2E(G)u_{1}u_{2}\notin E(G). We colour u1,u2u_{1},u_{2} by a colour cL(u1)L(u2)Ac\in L(u_{1})\cap L(u_{2})\subseteq A (which exists by the description of LL in Theorem 3.1), and colour v1v_{1} and y1y_{1} by a colour cB2c^{\prime}\in B_{2}.

Let G=G{u1,u2,v1,y1}G^{\prime}=G-\{u_{1},u_{2},v_{1},y_{1}\} and let L(v)=L(v){c,c}L^{\prime}(v)=L(v)-\{c,c^{\prime}\} for vV(G)v\in V(G^{\prime}). It easy to verify that GG^{\prime} and LL^{\prime} satisfies the conditions of Lemma 2.2 and hence GG^{\prime} is LL^{\prime}-colourable, and hence GG is LL-colourable.  

For k=2k=2, it is easy to verify (and also follows from the characterization of 2-choosable graphs in [3]) that, up to isomorphism, K3,3K_{3,3} has two proper subgraphs that are not 2-choosable. In the following, we show that for k4k\geq 4, all proper subgraph of K3(k/2+1),1(k/21)K_{3\star(k/2+1),1\star(k/2-1)} is kk-choosable.

Theorem 5.2

If k4k\geq 4 and GG is a proper subgraph of K3(k/2+1),1(k/21)K_{3\star(k/2+1),1\star(k/2-1)}, then GG is kk-choosable.

Proof. Let Pi={ui,vi,wi}P_{i}=\{u_{i},v_{i},w_{i}\} for 1ik/2+11\leq i\leq k/2+1 and Pi={ui}P_{i}=\{u_{i}\} for k/2+2ikk/2+2\leq i\leq k. By Noel-Reed-Wu Theorem, we may assume G=K3(k/2+1),1(k/21){e}G=K_{3\star(k/2+1),1\star(k/2-1)}-\{e\} for some edge e=xye=xy, say xPix\in P_{i} and yPjy\in P_{j}, i<ji<j. If jk/2+2j\geq k/2+2, then GG is a subgraph of K3k/2,22,1(k/22)K_{3\star k/2,2\star 2,1\star(k/2-2)} which is kk-choosable by Theorem 1.1. Hence, GG is LL-colourable, a contradiction.

Thus we may assume x=u1x=u_{1} and y=u2y=u_{2}. Since |C|=3k/2|C|=3k/2, we have |L(u1)L(u2)|k/2|L(u_{1})\cap L(u_{2})|\geq k/2 and |L(vi)L(wi)|k/2|L(v_{i})\cap L(w_{i})|\geq k/2 for i=1,2i=1,2. Let L(u1)L(u2)=A1L(u_{1})\cap L(u_{2})=A_{1}, L(v1)L(w1)=A2L(v_{1})\cap L(w_{1})=A_{2} and L(v2)L(w2)=A3L(v_{2})\cap L(w_{2})=A_{3}.

Note that L(u1)CA2L(u_{1})\subseteq C-A_{2} and L(u2)CA3L(u_{2})\subseteq C-A_{3}. Hence |A2|=|A3|=k/2|A_{2}|=|A_{3}|=k/2, L(u1)=CA2L(u_{1})=C-A_{2} and L(u2)=CA3L(u_{2})=C-A_{3}. This implies that

|A1A2A3|=|(CA2)(CA3)|+|A2A3|=|C(A2A3)|+|A2A3|=|C|>k.|A_{1}\cup A_{2}\cup A_{3}|=|(C-A_{2})\cap(C-A_{3})|+|A_{2}\cup A_{3}|=|C-(A_{2}\cup A_{3})|+|A_{2}\cup A_{3}|=|C|>k.

So there exists ciAic_{i}\in A_{i} such that |L(uk){c1,c2,c3}|k2|L(u_{k})-\{c_{1},c_{2},c_{3}\}|\geq k-2.

Now, we colour u1u_{1}, u2u_{2} by colour c1c_{1}, colour v1v_{1}, w1w_{1} by colour c2c_{2} and colour v2v_{2}, w2w_{2} by colour c3c_{3}. Let L(v)=L(v){c1,c2,c3}L^{\prime}(v)=L(v)-\{c_{1},c_{2},c_{3}\} for any vertex vv of G=GP1P2G^{\prime}=G-P_{1}-P_{2}.

It easy to verify that GG^{\prime} and LL^{\prime} satisfies the condition of Lemma 2.2 (for the verification of condition (c-2) , if k6k\geq 6, then it is trivial and if k=4k=4, then we need to use the fact that |L(u)L(v)|2|L(u)\cap L(v)|\leq 2 for any u,vu,v of 3-part PP.) and hence GG^{\prime} is LL^{\prime}-colourable, a contradiction.  

Corollary 1.2 follows from Theorem 5.1 and Theorem 5.2.

References

  • [1] Béla Bollobás and Andrew Harris. List-colourings of graphs. Graphs Combin., 1(2):115–127, 1985.
  • [2] H. Enomoto, K. Ohba, K. Ota and J. Sakamoto. Choice number of some complete multi-partite graphs. Discrete Mathematics 244 (2002) 55–66.
  • [3] P. Erdős, A. L. Rubin and H. Taylor. Choosability in graphs. In Proceedings of the West Coast Conference on Combinatorics, Graph Theory and Computing (Humboldt State Univ., Arcata, Calif., 1979), Congress. Numer., XXVI, pages 125–157. Utilitas Math., Winnipeg, Man., 1980.
  • [4] F. Galvin. The list chromatic index of a bipartite multigraph. J Combin Theory Ser B 63(1) (1995), 153–158.
  • [5] S. Gravier, F. MaCray. Graphs whose choice number is equal to their chromatic number. J. Graph Theory, 27 (1998) 87–97.
  • [6] R. Häggkvist and A. Chetwynd. Some upper bounds on the total and list chromatic numbers of multigraphs. J Graph Theory 16(5) (1992), 503–516.
  • [7] H.A. Kierstead. On the choosability of complete multipartite graphs with part size three. Discrete Math. 211 (2000) 255–259.
  • [8] J. Kozik, P. Micek, and X. Zhu. Towards an on-line version of Ohbas{O}hba^{\prime}s conjecture. European J. Combin., 36:110–121, 2014.
  • [9] J. A. Noel. Choosability of graphs with bounded order: Ohba’s conjecture and beyond. Master’s thesis, McGill University, Montréal, Québec, 2013.
  • [10] J. A. Noel, D. B. West, H. Wu and X. Zhu. Beyond Ohba’s Conjecture: A bound on the choice number of kk-chromatic graphs with n vertices. European J. Combin. 43 (2015), 295–305.
  • [11] J. A. Noel, B. A. Reed, and H. Wu. A proof of a conjecture of Ohba. J. Graph Theory, 79(2):86–102, 2015.
  • [12] K. Ohba. On chromatic-choosable graphs. J Graph Theory 40(2) (2002), 130–135.
  • [13] K. Ohba. Choice number of complete multipartite graphs with part size at most three. Ars Combin 72 (2004), 133–139.
  • [14] U. Schauz. Proof of the list edge coloring conjecture for complete graphs of prime degree. Electron. J. Combin. 21 (2014), no. 3, Paper 3.43, 17 pp.
  • [15] Z. Tuza. Graph colorings with local constraints—a survey. Discuss. Math. Graph Theory 17 (1997), no. 2, 161–228.
  • [16] Vizing. Coloring the vertices of a graph in prescribed colors. (Russian) Diskret. Analiz 1976, no. 29, Metody Diskret. Anal. v Teorii Kodov i Shem, 3–10, 101.
  • [17] J. Zhu and X. Zhu. Minimum non-chromatic-choosable graphs with given chromatic number. arXiv:2201.02060.