This paper was converted on www.awesomepapers.org from LaTeX by an anonymous user.
Want to know more? Visit the Converter page.

An NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theory without the existence axiom

Scott Mutchnik Department of Mathematics, Statistics, and Computer Science, University of Illinois at Chicago [email protected]
Abstract.

Answering a question of Dobrowolski, Kim and Ramsey, we find an NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theory that does not satisfy the existence axiom.

This work was supported by the NSF under Grant No. DMS-2303034.

1. Introduction

One of the core informal questions of model theory is to determine what role stability theory, famously introduced by Morley ([19]) and Shelah ([23]) to classify the number of non-isomorphic models (of a given size) of a first-order theory, can play in describing theories that are themselves unstable–and that may not even be simple. This project was initiated in large part in celebrated work of Kim ([15]) and Kim and Pillay ([17]), who showed that the (forking-)independence relation has many of the same properties in simple theories that it does in stable theories, and in fact that these properties characterize simplicity. In a key step towards the non-simple case, Kaplan and Ramsey ([12]) then defined Kim-independence over models, which generalizes the definition of forking-independence:

Definition 1.1.

Let MTM\models T. A formula φ(x,b)\varphi(x,b) Kim-divides over MM if there is an MM-invariant Morley sequence {bi}iω\{b_{i}\}_{i\in\omega} starting with bb such that {φ(x,bi)}iω\{\varphi(x,b_{i})\}_{i\in\omega} is inconsistent. A formula φ(x,b)\varphi(x,b) Kim-forks over MM if it implies a (finite) disjunction of formulas Kim-dividing over MM. We write aMKba\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}^{K}_{M}b, and say that aa is Kim-independent from bb over MM, if tp(a/Mb)\mathrm{tp}(a/Mb) does not include any formulas Kim-forking over MM.

In, for example, [6], [12], [13], [14], it is shown that Kim-independence has many of the same properties in theories without the first strict order property–NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theories–that forking-independence has in simple theories. It is also shown that NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theories have a characterization in terms of properties of Kim-independence, similarly to how simplicity has a characterization in terms of properties of forking-independence. However, in contrast to the case of simple theories, this work only describes the properties of a relation aMKba\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{M}^{K}b defined when MM is a model, leaving open the question of whether independence phenomena in NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theories extend from independence over models to independence over sets.

The following axiom of first-order theories, though introduced earlier under different names (see, e.g. [5]), was defined by Dobrowolski, Kim and Ramsey in [9]:

Definition 1.2.

A theory TT satisfies the existence axiom if no type pS(A)p\in S(A) forks over AA.

This is equivalent to every type pS(A)p\in S(A) having a global extension that does not fork over AA. All simple theories satisfy the existence axiom ([15]), while the circular ordering is an example of a dependent theory not satisfying the existence axiom ([16], Example 2.11). In [9] it is shown that, in NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theories satisfying the existence axiom, it is possible to extend the definition of Kim-independence aCKba\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{C}^{K}b from the case where CC is a model to the case where CC is an arbitrary set, so that the relation aCKba\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{C}^{K}b will have similar properties to Kim-independence over models in general NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theories. Specifically, because, under the existence axiom, (nonforking-)Morley sequences are defined over arbitrary sets, they can be used in place of invariant Morley sequences111It is easy to see that invariant Morley sequences are not defined over arbitrary sets in NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theories: for example, any set AA such that acl(A)dcl(A)\mathrm{acl}(A)\neq\mathrm{dcl}(A). to define Kim-dividing of a formula over a set:

Definition 1.3.

([9]) Let TT be a NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theory, and let C𝕄C\subset\mathbb{M} be an arbitrary set. A formula φ(x,b)\varphi(x,b) Kim-divides over CC if there is a (nonforking-)Morley sequence {bi}iω\{b_{i}\}_{i\in\omega} over CC starting with bb such that {φ(x,bi)}iω\{\varphi(x,b_{i})\}_{i\in\omega} is inconsistent. A formula φ(x,b)\varphi(x,b) Kim-forks over CC if it implies a (finite) disjunction of formulas Kim-dividing over CC. We write aAKba\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}^{K}_{A}b, and say that aa is Kim-independent from bb over CC, if tp(a/Ab)\mathrm{tp}(a/Ab) does not include any formulas Kim-forking over CC.

Dobrowolski, Kim and Ramsey ([9]) show that, in an NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theory satisfying the existence axiom, the Kim-independence relation K\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}^{K} as defined above over arbitrary sets satisfies symmetry and the independence theorem (for Lascar strong types), and that Kim-dividing over arbitrary sets satisfies Kim’s lemma and coincides with Kim-forking. Chernikov, Kim and Ramsey, in [2], show even more properties of Kim-independence over arbitrary sets in NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theories satisfying the existence axiom, including transitivity and witnessing. (All of these properties correspond to the properties of Kim-independence over models proven in general NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theories in [12], [13].) Motivated by these results, [9], and later [3], ask:

Question 1.4.

Does every NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theory satisfy the existence axiom?

We show that the answer to this question is no:

Theorem 1.5.

There is an NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theory not satisfying the existence axiom.

This contrasts with the work of Kim, Kim and Lee in [3], where, for the definition of Kim-forking over sets given by Dobrowolski, Kim and Ramsey in [9] (Defintion 1.3 above), it is shown that no type pS(A)p\in S(A) Kim-forks over AA (i.e. contains a formula Kim-forking over AA), where AA is an arbitrary set in an NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theory. In fact, our example is the first known example of a theory without the strict order property, or NSOP\mathrm{NSOP} theory, not satisfying the existence axiom. Prior to our results, the theory of an algebraically closed field with a generic multiplicative endomorphism, constructed by d’Elbée in [8], was suggested there as a candidate for an NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theory without the existence axiom; whether the theory constructed by d’Elbée satisfies the existence axiom was left unresolved in that article. However, as discussed in a personal communication with d’Elbée ([7]), it is expected that that theory, which was shown in [8] to be NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1}, actually does satisfy the existence axiom.

Our construction is based on the theory of ω\omega-stable free pseudoplanes, a classical example of a non-one-based ω\omega-stable theory with trivial forking discussed in, say, [20]. The theory of ω\omega-stable free pseudoplanes is the theory of undirected graphs of infinite minimum degree without cycles. Variations of this construction appear in e.g. [10], [1], [24], [11]. Note also that some arguments from the below, including the strategy, in axiom schema T4T_{4}, of requiring that nn connected sets of pairwise distance greater than 2n2^{n} can be colored independently, and the associated Claims 2.1 and 2.2, their proofs, and their application in proving claim (***), are formally similar to those of Section 3 of Chernikov, Hrushovski, Kruckman, Krupiński, Moconja, Pillay and Ramsey ([4]).

2. The construction

Let \mathcal{L} be the language with sorts PP and OO, symbols R1R_{1} and R2R_{2} for binary relations on OO, and symbols ρ1\rho_{1} and ρ2\rho_{2} for binary relations between PP and OO. Call an \mathcal{L}-structure AA copacetic if:

(C1) For i=1,2i=1,2, Ri(A)R_{i}(A) is a symmetric, irreflexive relation on O(A)O(A), and the two are mutually exclusive: for a1,a2O(A)a_{1},a_{2}\in O(A), A⊧̸R1(a1,a2)R2(a1,a2)A\not\models R_{1}(a_{1},a_{2})\wedge R_{2}(a_{1},a_{2}).

(C2) The relation R1(A)R2(A)R_{1}(A)\cup R_{2}(A) has no loops on O(A)O(A) (i.e. there are no distinct a0an1O(A)a_{0}\ldots a_{n-1}\in O(A), n>2n>2, and i1in{1,2}i_{1}\ldots i_{n}\in\{1,2\} so that, for 0jn10\leq j\leq n-1, ARij(ai,ai+1modn)A\models R_{i_{j}}(a_{i},a_{i+1\mathrm{\>mod\>}n})).

(C3) For all bP(A)b\in P(A), aO(A)a\in O(A), exactly one of Aρ1(b,a)A\models\rho_{1}(b,a) and Aρ2(b,a)A\models\rho_{2}(b,a) hold.

(C4):

(a) For each bP(A)b\in P(A), there are no distinct a1,a2O(A)a_{1},a_{2}\in O(A), so that there there is some aO(A)a_{*}\in O(A) so that AR1(a1,a)R1(a2,a)A\models R_{1}(a_{1},a_{*})\wedge R_{1}(a_{2},a_{*}), and Aρ1(b,a1)ρ1(b,a2)A\models\rho_{1}(b,a_{1})\wedge\rho_{1}(b,a_{2}).

(b) For each bP(A)b\in P(A), there are no distinct a1,a2,a3O(A)a_{1},a_{2},a_{3}\in O(A), so that there there is some aO(A)a_{*}\in O(A) so that AR2(a1,a)R2(a2,a)R2(a3,a)A\models R_{2}(a_{1},a_{*})\wedge R_{2}(a_{2},a_{*})\wedge R_{2}(a_{3},a_{*}), and Aρ2(b,a1)ρ2(b,a2)ρ2(b,a3)A\models\rho_{2}(b,a_{1})\wedge\rho_{2}(b,a_{2})\wedge\rho_{2}(b,a_{3}).

Let AA be copacetic, and let bP(A)b\in P(A), aO(A)a\in O(A), i1,2i\in{1,2}. Then there are at most ii many aO(A)a^{\prime}\in O(A) with ARi(a,a)A\models R_{i}(a,a^{\prime}) and Aρi(b,a)A\models\rho_{i}(b,a^{\prime}). For NN the number of such aa^{\prime} that are defined, let biA,j(a)b^{A,j}_{\to^{i}}(a), 1jN1\leq j\leq N, denote the NN many such aa^{\prime} (so if i=2i=2 and there are two such aa^{\prime}, make an arbitrary choice of which is biA,1(a)b^{A,1}_{\to^{i}}(a) and which is biA,2(a)b^{A,2}_{\to^{i}}(a), while if i=1i=1, then biA,1(a)b^{A,1}_{\to^{i}}(a) is the sole such aa^{\prime}, if it exists.)

If BB is copacetic and ABA\subset B is a substructure of BB (and is therefore also copacetic), call AA closed in BB (denoted ABA\leq B) if

(i) For bP(A)b\in P(A), aO(A)a\in O(A), i{1,2}i\in\{1,2\}, 1ji1\leq j\leq i, if biB,j(a)b^{B,j}_{\to^{i}}(a) exists, then biB,j(a)Ab^{B,j}_{\to^{i}}(a)\in A.

(ii) Any R1(B)R2(B)R_{1}(B)\cup R_{2}(B)-path between nodes of O(A)O(A) lies in O(A)O(A): for all a1,anO(A)a_{1},a_{n}\in O(A), a2,an1O(B)a_{2},\ldots a_{n-1}\in O(B) which are distinct and distinct from a1a_{1}, ana_{n}, and i1,,in1{1,2}i_{1},\ldots,i_{n-1}\in\{1,2\}, if ARij(ai,ai+1)A\models R_{i_{j}}(a_{i},a_{i+1}) for 1jn11\leq j\leq n-1, then for all 2in12\leq i\leq n-1, aiO(A)a_{i}\in O(A).

Call a copacetic \mathcal{L}-structure AA connected if R1(A)R2(A)R_{1}(A)\cup R_{2}(A) forms a connected graph on O(A)O(A): for all a,aO(A)a,a^{\prime}\in O(A), there are a2,an1O(A)a_{2},\ldots a_{n-1}\in O(A), i1,,in1{1,2}i_{1},\ldots,i_{n-1}\in\{1,2\} for some nn, so that for a1=aa_{1}=a, an=aa_{n}=a^{\prime}, ARij(ai,ai+1)A\models R_{i_{j}}(a_{i},a_{i+1}) for all 1jn11\leq j\leq n-1. So if BB is copacetic and ABA\subseteq B, connectedness of AA supplants requirement (ii) of AA being closed in BB. Call a subset of AA a connected component of AA if it is a maximal connected subset of O(A)O(A).

Let OO be an undirected graph without cycles and with a 22-coloring of its edges, with R1R_{1}, R2R_{2} denoting edges of either color. Let ρ1,ρ2O\rho_{1},\rho_{2}\subset O, O=ρ1ρ2O=\rho_{1}\cup\rho_{2}, ρ1ρ2=\rho_{1}\cap\rho_{2}=\emptyset be a coloring of the vertices of OO so that, for i={1,2}i=\{1,2\}, no i+1i+1 distinct vertices of OO, lying on the boundary of the same RiR_{i}-ball of radius 11 (i.e. they have a common RiR_{i}-neighbor), are both colored by ρi\rho_{i}. Then we call ρ1,ρ2\rho_{1},\rho_{2} a (C4)-coloring of OO. For AA copacetic, OO(A)O^{\prime}\subseteq O(A), and ρ1,ρ2O\rho_{1},\rho_{2}\subseteq O^{\prime} a (C4)-coloring of OO^{\prime}, say that bP(A)b\in P(A) induces the (C4)-coloring ρ1,ρ2\rho_{1},\rho_{2} on OO^{\prime} if for i{1,2}i\in\{1,2\}, ρi={aO:Aρi(b,a)}\rho_{i}=\{a\in O^{\prime}:A\models\rho_{i}(b,a)\}.

The following assumptions on an \mathcal{L}-structure AA are expressible by a set of first-order sentences:

(T1T_{1}) (Copaceticity) AA is copacetic.

(T2T_{2}) (Completeness) For bP(A)b\in P(A), aO(A)a\in O(A), i{1,2}i\in\{1,2\}, if A¬ρi(b,a)A\models\neg\rho_{i}(b,a), then biA,j(a)b^{A,j}_{\to^{i}}(a) exists for 1ji1\leq j\leq i.

(T3T_{3}) (Tree extension) For CAC\subseteq A, and BCB\geq C finite and copacetic with P(B)=P(C)P(B)=P(C), there is an embedding ι:BA\iota:B\hookrightarrow A with ι|C=idC\iota|_{C}=\mathrm{id}_{C}.

(T4T_{4}) (Parameter introduction) For any n<ωn<\omega, finite connected sets O1,,OnO(A)O_{1},\ldots,O_{n}\subseteq O(A) so that there does not exist an R1R2R_{1}\vee R_{2}-path of length at most 2n2^{n} between a vertex of OiO_{i} and a vertex of OjO_{j} for any distinct i,jni,j\leq n (so in particular, OiO_{i} and OjO_{j} are disjoint), and (C4)-colorings ρ1i,ρ2iOi\rho^{i}_{1},\rho^{i}_{2}\subseteq O_{i} of OiO_{i} for ini\leq n, there are infinitely many bP(A)b\in P(A) so that, for each ini\leq n, bb induces the (C4)-coloring ρ1i,ρ2iOi\rho^{i}_{1},\rho^{i}_{2}\subseteq O_{i} on OiO_{i}.

Let T=T1T2T3T4T^{\not\exists}=T_{1}\cup T_{2}\cup T_{3}\cup T_{4}. We claim that TT^{\not\exists} is consistent. This will follow by induction from the following three claims:

(*) If AA is copacetic, bP(A)b\in P(A), aO(A)a\in O(A), i{1,2}i\in\{1,2\}, and 1ji1\leq j\leq i, there is a copacetic \mathcal{L}-structure AAA^{\prime}\supseteq A (i.e. containing AA as a substructure) so that biA,j(a)b^{A^{\prime},j}_{\to^{i}}(a) exists.

(**) If AA is copacetic, CAC\subseteq A, and BCB\geq C is finite and copacetic with P(B)=P(C)P(B)=P(C), there is a copacetic structure AAA^{\prime}\supseteq A and an embedding ι:BA\iota:B\hookrightarrow A^{\prime} with ι|C=idC\iota|_{C}=\mathrm{id}_{C}.

(***) If AA is copacetic, for any n<ωn<\omega, finite connected sets O1,,OnO(A)O_{1},\ldots,O_{n}\subseteq O(A) so that there does not exist an R1R2R_{1}\vee R_{2}-path of length at most 2n2^{n} between a vertex of OiO_{i} and a vertex of OjO_{j} for any distinct i,jni,j\leq n, and (C4)-colorings ρ1i,ρ2iOi\rho^{i}_{1},\rho^{i}_{2}\subseteq O_{i} of OiO_{i} for ini\leq n, there is some copacetic AAA^{\prime}\supset A and pP(A\A)p\in P(A^{\prime}\backslash A) so that, for each ini\leq n, pp induces the (C4)-coloring ρ1i,ρ2i\rho^{i}_{1},\rho^{i}_{2} on OiO_{i}.

We first show (*). Suppose biA,j(a)b^{A,j}_{\to^{i}}(a) does not already exist. Let A=A{}A^{\prime}=A\cup\{*\} for * a new point of sort OO, and let Ri(A)=R(A){(a,),(,a)}R_{i}(A^{\prime})=R(A)\cup\{(a,*),(*,a)\}, R3i(A)=R3i(A)R_{3-i}(A^{\prime})=R_{3-i}(A), ρ3i(A)=ρ3i(A)(P(A)\{b})×{}\rho_{3-i}(A^{\prime})=\rho_{3-i}(A)\cup(P(A)\backslash\{b\})\times\{*\}, ρi(A)=ρi(A){(b,)}\rho_{i}(A^{\prime})=\rho_{i}(A)\cup\{(b,*)\}. Then AA^{\prime} is copacetic; first, (C1)-(C3) are clearly satisfied. Second, no point of P(A)\{b}P(A)\backslash\{b\} can witness a failure of (C4), because AA is copacetic and * is not an R3iR_{3-i}-neighbor of any point of O(A)O(A^{\prime}). Finally, neither can bb witness a failure of (C4), because * is not an Ri3R_{i-3} neighbor of any point of O(A)O(A^{\prime}) and aa is the unique RiR_{i}-neighbor of * in O(A)O(A^{\prime}), that failure must by copaceticity of AA be witnessed on the boundary of the RiR_{i}-ball of radius 11 centered at aa. But because biA,j(a)b^{A,j}_{\to^{i}}(a) does not already exist, there are fewer than ii many RiR_{i}-neighbors aa^{\prime} of aa in O(A)O(A) with Aρi(b,a)A\models\rho_{i}(b,a^{\prime}), so there are at most ii many RiR_{i}-neighbors aa^{\prime} of AA in O(A)O(A^{\prime}) with Aρi(b,a)A\models\rho_{i}(b,a^{\prime}); thus the failure of (C4) is not in fact witnessed on this ball’s boundary. By construction, we can then choose biA,j(a)=b^{A^{\prime},j}_{\to^{i}}(a)=*.

We next show (**). For this we need the following claim:

Claim 2.1.

Let OO^{\prime} be undirected graph without cycles and with a 22-coloring of its edges, with R1R_{1}, R2R_{2} denoting edges of either color. Let OOO\subset O^{\prime} be a subgraph with the induced coloring, and with OOO\leq O^{\prime} (in the sense of (ii), so any path between two vertices of OO^{\prime} consisting of edges of any colors is contained in OO). Then any (C4)-coloring ρ1,ρ2\rho_{1},\rho_{2} of OO extends to a (C4)-coloring ρ1,ρ2\rho_{1}^{\prime},\rho^{\prime}_{2} of OO^{\prime}, which has the following additional property: if vO\Ov\in O^{\prime}\backslash O has an RiR_{i}-neighbor in OO, then vρ3iv\in\rho^{\prime}_{3-i}.

Proof.

By the assumption on paths in OO^{\prime} between two vertices of OO, we may decompose O\OO^{\prime}\backslash O into a disjoint union Oi\sqcup O^{i} of connected subgraphs, so that each OiO^{i} has at most one vertex viv_{i} with any neighbors in OO; viv_{i} will in fact have only one neighbor wiw_{i} in OO. For every OiO^{i} all of whose vertices have no neighbors in OO, let viv_{i} be an arbitrary vertex of OiO^{i}. Then inductively, we can order each OiO^{i} as a tree (i.e., a partial order with linearly ordered downsets) so that viv_{i} is the root, any node’s immediate successors are all neighbors of that node and, among any two neighbors, one must be an immediate successor of the other, and each maximal linearly ordered set is well-ordered of order type at most ω\omega. Extend ρ1,ρ2\rho_{1},\rho_{2} on each OiO_{i} as follows, starting from viv_{i} and proceeding by induction. If wiw_{i} is an RiR_{i}-neighbor of viv_{i}, color viv_{i} by ρ3i\rho^{\prime}_{3-i}; otherwise, color viv_{i} arbitrarily. Then for each vertex vv of OiO^{i}, each immediate successor of vv will be an RiR_{i}-neighbor of vv for some i{1,2}i\in\{1,2\}; color it by ρ3i\rho_{3-i}. No two distinct vertices v,wv,w with an RiR_{i}-distance of exactly 22 in OO^{\prime} can then be colored in ρi\rho^{i}: if the RiR_{i}-path between vv and ww goes through OO, then whichever of vv and ww is not in OO will be colored by ρ3i\rho^{\prime}_{3-i}, and if the RiR_{i}-path between vv and ww stays in OiO^{i}, whichever of vv and ww is not the least in the path will be colored by ρ3i\rho^{\prime}_{3-i}. This shows that ρ1,ρ2\rho^{\prime}_{1},\rho^{\prime}_{2} is a (C4)-coloring, and the additional property is immediate from the construction.

Now, take the set AA^{\prime} to be the disjoint union of AA and BB over CC; for notational simplicity we identify AA, BB and CC respectively with their images in AA^{\prime}. Let the R1,R2R_{1},R_{2}-structure on O(A)O(A^{\prime}) be given as follows: the identification on O(A)O(A) and O(B)O(B) preserves the RiR_{i}-structure, and O(A)O(A) and O(B)O(B) are freely amalgamated over O(C)O(C) (i.e. there are no RiR_{i}-edges between O(A\C)O(A\backslash C) and O(B\C)O(B\backslash C)). This guarantees (C1), and also guarantees (C2) by condition (ii) of CBC\leq B. Now let the ρ1,ρ2\rho_{1},\rho_{2}-structure on AA^{\prime} be given as follows: the identifications on AA and BB preserve the ρi\rho_{i}-structure, which, by the assumption that P(B)=P(C)P(B)=P(C), leaves us only by way of satisfying (C3) to define the ρ1,ρ2\rho_{1},\rho_{2}-structure on P(A\C)×O(B\C)P(A\backslash C)\times O(B\backslash C), and this will be the following. Let pP(A\C)p\in P(A\backslash C); the requirement that the ρi\rho_{i}-structure on AA is preserved tells us the (C4)-coloring that pp induces on O(C)O(C), and we extend this to a (C4)-coloring on O(B)O(B) as in Claim 2.1; here we use condition (ii) of CBC\leq B. We have defined the full \mathcal{L}-structure on AA^{\prime}, so it remains to show (C4); in other words, we show that pp induces a (C4)-coloring on AA^{\prime} in the case where pP(C)p\in P(C) and in the case where pP(A\C)p\in P(A\backslash C). In either case pp induces a (C4)-coloring on AA and on BB, so the only way (C4) can fail is on the boundary of an RiR_{i}-ball of radius 11 centered at cCc\in C. But (C4) cannot fail on the boundary of this ball, because it does not fail there in AA, and by condition (i) of CBC\leq B in the first case, or by the additional clause of Claim 2.1 in the second case, any RiR_{i}-neighbor of cc in B\CB\backslash C is colored by ρ3i\rho_{3-i} in the (C4)-coloring induced by pp on BB, so (C4) still cannot fail on the boundary of this ball in AA^{\prime}. So AA^{\prime} is a copacetic \mathcal{L}-structure containing AA, and clearly, the embedding ι\iota as in (**) exists, so this shows (**).

Finally, we show (***). For this, we need an additional combinatorial claim:

Claim 2.2.

Let OO be be undirected graph without cycles and with a 22-coloring of its edges, with R1R_{1}, R2R_{2} denoting edges of either color, and let O1,,OnOO_{1},\ldots,O_{n}\subseteq O be connected subsets so that there does not exist an R1R2R_{1}\vee R_{2}-path of length at most 2n2^{n} between a vertex of OiO_{i} and a vertex of OjO_{j} for any distinct i,jni,j\leq n. Let ρ1i,ρ2iOi\rho^{i}_{1},\rho^{i}_{2}\subseteq O_{i} be a (C4)-coloring of OiO_{i} for ini\leq n. Then there is some OOO^{\prime}\leq O containing O1OnO_{1}\cup\ldots\cup O_{n} and (C4)-coloring ρ1,ρ2\rho_{1},\rho_{2} of OO so that, for ini\leq n, ρ1,ρ2\rho_{1},\rho_{2} restricts to ρ1i,ρ2i\rho^{i}_{1},\rho^{i}_{2} on OiO_{i}.

Proof.

Considering each connected component of OO individually, we may assume OO to be connected. We prove this claim by induction on nn. Because we will later consider a variant of this construction where the case n=2n=2 is the main difference, we isolate this case, which is necessary for the induction, as a subclaim:

Subclaim 2.3.

Claim 2.2 is true where OO is connected and n=2n=2.

Proof.

Let II be the shortest path between O1O_{1} to O2O_{2}, which will consist, ordered in the direction from O1O_{1} to O2O_{2}, of o0,ono_{0},\ldots o_{n}, for o0O1o_{0}\in O_{1}, onO2o_{n}\in O_{2}, o1on1O\(O1O2)o_{1}\ldots o_{n-1}\in O\backslash(O_{1}\cup O_{2}), and n5n\geq 5. Because O1O_{1} and O2O_{2} are connected, it suffices to color O1O2IO_{1}\cup O_{2}\cup I so as to extend the colorings ρ1i,ρ2i\rho^{i}_{1},\rho^{i}_{2} on OiO_{i} for i=1,2i=1,2, and to preserve the condition of being a (C4)-coloring. So color O1O_{1} by ρ11,ρ21\rho^{1}_{1},\rho^{1}_{2}, O2O_{2} by ρ12,ρ22\rho^{2}_{1},\rho^{2}_{2}, and color o1on1o_{1}\ldots o_{n-1} as follows: first, color o1o_{1} by ρ3i\rho_{3-i}, for ii so that o0o_{0} is an RiR_{i}-neighbor of o1o_{1}, and color on1o_{n-1} by ρ3i\rho_{3-i}, so that on1o_{n-1} is an RiR_{i}-neighbor of ono_{n}. Since we colored O1O_{1} by ρ11,ρ21\rho^{1}_{1},\rho^{1}_{2} and O2O_{2} by ρ12,ρ22\rho^{2}_{1},\rho^{2}_{2}, the only vertices oo of the OiO_{i} so that the condition of being a (C4)-coloring can fail in O1O2IO_{1}\cup O_{2}\cup I on the boundary of the RiR_{i}-ball of radius 11 centered at oo are o0o_{0} and ono_{n}, and we have just prevented this. It remains to color o2,on2o_{2},\ldots o_{n-2}; we color them all by ρ2\rho_{2}. The only remaining vertices oo of O1O2IO_{1}\cup O_{2}\cup I where the condition of being a (C4)-coloring can fail on the 11-ball centered at OO are now o1on1o_{1}\ldots o_{n-1}, but the boundaries of the 11-balls centered at those vertices in O1O2IO_{1}\cup O_{2}\cup I have just two points, at least one of which must be colored by ρ2\rho_{2}, because n5n\geq 5 and the interval {o2,on2}\{o_{2},\ldots o_{n-2}\} whose points we colored by ρ2\rho_{2} contains at least one of the two neighbors of each o1,,on1o_{1},\ldots,o_{n-1}. So the condition of being a (C4)-coloring cannot fail there. ∎

We now consider the general case of the induction. Without loss of generality, we may assume that On1O_{n-1} and OnO_{n} have minimum distance d>2nd>2^{n} among any Oi,OjO_{i},O_{j} with i,ji,j distinct. By Lemma 2.3, we may find a (C4)-coloring (ρ)1n1,(ρ)2n1(\rho^{\prime})^{n-1}_{1},(\rho^{\prime})^{n-1}_{2} of On1=:On1OnIO^{\prime}_{n-1}=:O_{n-1}\cup O_{n}\cup I extending ρ1n1,ρ2n1\rho^{n-1}_{1},\rho^{n-1}_{2} and ρ1n,ρ2n\rho^{n}_{1},\rho^{n}_{2}, where II is the shortest path, which will be of length dd, between On1O_{n-1} and OnO_{n}. Clearly On1O^{\prime}_{n-1} is connected, so it suffices to show that no two of O1,On2,On1O_{1},\ldots O_{n-2},O^{\prime}_{n-1} have distance less than d2>2n1\frac{d}{2}>2^{n-1}, because then we can apply the inductive step. Let in2i\leq n-2; it suffices to show that OiO_{i} does not have distance less than d2\frac{d}{2} from On1O^{\prime}_{n-1}. Suppose otherwise; then it has distance less than d2\frac{d}{2} from some point pp of On1O^{\prime}_{n-1}, but by definition of On1O^{\prime}_{n-1}, pp must have distance at most d2\frac{d}{2} from either On1O_{n-1} or OnO_{n}. So OiO_{i} must have distance less than d2+d2=d\frac{d}{2}+\frac{d}{2}=d from either On1O_{n-1} or OnO_{n}, contradicting minimality of dd. ∎

By Claims 2.2 and 2.1, there is a (C4)-coloring ρ1,ρ2\rho_{1},\rho_{2} on O(A)O(A) extending the (C4)-coloring ρ1i,ρ2i\rho^{i}_{1},\rho^{i}_{2} on OiO_{i} for each ini\leq n. So we can extend AA to A=ApA^{\prime}=A\cup p, where pP(A\A)p\in P(A^{\prime}\backslash A), and define the relations ρ1\rho_{1} and ρ2\rho_{2} on O(A)×{p}O(A)\times\{p\} so that pp induces the (C4)-coloring ρ1,ρ2\rho_{1},\rho_{2} on O(A)O(A). This proves (***), and the consistency of TT^{\not\exists}.

We call a copacetic \mathcal{L}-structure complete if it satisfies axiom T2T_{2}; completeness of AA will always supplant condition (i) of ABA\leq B.

We now prove that TT^{\not\exists} has the following embedding property:

Lemma 2.4.

Let 𝕄\mathbb{M} be a sufficiently saturated model of TT^{\not\exists}. Let C𝕄C\leq\mathbb{M}, and let BCB\geq C be a small copacetic \mathcal{L}-structure. Assume additionally that BB is complete. Then there is an embedding ι:B𝕄\iota:B\hookrightarrow\mathbb{M} that is the identity on CC and satisfies ι(B)𝕄\iota(B)\leq\mathbb{M}.

Proof.

We prove the lemma in the following two cases:

(1) P(B)=P(C)P(B)=P(C)

(2) O(B)=O(C)O(B)=O(C) and |P(B\C)|=1|P(B\backslash C)|=1.

These cases suffice, because the closed extension CBC\leq B can be decomposed into a closed extension satisfying (1) followed by an ascending chain of (obviously closed) extensions satisfying (2), and the property ι(B)𝕄\iota(B)\leq\mathbb{M} is clearly preserved under taking unions.

To prove case (1), by completeness of BB and saturatedness of 𝕄\mathbb{M}, it suffices to find, for arbitrarily large n<ωn<\omega, an embedding ιn:B𝕄\iota_{n}:B\hookrightarrow\mathbb{M} that is the identity on CC and so that points of ιn(B)\iota_{n}(B) that are not connected by a path in ιn(B)\iota_{n}(B) have distance at least nn in 𝕄\mathbb{M}. We claim that, for every copacetic BCB^{\prime}\geq C, and any points b,bO(B)b,b^{\prime}\in O(B) so that bb and bb^{\prime} belong to distinct connected components of BB and bb^{\prime} belongs to a connected component of BB not containing any point of CC, there is some copacetic B′′BB^{\prime\prime}\supseteq B^{\prime} so that CB′′C\leq B^{\prime\prime}, that consists of BB^{\prime} together with a path of from bb to bb^{\prime} of length greater than nn. One way to do this is to add an R1R_{1}-path of length greater than nn (and greater than 22) between bb and bb^{\prime}, so that all induced (C4)-colorings color the new nodes of this path by ρ2\rho_{2}. By choice of induced colorings, the resulting \mathcal{L}-structure B′′B^{\prime\prime} will satisfy (C4) and condition (i) of CBC\leq B, and B′′B^{\prime\prime} will also satisfy condition (ii) of CBC\leq B by the assumption of what connected components of B′′B^{\prime\prime} have bb and bb^{\prime} as members. By repeatedly applying this claim to connect each connected component of BB not meeting CC to some fixed connected component of BB meeting CC (or an arbitrary fixed connected component of BB, if CC is empty), we then obtain a copacetic \mathcal{L}-structure BBB^{\prime}\supseteq B with P(B)=P(C)P(B^{\prime})=P(C) and BCB^{\prime}\geq C such that, for any b,bBb,b^{\prime}\in B that are not connected in BB, either bb and bb^{\prime} have finite distance greater than nn in BB^{\prime}, or they belong to different connected components of BB^{\prime} meeting CC. Now suppose ι:B𝕄\iota^{\prime}:B^{\prime}\hookrightarrow\mathbb{M} is any embedding restricting to the identity on CC; then for ι(b),ι(b)ι(B)\iota^{\prime}(b),\iota^{\prime}(b^{\prime})\in\iota^{\prime}(B), that are not connected in ι(B)\iota^{\prime}(B), either bb and bb^{\prime} have finite distance greater than nn in BB^{\prime}, so ι(b)\iota(b) and ι(b)\iota(b^{\prime}) have distance greater than nn in 𝕄\mathbb{M} as desired, or bb and bb^{\prime} belong to different connected components of BB^{\prime} meeting CC, so ι(b)\iota(b) and ι(b)\iota(b^{\prime}) belong to different connected components of ι(B)\iota(B^{\prime}) meeting CC, so are not connected in 𝕄\mathbb{M} because C𝕄C\leq\mathbb{M}; then ιn=ι|B\iota_{n}=\iota^{\prime}|_{B} is as desired. So if we can show that, for any small, copacetic \mathcal{L}-structure BCB^{\prime}\geq C with P(B)=P(C)P(B^{\prime})=P(C), there is an embedding ι:B𝕄\iota:B^{\prime}\to\mathbb{M} that is the identity on CC (with no additional requirements on ι(B)\iota(B)), we will have proven case (1). Note that if B0BB_{0}\subseteq B^{\prime}, B0CB0B_{0}\cap C\leq B_{0}, so we may assume that BB^{\prime} is finite by saturatedness of 𝕄\mathbb{M}. Then we can just apply tree extension.

To prove case (2), let ρ1,ρ2\rho_{1},\rho_{2} be the (C4)-coloring induced by pp, where {p}=P(B\C)\{p\}=P(B\backslash C), on CC. Since BB is complete and C𝕄C\leq\mathbb{M}, any embedding ι:B𝕄\iota:B\to\mathbb{M} with ι|C=id\iota|_{C}=\mathrm{id} will satisfy ι(B)𝕄\iota(B)\leq\mathbb{M}. By saturatedness of 𝕄\mathbb{M} it suffices to find, for every finite P0P(C)P_{0}\subset P(C) and finite C0O(C)C_{0}\subset O(C), some p𝕄\P0p\in\mathbb{M}\backslash P_{0} inducing the (C4)-coloring ρ1|C0,ρ2|C0\rho_{1}|_{C_{0}},\rho_{2}|_{C_{0}} on C0C_{0}. We may enlarge C0C_{0} to a finite subset of O(C)O(C) consisting of a finite union of nn connected sets that are not connected in CC, so by condition (ii) of C𝕄C\leq\mathbb{M}, are not connected in 𝕄\mathbb{M}; in particular, any two of them have distance greater than 2n2^{n} in 𝕄\mathbb{M}. So by parameter introduction, we may find infinitely many pP(𝕄)p\in P(\mathbb{M}) inducing the (C4)-coloring ρ1|C0,ρ2|C0\rho_{1}|_{C_{0}},\rho_{2}|_{C_{0}} on C0C_{0}, so in particular, one not belonging to P0P_{0}.

We now fix a sufficiently saturated 𝕄T\mathbb{M}\models T^{\not\exists}, which we take as the ambient model; for pP(𝕄)p\in P(\mathbb{M}), fix the notation, pij=:pi𝕄,jp^{j}_{\to^{i}}=:p^{\mathbb{M},j}_{\to^{i}} The following quantifier elimination is a corollary of the above:

Corollary 2.5.

Let A,B𝕄A,B\leq\mathbb{M}. Then if qftp(A)=qftp(B)\mathrm{qftp}_{\mathcal{L}}(A)=\mathrm{qftp}_{\mathcal{L}}(B), tp(A)=tp(B)\mathrm{tp}(A)=\mathrm{tp}(B).

Proof.

For any A𝕄A\leq\mathbb{M} and a𝕄a\in\mathbb{M}, there is some (small) B𝕄B\leq\mathbb{M} so that AaBAa\subset B, and in particular ABA\leq B. Because B𝕄B\leq\mathbb{M} and 𝕄\mathbb{M} satisfies completeness, BB is complete. So the corollary follows by Lemma 2.4 by a back-and-forth argument. ∎

Next, we show that TT^{\not\exists} is NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1}. By Theorem 9.1 of [12], it suffices to find an invariant ternary relation \mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}} between subsets of 𝕄\mathbb{M} over models with the following properties:

(a) Strong finite character: For all a,ba,b and MTM\models T, if a/Mba\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mathchar 12854\relax$\kern 8.00134pt\hss}\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mathchar 12854\relax$\kern 8.00134pt\hss}\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mathchar 12854\relax$\kern 8.00134pt\hss}\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mathchar 12854\relax$\kern 8.00134pt\hss}\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{M}b, then there is some formula φ(x,b)tp(a/Mb)\varphi(x,b)\in\mathrm{tp}(a/Mb), where φ(x,y)\varphi(x,y) has parameters in MM, such that for every aφ(x,b)a^{\prime}\models\varphi(x,b), a/Mba^{\prime}\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mathchar 12854\relax$\kern 8.00134pt\hss}\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mathchar 12854\relax$\kern 8.00134pt\hss}\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mathchar 12854\relax$\kern 8.00134pt\hss}\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mathchar 12854\relax$\kern 8.00134pt\hss}\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{M}b.

(b) Existence over models: for all aa and MTM\models T, aMMa\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{M}M.

(c) Monotonicity: For all AAA^{\prime}\subseteq A, BBB^{\prime}\subseteq B, MTM\models T, AMBA\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{M}B implies AMBA^{\prime}\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{M}B^{\prime}.

(d) Symmetry: For all a,ba,b and MTM\models T, aMba\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{M}b implies bMab\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{M}a (and vice versa).

(e) The independence theorem: for any a,a,b,ca,a^{\prime},b,c and MTM\models T, aMba\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{M}b, aMca^{\prime}\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{M}c, bMcb\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{M}c and aMaa\equiv_{M}a^{\prime} implies that there is a′′a^{\prime\prime} with a′′bMaba^{\prime\prime}b\equiv_{M}ab, a′′cMaca^{\prime\prime}c\equiv_{M}a^{\prime}c and a′′Mbca^{\prime\prime}\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{M}bc.

First, note that for any AA, there is AAA^{\prime}\supseteq A such that A𝕄A^{\prime}\leq\mathbb{M} and for all A′′AA^{\prime\prime}\supseteq A with A′′𝕄A^{\prime\prime}\leq\mathbb{M}, AA′′A^{\prime}\subseteq A^{\prime\prime}. Denote this cl(A)\mathrm{cl}(A); clearly, this is contained in acl(A)\mathrm{acl}(A) (and it can even be checked that cl(A)=acl(A)\mathrm{cl}(A)=\mathrm{acl}(A)). This allows us to define \mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}: AMBA\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{M}B if cl(MA)cl(MB)=M\mathrm{cl}(MA)\cap\mathrm{cl}(MB)=M, and every (R1(𝕄)R2(𝕄)R_{1}(\mathbb{M})\cup R_{2}(\mathbb{M}))-path between a point of O(cl(MA)\M)O(\mathrm{cl}(MA)\backslash M) and O(cl(MB)\M)O(\mathrm{cl}(MB)\backslash M) contains a point of MM.

We see this has strong finite character: for a/Mba\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mathchar 12854\relax$\kern 8.00134pt\hss}\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mathchar 12854\relax$\kern 8.00134pt\hss}\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mathchar 12854\relax$\kern 8.00134pt\hss}\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mathchar 12854\relax$\kern 8.00134pt\hss}\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{M}b, a0cl(aM)a_{0}\in\mathrm{cl}(aM), b0cl(bM)b_{0}\in\mathrm{cl}(bM) the endpoints of the path of length nn witnessing this, let φ1(y,b)\varphi_{1}(y,b) isolate b0b_{0} over MbMb, φ2(x)\varphi_{2}(x) say that xx is not within distance nn of the closest point of MM to some (any) b0φ1(x,b)b^{\prime}_{0}\models\varphi_{1}(x,b) (which would be required, should there be a (non-self-overlapping) path of length nn between xx and b0b_{0} going through MM), and φ3(x,b)\varphi_{3}(x,b) say that there is a path of length nn from xx to some point cc satisfying φ1(c,b)\models\varphi_{1}(c,b). Then φ(x,b)=:φ2(x)φ3(x,b)\varphi(x,b)=:\varphi_{2}(x)\wedge\varphi_{3}(x,b) suffices.

Existence over models, monotonicity, and symmetry are immediate. So it remains to show the independence theorem. By definition of \mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}, we may assume a=cl(aM)a=\mathrm{cl}(aM) and similar for a,b,ca^{\prime},b,c. We first give an analysis of the structure of pairs a,ba,b with aMba\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{M}b:

Lemma 2.6.

Let a=cl(aM)a=\mathrm{cl}(aM), b=cl(bM)b=\mathrm{cl}(bM), and aMba\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{M}b. Then cl(ab)=ab\mathrm{cl}(ab)=a^{*}b^{*}, where for P0=P(ab)P_{0}=P(ab), aa^{*} is the closure of aa under the functions pijp^{j}_{\to^{i}} for pP0p\in P_{0} (so in particular, P(a)=P(a)P(a^{*})=P(a)), and bb^{*} is the closure of bb under these same functions. Every point of O(a\a)O(a^{*}\backslash a) is connected by some (R1R2R_{1}\vee R_{2})-path to a point of a\Ma\backslash M, and aaa\leq a^{*}; similarly for bb^{*}.

Proof.

The second sentence follows from the definition of the pijp^{j}_{\to^{i}}, and the fact that M,a,b𝕄M,a,b\leq\mathbb{M}; it remains to show that ab𝕄a^{*}b^{*}\leq\mathbb{M}. But aba^{*}b^{*} is the closure of abab under the functions pijp^{j}_{\to^{i}} for pP0p\in P_{0}, so is complete, and condition (i) is satisfied. Moreover, O(a)O(b)𝕄O(a)O(b)\leq\mathbb{M} (i.e., condition (ii) of being closed in 𝕄\mathbb{M} holds for abab): any path with endpoints in O(a)O(b)O(a)O(b) and intermediate points all in O(𝕄\ab)O(\mathbb{M}\backslash ab) must, because aMba\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{M}b and Ma,bM\subseteq a,b, have both endpoints in either of O(a)O(a) or O(b)O(b), a contradiction because O(a)O(a) and O(b)O(b) are closed in 𝕄\mathbb{M}. Because every point of O(a)O(b)O(a^{*})O(b^{*}) is connected to abab by the second clause of this lemma, condition (ii) of ab𝕄a^{*}b^{*}\leq\mathbb{M} then follows from O(a)O(b)𝕄O(a)O(b)\leq\mathbb{M}. ∎

In the following, for P0P(𝕄)P_{0}\subset P(\mathbb{M}) and A𝕄A\subset\mathbb{M}, let clP0(A)\mathrm{cl}_{P_{0}}(A) denote the closure of AA under pijp^{j}_{\to^{i}} for pP0p\in P_{0}, as in Lemma 2.6. We want to find a~,b~,c~\tilde{a},\tilde{b},\tilde{c} so that a~b~Mab\tilde{a}\tilde{b}\equiv_{M}ab, a~c~Mac\tilde{a}\tilde{c}\equiv_{M}a^{\prime}c, b~c~Mbc\tilde{b}\tilde{c}\equiv_{M}bc, a~Mb~c~\tilde{a}\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{M}\tilde{b}\tilde{c}. Let bc=clP(b)P(c)(b)b^{*_{c}}=\mathrm{cl}_{P(b)P(c)}(b), cb=clP(b)P(c)(c)c^{*_{b}}=\mathrm{cl}_{P(b)P(c)}(c), ba=clP(a)P(b)(b)b^{*_{a}}=\mathrm{cl}_{P(a)P(b)}(b), ca=clP(a)P(c)(c)c^{*_{a^{\prime}}}=\mathrm{cl}_{P(a^{\prime})P(c)}(c), ab=clP(a)P(b)(a)a^{*_{b}}=\mathrm{cl}_{P(a)P(b)}(a), ac=clP(a)P(c)(a)a^{*_{c}}=\mathrm{cl}_{P(a^{\prime})P(c)}(a^{\prime}). We now build a copacetic \mathcal{L}-structure extending MM as follows. Let A0=:a~0b~0c~0A_{0}=:\tilde{a}_{0}\tilde{b}_{0}\tilde{c}_{0} where R1,R2R_{1},R_{2} is defined on O(a~0),O(b~0),O(c~0)O(\tilde{a}_{0}),O(\tilde{b}_{0}),O(\tilde{c}_{0}) so that these are freely amalgamated sets isomorphic to O(a),O(b),O(c)O(a),O(b),O(c) over O(M)O(M) (so in particular, O(a)O(b)O(M)qftpO(a~0)O(b~0)O(a)O(b)\equiv^{\mathcal{L}-\mathrm{qftp}}_{O(M)}O(\tilde{a}_{0})O(\tilde{b}_{0}) because aMba\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{M}b, and so on), and so that P(a~0),P(b~0),P(c~0)P(\tilde{a}_{0}),P(\tilde{b}_{0}),P(\tilde{c}_{0}) and ρ1,ρ2\rho_{1},\rho_{2} are defined so that a~0b~0Mqftpab\tilde{a}_{0}\tilde{b}_{0}\equiv^{\mathcal{L}-\mathrm{qftp}}_{M}ab, a~0c~0Mqftpac\tilde{a}_{0}\tilde{c}_{0}\equiv^{\mathcal{L}-\mathrm{qftp}}_{M}a^{\prime}c, b~0c~0Mqftpbc\tilde{b}_{0}\tilde{c}_{0}\equiv^{\mathcal{L}-\mathrm{qftp}}_{M}bc; this makes sense because aMaa\equiv_{M}a^{\prime}. Then A0A_{0} is copacetic, because the only way axiom (C4) can fail is, without loss of generality, when there is pP(a~0\M)p\in P(\tilde{a}_{0}\backslash M), o1O(b~0\M)o_{1}\in O(\tilde{b}_{0}\backslash M), o2O(c~0\M)o_{2}\in O(\tilde{c}_{0}\backslash M) so that o1,o2o_{1},o_{2} lie on the boundary of some common R1R_{1}-ball and A0ρ1(p,o1)ρ1(p,o2)A_{0}\models\rho_{1}(p,o_{1})\wedge\rho_{1}(p,o_{2}). Because O(b~0),O(c~0)O(\tilde{b}_{0}),O(\tilde{c}_{0}) are freely amalgamated over MM, the only way the former can happen is for o1o_{1} and o2o_{2} to have a common R1R_{1}-neighbor mMm\in M. But then (say) o1=p11(m)a~0o_{1}=p^{1}_{\to^{1}}(m)\in\tilde{a}_{0}, contradicting a~0b~0=M\tilde{a}_{0}\cap\tilde{b}_{0}=M. Now extend A0A_{0} to A1=:a~b~a~c~b~a~b~c~c~a~c~b~A_{1}=:\tilde{a}^{*_{\tilde{b}}}\tilde{a}^{*_{\tilde{c}}}\tilde{b}^{*_{\tilde{a}}}\tilde{b}^{*_{\tilde{c}}}\tilde{c}^{*_{\tilde{a}}}\tilde{c}^{*_{\tilde{b}}}, where

(1)a~b~=a~0O(a~b~\a~0)\tilde{a}^{*_{\tilde{b}}}=\tilde{a}_{0}\cup O(\tilde{a}^{*_{\tilde{b}}}\backslash\tilde{a}_{0}), a~c~=a~0O(a~c~\a~0)\tilde{a}^{*_{\tilde{c}}}=\tilde{a}_{0}\cup O(\tilde{a}^{*_{\tilde{c}}}\backslash\tilde{a}_{0}), b~a~=b~0O(b~a~\b~0)\tilde{b}^{*_{\tilde{a}}}=\tilde{b}_{0}\cup O(\tilde{b}^{*_{\tilde{a}}}\backslash\tilde{b}_{0}), b~c~=b~0O(b~c~\b~0)\tilde{b}^{*_{\tilde{c}}}=\tilde{b}_{0}\cup O(\tilde{b}^{*_{\tilde{c}}}\backslash\tilde{b}_{0}), c~a~=c~0O(c~a~\c~0)\tilde{c}^{*_{\tilde{a}}}=\tilde{c}_{0}\cup O(\tilde{c}^{*_{\tilde{a}}}\backslash\tilde{c}_{0}), c~b~=c~0O(c~b~\c~0)\tilde{c}^{*_{\tilde{b}}}=\tilde{c}_{0}\cup O(\tilde{c}^{*_{\tilde{b}}}\backslash\tilde{c}_{0}),

(2) O(a~b~\a~0)O(\tilde{a}^{*_{\tilde{b}}}\backslash\tilde{a}_{0}), O(a~c~\a~0)O(\tilde{a}^{*_{\tilde{c}}}\backslash\tilde{a}_{0}), O(b~a~\b~0)O(\tilde{b}^{*_{\tilde{a}}}\backslash\tilde{b}_{0}), O(b~c~\b~0)O(\tilde{b}^{*_{\tilde{c}}}\backslash\tilde{b}_{0}), O(c~a~\c~0)O(\tilde{c}^{*_{\tilde{a}}}\backslash\tilde{c}_{0}), O(c~b~\c~0)O(\tilde{c}^{*_{\tilde{b}}}\backslash\tilde{c}_{0}) are pairwise disjoint and disjoint from A0A_{0}

(3) The only RiR_{i}-edges of A1A_{1} are those of A0A_{0}, as well as those required to make O(a~b~)O(M)qftpO(ab)O(\tilde{a}^{*_{\tilde{b}}})\equiv^{\mathcal{L}-\mathrm{qftp}}_{O(M)}O(a^{*_{b}}), O(a~c~)O(M)qftpO(ac)O(\tilde{a}^{*_{\tilde{c}}})\equiv^{\mathcal{L}-\mathrm{qftp}}_{O(M)}O(a^{\prime*_{c}}), O(b~a~)O(M)qftpO(ba)O(\tilde{b}^{*_{\tilde{a}}})\equiv^{\mathcal{L}-\mathrm{qftp}}_{O(M)}O(b^{*_{a}}), O(b~c~)O(M)qftpO(bc)O(\tilde{b}^{*_{\tilde{c}}})\equiv^{\mathcal{L}-\mathrm{qftp}}_{O(M)}O(b^{*_{c}}), O(c~a~)O(M)qftpO(ca)O(\tilde{c}^{*_{\tilde{a}}})\equiv^{\mathcal{L}-\mathrm{qftp}}_{O(M)}O(c^{*_{a^{\prime}}}), O(c~b~)O(M)qftpO(cb)O(\tilde{c}^{*_{\tilde{b}}})\equiv^{\mathcal{L}-\mathrm{qftp}}_{O(M)}O(c^{*_{b}}).

(4) Let us extend ρ1ρ2\rho_{1}\rho_{2} where required so that a~b~b~a~Mqftpabba\tilde{a}^{*_{\tilde{b}}}\tilde{b}^{*_{\tilde{a}}}\equiv^{\mathcal{L}-\mathrm{qftp}}_{M}a^{*_{b}}b^{*_{a}}, a~c~c~a~Mqftpacca\tilde{a}^{*_{\tilde{c}}}\tilde{c}^{*_{\tilde{a}}}\equiv^{\mathcal{L}-\mathrm{qftp}}_{M}a^{\prime*_{c}}c^{*_{a^{\prime}}}, b~c~c~b~Mqftpbccb\tilde{b}^{*_{\tilde{c}}}\tilde{c}^{*_{\tilde{b}}}\equiv^{\mathcal{L}-\mathrm{qftp}}_{M}b^{*_{c}}c^{*_{b}}. Because a~b~b~a~,a~c~c~a~,b~c~c~b~\tilde{a}^{*_{\tilde{b}}}\tilde{b}^{*_{\tilde{a}}},\tilde{a}^{*_{\tilde{c}}}\tilde{c}^{*_{\tilde{a}}},\tilde{b}^{*_{\tilde{c}}}\tilde{c}^{*_{\tilde{b}}} are already known to satisfy (C4), a failure of (C4), which would then be witnessed by pP(A1)p\in P(A_{1}), o1,o2,o3O(A1)o_{1},o_{2},o_{3}\in O(A_{1}) (with the last two perhaps equal), could now happen in the following two cases (among the instances where the ρi\rho_{i} are yet defined), both of which we rule out. First, one of the oio_{i} is in a\A0a^{\dagger}\backslash{A_{0}}, where aa^{\dagger} is one of a~b~a~c~,b~a~b~c~,c~a~c~b~\tilde{a}^{*_{\tilde{b}}}\tilde{a}^{*_{\tilde{c}}},\tilde{b}^{*_{\tilde{a}}}\tilde{b}^{*_{\tilde{c}}},\tilde{c}^{*_{\tilde{a}}}\tilde{c}^{*_{\tilde{b}}}, and the other is in A1\aA_{1}\backslash a^{\dagger}. But then, by the connectedness claim in the second clause of Lemma 2.6, (3) and the construction of O(A0)O(A_{0}) tell us that these two oio_{i} must have distance at least 22 apart, so a failure of (C4) cannot arise here. The other case is where o1,o2,o3ao_{1},o_{2},o_{3}\in a^{\dagger} for aa^{\dagger} one of a~b~a~c~,b~a~b~c~,c~a~c~b~\tilde{a}^{*_{\tilde{b}}}\tilde{a}^{*_{\tilde{c}}},\tilde{b}^{*_{\tilde{a}}}\tilde{b}^{*_{\tilde{c}}},\tilde{c}^{*_{\tilde{a}}}\tilde{c}^{*_{\tilde{b}}}, and some two do not belong to the same a~b~,a~c~,b~a~,b~c~,c~a~,c~b~\tilde{a}^{*_{\tilde{b}}},\tilde{a}^{*_{\tilde{c}}},\tilde{b}^{*_{\tilde{a}}},\tilde{b}^{*_{\tilde{c}}},\tilde{c}^{*_{\tilde{a}}},\tilde{c}^{*_{\tilde{b}}}; then pap\in a^{\dagger} because this is the only way the ρi\rho_{i} can be defined so far for pp, o1,o2,o3o_{1},o_{2},o_{3}. Then these two ojo_{j}, say o1o_{1} and o2o_{2} must satisfy ρi(p,o1),ρi(p,o2)\rho_{i}(p,o_{1}),\rho_{i}(p,o_{2}) for some i{1,2}i\in\{1,2\}, and must be common RiR_{i}-neighbors of the evident a~,b~,c~\tilde{a},\tilde{b},\tilde{c} while lying outside of this a~,b~,c~\tilde{a},\tilde{b},\tilde{c}. But this is impossible, by the claim aaa\leq a^{*}, bbb\leq b^{*} of Lemma 2.6. Therefore, we do not yet get a failure of (C4), and it remains to extend ρ1,ρ2\rho_{1},\rho_{2} to get (C3) while maintaining (C4), which we do in the next step.

(5) By the claim aaa\leq a^{*}, bbb\leq b^{*} in the second clause of Lemma 2.6, we can use Claim 2.1 to extend ρ1,ρ2\rho_{1},\rho_{2} where not yet defined, maintaining (C4) by the description of the R1,R2R_{1},R_{2}-structure in (3), and thereby producing a copacetic \mathcal{L}-structure.

Observe also the following:

(6) In A0A_{0}, there is no path between a~\tilde{a} and b~c~\tilde{b}\tilde{c} not going through MM. So by the connectedness claim in Lemma 2.6 applied to cb,bcc^{*_{b}},b^{*_{c}}, in A1A_{1} there is no path between a~\tilde{a} and c~b~b~c~\tilde{c}^{*_{\tilde{b}}}\tilde{b}^{*_{\tilde{c}}} not going through MM.

(7). By construction, O(a~),O(b~),O(c~)O(\tilde{a}),O(\tilde{b}),O(\tilde{c}) are closed in O(A1)O(A_{1}). So by the proof of the first clause of Lemma 2.6, a~b~b~a~,a~c~c~a~,b~c~c~b~\tilde{a}^{*_{\tilde{b}}}\tilde{b}^{*_{\tilde{a}}},\tilde{a}^{*_{\tilde{c}}}\tilde{c}^{*_{\tilde{a}}},\tilde{b}^{*_{\tilde{c}}}\tilde{c}^{*_{\tilde{b}}} are each closed in A1A_{1} (and are also each complete).

Finally, we extend A1A_{1} to a complete copacetic \mathcal{L}-structure, so that (6) and (7) still hold replacing A1A_{1} with A2A_{2}; since a~b~b~a~,a~c~c~a~,b~c~c~b~\tilde{a}^{*_{\tilde{b}}}\tilde{b}^{*_{\tilde{a}}},\tilde{a}^{*_{\tilde{c}}}\tilde{c}^{*_{\tilde{a}}},\tilde{b}^{*_{\tilde{c}}}\tilde{c}^{*_{\tilde{b}}} are complete, to preserve (7) we must just preserve clause (ii). We can extend A1A_{1} to a complete copacetic \mathcal{L}-structure just by repeated applications of the proof of (ii). But notice that this proceeds just by successively adding nodes in the sort OO with exactly one R1R2R_{1}\vee R_{2}-neighbor in the previously added nodes, so adds no new paths between nodes in O(A1)O(A_{1}). So (6) and (7) are in fact preserved.

Note that ABCA\leq B\leq C implies ACA\leq C, so by (4) and (7) (i.e., the version where A1A_{1} is replaced with A2A_{2}), MA2M\leq A_{2}. Now use Lemma 2.4 to obtain an embedding ι:A2𝕄\iota:A_{2}\hookrightarrow\mathbb{M} which is the identity on MM, and such that ι(A2)𝕄\iota(A_{2})\leq\mathbb{M}. Let a~=ι(a~0)\tilde{a}=\iota(\tilde{a}_{0}), b~=ι(b~0)\tilde{b}=\iota(\tilde{b}_{0}), c~=ι(c~0)\tilde{c}=\iota(\tilde{c}_{0}). Then (using Corollary 2.5) by (4), (7) (again, the version where A1A_{1} is replaced with A2A_{2}), ι(A2)M\iota(A_{2})\leq M, and the first clause of Lemma 2.6, a~b~Mab\tilde{a}\tilde{b}\equiv_{M}ab, a~c~Mac\tilde{a}\tilde{c}\equiv_{M}a^{\prime}c, b~c~Mbc\tilde{b}\tilde{c}\equiv_{M}bc. Moreover, by (6) (yet again, the version where A1A_{1} is replaced with A2A_{2}) and ι(A2)M\iota(A_{2})\leq M , a~Mb~c~\tilde{a}\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{M}\tilde{b}\tilde{c}. So we have proven the independence theorem for \mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}, and TT^{\not\exists} is NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1}.

It remains to show that TT^{\not\exists} does not satisfy the existence axiom. Let p(x)p(x) be the unique type in the sort PP (in one variable) over \emptyset. Let oO(𝕄)o\in O(\mathbb{M}). Then p(x)ρ1(x,o)ρ2(x,o)p(x)\vdash\rho_{1}(x,o)\vee\rho_{2}(x,o), by (C3). We show that ρ1(x,o)\rho_{1}(x,o) 22-divides over \emptyset. We can find an \emptyset-indiscernible sequence {oi}i<ω\{o_{i}\}_{i<\omega}, o0=oo_{0}=o, so that the oio_{i} lie on the boundary of some fixed R1R_{1}-ball of radius 11. Then {ρ(x,oi)}i<ω\{\rho(x,o_{i})\}_{i<\omega} is 22-inconsistent by (C4), so ρ1(x,oi)\rho_{1}(x,o_{i}) 22-divides over \emptyset. That ρ2(x,oi)\rho_{2}(x,o_{i}) 33-divides over \emptyset will be similar. So pS()p\in S(\emptyset) forks over \emptyset, violating the existence axiom.

This proves the main theorem of this paper, Theorem 1.5, and answers the main question, Question 1.4.

Remark 2.7.

It is not too hard to show that \mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}} above even satisfies the following axiom:

(f) Witnessing: Let a/Mba\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mathchar 12854\relax$\kern 8.00134pt\hss}\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mathchar 12854\relax$\kern 8.00134pt\hss}\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mathchar 12854\relax$\kern 8.00134pt\hss}\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mathchar 12854\relax$\kern 8.00134pt\hss}\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{M}b, and let {bi}i<ω\{b_{i}\}_{i<\omega}, b0=bb_{0}=b, be an MM-indiscernible sequence with biMb0bi1b_{i}\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{M}b_{0}\ldots b_{i-1} for all i<ωi<\omega. Then there is a formula φ(x,b)tp(a/Mb)\varphi(x,b)\in\mathrm{tp}(a/Mb), φ(x,y)L(M)\varphi(x,y)\in L(M), so that {φ(x,bi)}i<ω\{\varphi(x,b_{i})\}_{i<\omega} is inconsistent.

Theorem 6.11 of [13] says that if an invariant ternary relation \mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}} between subsets of 𝕄\mathbb{M} over models satisfies strong finite character, existence over models, monotonicity, symmetry, the independence theorem and witnessing, then \mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}} coincides with Kim-independence K\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}^{K} (Definition 1.1.) So in TT^{\not\exists}, Kim-independence (over models) is given by \mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}. Because TT^{\not\exists} does not satisfy the existence axiom, the results on Kim-independence over sets from [9], [2]) do not apply to TT^{\not\exists}. But note that it makes sense to define aCba\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{C}b the same way as above when (acl(C)=\mathrm{acl}(C)=) cl(C)=C\mathrm{cl}(C)=C, and, when CC is any set, define aCba\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{C}b by acl(C)ba\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{\mathrm{cl}(C)}b, giving a ternary relation on sets. Over sets, by the same proofs as above, \mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}} satisfies the analogues of strong finite character, monotonicity, symmetry, the independence theorem (where C\equiv_{C} is replaces by CLstp\equiv^{\mathrm{Lstp}}_{C}, though this is the same as cl(C)\equiv_{\mathrm{cl}(C)}, with respect to which the independence theorem holds for \mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}), and witnessing; moreover \mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}} satisfies a stronger version of existence over sets:

(b) Existence and extension over sets: for any a,Ca,C and BBCB^{\prime}\supseteq B\supseteq C, aCCa\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{C}C, and if aCBa\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{C}B there is aBaa^{\prime}\equiv_{B}a with aCBa^{\prime}\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{C}B^{\prime}.

Ramsey, in a presentation at the Banff International Research Station on joint work with Itay Kaplan ([22]), defines the assertion that Kim-independence is defined over sets to mean that there is a ternary relation \mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}} between sets satisfying the analogues over sets of strong finite character, monotonicity, symmetry, the independence theorem, and witnessing, as well as existence and extension over sets, and shows that such \mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}} is uniquely determined when it exists. So by [9], [2], in any NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theory satisfying the existence axiom, Kim-independence is defined over sets in the sense of [22]. But also, despite TT^{\not\exists} not satisfying the existence axiom, Kim-independence is defined over sets in this sense in the theory TT^{\not\exists}, even if the results of [9] on Kim-independence as defined by Dobrowolski, Kim, and Ramsey (Definition 1.3 above) do not apply in TT^{\not\exists}.222In fact, in TT^{\not\exists}, \mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}} actually coincides with K\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}^{K} as defined by [9] (i.e. Kim-forking independence with respect to nonforking Morley sequences, Definition 1.3 above), so the conclusions of, say, Corollary 4.9 or Theorem 5.6 of [9] hold: K\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}^{K} as defined there is symmetric, and satisfies the independence theorem, over arbitrary sets. (If a/Cba\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mathchar 12854\relax$\kern 8.00134pt\hss}\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mathchar 12854\relax$\kern 8.00134pt\hss}\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mathchar 12854\relax$\kern 8.00134pt\hss}\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mathchar 12854\relax$\kern 8.00134pt\hss}\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{C}b and aCaC is algebraically closed, then tp(a/Cb)\mathrm{tp}(a/Cb) implies a finite disjunction of formulas of the form φ(x,b)\varphi(x,b^{\prime}), where bcl(C)b^{\prime}\notin\mathrm{cl}(C) is a singleton of OO or PP and φ(x,b)\varphi(x,b^{\prime}) either says that x=bx=b^{\prime} or implies that there is a path between xx and bb^{\prime} with no points in cl(C)\mathrm{cl}(C), and a formula of either kind divides over CC with respect to a cl(C)\mathrm{cl}(C)-invariant Morley sequence. On the other hand, aCba\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{C}b implies aCMa\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}_{C}M for MM some |C|+|C|^{+}-saturated model containing CbCb, so aCKMa\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}^{K}_{C}M by the independence theorem and |C|+|C|^{+}-saturatedness of MM; see the clause K\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}\Rightarrow\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}^{K} of Theorem 9.1 of [12], and the standard argument that forking-dependence on a sufficiently saturated model implies dividing-dependence on that model.) But Proposition 4.9 of [9] fails–it is not necessarily true that φ(x,b)\varphi(x,b) forks over CC with respect to nonforking Morley sequences if and only if it divides with respect to nonforking Morley sequences. For example, for oO,pPo\in O,p\in P, let φ(x,op)=:x=p\varphi(x,op)=:x=p; then φ(x,op)\varphi(x,op) does not divide with respect to a nonforking Morley sequence over \emptyset (i.e. Kim-divide over \emptyset, as in Definition 1.3), because there are no nonforking Morley sequences over \emptyset starting with opop), but it implies φ~(x,p)=:x=p\tilde{\varphi}(x,p)=:x=p, which does divide with respect to a nonforking Morley sequence over \emptyset, so φ(x,op)\varphi(x,op) Kim-forks over \emptyset. Moreover, Kim’s lemma, Theorem 3.5 of [9], is also false in TT^{\not\exists}: φ(x,op)\varphi(x,op) divides over \emptyset with respect to all nonforking Morley sequences over \emptyset starting with opop, but not with respect to some nonforking Morley sequence over \emptyset starting with opop! By way of obtaining an NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theory where K\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}^{K} as defined over sets by [9] (Defintion 1.3 here) does not, say, satisfy the independence theorem, we expect that, by an extremely tedious verification, TT^{\not\exists} can be shown to eliminate \exists^{\infty}. So by Theorem 5 of [25] and Theorem 4.5 of [18], the generic expansion of TT^{\not\exists} by functions from PP to OO and from OO to pp (i.e. the model companion of models of (the Morleyization of) TT^{\not\exists} expanded by a unary function from sort PP to sort OO and a unary function from sort OO to sort PP) will exist and have NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1}, and no consistent formula can Kim-divide over \emptyset, because every nonempty parameter will have an element of OO and an element of PP in its definable closure, so can be shown to begin no Morley sequence over \emptyset as in the original proof that TT^{\not\exists} does not satisfy the existence axiom. So, using Definition 1.3 to define K\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}^{K} over arbitrary sets, any set will be Kim-independent over \emptyset from any nonempty set. So the results stated in [22] are independent of the previous work on the existence axiom.

3. Quantitative results

Doborowolski, Kim, and Ramsey show, in Remark 6.7 of [9], that in a theory without the strict order property (i.e. an NSOP\mathrm{NSOP} theory), the failure of the existence axiom cannot be witnessed by two formulas that 22-divide:

Fact 3.1.

Let TT be NSOP\mathrm{NSOP}, and pS(A)p\in S(A). Then there are no formulas φ1(x,b1)\varphi_{1}(x,b_{1}), φ2(x,b2)\varphi_{2}(x,b_{2}), each of which 22-divide over AA, such that pφ1(x,b1)φ2(x,b2)p\vdash\varphi_{1}(x,b_{1})\vee\varphi_{2}(x,b_{2}).

In the previous section, we gave an example, TT^{\not\exists}, of an NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theory where, for pS()p\in S(\emptyset), pφ1(x,b)φ2(x,b)p\vdash\varphi_{1}(x,b)\vee\varphi_{2}(x,b), where φ1(x,b)\varphi_{1}(x,b) 22-divides over \emptyset and φ2(x,b)\varphi_{2}(x,b) 33-divides over \emptyset. Here, we describe an example, T2,2,2T^{\not\exists^{2,2,2}}, of an NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theory where, for pS()p\in S(\emptyset), pφ1(x,b)φ2(x,b)φ3(x,b)p\vdash\varphi_{1}(x,b)\vee\varphi_{2}(x,b)\vee\varphi_{3}(x,b), where for i=1,2,3i=1,2,3 each φi(x,b)\varphi_{i}(x,b) 22-divides over \emptyset. This will show the optimality of Fact 3.1.

Let \mathcal{L} be the language with sorts PP and OO, symbols R1R_{1}, R2R_{2} and R3R_{3} for binary relations on OO, and symbols ρ1\rho_{1}, ρ2\rho_{2}, and ρ3\rho_{3} for binary relations between PP and OO. Call an \mathcal{L}-structure AA copacetic2,2,2 if:

(C1)2,2,2 For i=1,2,3i=1,2,3, Ri(A)R_{i}(A) is a symmetric, irreflexive relation on O(A)O(A), and the three are mutually exclusive: for a1,a2O(A)a_{1},a_{2}\in O(A), A⊧̸Ri(a1,a2)Rj(a1,a2)A\not\models R_{i}(a_{1},a_{2})\wedge R_{j}(a_{1},a_{2}) for ij{1,2,3}i\neq j\in\{1,2,3\}

(C2)2,2,2 The relation R1(A)R2(A)R3(A)R_{1}(A)\cup R_{2}(A)\cup R_{3}(A) has no loops on O(A)O(A) (i.e. there are no distinct a0an1O(A)a_{0}\ldots a_{n-1}\in O(A), n>2n>2, and i1in{1,2,3}i_{1}\ldots i_{n}\in\{1,2,3\} so that, for 0jn10\leq j\leq n-1, ARij(ai,ai+1modn)A\models R_{i_{j}}(a_{i},a_{i+1\mathrm{\>mod\>}n})).

(C3)2,2,2 For all bP(A)b\in P(A), aO(A)a\in O(A), exactly one of Aρ1(b,a)A\models\rho_{1}(b,a), Aρ2(b,a)A\models\rho_{2}(b,a), and ρ3(b,a)\rho_{3}(b,a) hold.

(C4)2,2,2: For i{1,2,3}i\in\{1,2,3\}, there is no bP(A)b\in P(A) and distinct a1,a2a_{1},a_{2} on the boundary of some fixed unit RiR_{i}-ball so that Aρi(b,a1)ρi(b,a2)A\models\rho_{i}(b,a_{1})\wedge\rho_{i}(b,a_{2}).

We define the closure relation \leq analogously to the previous section, and construct a theory satisfying the analogous statement to Lemma 2.4, which will be NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} and satisfy pρ1(x,o)ρ2(x,o)ρ3(x,o)p\vdash\rho_{1}(x,o)\vee\rho_{2}(x,o)\vee\rho_{3}(x,o) for any oO(𝕄)o\in O(\mathbb{M}) and pS()p\in S(\emptyset) the unique type (in one variable) in sort PP over \emptyset; ρi(x,o)\rho_{i}(x,o) will 22-divide over \emptyset for i{1,2,3}i\in\{1,2,3\}, as desired. The entire proof is a straightforward generalization of the previous section, with a single exception: in place of Subclaim 2.3, we must prove the below subclaim. Let OO be an undirected graph without cycles and with a 33-coloring of its edges, with R1R_{1}, R2R_{2}, R3R_{3} denoting edges of each color. Let ρ1,ρ2,ρ3O\rho_{1},\rho_{2},\rho_{3}\subset O, O=ρ1ρ2ρ3O=\rho_{1}\cup\rho_{2}\cup\rho_{3}, ρiρj=\rho_{i}\cap\rho_{j}=\emptyset for ij{1,2,3}i\neq j\in\{1,2,3\} be a coloring of the vertices of OO so that, for i={1,2,3}i=\{1,2,3\}, no two distinct vertices of OO, lying on the boundary of the same RiR_{i}-ball of radius 11 (i.e. they have a common RiR_{i}-neighbor), are both colored by ρi\rho_{i}. Then we call ρ1,ρ2,ρ3\rho_{1},\rho_{2},\rho_{3} a (C4)2,2,2-coloring of OO.

Subclaim 3.2.

Let OO be a connected graph without cycles, and with a 33-coloring of its edges. Let O1,O2OO_{1},O_{2}\subset O be connected subgraphs so that each vertex of O1O_{1} has distance at least 55 from each vertex of O2O_{2}. For i=1,2i=1,2, let ρ1i,ρ2i,ρ3i\rho_{1}^{i},\rho_{2}^{i},\rho_{3}^{i} be a (C4)2,2,2-coloring of OiO_{i}. Then there is a (C4)2,2,2-coloring ρ1,ρ2,ρ3\rho_{1},\rho_{2},\rho_{3} of some connected set OO^{\prime} containing O1O_{1} and O2O_{2}, where for i=1,2i=1,2, ρ1,ρ2,ρ3\rho_{1},\rho_{2},\rho_{3} extends ρ1i,ρ2i,ρ3i\rho_{1}^{i},\rho_{2}^{i},\rho_{3}^{i} on OiO_{i}.

Proof.

As in the proof of Subclaim 2.3, let O=O1O2IO^{\prime}=O_{1}\cup O_{2}\cup I where II is the shortest path between O1O_{1} and O2O_{2}, and let II consist, ordered in the direction from O1O_{1} to O2O_{2}, of o0,ono_{0},\ldots o_{n}, for o0O1o_{0}\in O_{1}, onO2o_{n}\in O_{2}, o1on1O\(O1O2)o_{1}\ldots o_{n-1}\in O\backslash(O_{1}\cup O_{2}), and n5n\geq 5. Again, as in that proof, color OiO_{i} by ρ1i,ρ2i,ρ3i\rho^{i}_{1},\rho^{i}_{2},\rho^{i}_{3} for i{1,2}i\in\{1,2\}, color o1o_{1} by ρi\rho_{i} where ii is such that o1o_{1} is not an RiR_{i}-neighbor of o0o_{0}, and color on1o_{n-1} by ρj\rho_{j} where jj is such that on1o_{n-1} is not an RjR_{j}-neighbor of ono_{n}–then as before, the condition of being a (C4)2,2,2-coloring cannot fail at the boundary of a unit ball centered at a point of O1O_{1} or O2O_{2}. Now let neven,noddn_{\mathrm{even}},n_{\mathrm{odd}}, respectively, be the least even and odd numbers less than n1n-1. Then, because there are three colors available, we can color o2,,o2i,,oneveno_{2},\ldots,o_{2i},\ldots,o_{n_{\mathrm{even}}} so that each vertex in the sequence o0,o2,,o2i,,oneven,oneven+2o_{0},o_{2},\ldots,o_{2i},\ldots,o_{n_{\mathrm{even}}},o_{n_{\mathrm{even}}+2} is colored differently from the previous vertex in that sequence–noting that the colors of o0o_{0} and oneven+2o_{n_{\mathrm{even}}+2} are already decided, alternate the color of o0o_{0} with a color distinct from that of o0o_{0} and oneven+2o_{n_{\mathrm{even}}+2}. Similarly, we can color o3,,o2i+1,onoddo_{3},\ldots,o_{2i+1},\ldots o_{n_{\mathrm{odd}}} so that each vertex in the sequence o1,o3,,o2i+1,,onodd,onodd+2o_{1},o_{3},\ldots,o_{2i+1},\ldots,o_{n_{\mathrm{odd}}},o_{n_{\mathrm{odd}}+2} is colored differently from the previous vertex in that sequence. Coloring the intermediate vertices o2,on2o_{2},\ldots o_{n-2} according to these observations, we see that the condition of being a (C4)2,2,2-coloring cannot fail on the boundary of a unit ball centered at one of o1,on1o_{1},\ldots o_{n-1}, because the boundary of such a ball will always be colored by two different colors. ∎

Note that a similar subclaim would fail, were we to try to use an analogous construction to obtain an NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theory where, for pS()p\in S(\emptyset), pφ1(x,b1)φ2(x,b2)p\vdash\varphi_{1}(x,b_{1})\vee\varphi_{2}(x,b_{2}) for φi(x,bi)\varphi_{i}(x,b_{i}) 22-dividing over \emptyset.

4. Open questions

The theory TT^{\not\exists}, despite being an NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theory that does not satisfy the existence axiom, is not countably categorical. Motivated by this, we ask:

Question 4.1.

Does every countably categorical NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} (or even NSOP\mathrm{NSOP}) theory satisfy the existence axiom?

Moreover, in TT^{\not\exists}, Kim-independence over models is not just given by the operation acleq\mathrm{acl}^{eq}; see Remark 2.7. In Definition 6.10 of [11], the definition of the property of being one-based is extended (up to elimination of hyperimaginaries) from simple theories to NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theories:

Definition 4.2.

Let TT be an NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theory. Then TT is one-based if A/MKBA\mathop{\mathchoice{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mathchar 12854\relax$\kern 8.00134pt\hss}\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\displaystyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mathchar 12854\relax$\kern 8.00134pt\hss}\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\textstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mathchar 12854\relax$\kern 8.00134pt\hss}\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptstyle{}}{\kern 5.71527pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mathchar 12854\relax$\kern 8.00134pt\hss}\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\mid$\hss}\lower 3.87495pt\hbox to0.0pt{\hss$\smile$\hss}\kern 5.71527pt\scriptscriptstyle{}}}^{K}_{M}B implies (equivalently, is equivalent to) acleq(AM)acleq(BM)M\mathrm{acl}^{eq}(AM)\cap\mathrm{acl}^{eq}(BM)\supsetneq M.

So TT^{\not\exists} is not one-based. (See Example 4.6.1 of [20].) This leads us to ask:

Question 4.3.

Does every one-based NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theory satisfy the existence axiom?

Recall that, as stated in Remark 2.7, Kim-independence is defined over sets in any NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theory satisfying the existence axiom, but is also defined over sets in TT^{\not\exists} despite TT^{\not\exists} not satisfying the existence axiom. A final question, motivated by this remark and by the original motivation discussed in the introduction for Question 1.4, the main question of this paper, is asked by Ramsey:

Question 4.4.

([22], [21]) Is Kim-independence defined over sets in every NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theory?

Acknowledgements

The author would like to thank James Freitag, Maryanthe Malliaris and Nicholas Ramsey for many insightful conversations. In particular, conversations with Nicholas Ramsey were instrumental in inspiring the discussion in Remark 2.7 and Question 4.4 of this paper.

References

  • [1] Anna-Maria Ammer and Katrin Tent. Model theory of open generalized polygons, Preprint. Available at https://arxiv.org/pdf/2308.03677.pdf. 2023,.
  • [2] Byunghan Kim Artem Chernikov and Nicholas Ramsey. Transitivity, lowness and ranks in NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theories, Preprint. Available at https://arxiv.org/pdf/2006.10486.pdf. 2020,.
  • [3] Joonhee Kim Byunghan Kim and Hyoyoon Lee. Existence in NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theories, Preprint. Available at https://arxiv.org/pdf/2405.13741v1. 2024.
  • [4] Artem Chernikov, Ehud Hrushovski, Alex Kruckman, Krzysztof Krupiński, Slavko Moconja, Anand Pillay, and Nicholas Ramsey. Invariant measures in simple and in small theories. Journal of Mathematical Logic, 23(02):2250025, 2023.
  • [5] Artem Chernikov and Itay Kaplan. Forking and dividing in NTP2\mathrm{NTP}_{2} theories. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 77(1):1–20, 2012.
  • [6] Artem Chernikov and Nicholas Ramsey. On model-theoretic tree properties. Journal of Mathematical Logic, 16(2):1650009, 2016.
  • [7] Christian d’Elbée, personal communication, February 2023.
  • [8] Christian d’Elbée. Generic multiplicative endomorphism of a field, Preprint. Available at https://arxiv.org/abs/2212.02115. 2022.
  • [9] Jan Dobrowolski, Byunghan Kim, and Nicholas Ramsey. Independence over arbitrary sets in nsop1 theories. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 173(2):103058, 2022.
  • [10] Tapani Hyttinen and Gianluca Paolini. First-order model theory of free projective planes. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 172(2):102888, 2021.
  • [11] Jim Freitag John Baldwin and Scott Mutchnik. Simple homogeneous structures and indiscernible sequence invariants, Preprint. Available at https://arxiv.org/abs/2405.08211. 2024.
  • [12] Itay Kaplan and Nicholas Ramsey. On Kim-independence. Journal of the European Mathematical Society, 22, 02 2017.
  • [13] Itay Kaplan and Nicholas Ramsey. Transitivity of Kim-independence. Advances in Mathematics, 379:107573, 2021.
  • [14] Itay Kaplan, Nicholas Ramsey, and Saharon Shelah. Local character of kim-independence. Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, 147, 07 2017.
  • [15] Byunghan Kim. Forking in Simple Unstable Theories. Journal of the London Mathematical Society, 57(2):257–267, 04 1998.
  • [16] Byunghan Kim. Simple first order theories, PhD thesis, University of Notre Dame, 1996.
  • [17] Byunghan Kim and Anand Pillay. Simple theories. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 88(2):149–164, 1997. Joint AILA-KGS Model Theory Meeting.
  • [18] Alex Kruckman and Nicholas Ramsey. Generic expansion and Skolemization in NSOP1\mathrm{NSOP}_{1} theories. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 169(8):755–774, aug 2018.
  • [19] Michael Morley. Categoricity in power. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 114(2):514–538, 1965.
  • [20] A. Pillay. Geometric Stability Theory. Oxford logic guides. Clarendon Press, 1996.
  • [21] Nicholas Ramsey, personal communication, May 2024.
  • [22] Nicholas Ramsey. What is kim-independence, Presentation, “Neostability Theory,” Banff International Research Station, February 2024. Available at https://www.birs.ca/events/2023/5-day-workshops/23w5145/videos/watch/202302201059-Ramsey.html.
  • [23] Saharon Shelah. Classification theory: and the number of non-isomorphic models. Elsevier, 1990.
  • [24] KATRIN TENT. The free pseudospace is n-ample. but not (n + 1)-ample. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 79(2):410–428, 2014.
  • [25] Peter M. Winkler. Model-completeness and skolem expansions. Model Theory and Algebra, page 408–463, 1975.