An theory without the existence axiom
Abstract.
Answering a question of Dobrowolski, Kim and Ramsey, we find an theory that does not satisfy the existence axiom.
1. Introduction
One of the core informal questions of model theory is to determine what role stability theory, famously introduced by Morley ([19]) and Shelah ([23]) to classify the number of non-isomorphic models (of a given size) of a first-order theory, can play in describing theories that are themselves unstable–and that may not even be simple. This project was initiated in large part in celebrated work of Kim ([15]) and Kim and Pillay ([17]), who showed that the (forking-)independence relation has many of the same properties in simple theories that it does in stable theories, and in fact that these properties characterize simplicity. In a key step towards the non-simple case, Kaplan and Ramsey ([12]) then defined Kim-independence over models, which generalizes the definition of forking-independence:
Definition 1.1.
Let . A formula Kim-divides over if there is an -invariant Morley sequence starting with such that is inconsistent. A formula Kim-forks over if it implies a (finite) disjunction of formulas Kim-dividing over . We write , and say that is Kim-independent from over , if does not include any formulas Kim-forking over .
In, for example, [6], [12], [13], [14], it is shown that Kim-independence has many of the same properties in theories without the first strict order property– theories–that forking-independence has in simple theories. It is also shown that theories have a characterization in terms of properties of Kim-independence, similarly to how simplicity has a characterization in terms of properties of forking-independence. However, in contrast to the case of simple theories, this work only describes the properties of a relation defined when is a model, leaving open the question of whether independence phenomena in theories extend from independence over models to independence over sets.
The following axiom of first-order theories, though introduced earlier under different names (see, e.g. [5]), was defined by Dobrowolski, Kim and Ramsey in [9]:
Definition 1.2.
A theory satisfies the existence axiom if no type forks over .
This is equivalent to every type having a global extension that does not fork over . All simple theories satisfy the existence axiom ([15]), while the circular ordering is an example of a dependent theory not satisfying the existence axiom ([16], Example 2.11). In [9] it is shown that, in theories satisfying the existence axiom, it is possible to extend the definition of Kim-independence from the case where is a model to the case where is an arbitrary set, so that the relation will have similar properties to Kim-independence over models in general theories. Specifically, because, under the existence axiom, (nonforking-)Morley sequences are defined over arbitrary sets, they can be used in place of invariant Morley sequences111It is easy to see that invariant Morley sequences are not defined over arbitrary sets in theories: for example, any set such that . to define Kim-dividing of a formula over a set:
Definition 1.3.
([9]) Let be a theory, and let be an arbitrary set. A formula Kim-divides over if there is a (nonforking-)Morley sequence over starting with such that is inconsistent. A formula Kim-forks over if it implies a (finite) disjunction of formulas Kim-dividing over . We write , and say that is Kim-independent from over , if does not include any formulas Kim-forking over .
Dobrowolski, Kim and Ramsey ([9]) show that, in an theory satisfying the existence axiom, the Kim-independence relation as defined above over arbitrary sets satisfies symmetry and the independence theorem (for Lascar strong types), and that Kim-dividing over arbitrary sets satisfies Kim’s lemma and coincides with Kim-forking. Chernikov, Kim and Ramsey, in [2], show even more properties of Kim-independence over arbitrary sets in theories satisfying the existence axiom, including transitivity and witnessing. (All of these properties correspond to the properties of Kim-independence over models proven in general theories in [12], [13].) Motivated by these results, [9], and later [3], ask:
Question 1.4.
Does every theory satisfy the existence axiom?
We show that the answer to this question is no:
Theorem 1.5.
There is an theory not satisfying the existence axiom.
This contrasts with the work of Kim, Kim and Lee in [3], where, for the definition of Kim-forking over sets given by Dobrowolski, Kim and Ramsey in [9] (Defintion 1.3 above), it is shown that no type Kim-forks over (i.e. contains a formula Kim-forking over ), where is an arbitrary set in an theory. In fact, our example is the first known example of a theory without the strict order property, or theory, not satisfying the existence axiom. Prior to our results, the theory of an algebraically closed field with a generic multiplicative endomorphism, constructed by d’Elbée in [8], was suggested there as a candidate for an theory without the existence axiom; whether the theory constructed by d’Elbée satisfies the existence axiom was left unresolved in that article. However, as discussed in a personal communication with d’Elbée ([7]), it is expected that that theory, which was shown in [8] to be , actually does satisfy the existence axiom.
Our construction is based on the theory of -stable free pseudoplanes, a classical example of a non-one-based -stable theory with trivial forking discussed in, say, [20]. The theory of -stable free pseudoplanes is the theory of undirected graphs of infinite minimum degree without cycles. Variations of this construction appear in e.g. [10], [1], [24], [11]. Note also that some arguments from the below, including the strategy, in axiom schema , of requiring that connected sets of pairwise distance greater than can be colored independently, and the associated Claims 2.1 and 2.2, their proofs, and their application in proving claim (***), are formally similar to those of Section 3 of Chernikov, Hrushovski, Kruckman, Krupiński, Moconja, Pillay and Ramsey ([4]).
2. The construction
Let be the language with sorts and , symbols and for binary relations on , and symbols and for binary relations between and . Call an -structure copacetic if:
(C1) For , is a symmetric, irreflexive relation on , and the two are mutually exclusive: for , .
(C2) The relation has no loops on (i.e. there are no distinct , , and so that, for , ).
(C3) For all , , exactly one of and hold.
(C4):
(a) For each , there are no distinct , so that there there is some so that , and .
(b) For each , there are no distinct , so that there there is some so that , and .
Let be copacetic, and let , , . Then there are at most many with and . For the number of such that are defined, let , , denote the many such (so if and there are two such , make an arbitrary choice of which is and which is , while if , then is the sole such , if it exists.)
If is copacetic and is a substructure of (and is therefore also copacetic), call closed in (denoted ) if
(i) For , , , , if exists, then .
(ii) Any -path between nodes of lies in : for all , which are distinct and distinct from , , and , if for , then for all , .
Call a copacetic -structure connected if forms a connected graph on : for all , there are , for some , so that for , , for all . So if is copacetic and , connectedness of supplants requirement (ii) of being closed in . Call a subset of a connected component of if it is a maximal connected subset of .
Let be an undirected graph without cycles and with a -coloring of its edges, with , denoting edges of either color. Let , , be a coloring of the vertices of so that, for , no distinct vertices of , lying on the boundary of the same -ball of radius (i.e. they have a common -neighbor), are both colored by . Then we call a (C4)-coloring of . For copacetic, , and a (C4)-coloring of , say that induces the (C4)-coloring on if for , .
The following assumptions on an -structure are expressible by a set of first-order sentences:
() (Copaceticity) is copacetic.
() (Completeness) For , , , if , then exists for .
() (Tree extension) For , and finite and copacetic with , there is an embedding with .
() (Parameter introduction) For any , finite connected sets so that there does not exist an -path of length at most between a vertex of and a vertex of for any distinct (so in particular, and are disjoint), and (C4)-colorings of for , there are infinitely many so that, for each , induces the (C4)-coloring on .
Let . We claim that is consistent. This will follow by induction from the following three claims:
(*) If is copacetic, , , , and , there is a copacetic -structure (i.e. containing as a substructure) so that exists.
(**) If is copacetic, , and is finite and copacetic with , there is a copacetic structure and an embedding with .
(***) If is copacetic, for any , finite connected sets so that there does not exist an -path of length at most between a vertex of and a vertex of for any distinct , and (C4)-colorings of for , there is some copacetic and so that, for each , induces the (C4)-coloring on .
We first show (*). Suppose does not already exist. Let for a new point of sort , and let , , , . Then is copacetic; first, (C1)-(C3) are clearly satisfied. Second, no point of can witness a failure of (C4), because is copacetic and is not an -neighbor of any point of . Finally, neither can witness a failure of (C4), because is not an neighbor of any point of and is the unique -neighbor of in , that failure must by copaceticity of be witnessed on the boundary of the -ball of radius centered at . But because does not already exist, there are fewer than many -neighbors of in with , so there are at most many -neighbors of in with ; thus the failure of (C4) is not in fact witnessed on this ball’s boundary. By construction, we can then choose .
We next show (**). For this we need the following claim:
Claim 2.1.
Let be undirected graph without cycles and with a -coloring of its edges, with , denoting edges of either color. Let be a subgraph with the induced coloring, and with (in the sense of (ii), so any path between two vertices of consisting of edges of any colors is contained in ). Then any (C4)-coloring of extends to a (C4)-coloring of , which has the following additional property: if has an -neighbor in , then .
Proof.
By the assumption on paths in between two vertices of , we may decompose into a disjoint union of connected subgraphs, so that each has at most one vertex with any neighbors in ; will in fact have only one neighbor in . For every all of whose vertices have no neighbors in , let be an arbitrary vertex of . Then inductively, we can order each as a tree (i.e., a partial order with linearly ordered downsets) so that is the root, any node’s immediate successors are all neighbors of that node and, among any two neighbors, one must be an immediate successor of the other, and each maximal linearly ordered set is well-ordered of order type at most . Extend on each as follows, starting from and proceeding by induction. If is an -neighbor of , color by ; otherwise, color arbitrarily. Then for each vertex of , each immediate successor of will be an -neighbor of for some ; color it by . No two distinct vertices with an -distance of exactly in can then be colored in : if the -path between and goes through , then whichever of and is not in will be colored by , and if the -path between and stays in , whichever of and is not the least in the path will be colored by . This shows that is a (C4)-coloring, and the additional property is immediate from the construction.
∎
Now, take the set to be the disjoint union of and over ; for notational simplicity we identify , and respectively with their images in . Let the -structure on be given as follows: the identification on and preserves the -structure, and and are freely amalgamated over (i.e. there are no -edges between and ). This guarantees (C1), and also guarantees (C2) by condition (ii) of . Now let the -structure on be given as follows: the identifications on and preserve the -structure, which, by the assumption that , leaves us only by way of satisfying (C3) to define the -structure on , and this will be the following. Let ; the requirement that the -structure on is preserved tells us the (C4)-coloring that induces on , and we extend this to a (C4)-coloring on as in Claim 2.1; here we use condition (ii) of . We have defined the full -structure on , so it remains to show (C4); in other words, we show that induces a (C4)-coloring on in the case where and in the case where . In either case induces a (C4)-coloring on and on , so the only way (C4) can fail is on the boundary of an -ball of radius centered at . But (C4) cannot fail on the boundary of this ball, because it does not fail there in , and by condition (i) of in the first case, or by the additional clause of Claim 2.1 in the second case, any -neighbor of in is colored by in the (C4)-coloring induced by on , so (C4) still cannot fail on the boundary of this ball in . So is a copacetic -structure containing , and clearly, the embedding as in (**) exists, so this shows (**).
Finally, we show (***). For this, we need an additional combinatorial claim:
Claim 2.2.
Let be be undirected graph without cycles and with a -coloring of its edges, with , denoting edges of either color, and let be connected subsets so that there does not exist an -path of length at most between a vertex of and a vertex of for any distinct . Let be a (C4)-coloring of for . Then there is some containing and (C4)-coloring of so that, for , restricts to on .
Proof.
Considering each connected component of individually, we may assume to be connected. We prove this claim by induction on . Because we will later consider a variant of this construction where the case is the main difference, we isolate this case, which is necessary for the induction, as a subclaim:
Subclaim 2.3.
Claim 2.2 is true where is connected and .
Proof.
Let be the shortest path between to , which will consist, ordered in the direction from to , of , for , , , and . Because and are connected, it suffices to color so as to extend the colorings on for , and to preserve the condition of being a (C4)-coloring. So color by , by , and color as follows: first, color by , for so that is an -neighbor of , and color by , so that is an -neighbor of . Since we colored by and by , the only vertices of the so that the condition of being a (C4)-coloring can fail in on the boundary of the -ball of radius centered at are and , and we have just prevented this. It remains to color ; we color them all by . The only remaining vertices of where the condition of being a (C4)-coloring can fail on the -ball centered at are now , but the boundaries of the -balls centered at those vertices in have just two points, at least one of which must be colored by , because and the interval whose points we colored by contains at least one of the two neighbors of each . So the condition of being a (C4)-coloring cannot fail there. ∎
We now consider the general case of the induction. Without loss of generality, we may assume that and have minimum distance among any with distinct. By Lemma 2.3, we may find a (C4)-coloring of extending and , where is the shortest path, which will be of length , between and . Clearly is connected, so it suffices to show that no two of have distance less than , because then we can apply the inductive step. Let ; it suffices to show that does not have distance less than from . Suppose otherwise; then it has distance less than from some point of , but by definition of , must have distance at most from either or . So must have distance less than from either or , contradicting minimality of . ∎
By Claims 2.2 and 2.1, there is a (C4)-coloring on extending the (C4)-coloring on for each . So we can extend to , where , and define the relations and on so that induces the (C4)-coloring on . This proves (***), and the consistency of .
We call a copacetic -structure complete if it satisfies axiom ; completeness of will always supplant condition (i) of .
We now prove that has the following embedding property:
Lemma 2.4.
Let be a sufficiently saturated model of . Let , and let be a small copacetic -structure. Assume additionally that is complete. Then there is an embedding that is the identity on and satisfies .
Proof.
We prove the lemma in the following two cases:
(1)
(2) and .
These cases suffice, because the closed extension can be decomposed into a closed extension satisfying (1) followed by an ascending chain of (obviously closed) extensions satisfying (2), and the property is clearly preserved under taking unions.
To prove case (1), by completeness of and saturatedness of , it suffices to find, for arbitrarily large , an embedding that is the identity on and so that points of that are not connected by a path in have distance at least in . We claim that, for every copacetic , and any points so that and belong to distinct connected components of and belongs to a connected component of not containing any point of , there is some copacetic so that , that consists of together with a path of from to of length greater than . One way to do this is to add an -path of length greater than (and greater than ) between and , so that all induced (C4)-colorings color the new nodes of this path by . By choice of induced colorings, the resulting -structure will satisfy (C4) and condition (i) of , and will also satisfy condition (ii) of by the assumption of what connected components of have and as members. By repeatedly applying this claim to connect each connected component of not meeting to some fixed connected component of meeting (or an arbitrary fixed connected component of , if is empty), we then obtain a copacetic -structure with and such that, for any that are not connected in , either and have finite distance greater than in , or they belong to different connected components of meeting . Now suppose is any embedding restricting to the identity on ; then for , that are not connected in , either and have finite distance greater than in , so and have distance greater than in as desired, or and belong to different connected components of meeting , so and belong to different connected components of meeting , so are not connected in because ; then is as desired. So if we can show that, for any small, copacetic -structure with , there is an embedding that is the identity on (with no additional requirements on ), we will have proven case (1). Note that if , , so we may assume that is finite by saturatedness of . Then we can just apply tree extension.
To prove case (2), let be the (C4)-coloring induced by , where , on . Since is complete and , any embedding with will satisfy . By saturatedness of it suffices to find, for every finite and finite , some inducing the (C4)-coloring on . We may enlarge to a finite subset of consisting of a finite union of connected sets that are not connected in , so by condition (ii) of , are not connected in ; in particular, any two of them have distance greater than in . So by parameter introduction, we may find infinitely many inducing the (C4)-coloring on , so in particular, one not belonging to .
∎
We now fix a sufficiently saturated , which we take as the ambient model; for , fix the notation, The following quantifier elimination is a corollary of the above:
Corollary 2.5.
Let . Then if , .
Proof.
For any and , there is some (small) so that , and in particular . Because and satisfies completeness, is complete. So the corollary follows by Lemma 2.4 by a back-and-forth argument. ∎
Next, we show that is . By Theorem 9.1 of [12], it suffices to find an invariant ternary relation between subsets of over models with the following properties:
(a) Strong finite character: For all and , if , then there is some formula , where has parameters in , such that for every , .
(b) Existence over models: for all and , .
(c) Monotonicity: For all , , , implies .
(d) Symmetry: For all and , implies (and vice versa).
(e) The independence theorem: for any and , , , and implies that there is with , and .
First, note that for any , there is such that and for all with , . Denote this ; clearly, this is contained in (and it can even be checked that ). This allows us to define : if , and every ()-path between a point of and contains a point of .
We see this has strong finite character: for , , the endpoints of the path of length witnessing this, let isolate over , say that is not within distance of the closest point of to some (any) (which would be required, should there be a (non-self-overlapping) path of length between and going through ), and say that there is a path of length from to some point satisfying . Then suffices.
Existence over models, monotonicity, and symmetry are immediate. So it remains to show the independence theorem. By definition of , we may assume and similar for . We first give an analysis of the structure of pairs with :
Lemma 2.6.
Let , , and . Then , where for , is the closure of under the functions for (so in particular, ), and is the closure of under these same functions. Every point of is connected by some ()-path to a point of , and ; similarly for .
Proof.
The second sentence follows from the definition of the , and the fact that ; it remains to show that . But is the closure of under the functions for , so is complete, and condition (i) is satisfied. Moreover, (i.e., condition (ii) of being closed in holds for ): any path with endpoints in and intermediate points all in must, because and , have both endpoints in either of or , a contradiction because and are closed in . Because every point of is connected to by the second clause of this lemma, condition (ii) of then follows from . ∎
In the following, for and , let denote the closure of under for , as in Lemma 2.6. We want to find so that , , , . Let , , , , , . We now build a copacetic -structure extending as follows. Let where is defined on so that these are freely amalgamated sets isomorphic to over (so in particular, because , and so on), and so that and are defined so that , , ; this makes sense because . Then is copacetic, because the only way axiom (C4) can fail is, without loss of generality, when there is , , so that lie on the boundary of some common -ball and . Because are freely amalgamated over , the only way the former can happen is for and to have a common -neighbor . But then (say) , contradicting . Now extend to , where
(1), , , , , ,
(2) , , , , , are pairwise disjoint and disjoint from
(3) The only -edges of are those of , as well as those required to make , , , , , .
(4) Let us extend where required so that , , . Because are already known to satisfy (C4), a failure of (C4), which would then be witnessed by , (with the last two perhaps equal), could now happen in the following two cases (among the instances where the are yet defined), both of which we rule out. First, one of the is in , where is one of , and the other is in . But then, by the connectedness claim in the second clause of Lemma 2.6, (3) and the construction of tell us that these two must have distance at least apart, so a failure of (C4) cannot arise here. The other case is where for one of , and some two do not belong to the same ; then because this is the only way the can be defined so far for , . Then these two , say and must satisfy for some , and must be common -neighbors of the evident while lying outside of this . But this is impossible, by the claim , of Lemma 2.6. Therefore, we do not yet get a failure of (C4), and it remains to extend to get (C3) while maintaining (C4), which we do in the next step.
(5) By the claim , in the second clause of Lemma 2.6, we can use Claim 2.1 to extend where not yet defined, maintaining (C4) by the description of the -structure in (3), and thereby producing a copacetic -structure.
Observe also the following:
(6) In , there is no path between and not going through . So by the connectedness claim in Lemma 2.6 applied to , in there is no path between and not going through .
(7). By construction, are closed in . So by the proof of the first clause of Lemma 2.6, are each closed in (and are also each complete).
Finally, we extend to a complete copacetic -structure, so that (6) and (7) still hold replacing with ; since are complete, to preserve (7) we must just preserve clause (ii). We can extend to a complete copacetic -structure just by repeated applications of the proof of (ii). But notice that this proceeds just by successively adding nodes in the sort with exactly one -neighbor in the previously added nodes, so adds no new paths between nodes in . So (6) and (7) are in fact preserved.
Note that implies , so by (4) and (7) (i.e., the version where is replaced with ), . Now use Lemma 2.4 to obtain an embedding which is the identity on , and such that . Let , , . Then (using Corollary 2.5) by (4), (7) (again, the version where is replaced with ), , and the first clause of Lemma 2.6, , , . Moreover, by (6) (yet again, the version where is replaced with ) and , . So we have proven the independence theorem for , and is .
It remains to show that does not satisfy the existence axiom. Let be the unique type in the sort (in one variable) over . Let . Then , by (C3). We show that -divides over . We can find an -indiscernible sequence , , so that the lie on the boundary of some fixed -ball of radius . Then is -inconsistent by (C4), so -divides over . That -divides over will be similar. So forks over , violating the existence axiom.
This proves the main theorem of this paper, Theorem 1.5, and answers the main question, Question 1.4.
Remark 2.7.
It is not too hard to show that above even satisfies the following axiom:
(f) Witnessing: Let , and let , , be an -indiscernible sequence with for all . Then there is a formula , , so that is inconsistent.
Theorem 6.11 of [13] says that if an invariant ternary relation between subsets of over models satisfies strong finite character, existence over models, monotonicity, symmetry, the independence theorem and witnessing, then coincides with Kim-independence (Definition 1.1.) So in , Kim-independence (over models) is given by . Because does not satisfy the existence axiom, the results on Kim-independence over sets from [9], [2]) do not apply to . But note that it makes sense to define the same way as above when () , and, when is any set, define by , giving a ternary relation on sets. Over sets, by the same proofs as above, satisfies the analogues of strong finite character, monotonicity, symmetry, the independence theorem (where is replaces by , though this is the same as , with respect to which the independence theorem holds for ), and witnessing; moreover satisfies a stronger version of existence over sets:
(b′) Existence and extension over sets: for any and , , and if there is with .
Ramsey, in a presentation at the Banff International Research Station on joint work with Itay Kaplan ([22]), defines the assertion that Kim-independence is defined over sets to mean that there is a ternary relation between sets satisfying the analogues over sets of strong finite character, monotonicity, symmetry, the independence theorem, and witnessing, as well as existence and extension over sets, and shows that such is uniquely determined when it exists. So by [9], [2], in any theory satisfying the existence axiom, Kim-independence is defined over sets in the sense of [22]. But also, despite not satisfying the existence axiom, Kim-independence is defined over sets in this sense in the theory , even if the results of [9] on Kim-independence as defined by Dobrowolski, Kim, and Ramsey (Definition 1.3 above) do not apply in .222In fact, in , actually coincides with as defined by [9] (i.e. Kim-forking independence with respect to nonforking Morley sequences, Definition 1.3 above), so the conclusions of, say, Corollary 4.9 or Theorem 5.6 of [9] hold: as defined there is symmetric, and satisfies the independence theorem, over arbitrary sets. (If and is algebraically closed, then implies a finite disjunction of formulas of the form , where is a singleton of or and either says that or implies that there is a path between and with no points in , and a formula of either kind divides over with respect to a -invariant Morley sequence. On the other hand, implies for some -saturated model containing , so by the independence theorem and -saturatedness of ; see the clause of Theorem 9.1 of [12], and the standard argument that forking-dependence on a sufficiently saturated model implies dividing-dependence on that model.) But Proposition 4.9 of [9] fails–it is not necessarily true that forks over with respect to nonforking Morley sequences if and only if it divides with respect to nonforking Morley sequences. For example, for , let ; then does not divide with respect to a nonforking Morley sequence over (i.e. Kim-divide over , as in Definition 1.3), because there are no nonforking Morley sequences over starting with ), but it implies , which does divide with respect to a nonforking Morley sequence over , so Kim-forks over . Moreover, Kim’s lemma, Theorem 3.5 of [9], is also false in : divides over with respect to all nonforking Morley sequences over starting with , but not with respect to some nonforking Morley sequence over starting with ! By way of obtaining an theory where as defined over sets by [9] (Defintion 1.3 here) does not, say, satisfy the independence theorem, we expect that, by an extremely tedious verification, can be shown to eliminate . So by Theorem 5 of [25] and Theorem 4.5 of [18], the generic expansion of by functions from to and from to (i.e. the model companion of models of (the Morleyization of) expanded by a unary function from sort to sort and a unary function from sort to sort ) will exist and have , and no consistent formula can Kim-divide over , because every nonempty parameter will have an element of and an element of in its definable closure, so can be shown to begin no Morley sequence over as in the original proof that does not satisfy the existence axiom. So, using Definition 1.3 to define over arbitrary sets, any set will be Kim-independent over from any nonempty set. So the results stated in [22] are independent of the previous work on the existence axiom.
3. Quantitative results
Doborowolski, Kim, and Ramsey show, in Remark 6.7 of [9], that in a theory without the strict order property (i.e. an theory), the failure of the existence axiom cannot be witnessed by two formulas that -divide:
Fact 3.1.
Let be , and . Then there are no formulas , , each of which -divide over , such that .
In the previous section, we gave an example, , of an theory where, for , , where -divides over and -divides over . Here, we describe an example, , of an theory where, for , , where for each -divides over . This will show the optimality of Fact 3.1.
Let be the language with sorts and , symbols , and for binary relations on , and symbols , , and for binary relations between and . Call an -structure copacetic2,2,2 if:
(C1)2,2,2 For , is a symmetric, irreflexive relation on , and the three are mutually exclusive: for , for
(C2)2,2,2 The relation has no loops on (i.e. there are no distinct , , and so that, for , ).
(C3)2,2,2 For all , , exactly one of , , and hold.
(C4)2,2,2: For , there is no and distinct on the boundary of some fixed unit -ball so that .
We define the closure relation analogously to the previous section, and construct a theory satisfying the analogous statement to Lemma 2.4, which will be and satisfy for any and the unique type (in one variable) in sort over ; will -divide over for , as desired. The entire proof is a straightforward generalization of the previous section, with a single exception: in place of Subclaim 2.3, we must prove the below subclaim. Let be an undirected graph without cycles and with a -coloring of its edges, with , , denoting edges of each color. Let , , for be a coloring of the vertices of so that, for , no two distinct vertices of , lying on the boundary of the same -ball of radius (i.e. they have a common -neighbor), are both colored by . Then we call a (C4)2,2,2-coloring of .
Subclaim 3.2.
Let be a connected graph without cycles, and with a -coloring of its edges. Let be connected subgraphs so that each vertex of has distance at least from each vertex of . For , let be a (C4)2,2,2-coloring of . Then there is a (C4)2,2,2-coloring of some connected set containing and , where for , extends on .
Proof.
As in the proof of Subclaim 2.3, let where is the shortest path between and , and let consist, ordered in the direction from to , of , for , , , and . Again, as in that proof, color by for , color by where is such that is not an -neighbor of , and color by where is such that is not an -neighbor of –then as before, the condition of being a (C4)2,2,2-coloring cannot fail at the boundary of a unit ball centered at a point of or . Now let , respectively, be the least even and odd numbers less than . Then, because there are three colors available, we can color so that each vertex in the sequence is colored differently from the previous vertex in that sequence–noting that the colors of and are already decided, alternate the color of with a color distinct from that of and . Similarly, we can color so that each vertex in the sequence is colored differently from the previous vertex in that sequence. Coloring the intermediate vertices according to these observations, we see that the condition of being a (C4)2,2,2-coloring cannot fail on the boundary of a unit ball centered at one of , because the boundary of such a ball will always be colored by two different colors. ∎
Note that a similar subclaim would fail, were we to try to use an analogous construction to obtain an theory where, for , for -dividing over .
4. Open questions
The theory , despite being an theory that does not satisfy the existence axiom, is not countably categorical. Motivated by this, we ask:
Question 4.1.
Does every countably categorical (or even ) theory satisfy the existence axiom?
Moreover, in , Kim-independence over models is not just given by the operation ; see Remark 2.7. In Definition 6.10 of [11], the definition of the property of being one-based is extended (up to elimination of hyperimaginaries) from simple theories to theories:
Definition 4.2.
Let be an theory. Then is one-based if implies (equivalently, is equivalent to) .
So is not one-based. (See Example 4.6.1 of [20].) This leads us to ask:
Question 4.3.
Does every one-based theory satisfy the existence axiom?
Recall that, as stated in Remark 2.7, Kim-independence is defined over sets in any theory satisfying the existence axiom, but is also defined over sets in despite not satisfying the existence axiom. A final question, motivated by this remark and by the original motivation discussed in the introduction for Question 1.4, the main question of this paper, is asked by Ramsey:
Acknowledgements
References
- [1] Anna-Maria Ammer and Katrin Tent. Model theory of open generalized polygons, Preprint. Available at https://arxiv.org/pdf/2308.03677.pdf. 2023,.
- [2] Byunghan Kim Artem Chernikov and Nicholas Ramsey. Transitivity, lowness and ranks in theories, Preprint. Available at https://arxiv.org/pdf/2006.10486.pdf. 2020,.
- [3] Joonhee Kim Byunghan Kim and Hyoyoon Lee. Existence in theories, Preprint. Available at https://arxiv.org/pdf/2405.13741v1. 2024.
- [4] Artem Chernikov, Ehud Hrushovski, Alex Kruckman, Krzysztof Krupiński, Slavko Moconja, Anand Pillay, and Nicholas Ramsey. Invariant measures in simple and in small theories. Journal of Mathematical Logic, 23(02):2250025, 2023.
- [5] Artem Chernikov and Itay Kaplan. Forking and dividing in theories. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 77(1):1–20, 2012.
- [6] Artem Chernikov and Nicholas Ramsey. On model-theoretic tree properties. Journal of Mathematical Logic, 16(2):1650009, 2016.
- [7] Christian d’Elbée, personal communication, February 2023.
- [8] Christian d’Elbée. Generic multiplicative endomorphism of a field, Preprint. Available at https://arxiv.org/abs/2212.02115. 2022.
- [9] Jan Dobrowolski, Byunghan Kim, and Nicholas Ramsey. Independence over arbitrary sets in nsop1 theories. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 173(2):103058, 2022.
- [10] Tapani Hyttinen and Gianluca Paolini. First-order model theory of free projective planes. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 172(2):102888, 2021.
- [11] Jim Freitag John Baldwin and Scott Mutchnik. Simple homogeneous structures and indiscernible sequence invariants, Preprint. Available at https://arxiv.org/abs/2405.08211. 2024.
- [12] Itay Kaplan and Nicholas Ramsey. On Kim-independence. Journal of the European Mathematical Society, 22, 02 2017.
- [13] Itay Kaplan and Nicholas Ramsey. Transitivity of Kim-independence. Advances in Mathematics, 379:107573, 2021.
- [14] Itay Kaplan, Nicholas Ramsey, and Saharon Shelah. Local character of kim-independence. Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, 147, 07 2017.
- [15] Byunghan Kim. Forking in Simple Unstable Theories. Journal of the London Mathematical Society, 57(2):257–267, 04 1998.
- [16] Byunghan Kim. Simple first order theories, PhD thesis, University of Notre Dame, 1996.
- [17] Byunghan Kim and Anand Pillay. Simple theories. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 88(2):149–164, 1997. Joint AILA-KGS Model Theory Meeting.
- [18] Alex Kruckman and Nicholas Ramsey. Generic expansion and Skolemization in theories. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 169(8):755–774, aug 2018.
- [19] Michael Morley. Categoricity in power. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 114(2):514–538, 1965.
- [20] A. Pillay. Geometric Stability Theory. Oxford logic guides. Clarendon Press, 1996.
- [21] Nicholas Ramsey, personal communication, May 2024.
- [22] Nicholas Ramsey. What is kim-independence, Presentation, “Neostability Theory,” Banff International Research Station, February 2024. Available at https://www.birs.ca/events/2023/5-day-workshops/23w5145/videos/watch/202302201059-Ramsey.html.
- [23] Saharon Shelah. Classification theory: and the number of non-isomorphic models. Elsevier, 1990.
- [24] KATRIN TENT. The free pseudospace is n-ample. but not (n + 1)-ample. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 79(2):410–428, 2014.
- [25] Peter M. Winkler. Model-completeness and skolem expansions. Model Theory and Algebra, page 408–463, 1975.