This paper was converted on www.awesomepapers.org from LaTeX by an anonymous user.
Want to know more? Visit the Converter page.

A pictorial proof of the Four Colour Theorem

Bhupinder Singh Anand111# 1003, Lady Ratan Tower, Dainik Shivner Marg, Gandhinagar, Worli, Mumbai - 400 018, Maharashtra, India. Email: [email protected]. Mbl: +91 93225 91328. Tel: +91 (22) 2491 9821.
Abstract

We give a pictorial, and absurdly simple, proof that transparently illustrates why four colours suffice to chromatically differentiate any set of contiguous, simply connected and bounded, planar spaces; by showing that there is no minimal planar map. We show, moreover, why the proof cannot be expressed within classical graph theory.

keywords:
contiguous area, four colour theorem, planar map, simply connected.
journal: Update as on .

2010 Mathematics Subject Classification. 05C15
DECLARATIONS \bullet Funding: Not applicable \bullet Conflicts of interest/Competing interests: Not applicable \bullet Availability of data and material: Not applicable \bullet Code availability: Not applicable \bullet Authors’ contributions: Not applicable

1 Introduction

Although the Four Colour Theorem 4CT is considered passé (see §1.1), we give a pictorial, and absurdly simple, proof222Extracted from [An21], §1.G: Evidence-based (pictorial), pre-formal, proofs of the Four Colour Theorem. that transparently illustrates why four colours suffice to chromatically differentiate any set of contiguous, simply connected and bounded, planar spaces; by showing that:

  1. (1)

    If, for some natural numbers m,nm,n, every planar map of less than m+nm+n contiguous, simply connected and bounded, areas can be 44-coloured;

  2. (2)

    And, we assume (Hypothesis 1) that there is a sub-minimal 44-coloured planar map \mathcal{M}, of m+nm+n such areas, where finitary creation of a specific, additional, contiguous, simply connected and bounded, area CC within \mathcal{M} yields a minimal map \mathcal{H} which entails that CC require a 5th colour;

  3. (3)

    Then Hypothesis 1 is false (by Theorem 21), since there can be no such sub-minimal 44-coloured planar map \mathcal{M}.

Moreover we show why—challenging deep-seated dogmas that seemingly yet await, even if not actively seek, a mathematically ‘insightful’, and philosophically ‘satisfying’, proof of 4CT within inherited paradigms—the pictorial proof cannot be expressed within classical graph theory.

1.1 A historical perspective

It would probably be a fair assessment that the mathematical significance of any new proof of the Four Colour Theorem 4CT continues to be perceived as lying not in any ensuing theoretical or practical utility of the Theorem per se, but in whether the proof can address the philosophically ‘unsatisfying’, and occasionally ‘despairing’ (see [Tym79]; [Sw80]; [Gnt08], [Cl01]), lack of mathematical ‘insight’, ‘simplicity’, and ‘elegance’ in currently known proofs of the Theorem (eg. [AH77], [AHK77], [RSST], [Gnt08])—an insight and simplicity this investigation seeks in a pre-formal333The need for distinguishing between belief-based ‘informal’, and evidence-based ‘pre-formal’, reasoning is addressed by Markus Pantsar in [Pan09]; see also [An21], §1.D. proof of 4CT.

For instance we note—amongst others—some candid comments from Robertson, Sanders, Seymour, and Thomas’s 1995-dated (apparently pre-publication) summary444See [RSSp]; also [Thm98], [Cl01], and the survey [Rgrs] by Leo Rogers. of their proof [RSST]:

Why a new proof?

There are two reasons why the Appel-Haken proof is not completely satisfactory.

\bullet Part of the Appel-Haken proof uses a computer, and cannot be verified by hand, and

\bullet even the part that is supposedly hand-checkable is extraordinarily complicated and tedious, and as far as we know, no one has verified it in its entirety.” …Robertson et al: [RSSp], Pre-publication.

“It has been known since 1913 that every minimal counterexample to the Four Color Theorem is an internally six-connected triangulation. In the second part of the proof, published in [4, p. 432], Robertson et al. proved that at least one of the 633 configurations appears in every internally six-connected planar triangulation. This condition is called “unavoidability,” and uses the discharging method, first suggested by Heesch. Here, the proof differs from that of Appel and Haken in that it relies far less on computer calculation. Nevertheless, parts of the proof still cannot be verified by a human. The search continues for a computer-free proof of the Four Color Theorem.” …Brun: [Bru02], §1. Introduction (Article for undergraduates)

“The four-colour problem had a long life before it eventually became the four-colour theorem. In 1852 Francis Gutherie (later Professor of Mathematics at the University of Cape Town) noticed that a map of the counties of England could be coloured using only four colours. He wondered if four colours would always suffice for any map. He, or his brother Frederick, proposed the problem to Augustus De Morgan (see the box at the end of Section 3.5 in Chapter 3) who liked it and suggested it to other mathematicians. Interest in the problem increased after Arthur Cayley presented it to the London Mathematical Society in 1878 ([Cay79]). The next year Alfred Bray Kempe (a British lawyer) gave a proof of the conjecture. His proof models the problem in terms of graphs and breaks it up into a number of necessary cases to be checked. Another proof was given by Peter Tait in 1880. It seemed that the four-colour problem had been settled in the affirmative.

However, in 1890 Percy John Heawood found that Kempe’s proof missed one crucial case, but that the approach could still be used to prove that five colours are sufficient to colour any map. In the following year Tait’s proof was also shown to be flawed, this time by Julius Petersen, after whom the Petersen graph is named. The four-colour problem was therefore again open, and would remain so for the next 86 years. In that time it attracted a lot of attention from professional mathematicians and good (and not so good) amateurs alike. In the words of Underwood Dudley:

The four-color conjecture was easy to state and easy to understand, no large amount of technical mathematics is needed to attack it, and errors in proposed proofs are hard to see, even for professionals; what an ideal combination to attract cranks!

The four-colour theorem was finally proved in 1976 by Kenneth Appel and Wolfgang Haken at the University of Illinois. They reduced the problem to a large number of cases, which were then checked by computer. This was the first mathematical proof that needed computer assistance. In 1997 N. Robertson, D.P. Sanders, P.D. Seymour and R. Thomas published a refinement of Appel [and] Haken’s proof, which reduces the number of necessary cases, but which still relies on computer assistance. The search is still on for a short proof that does not require a computer.” …Conradie/Goranko: [CG15], §7.7.1, Graph Colourings, p.417.

“The first example concerns a notorious problem within the philosophy of mathematics, namely the acceptability of computer-generated proofs or proofs that can only be checked by a computer; for instance because it includes the verification of an excessively large set of cases. The text-book example of such a mathematical result is the proof of the 4-colour theorem, which continues to preoccupy philosophers of mathematics (Calude 2001). Here, we only need to note that the debate does not primarily concern the correctness of the result, but rather its failure to adhere to the standard of surveyability to which mathematical proofs should conform.” …Allo: [All17], Conclusion, p.562.

“Being the first ever proof to be achieved with substantial help of a computer, it has raised questions to what a proof really is. Many mathematicians remain sceptical about the nature of this proof due to the involvement of a computer. With the possibility of a computing error, they do not feel comfortable relying on a machine to do their work as they would be if it were a simple pen-and-paper proof.

The controversy lies not so much on whether or not the proof is valid but rather whether the proof is a valid proof. To mathematicians, it is as important to understand why something is correct as it is finding the solution. They hate that there is no way of knowing how a computer reasons. Since a computer runs programs as they are fed into it, designed to tackle a problem in a particular way, it is likely they will return what the programmer wants to find leaving out any other possible outcomes outside the bracket.

Many mathematicians continue to search for a better proof to the problem. They prefer to think that the Four Colour problem has not been solved and that one day someone will come up with a simple completely hand checkable proof to the problem.” …Nanjwenge: [Nnj18], Chapter 8, Discussion (Student Thesis).

“The heavy reliance on computers in Appel and Haken’s proof was immediately a topic of discussion and concern in the mathematical community. The issue was the fact that no individual could check the proof; of special concern was the reductibility [sic] part of the proof because the details were “hidden” inside the computer. Though it isn’t so much the validity of the result, but the understanding of the proof. Appel himself commented: “…there were people who said, ‘This is terrible mathematics, because mathematics should be clean and elegant,’ and I would agree. It would be nicer to have clean and elegant proofs.” See page 222 of Wilson.” …Gardner: [Grd21], §11.1, Colourings of Planar Maps, pp.6-7 (Lecture notes).

2 A pictorial proof of the 4-Colour Theorem

\begin{picture}(50.0,20.0)\par \leavevmode\hbox to114.21pt{\vbox to341.83pt{\pgfpicture\makeatletter\hbox{\hskip 57.10551pt\lower-57.10551pt\hbox to0.0pt{\pgfsys@beginscope\pgfsys@invoke{ }\definecolor{pgfstrokecolor}{rgb}{0,0,0}\pgfsys@color@rgb@stroke{0}{0}{0}\pgfsys@invoke{ }\pgfsys@color@rgb@fill{0}{0}{0}\pgfsys@invoke{ }\pgfsys@setlinewidth{0.4pt}\pgfsys@invoke{ }\nullfont\hbox to0.0pt{\pgfsys@beginscope\pgfsys@invoke{ } \par\pgfsys@beginscope\pgfsys@invoke{ }{}{{}}{} {}{{}}{}{}{}{}{{}}{}\pgfsys@moveto{-56.90552pt}{-56.90552pt}\pgfsys@moveto{-56.90552pt}{-56.90552pt}\pgfsys@lineto{-56.90552pt}{56.90552pt}\pgfsys@lineto{0.0pt}{56.90552pt}\pgfsys@lineto{0.0pt}{-56.90552pt}\pgfsys@closepath\pgfsys@moveto{0.0pt}{56.90552pt}\pgfsys@clipnext\pgfsys@discardpath\pgfsys@invoke{ }{}{{}}{}{{{}}{}{}{}{}{}{}{}{}}{}\pgfsys@moveto{0.0pt}{0.0pt}\pgfsys@moveto{56.90552pt}{0.0pt}\pgfsys@curveto{56.90552pt}{31.42845pt}{31.42845pt}{56.90552pt}{0.0pt}{56.90552pt}\pgfsys@curveto{-31.42845pt}{56.90552pt}{-56.90552pt}{31.42845pt}{-56.90552pt}{0.0pt}\pgfsys@curveto{-56.90552pt}{-31.42845pt}{-31.42845pt}{-56.90552pt}{0.0pt}{-56.90552pt}\pgfsys@curveto{31.42845pt}{-56.90552pt}{56.90552pt}{-31.42845pt}{56.90552pt}{0.0pt}\pgfsys@closepath\pgfsys@moveto{0.0pt}{0.0pt}\pgfsys@stroke\pgfsys@invoke{ } {}{{}}{} {}{}{}\pgfsys@moveto{-56.90552pt}{284.52759pt}\pgfsys@lineto{56.90552pt}{284.52759pt}\pgfsys@stroke\pgfsys@invoke{ } \pgfsys@invoke{\lxSVG@closescope }\pgfsys@endscope \pgfsys@invoke{\lxSVG@closescope }\pgfsys@endscope{{ {}{}{}{}{}}}{}{}\hss}\pgfsys@discardpath\pgfsys@invoke{\lxSVG@closescope }\pgfsys@endscope\hss}}\lxSVG@closescope\endpgfpicture}} \par\put(4.45,-57.0){\oval(25.0,113.0)} \put(-36.0,-100.0){\color[rgb]{1,0,0}\definecolor[named]{pgfstrokecolor}{rgb}{1,0,0}\line(0,1){86.0}} \par\put(-30.0,-100.0){\line(1,0){21.0}} \put(-30.0,-90.0){\line(1,0){21.0}} \put(-30.0,-80.0){\line(1,0){21.0}} \put(-30.0,-70.0){\line(1,0){21.0}} \put(-30.0,-50.0){\line(1,0){21.0}} \put(-30.0,-40.0){\line(1,0){21.0}} \put(-30.0,-30.0){\line(1,0){21.0}} \put(-30.0,-22.0){\line(1,0){21.0}} \put(-30.0,-14.0){\line(1,0){21.0}} \par\put(25.0,-35.0){\color[rgb]{1,0,0}\definecolor[named]{pgfstrokecolor}{rgb}{1,0,0}\vector(-1,0){40.0}} \par\put(3.0,-63.0){$C$} \put(-30.0,-63.0){$B_{n}$} \put(-55.0,-63.0){$A_{m}$} \par\put(73.0,0.0){{{\footnotesize Minimal Planar Map $\mathcal{H}$}}} \par\put(-30.0,-63.0){$B_{n}$} \par\put(27.0,-38.0){\footnotesize{Only the immediate portion of each area $c_{n,1},c_{n,2},\ldots,c_{n,r}$ of $B_{n}$ abutting $C$ is indicated.}} \put(-30.0,-37.0){\footnotesize$c_{n,i}$} \par\put(-5.0,-125.0){\footnotesize{Fig.1}} \end{picture}

CCBnB_{n}AmA_{m}

Minimal Planar Map \mathcal{H}

BnB_{n}

Only the immediate portion of each area cn,1,cn,2,,cn,rc_{n,1},c_{n,2},\ldots,c_{n,r} of BnB_{n} abutting CC is indicated.cn,ic_{n,i}

Fig.1

We consider the surface of the hemisphere (minimal planar map \mathcal{H}) in Fig.1 where:

  1. 1.

    AmA_{m} denotes a region of mm contiguous, simply connected and bounded, surface areas am,1,am,2,a_{m,1},a_{m,2}, ,am,m\ldots,a_{m,m}, none of which share a non-zero boundary segment with the contiguous, simply connected, surface area CC (as indicated by the red barrier which, however, is not to be treated as a boundary of the region AmA_{m});

  2. 2.

    BnB_{n} denotes a region of nn contiguous, simply connected and bounded, surface areas bn,1,bn,2,b_{n,1},b_{n,2}, ,bn,n\ldots,b_{n,n}, some of which, say cn,1,cn,2,,cn,rc_{n,1},c_{n,2},\ldots,c_{n,r}, share at least one non-zero boundary segment of cn,ic_{n,i} with CC; where, for each 1ir1\leq i\leq r, cn,i=bn,jc_{n,i}=b_{n,j} for some 1jn1\leq j\leq n;

  3. 3.

    CC is a single contiguous, simply connected and bounded, area created finitarily (i.e., not postulated) by sub-dividing and annexing one or more contiguous, simply connected, portions of each area cn,ic_{n,i}^{-} (defined in Hypothesis 1(b) below) in the region BnB_{n}^{-} (defined in Hypothesis 1(b)).

Hypothesis 1 (Minimality Hypothesis)

Since four colours suffice for maps with fewer than 5 regions, we assume the existence of some m,nm,n, in a putatively minimal planar map \mathcal{H}, which defines a minimal configuration of the region {Am+Bn+C}\{A_{m}+B_{n}+C\} where:

  1. (a)

    any configuration of pp contiguous, simply connected and bounded, areas can be 44-coloured if pm+np\leq m+n, where p,m,np,m,n\in\mathbb{N}, and m+n5m+n\geq 5;

  2. (b)

    any configuration of the m+nm+n contiguous, simply connected and bounded, areas of the region, say {Am+Bn}\{A_{m}^{-}+B_{n}^{-}\}, in a putative, sub-minimal, planar map \mathcal{M} before the creation of CC—constructed finitarily by sub-dividing and annexing some portions from each area, say cn,ic_{n,i}^{-}, of BnB_{n}^{-} in \mathcal{M}—can be 4-coloured;

  3. (c)

    the region {Am+Bn+C}\{A_{m}+B_{n}+C\} in the planar map \mathcal{H} is a specific configuration of m+n+1m+n+1 contiguous, simply connected and bounded, areas that cannot be 4-coloured (whence the area CC necessarily requires a 5th colour by the Minimality Hypothesis).

Theorem 21 (Four Colour Theorem)

No planar map needs more than four colours.

\begin{picture}(50.0,20.0)\par \leavevmode\hbox to114.21pt{\vbox to341.83pt{\pgfpicture\makeatletter\hbox{\hskip 57.10551pt\lower-57.10551pt\hbox to0.0pt{\pgfsys@beginscope\pgfsys@invoke{ }\definecolor{pgfstrokecolor}{rgb}{0,0,0}\pgfsys@color@rgb@stroke{0}{0}{0}\pgfsys@invoke{ }\pgfsys@color@rgb@fill{0}{0}{0}\pgfsys@invoke{ }\pgfsys@setlinewidth{0.4pt}\pgfsys@invoke{ }\nullfont\hbox to0.0pt{\pgfsys@beginscope\pgfsys@invoke{ } \par\pgfsys@beginscope\pgfsys@invoke{ }{}{{}}{} {}{{}}{}{}{}{}{{}}{}\pgfsys@moveto{-56.90552pt}{-56.90552pt}\pgfsys@moveto{-56.90552pt}{-56.90552pt}\pgfsys@lineto{-56.90552pt}{56.90552pt}\pgfsys@lineto{0.0pt}{56.90552pt}\pgfsys@lineto{0.0pt}{-56.90552pt}\pgfsys@closepath\pgfsys@moveto{0.0pt}{56.90552pt}\pgfsys@clipnext\pgfsys@discardpath\pgfsys@invoke{ }{}{{}}{}{{{}}{}{}{}{}{}{}{}{}}{}\pgfsys@moveto{0.0pt}{0.0pt}\pgfsys@moveto{56.90552pt}{0.0pt}\pgfsys@curveto{56.90552pt}{31.42845pt}{31.42845pt}{56.90552pt}{0.0pt}{56.90552pt}\pgfsys@curveto{-31.42845pt}{56.90552pt}{-56.90552pt}{31.42845pt}{-56.90552pt}{0.0pt}\pgfsys@curveto{-56.90552pt}{-31.42845pt}{-31.42845pt}{-56.90552pt}{0.0pt}{-56.90552pt}\pgfsys@curveto{31.42845pt}{-56.90552pt}{56.90552pt}{-31.42845pt}{56.90552pt}{0.0pt}\pgfsys@closepath\pgfsys@moveto{0.0pt}{0.0pt}\pgfsys@stroke\pgfsys@invoke{ } {}{{}}{} {}{}{}\pgfsys@moveto{-56.90552pt}{284.52759pt}\pgfsys@lineto{56.90552pt}{284.52759pt}\pgfsys@stroke\pgfsys@invoke{ } \pgfsys@invoke{\lxSVG@closescope }\pgfsys@endscope \pgfsys@invoke{\lxSVG@closescope }\pgfsys@endscope{{ {}{}{}{}{}}}{}{}\hss}\pgfsys@discardpath\pgfsys@invoke{\lxSVG@closescope }\pgfsys@endscope\hss}}\lxSVG@closescope\endpgfpicture}} \par\put(4.45,-57.0){\oval(25.0,113.0)} \put(-36.0,-100.0){\color[rgb]{1,0,0}\definecolor[named]{pgfstrokecolor}{rgb}{1,0,0}\line(0,1){86.0}} \par\put(-30.0,-100.0){\line(1,0){21.0}} \put(-30.0,-90.0){\line(1,0){21.0}} \put(-30.0,-80.0){\line(1,0){21.0}} \put(-30.0,-70.0){\line(1,0){21.0}} \put(-30.0,-50.0){\line(1,0){21.0}} \put(-30.0,-40.0){\line(1,0){21.0}} \put(-30.0,-30.0){\line(1,0){21.0}} \put(-30.0,-22.0){\line(1,0){21.0}} \put(-30.0,-14.0){\line(1,0){21.0}} \par\par\par\put(3.0,-17.0){\tiny$E_{1}$} \put(3.0,-93.0){\tiny$E_{1}$} \put(-5.0,-37.0){\tiny$D_{1}$} \par\par\put(3.0,-63.0){\tiny$E_{1}$} \put(-30.0,-63.0){$B_{n}$} \put(-55.0,-63.0){$A_{m}$} \par\par\put(73.0,0.0){{{\footnotesize Planar Map $\mathcal{H^{\prime}}$}}} \par\put(-30.0,-63.0){$B_{n}$} \par\par\put(-30.0,-37.0){\footnotesize$c_{n,i}$} \put(-10.0,-40.0){\line(1,0){16.0}} \put(-10.0,-30.0){\line(1,0){16.0}} \put(5.0,-40.0){\line(0,1){10.0}} \par\par\par\put(-5.0,-125.0){\footnotesize{Fig.2}} \end{picture}

E1E_{1}E1E_{1}D1D_{1}

E1E_{1}BnB_{n}AmA_{m}

Planar Map \mathcal{H^{\prime}}

BnB_{n}

cn,ic_{n,i}

Fig.2

Proof 22.

If the area CC of the minimal planar map \mathcal{H} in Fig.1 is divided further (as indicated in Fig.2) into two non-empty areas D1\small D_{1} and E1\small E_{1}, where:

  • D1\small D_{1} shares a non-zero boundary segment with only one of the areas cn,ic_{n,i}; and

  • D1D_{1} can be treated as an original area of cn,ic_{n,i}^{-} in \mathcal{M} (see Hypothesis 1(b)) that was annexed to form part of CC in \mathcal{H} (in Fig.1);

then D1D_{1} can be absorbed back into cn,ic_{n,i} without violating the Minimality Hypothesis. Moreover, cn,i+D1c_{n,i}+\small{D_{1}} must share a non-zero boundary with E1\small E_{1} in \mathcal{H^{\prime}} if cn,i=bn,jc_{n,i}=b_{n,j} for some 1<j<n1<j<n, and bn,j,Cb_{n,j},C are required to be differently coloured, in \mathcal{H}.

Such a division, as illustrated in Fig.2, followed by re-absorption of D1\small D_{1} into cn,ic_{n,i}^{-} (denoted, say, by Bn+D1B_{n}+\small{D_{1}}), would reduce the configuration \mathcal{H^{\prime}} in Fig.2 again to a minimal planar map, say 1\mathcal{H}_{1} with a configuration {Am+Bn+E1}\{A_{m}+B_{n}^{\prime}+\small{E_{1}}\}, where Bn=(Bn+D1)B_{n}^{\prime}=(B_{n}+\small{D_{1}}); which would in turn necessitate a 5th colour for the area E1C\small E_{1}\subset C by the Minimality Hypothesis.

Since we cannot, by reiteration, have a non-terminating sequence CE1E2E3C\supset\small{E_{1}}\supset\small{E_{2}}\supset\small{E_{3}}\supset\ldots, the sequence must terminate in a non-empty area Ek\small{E_{k}} of a minimal planar map, say k\mathcal{H}_{k}, for some finite integer kk; where Ek\small E_{k} contains no area that is annexed from any of the areas of BnB_{n}^{-} in \mathcal{M} prior to the formation of the minimal planar map \mathcal{H} (in Fig.1).

Comment: Note that we cannot admit as a putative limit of CE1E2E3C\supset\small{E_{1}}\supset\small{E_{2}}\supset\small{E_{3}}\ldots the configuration where all the cn,ic^{-}_{n,i}—corresponding to the abutting areas cn,ic_{n,i} of CC in the Minimal Planar Map \mathcal{H}—meet at a point in the putative, sub-minimal, planar map \mathcal{M}, since any finitary (i.e., not postulated) creation of CC, begun by initially annexing a non-empty area of some cn,ic^{-}_{n,i} at such an apex (corresponding to the putative ‘finally merged’ area of the above non-terminating sequence CE1E2E3C\supset\small{E_{1}}\supset\small{E_{2}}\supset\small{E_{3}}\supset\ldots), would require, at most, a 4th but not a 5th colour.

However, by Hypothesis 1(b), this contradicts the definition of the area CC, in the minimal planar map \mathcal{H} (in Fig.1)—ergo of the area Ek\small{E_{k}} in the minimal planar map k\mathcal{H}_{k}—as formed finitarily by sub-division and annexation of existing areas of BnB_{n}^{-} in \mathcal{M}.

Hence there can be no minimal planar map \mathcal{H} which defines a minimal configuration such as the region {Am+Bn+C}\{A_{m}+B_{n}+C\} in Fig.1. The theorem follows. \Box

We conclude by noting that, since classical graph theory555See, for instance, Brun [Bru02], Conradie/Goranko [CG15], Gardner [Grd21]. represents non-empty areas as points (vertices), and a non-zero boundary between two areas as a line (edge) joining two points (vertices), it cannot express the proof of Theorem 21 graphically.

Reason: The proof of Theorem 21 appeals to finitarily distinguishable properties of a series of, putatively minimal, planar maps ,1,2,\mathcal{H},\mathcal{H}_{1},\mathcal{H}_{2},\ldots, created by a corresponding sequence of areas C,E1,E2,,C,\small{E_{1}},\small{E_{2}},\ldots, where each area is finitarily created from, or as a proper subset of, some preceding area/s in such a way that the graphs of ,1,2,\mathcal{H},\mathcal{H}_{1},\mathcal{H}_{2},\ldots remain undistinguished.

References