This paper was converted on www.awesomepapers.org from LaTeX by an anonymous user.
Want to know more? Visit the Converter page.

A note on cardinal preserving embeddings

Gabriel Goldberg
Evans Hall
University Drive
Berkeley, CA 94720

1 Introduction

An elementary embedding between two transitive models of set theory is cardinal preserving if its domain and target models have the same class of cardinals. The purpose of this note is to extend some ideas due to Caicedo and Woodin, leading to a proof that the critical point κ\kappa of a cardinal preserving embedding from the universe into an inner model is strongly compact in VγV_{\gamma} for some inaccessible cardinal γ>κ\gamma>\kappa.

In particular, we have the following consistency result:

Theorem 2.10.

The existence of a cardinal preserving embedding from the universe into an inner model implies the consistency of ZFC + there is a strongly compact cardinal.

We also show that the existence of a cardinal preserving embedding from the universe into MM implies much stronger resemblance properties of VV and MM than are immediately apparent, especially assuming the Singular Cardinals Hypothesis:

Theorem 2.11 (SCH).

Suppose there is a cardinal preserving elementary embedding from the universe into an inner model MM. Then for any ordinal α\alpha, cfM(α)=cf(α)\textnormal{cf}^{M}(\alpha)=\textnormal{cf}(\alpha) and for any cardinal ρ\rho, (2ρ)M=2ρ(2^{\rho})^{M}=2^{\rho}.

2 Some proofs

If j:VMj:V\to M is an elementary embedding, then the critical sequence κn(j)\kappa_{n}(j) is defined by recursion, setting κ0(j)=crit(j)\kappa_{0}(j)=\textnormal{crit}(j) and κn+1(j)=j(κn(j))\kappa_{n+1}(j)=j(\kappa_{n}(j)). Finally, κω(j)=supn<ωκn(j)\kappa_{\omega}(j)=\sup_{n<\omega}\kappa_{n}(j) denotes the supremum of the critical sequence of jj.

The following is straightforward using an observation of Caicedo:

Proposition 2.1.

Suppose there is a cardinal preserving embedding j:VMj:V\to M. Let κ=crit(j)\kappa=\textnormal{crit}(j) and let λ=κω(j)\lambda=\kappa_{\omega}(j). Then κ\kappa is λ\lambda-strongly compact.

Proof.

By Ketonen’s Theorem [3], it suffices to show that every regular cardinal in the interval [κ,λ][\kappa,\lambda] carries a κ\kappa-complete uniform ultrafilter. By Príkry’s Theorem [4], it suffices to show that every successor cardinal in the interval [κ,λ][\kappa,\lambda] carries a κ\kappa-complete uniform ultrafilter.

Suppose δ\delta is an ordinal with κδ<λ\kappa\leq\delta<\lambda. We claim there is a κ\kappa-complete uniform ultrafilter on δ+\delta^{+}. First, since κδ+<λ\kappa\leq\delta^{+}<\lambda, δ+<j(δ+)\delta^{+}<j(\delta^{+}). Also, note that j(δ+)=j(δ)+j(\delta^{+})=j(\delta)^{+} since MM correctly computes successor cardinals. This means that the cardinal j(δ+)j(\delta^{+}) is regular, and in particular it has cofinality strictly larger than δ+\delta^{+}. As a consequence, supj[δ+]<j(δ+)\sup j[\delta^{+}]<j(\delta^{+}). Therefore one can derive an ultrafilter on δ+\delta^{+} from jj using supj[δ+]\sup j[\delta^{+}], and this ultrafilter is clearly uniform; it is κ\kappa-complete since crit(j)=κ\textnormal{crit}(j)=\kappa. ∎

The proposition does not obviously yield the consistency of a strongly compact cardinal from a cardinal preserving embedding since it is not clear that the interval (κ,λ)(\kappa,\lambda) contains an inaccessible cardinal. In fact, it is not even clear that 2κ<λ2^{\kappa}<\lambda. We will prove that λ\lambda is a limit of inaccessible cardinals, and in fact κn(j)\kappa_{n}(j) is inaccessible for every n<ωn<\omega.

The key lemma is not hard, but it seems interesting in its own right. The main concept involved is the tightness function of an elementary embedding.

Definition 2.2.

If j:VMj:V\to M is an elementary embedding, then for any cardinal λ\lambda, tj(λ)t_{j}(\lambda) denotes the least MM-cardinality of a set in MM that covers j[λ]j[\lambda].

Note that for any set XX, tj(|X|)t_{j}(|X|) is the least MM-cardinality of a set in MM that covers j[X]j[X]. The following theorem, implicit in the work of Ketonen [3], appears explicitly in the author’s thesis [2, Theorem 7.2.12].

Theorem 2.3 (Ketonen, [3]).

If j:VMj:V\to M is an elementary embedding and δ\delta is a regular cardinal, then tj(δ)=cfM(supj[δ])t_{j}(\delta)=\textnormal{cf}^{M}(\sup j[\delta]).∎

Lemma 2.4.

Suppose j:VMj:V\to M is an elementary embedding with critical point κ\kappa and λ\lambda is a singular cardinal of cofinality ι<κ\iota<\kappa. Then for some MM-cardinal η\eta of MM-cofinality ι\iota, η<tj(λι)(ηι)M\eta<t_{j}(\lambda^{\iota})\leq(\eta^{\iota})^{M}.

Proof.

Let UU be the ultrafilter on λ+\lambda^{+} derived from jj using supj[λ+]\sup j[\lambda^{+}]. Let i:VNi:V\to N be the ultrapower associated to UU.

Let δα:α<ι\langle\delta_{\alpha}:\alpha<\iota\rangle be an increasing sequence of regular cardinals cofinal in λ\lambda. Let δα=ti(δα)\delta_{\alpha}^{\prime}=t_{i}(\delta_{\alpha}). Then since NN is closed under ι\iota-sequences, ti(λ)=supδαt_{i}(\lambda)=\sup\delta_{\alpha}^{\prime}. Moreover, 2.3 easily implies that δα<δβ\delta_{\alpha}^{\prime}<\delta_{\beta}^{\prime} whenever α<β\alpha<\beta. Therefore ti(λ)t_{i}(\lambda) has cofinality ι\iota (in NN). Let ν=ti(λ)\nu=t_{i}(\lambda). Fix ANA\in N covering i[λ]i[\lambda] with |A|N=ν|A|^{N}=\nu. Since NN is closed under ι\iota-sequences and crit(j)>ι\textnormal{crit}(j)>\iota, i[λι](Aι)Ni[{}^{\iota}\lambda]\subseteq({}^{\iota}A)^{N}. It follows that ti(λι)νιt_{i}(\lambda^{\iota})\leq\nu^{\iota}.

Let k:NMk:N\to M be the factor embedding, and set η=k(ν)\eta=k(\nu). Trivially, tj(λι)(ηι)Mt_{j}(\lambda^{\iota})\leq(\eta^{\iota})^{M}. Since k(supi[λ+])=supj[λ+]k(\sup i[\lambda^{+}])=\sup j[\lambda^{+}], 2.3 implies that k(ti(λ+))=tj(λ+)k(t_{i}(\lambda^{+}))=t_{j}(\lambda^{+}). Therefore since ν=ti(λ)<ti(λ+)\nu=t_{i}(\lambda)<t_{i}(\lambda^{+}), η<tj(λ+)tj(λι)\eta<t_{j}(\lambda^{+})\leq t_{j}(\lambda^{\iota}). This finishes the proof. ∎

Here is one intriguing consequence, which is very similar to a consequence of the Ultrapower Axiom [2, Lemma 8.4.14] originally proved in the analysis of cardinal preservation under UA.

Theorem 2.5 (SCH).

Suppose j:VMj:V\to M is an elementary embedding and δ\delta is the successor of a singular cardinal of cofinality ι<crit(j)\iota<\textnormal{crit}(j). Then in MM, the cofinality of supj[δ]\sup j[\delta] is the successor of a singular cardinal of cofinality ι\iota.∎

We will avoid the SCH in our main theorem by citing a local form of Solovay’s Theorem.

Theorem 2.6 (Solovay, [5]).

If κ\kappa is λ\lambda-strongly compact, then for any singular cardinal η\eta with κηλ\kappa\leq\eta\leq\lambda, ηcf(η)=η+2cf(η)\eta^{\textnormal{cf}(\eta)}=\eta^{+}\cdot 2^{\textnormal{cf}(\eta)}.∎

The author tentatively conjectures that the existence of a cardinal preserving embedding of the universe of sets is inconsistent with ZFC. The existence of the partially cardinal preserving embeddings involved in the hypotheses of the next few theorems, however, follows from the axiom I2I_{2}, and therefore is very likely to be consistent.

Theorem 2.7.

Suppose j:VMj:V\to M is an elementary embedding. Let κ=crit(j)\kappa=\textnormal{crit}(j), and let λ=κω(j)\lambda=\kappa_{\omega}(j). Assume jVλj\restriction V_{\lambda} is cardinal preserving, or in other words CardMλ=CardVλ\textnormal{Card}^{M}\cap\lambda=\textnormal{Card}^{V}\cap\lambda. Then for any ordinal αλ\alpha\leq\lambda, cfM(α)=cf(α)\textnormal{cf}^{M}(\alpha)=\textnormal{cf}(\alpha).

Proof.

First, fix a singular cardinal ρ\rho of cofinality ω\omega with ρλ\rho\leq\lambda. We will show that tj(ρ+)=ρ+t_{j}(\rho^{+})=\rho^{+}. If j(ρ+)=ρ+j(\rho^{+})=\rho^{+}, this is trivial, so we may assume κρ<λ\kappa\leq\rho<\lambda. By 2.4, there is a cardinal η\eta of MM-cofinality ω\omega such that η<tj(λ+)(ηω)M\eta<t_{j}(\lambda^{+})\leq(\eta^{\omega})^{M}.

We claim (ηω)M=η+(\eta^{\omega})^{M}=\eta^{+}. Note that κη<λ\kappa\leq\eta<\lambda, so since κ\kappa is λ\lambda-strongly compact by 2.1, ηω=η+\eta^{\omega}=\eta^{+} by Solovay’s Theorem. Therefore (ηω)M<η++(\eta^{\omega})^{M}<\eta^{++}, and so by cardinal correctness, (ηω)Mη+(\eta^{\omega})^{M}\leq\eta^{+}. By König’s Theorem, (ηω)M(η+)M=η+(\eta^{\omega})^{M}\geq(\eta^{+})^{M}=\eta^{+}. It follows that (ηω)M=η+(\eta^{\omega})^{M}=\eta^{+}, as claimed.

By 2.4, we can conclude that η<tj(λ+)η+\eta<t_{j}(\lambda^{+})\leq\eta^{+}, or in other words, tj(ρ+)=η+t_{j}(\rho^{+})=\eta^{+}. Hence cfM(supj[ρ+])=η+\textnormal{cf}^{M}(\sup j[\rho^{+}])=\eta^{+}, and so η+\eta^{+} and ρ+\rho^{+} have the same cofinality. Since successor cardinals are regular, η+=ρ+\eta^{+}=\rho^{+}.

Now let γ<λ\gamma<\lambda be a regular cardinal. We have

γtj(γ)<tj(γ+ω+1)=γ+ω+1\gamma\leq t_{j}(\gamma)<t_{j}(\gamma^{+\omega+1})=\gamma^{+\omega+1}

where the final equality follows from the previous paragraphs with ρ=γ+ω\rho=\gamma^{+\omega}. Thus tj(γ)=γ+nt_{j}(\gamma)=\gamma^{+n} for some n<ωn<\omega. But by 2.3, tj(γ)t_{j}(\gamma) has cofinality γ\gamma, and therefore tj(γ)=γt_{j}(\gamma)=\gamma.

Next, suppose δ<λ\delta<\lambda is a cardinal that is regular in MM. Assume towards a contradiction that δ\delta is singular in VV. By our work so far, δtj(δ)<tj(δ+)=δ+\delta\leq t_{j}(\delta)<t_{j}(\delta^{+})=\delta^{+}, so tj(δ)=δt_{j}(\delta)=\delta, and hence cfM(supj[δ])=δ\textnormal{cf}^{M}(\sup j[\delta])=\delta. But now let ι=cf(δ)\iota=\textnormal{cf}(\delta). Let UU be the ultrafilter on ι\iota derived from jj using supj[ι]\sup j[\iota]. Then tjU(ι)=ιt_{j_{U}}(\iota)=\iota. As a consequence, cfMU(supjU[δ])=ι\textnormal{cf}^{M_{U}}(\sup j_{U}[\delta])=\iota. Now let k:MUMk:M_{U}\to M be the factor embedding. Then k(ι)=ιk(\iota)=\iota. Hence kk is continuous at ordinals of cofinality ι\iota, and in particular, k(supjU[δ])=supj[δ]k(\sup j_{U}[\delta])=\sup j[\delta]. Thus cfM(supj[δ])=k(cfMU(supjU[δ]))=k(ι)=ι\textnormal{cf}^{M}(\sup j[\delta])=k(\textnormal{cf}^{M_{U}}(\sup j_{U}[\delta]))=k(\iota)=\iota, and this contradicts that cfM(supj[δ])=δ\textnormal{cf}^{M}(\sup j[\delta])=\delta.

Finally, we conclude the theorem. Fix an ordinal α\alpha. Then cfM(α)\textnormal{cf}^{M}(\alpha) is an MM-regular cardinal δ\delta, and so cf(α)=cf(δ)=δ\textnormal{cf}(\alpha)=\textnormal{cf}(\delta)=\delta. ∎

We now argue that cardinal preserving embeddings preserve the continuum function. This extends an argument due to Woodin-Caicedo [1].

Lemma 2.8.

Suppose j:VMj:V\to M is an elementary embedding. If ρ\rho is a cardinal and θ=tj(ρ)\theta=t_{j}(\rho) then (2θ)M2ρ(2^{\theta})^{M}\geq 2^{\rho}.

Proof.

Let AMA\in M be a cover of j[ρ]j[\rho] with |A|M=θ|A|^{M}=\theta. Note that |PM(A)|M=(2θ)M|P^{M}(A)|^{M}=(2^{\theta})^{M}. But there is an injection f:P(ρ)PM(A)f:P(\rho)\to P^{M}(A) defined by f(B)=j(B)Af(B)=j(B)\cap A. So 2ρ=|P(ρ)||PM(A)||PM(A)|M=(2θ)M2^{\rho}=|P(\rho)|\leq|P^{M}(A)|\leq|P^{M}(A)|^{M}=(2^{\theta})^{M}. ∎

Theorem 2.9.

Suppose j:VMj:V\to M is an elementary embedding. Let κ=crit(j)\kappa=\textnormal{crit}(j), and let λ=κω(j)\lambda=\kappa_{\omega}(j). Assume jVλj\restriction V_{\lambda} is cardinal preserving, or in other words CardMλ=CardVλ\textnormal{Card}^{M}\cap\lambda=\textnormal{Card}^{V}\cap\lambda. Then for any cardinal ρ<λ\rho<\lambda, (2ρ)M=2ρ(2^{\rho})^{M}=2^{\rho}.

Proof.

Since |(2ρ)M|=|PM(ρ)||(2^{\rho})^{M}|=|P^{M}(\rho)|, we have (2ρ)M<(2ρ)+(2^{\rho})^{M}<(2^{\rho})^{+}. But (2ρ)M(2^{\rho})^{M} is a cardinal, so it follows that (2ρ)M2ρ(2^{\rho})^{M}\leq 2^{\rho}. On the other hand, by 2.7, tj(ρ)=ρt_{j}(\rho)=\rho, and so by 2.8, (2ρ)M2ρ(2^{\rho})^{M}\geq 2^{\rho}. ∎

Theorem 2.10.

The existence of a cardinal preserving embedding from the universe into an inner model implies the consistency of ZFC + there is a strongly compact cardinal.

Proof.

If j:VMj:V\to M is cardinal preserving, then by a simple induction using 2.9, κn(j)\kappa_{n}(j) is strongly inaccessible for all n<ωn<\omega. By 2.1, for any n1n\geq 1, Vκn(j)V_{\kappa_{n}(j)} satisfies ZFC + there is a strongly compact cardinal. ∎

2.9 has some surprising reflection consequences: for example, the SCH must hold for all sufficiently large cardinals below the critical point κ\kappa of a cardinal preserving embedding j:VMj:V\to M. (It is open whether the SCH can fail everywhere below a strongly compact cardinal.) Moreover, if GCH holds below κ\kappa, it holds up to κω(j)\kappa_{\omega}(j). Can κ\kappa be the least measurable cardinal?

The same arguments almost prove that any cardinal preserving embedding j:VMj:V\to M is cofinality preserving and continuum function preserving, but now there is a problem applying Solovay’s Theorem that SCH holds above a strongly compact cardinal. For example, letting λ=κω(j)\lambda=\kappa_{\omega}(j), it is not clear how large λω\lambda^{\omega} can be. We do obtain:

Theorem 2.11 (SCH).

Suppose there is a cardinal preserving elementary embedding from the universe into the inner model MM. Then for any ordinal α\alpha, cfM(α)=cf(α)\textnormal{cf}^{M}(\alpha)=\textnormal{cf}(\alpha) and for any cardinal ρ\rho, (2ρ)M=2ρ(2^{\rho})^{M}=2^{\rho}.∎

References

  • [1] Andrés Eduardo Caicedo. Cardinal preserving elementary embeddings. In Logic Colloquium 2007, volume 35 of Lect. Notes Log., pages 14–31. Assoc. Symbol. Logic, La Jolla, CA, 2010.
  • [2] Gabriel Goldberg. The Ultrapower Axiom. PhD thesis, Harvard University, 2019.
  • [3] Jussi Ketonen. Strong compactness and other cardinal sins. Ann. Math. Logic, 5:47–76, 1972/73.
  • [4] Kenneth Kunen and Karel Prikry. On descendingly incomplete ultrafilters. J. Symbolic Logic, 36:650–652, 1971.
  • [5] Robert M. Solovay. Strongly compact cardinals and the GCH. In Proceedings of the Tarski Symposium (Proc. Sympos. Pure Math., Vol. XXV, Univ. California, Berkeley, Calif., 1971), pages 365–372. Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, R.I., 1974.